0% found this document useful (0 votes)
17 views57 pages

Chapter1p2 - Lectures 4,5

This document covers Predicate Logic, focusing on predicates, quantifiers, and their applications in logical reasoning. It explains the differences between propositional and predicate logic, introduces universal and existential quantifiers, and discusses negation and logical equivalences involving quantifiers. Additionally, it provides examples of translating English statements into logical expressions and highlights the importance of understanding the scope and properties of quantifiers.
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PPTX, PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
17 views57 pages

Chapter1p2 - Lectures 4,5

This document covers Predicate Logic, focusing on predicates, quantifiers, and their applications in logical reasoning. It explains the differences between propositional and predicate logic, introduces universal and existential quantifiers, and discusses negation and logical equivalences involving quantifiers. Additionally, it provides examples of translating English statements into logical expressions and highlights the importance of understanding the scope and properties of quantifiers.
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PPTX, PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 57

The Foundations: Logic

and Proofs
Chapter 1, Part II: Predicate Logic

With Question/Answer Animations

1
Chapter Summary
Propositional Logic
The Language of Propositions 1.1
Applications 1.2
Logical Equivalences 1.3
Predicate Logic (This Slide)
Predicates and Quantifiers 1.4
Nested Quantifiers 1.5
Proofs
Rules of Inference 1.6
Proof Methods 1.7
Proof Strategy 1.8
Predicate Logic Summary
Predicates and Quantifiers (Sec 1.4 -Lecture 4)
Universal and Existential Quantifier
Logical Equivalence involving quantifiers
Negating Quantifiers and De Morgan’s Laws for
Quantifiers
Translating English to Logic
Nested Quantifiers (Sec 1.5 – Lecture 5)
Order of Quantifiers
Translating
Negating Nested Quantifiers.

3
Predicates and Quantifiers
Section 1.4

4
Section Summary
Predicates , Variables, propositional function
Quantifiers
Universal Quantifier
Existential Quantifier
Logical Equivalence involving quantifiers
Negating Quantifiers
De Morgan’s Laws for Quantifiers
Translating English to Logic
Logic Programming (optional)

5
Propositional Logic Not Enough
If we have “All men are mortal.” and “Socrates is a
man.” Propositional logic doesn’t help to infer that
“Socrates is mortal”
Some statements can’t be represented as a
proposition. Need a language that talks about
objects, their properties, and their relations:
A students in the class is lazy.  needs assignment
Generalizing for simplicity:
Rafael is student or Kevin is student or …
There exist a person in the class who is student.
6
Introducing Predicate Logic
Predicate logic uses the following new
features:
Variables: x, y, z
Predicates: P(x), M(x)
Propositional functions are a generalization
of propositions.
They contain variables and a predicate, e.g.,
P(x)
Variables can be replaced by elements from
their domain.

7
Propositional Functions
 Propositional functions become propositions (and have truth
values) when their variables are each replaced by a value from the
domain (or bound by a quantifier, as we will see later).
 The statement P(x) is said to be the value of the propositional

 For example, let P(x) denote “x > 0” and the domain be the
function P at x.

integers. Then:
P(-3) is false.
P(0) is false.
P(3) is true.
 Often the domain is denoted by U. So in this example U is the
integers.

 Convention for 4075: for every question concerning


expressions in predicate logic determine U explicitly
8
Examples of Propositional Functions
 Let “x + y = z” be denoted by R(x, y, z) and U (for all three
variables) be the integers. Find these truth values:
R(2,-1,5)
Solution: F
R(3,4,7)

R(x, 3, z)
Solution: T

Solution: Not a Proposition


 Now let “x - y = z” be denoted by Q(x, y, z), with U as the
integers. Find these truth values:
Q(2,-1,3)
Solution: T
Q(3,4,7)

Q(x, 3, z)
Solution: F

Solution: Not a Proposition


9
Compound Expressions
 Connectives from propositional logic carry over to

 If P(x) denotes “x > 0,” find these truth values:


predicate logic.

∨ P(-1) Solution: T
∧ P(-1) Solution: F
P(3)

→ P(-1) Solution: F
P(3)

→ P(-1) Solution: T
P(3)
P(3)
 Expressions with variables are not propositions and

P(3) ∧ P(y)
therefore do not have truth values. For example,

P(x) → P(y)
 When used with quantifiers (to be introduced next), these
expressions (propositional functions) become propositions.
10
Quantifiers Charles Peirce (1839-
1914)
We need quantifiers to express the meaning of English
words including all and some:
“All men are Mortal.”
“Some cats do not have fur.”
The two most important quantifiers are:
Universal Quantifier, “For all,” symbol: 
Existential Quantifier, “There exists,” symbol: 
We write as in x P(x) and x P(x).
x P(x) asserts P(x) is true for every x in the domain.
x P(x) asserts P(x) is true for some x in the domain.
The quantifiers are said to bind the variable x in these
expressions.
11
Universal Quantifier
x P(x) is read as “For all x, P(x)” or “For every
x, P(x)”

If P(x) denotes “x > 0” and U is the integers, then


Examples:
1)

If P(x) denotes “x > 0” and U is the positive


x P(x) is false.

integers, then
2)

If P(x) denotes “x is even” and U is the integers,


x P(x) is true.

then  x P(x) is false.


3)

12
Existential Quantifier
x P(x) is read as “For some x, P(x)”, or as
“There is an x such that P(x),” or “For at
least one x, P(x).”

If P(x) denotes “x > 0” and U is the integers,


Examples:

then x P(x) is true. It is also true if U is the


1.

If P(x) denotes “x < 0” and U is the positive


positive integers.

integers, then
2.

If P(x) denotes “x is even” and U is the integers,


x P(x) is false.

then
3.
x P(x) is true.

13
Uniqueness Quantifier
 !x P(x) means that P(x) is true for one and only one x in the
universe of discourse.
 This is commonly expressed in English in the following
equivalent ways:
 “There is a unique x such that P(x).”
 “There is one and only one x such that P(x)”
 Examples:
1. If P(x) denotes “x + 1 = 0” and U is the integers, then !x P(x)

2. But if P(x) denotes “x > 0,” then !x P(x) is false.


is true.

 The uniqueness quantifier is not really needed as the restriction

x (P(x) ∧y (P(y) → y =x))


that there is a unique x such that P(x) can be expressed as:

x (P(x) ∧ P(y) → y =x) is not correct. Why?


14
Properties of Quantifiers
The truth value of x P(x) and  x P(x) depend on
both the propositional function P(x) and on the
domain U.
Examples:

“x < 2”, then x P(x) is true, but  x P(x) is


1. If U is the positive integers and P(x) is the statement

false.

“x < 2”, then both x P(x) and  x P(x) are true.


2. If U is the negative integers and P(x) is the statement

3. If U consists of 3, 4, and 5, and P(x) is the statement


“x > 2”, then both x P(x) and  x P(x) are
true. But if P(x) is the statement “x < 2”, then both x
P(x) and  x P(x) are false.
15
Precedence of Quantifiers
The quantifiers  and  have higher

For example, x P(x) ∨ Q(x) means (x


precedence than all the logical operators.

P(x))∨ Q(x)
x (P(x) ∨ Q(x)) means something different.
Unfortunately, often people write x P(x) ∨
Q(x) when they mean  x (P(x) ∨ Q(x)).

16
Thinking about Quantifiers as Conjunctions
and Disjunctions
If U consists of the integers 1,2, and 3:

Even if the domains are infinite, you can still


think of the quantifiers in this fashion, but the
equivalent expressions without quantifiers
will be infinitely long.

17
Thinking as a programmer
 When the domain of discourse is finite, we can think of
quantification as looping through the elements of the domain.
 To evaluate x P(x) loop through all x in the domain.
 If at every step P(x) is true, then x P(x) is true.
 If at a step P(x) is false, then x P(x) is false and the loop
terminates.
 To evaluate x P(x) loop through all x in the domain.
 If at some step, P(x) is true, then x P(x) is true and the loop
terminates.
 If the loop ends without finding an x for which P(x) is true, then
x P(x) is false.
 Even if the domains are infinite, we can still think of the
quantifiers this fashion, but the loops will not terminate in
some cases.
18
Equivalences in Predicate Logic
Statements involving predicates and
quantifiers are logically equivalent if and only
if they have the same truth value
for every predicate substituted into these
statements and
for every domain of discourse used for the

The notation S ≡T indicates that S and T are


variables in the expressions.

logically equivalent.
Example: x (S(x)T(x)) ≡ x S(x)  x T(x)

19
Negating Quantified Expressions
Consider x J(x)
“Every student in your class has taken a course in

Here J(x) is “x has taken a course in Java” and


Java.”

the domain is students in your class.


Negating the original statement gives “It is not
the case that every student in your class has
taken Java.” This implies that “There is a

Symbolically ¬x J(x) and x ¬J(x) are


student in your class who has not taken Java.”

equivalent
20
Negating Quantified Expressions
(continued)
Now Consider  x J(x)
“There is a student in this class who has taken a

Where J(x) is “x has taken a course in Java.”


course in Java.”

Negating the original statement gives “It is not


the case that there is a student in this class
who has taken Java.” This implies that “Every

Symbolically ¬ x J(x) and  x ¬J(x) are


student in this class has not taken Java”

equivalent

21
De Morgan’s Laws for Quantifiers
The rules for negating quantifiers are:

The reasoning in the table shows that:

These are important. You will use these.

22
Some Predicate Calculus Definitions
An assertion involving predicates and quantifiers is valid
if it is true
 for all domains
 every propositional function substituted for the predicates in the
assertion.
Example:
An assertion involving predicates is satisfiable if it is true
 for some domains
 some propositional functions that can be substituted for the
predicates in the assertion.
Otherwise it is unsatisfiable.
Example: not valid but satisfiable
Example: unsatisfiable

23
MorePredicate Calculus Definitions
The scope of a quantifier is the part of an
assertion in which variables are bound by the
quantifier.
Example: x has wide
scope

Example: x has narrow


scope

24
Translation from English to Logic
Examples:
1. “Some student in this class has visited Mexico.”
Solution: Let M(x) denote “x has visited Mexico”

U be all people.
and S(x) denote “x is a student in this class,” and

x (S(x) ∧ M(x))
2. “Every student in this class has visited Canada
or Mexico.”
Solution: Add C(x) denoting “x has visited

x (S(x)→ (M(x)∨C(x)))
Canada.”

25
Translating from English to Logic
Example 1: Translate the following sentence into
predicate logic: “Every student in this class has
taken a course in Java.”
Solution:
First decide on the domain U.
Solution 1: If U is all students in this class, define a

course in Java” and translate as x J(x).


propositional function J(x) denoting “x has taken a

Solution 2: But if U is all people, also define a

x (S(x)→ J(x)).
propositional function S(x) denoting “x is a student

x (S(x) ∧ J(x)) is not correct. What does it mean?


in this class” and translate as

26
Translating from English to Logic
Example 2: Translate the following sentence into
predicate logic: “Some student in this class has
taken a course in Java.”
Solution:
First decide on the domain U.
Solution 1: If U is all students in this class,

x J(x)
translate as

Solution 1: But if U is all people, then translate as


x (S(x) ∧ J(x))
x (S(x)→ J(x)) is not correct. What does it mean?
27
Lewis Carroll Example
Charles Lutwidge
Dodgson
(AKA Lewis Caroll)
 The first two are called premises and the third(1832-1898)
is called the
conclusion.
1. “All lions are fierce.” Self study to Slide
2. “Some lions do not drink coffee.” 40
3. “Some fierce creatures do not drink coffee.”
 Here is one way to translate these statements to predicate
logic. Let P(x), Q(x), and R(x) be the propositional
functions “x is a lion,” “x is fierce,” and “x drinks coffee,”

1. x (P(x)→ Q(x))
respectively.

2. x (P(x) ∧ ¬R(x))
3. x (Q(x) ∧ ¬R(x))
 Later we will see how to prove that the conclusion follows
from the premises.
28
System Specification Example
 Predicate logic is used for specifying properties that systems
must satisfy.
 For example, translate into predicate logic:
 “Every mail message larger than one megabyte will be
compressed.”
 “If a user is active, at least one network link will be
available.”
 Decide on predicates and domains (left implicit here) for the
variables:
 Let L(m, y) be “Mail message m is larger than y megabytes.”
 Let C(m) denote “Mail message m will be compressed.”
 Let A(u) represent “User u is active.”
 Let S(n, x) represent “Network link n is state x.
 Now we have:

29
Some Fun with Translating from English
into Logical Expressions
U = {fleegles, snurds, thingamabobs}
F(x): x is a fleegle
S(x): x is a snurd
T(x): x is a thingamabob
Translate “Everything is a fleegle”

Solution: x F(x)

30
Translation (cont)
U = {fleegles, snurds, thingamabobs}
F(x): x is a fleegle
S(x): x is a snurd
T(x): x is a thingamabob
“Nothing is a snurd.”

Solution: ¬x S(x) What is this equivalent


to?
Solution: x ¬ S(x)

31
Translation (cont)
U = {fleegles, snurds, thingamabobs}
F(x): x is a fleegle
S(x): x is a snurd
T(x): x is a thingamabob
“All fleegles are snurds.”

Solution: x (F(x)→ S(x))

32
Translation (cont)
U = {fleegles, snurds, thingamabobs}
F(x): x is a fleegle
S(x): x is a snurd
T(x): x is a thingamabob
“Some fleegles are thingamabobs.”

Solution: x (F(x) ∧ T(x))

33
Translation (cont)
U = {fleegles, snurds, thingamabobs}
F(x): x is a fleegle
S(x): x is a snurd
T(x): x is a thingamabob
“No snurd is a thingamabob.”

Solution: ¬x (S(x) ∧ T(x)) What is this


equivalent to?
Solution: x (¬S(x) ∨ ¬T(x))

34
Translation (cont)
U = {fleegles, snurds, thingamabobs}
F(x): x is a fleegle
S(x): x is a snurd
T(x): x is a thingamabob
“If any fleegle is a snurd then it is also a
thingamabob.”

Solution: x ((F(x) ∧ S(x))→ T(x))

35
Logic Programming (optional)
language developed in the 1970s by researchers in
Prolog (from Programming in Logic) is a programming

artificial intelligence (AI).


Prolog programs include Prolog facts and Prolog rules.
As an example of a set of Prolog facts consider the
following:
instructor(chan, math273).
instructor(patel, ee222).
instructor(grossman, cs301).
enrolled(kevin, math273).
enrolled(juna, ee222).
enrolled(juana, cs301).
enrolled(kiko, math273).
enrolled(kiko, cs301).

Here the predicates instructor(p,c) and enrolled(s,c)


represent that professor p is the instructor of course c
and that student s is enrolled in course c.
36
Logic Programming (cont)
In Prolog, names beginning with an
uppercase letter are variables.
If we have a predicate teaches(p,s)
representing “professor p teaches student s,”
we can write the rule:
teaches(P,S) :- instructor(P,C), enrolled(S,C).
This Prolog rule can be viewed as equivalent
to the following statement in logic (using our

p c s(I(p,c) ∧ E(s,c)) → T(p,s))


conventions for logical statements).

37
Logic Programming (cont)
Prolog programs are loaded into a Prolog
interpreter. The interpreter receives queries and
returns answers using the Prolog program.
For example, using our program, the following
query may be given:
?enrolled(kevin,math273).
Prolog produces the response:
yes
Note that the ? is the prompt given by the Prolog
interpreter indicating that it is ready to receive a
query.
38
Logic Programming (cont)
The query:
?enrolled(X,math273).

produces the response: The Prolog interpreter tries


to find an instantiation for
X = kevin; X. It does so and returns X
X = kiko; = kevin. Then the user
no types the ; indicating a
The query: request for another answer.
When Prolog is unable to
?teaches(X,juana).
find another answer it
produces the response: returns no.
X = patel;
X = grossman;
no
39
Logic Programming (cont)
The query:
?teaches(chan,X).

produces the response:


X = kevin;
X = kiko;
no

A number of very good Prolog texts are available.


Learn Prolog Now! is one such text with a free
online version at http://www.learnprolognow.org/
There is much more to Prolog and to the entire
field of logic programming.
40
Nested Quantifiers
Section 1.5

41
Section Summary
Nested Quantifiers
Order of Quantifiers
Translating from Nested Quantifiers into
English
Translating Mathematical Statements into
Statements involving Nested Quantifiers.
Translated English Sentences into Logical
Expressions.
Negating Nested Quantifiers.

42
Nested Quantifiers
Nested quantifiers are often necessary to
express the meaning of sentences in English
as well as important concepts in computer
science and mathematics.
Example: “Every real number has an

x y(x + y = 0)
inverse” is

where the domains of x and y are the real


numbers.
43
Thinking as a programmer
 Nested Loops
 To see if xy P (x,y) is true, loop through the values of x :
At each step, loop through the values for y.
If for some pair of x andy, P(x,y) is false, then x yP(x,y) is false and both the

x y P(x,y) is true if the outer loop ends after stepping through each x.
outer and inner loop terminate.

 To see if x yP(x,y) is true, loop through the values of x:


At each step, loop through the values for y.
The inner loop ends when a pair x and y is found such that P(x, y) is true.

If no y is found such that P(x, y) is true the outer loop terminates as x yP(x,y)

x y P(x,y) is true if the outer loop ends after stepping through each x.
has been shown to be false.

 If the domains of the variables are infinite, then this process can not
actually be carried out.
Write Java codes to simulate
xy P(x,y) and xyP(x,y) .

44
Order of Quantifiers
1. Let P(x,y) be the statement “x + y =0”
Examples:

Assume that U is the real numbers. Then x


yP(x,y) and

2. Let Q(x,y) be the statement “x + y = 0.”


y xP(x,y) have the same truth value.

Assume that U is the real numbers. Then x


yP(x,y) is true, but y xP(x,y) is false.

45
Questions on Order of Quantifiers
Example 1: Let U be the real numbers,
Define P(x,y) : x ∙ y = 0
What is the truth value of the following:
1. xyP(x,y)
Answer: False
2. xyP(x,y)

xy P(x,y)
Answer: True
3.

x  y P(x,y)
Answer: True
4.
Answer: True
46
Questions on Order of Quantifiers
Example 2: Let U be the R-{0},
Define P(x,y) : x / y = 1
What is the truth value of the following:
1. xyP(x,y)
Answer: False
2. xyP(x,y)

xy P(x,y)
Answer: True
3.

x  y P(x,y)
Answer: False
4.
Answer: True
47
Quantifications of Two Variables
Statement When True? When False
P(x,y) is true for There is a pair x, y
every pair x,y. for which P(x,y) is
false.
For every x there is a There is an x such
y for which P(x,y) is that P(x,y) is false for
true. every y.
There is an x for For every x there is a
which P(x,y) is true y for which P(x,y) is
for every y. false.
There is a pair x, y P(x,y) is false for
for which P(x,y) is every pair x,y
true.
48
Translating Nested Quantifiers into English
Example 1: Translate the statement
x (C(x )∨ y (C(y ) ∧ F(x, y)))
where C(x) is “x has a computer,” and F(x,y) is “x and y
are friends,” and the domain for both x and y consists of
all students in your school.
Solution: Every student in your school has a computer

Example 1: Translate the statement


or has a friend in the school who has a computer.

xy z ((F(x, y)∧ F(x,z) ∧ (y ≠z))→¬F(y,z))


Solution: There is at least one student in your
school that none of whose friends are also friends
with each other.
49
Translating Mathematical Statements into
Predicate Logic
Example : Translate “The sum of two positive integers
is always positive” into a logical expression.
Solution:
1. Rewrite the statement to make the implied quantifiers
and domains explicit:
“For every two integers, if these integers are both positive, then
the sum of these integers is positive.”
2. Introduce the variables x and y, and specify the
domain, to obtain:
“For all positive integers x and y, x + y is positive.”

x  y ((x > 0)∧ (y > 0)→ (x + y > 0))


3. The result is:

where the domain of both variables consists of all integers

50
Translating English into Logical Expressions
Example
Example: Use quantifiers to express the
statement “There is a woman who has taken a
flight on every airline in the world.”

1. Let P(w,f) be “w has taken f ” and Q(f,a) be “f


Solution:

is a flight on a .”
2. The domain of w is all women, the domain of f
is all flights, and the domain of a is all
airlines.

w a f (P(w,f ) ∧ Q(f,a))
3. Then the statement can be expressed as:

51
Questions on Translation from English
Example 1: “Brothers are siblings.”
Choose the obvious predicates and express in predicate logic.

Solution: x y (B(x,y) → S(x,y))


Example 2: “Siblinghood is symmetric.”
Solution: x y (S(x,y) → S(y,x))
Example 3: “Everybody loves somebody.”

Example 4: “There is someone who is loved by everyone.”


Solution: x y L(x,y)

Example 5: “There is someone who loves someone.”


Solution: y x L(x,y)

Example 6: “Everyone loves themselves”


Solution: x y L(x,y)

Solution: x L(x,x)
52
Negating Nested Quantifiers
Example 1: Recall the logical expression developed two slides back:
w a f (P(w,f ) ∧ Q(f,a))
Part 1: Use quantifiers to express the statement that “There does not exist a

Solution: ¬w a f (P(w,f ) ∧ Q(f,a))


woman who has taken a flight on every airline in the world.”

Part 2: Now use De Morgan’s Laws to move the negation as far inwards as
possible.

¬w a f (P(w,f ) ∧ Q(f,a))


Solution:

w ¬ a f (P(w,f ) ∧ Q(f,a)) by De Morgan’s for 


1.
2.
3. w  a ¬ f (P(w,f ) ∧ Q(f,a)) by De Morgan’s for 
w  a f ¬ (P(w,f ) ∧ Q(f,a)) by De Morgan’s for 
w  a f (¬ P(w,f ) ∨ ¬ Q(f,a)) by De Morgan’s for ∧.
4.

Part 3: Can you translate the result back into English?


5.

Solution:
“For every woman there is an airline such that for all flights, this woman has
not taken that flight or that flight is not on this airline”
53
Some Questions about Quantifiers
 Can you switch the order of quantifiers?
 Is this a valid equivalence?
Solution: Yes! The left and the right side will always have the same truth
value. The order in which x and y are picked does not matter.
 Is this a valid equivalence?

for some propositional functions for P. Try “x + y = 0” for P(x,y) with U being
Solution: No! The left and the right side may have different truth values

the integers. The order in which the values of x and y are picked does matter.
 Can you distribute quantifiers over logical connectives?
 Is this a valid equivalence?
Solution: Yes! The left and the right side will always have the same truth
value no matter what propositional functions are denoted by P(x) and Q(x).
 Is this a valid equivalence?
Solution: No! The left and the right side may have different truth values.
Pick “x is a fish” for P(x) and “x has scales” for Q(x) with the domain of
discourse being all animals. Then the left side is false, because there are
some fish that do not have scales. But the right side is true since not all
animals are fish.
54
Logic in Calculus
Example: Use quantifiers to express the definition of the limit
of a real-valued function f(x) of a real variable x at a point a
in its domain.
Solution: Recall the definition of the statement

is “For every real number ε > 0, there exists a real number


δ > 0 such that |f(x) – L| < ε whenever 0 < |x –a| < δ.”
Using quantifiers:

Where the domain for the variables ε and δ consists of all


positive real numbers and the domain for x consists of all
real numbers.
55
Logic in Calculus
Example : Recall the logical expression developed in the calculus example three slides back.
Use quantifiers and predicates to express that does not exist.

1. We need to say that for all real numbers L,

2. The result from the previous example can be negated to yield:

3. Now we can repeatedly apply the rules for negating quantified expressions:

The last step uses the equivalence ¬(p→q) ≡ p∧¬q

56
Logic in Calculus
4. Therefore, to say that does not exist
means that for all real numbers L,
can be expressed as:

Remember that ε and δ range over all positive


real numbers and x over all real numbers.

every real number L, there is a real number ε


5. Translating back into English we have, for

> 0, such that for every real number δ > 0,


there exists a real number x such that 0 < | x –
a | < δ and |f(x) – L | ≥ ε .
57

You might also like