0% found this document useful (0 votes)
4 views41 pages

Lecture2 1

Download as pptx, pdf, or txt
Download as pptx, pdf, or txt
Download as pptx, pdf, or txt
You are on page 1/ 41

Game Theory

--
Lecture 2

1
Lecture 1 recap
• Defined games in normal form
• Defined dominance notion
– Iterative deletion
– Does not always give a solution
• Defined best response and Nash equilibrium
– Computed Nash equilibrium in some examples

➔ Are some Nash equilibria better than others?


➔ Can we always find a Nash equilibrium?

2
Outline
1. Coordination games and Pareto optimality
2. Games with continuous action sets
– Equilibrium computation and existence theorem
– Example: Cournot duopoly

3
Outline
1. Coordination games and Pareto optimality
2. Games with continuous action sets
– Equilibrium computation and existence theorem
– Example: Cournot duopoly

4
The Investment Game
• The players: you
• The strategies: each of you chooses between investing
nothing in a class project ($0) or investing ($10)
• Payoffs:
– If you don’t invest your payoff is $0
– If you invest you make a net profit of $5 (gross profit =
$15; investment $10) if more than 90% of the class
chooses to invest. Otherwise, you lose $10

• Choose your action (no communication!)

5
Nash equilibrium
• What are the Nash equilibria?

• Remark: to find Nash equilibria, we used a


“guess and check method”
– Checking is easy, guessing can be hard
6
The Investment Game again
• Recall that:
– Players: you
– Strategies: invest $0 or invest $10
– Payoffs:
• If no invest ➔ $0
$5 net profit if ≥ 90% invest
• If invest $10 ➔
-$10 net profit if < 90% invest

• Let’s play again! (no communication)

• We are heading toward an equilibrium


-+There are certain cases in which playing converges in a
natural sense to an equilibrium 7
Pareto domination
• Is one equilibrium better than the other?

Definition: Pareto domination


A strategy profile s Pareto dominates strategy
profile s’ iif for all i, ui(s)≥ui(s’) and there exists j
such that uj(s)>uj(s’);
i.e., all players have at least as high payoffs and
at least one player has strictly higher payoff.
• In the investment game?
8
Convergence to equilibrium in the
Investment Game
• Why did we converge to the wrong NE?
• Remember when we started playing
– We were more or less 50 % investing
• The starting point was already bad for the people
who invested for them to lose confidence
• Then we just tumbled down

• What would have happened if we started with


95% of the class investing?

9
Coordination game
• This is a coordination game
– We’d like everyone to coordinate their actions and invest
• Many other examples of coordination games
– Party in a Villa
– On-line Web Sites
– Establishment of technological monopolies (Microsoft, HDTV)
– Bank runs
• Unlike in prisoner’s dilemma, communication helps in
coordination games ➔ scope for leadership
– In prisoner’s dilemma, a trusted third party (TTP) would need to
impose players to adopt a strictly dominated strategy
– In coordination games, a TTP just leads the crowd towards a
better NE point (there is no dominated strategy)

10
Battle of the sexes
Player 2
Opera Soccer
Opera 2,1 0,0
Player 1
Soccer 0,0 1,2

• Find the NE

• Is there a NE better than the other(s)?

11
Coordination Games
• Pure coordination games: there is no conflict whether
one NE is better than the other
– E.g.: in the investment game, we all agreed that the NE
with everyone investing was a “better” NE

• General coordination games: there is a source of


conflict as players would agree to coordinate, but one
NE is “better” for a player and not for the other
– E.g.: Battle of the Sexes

➔ Communication might fail in this case


12
Pareto optimality

Definition: Pareto optimality


A strategy profile s is Pareto optimal if there
does not exist a strategy profile s’ that Pareto
dominates s.

• Battle of the sexes?

13
Outline
1. Coordination games and Pareto optimality
2. Games with continuous action sets
– Equilibrium computation and existence theorem
– Example: Cournot duopoly

14
The partnership game (see exercise
sheet 2)
• Two partners choose effort si in Si=[0, 4]
• Share revenue and have quadratic costs
u1(s1 , s2) = ½ [4 (s1 + s2 + b s1 s2)] -
s12 u2(s1 , s2) = ½ [4 (s1 + s2 + b s1 s2)] -
s22
ŝ1 = 1 + b s2 = BR1(s2)
• Best responses:
ŝ2 = 1 + b s1 = BR2(s1)

15
Finding the best response (with twice
continuously differentiable utilities)
u1 (s1, s2 )  0 • First order condition (FOC)
s1
2 u1 (s1, s2 )
 • Second order condition (SOC)
 s1
2
0
• Remark: the SOC is automatically satisfied if ui(si,s-i) is
concave in si for all s-i (very standard assumption)
• Remark 2: be careful with the borders!
– Example u1(s1, s2) = 10-(s1+s2)2
– S1=[0, 4], what is the BR to s2=2?
– Solving the FOC, what do we get?

– When the FOC solution is outside Si, the BR is at the


Nash equilibrium graphically
s2

4 BR1(s2)

2 BR2(s1)

0 s1
1 2 3 4 5

• NE is fixed point of (s1, s2) ➔ (BR(s2), BR(s1)) 17


Best response correspondence
• Definition: ŝi is a BR to s-i if ŝi solves max ui(si , s-i)
• The BR to s-i may not be unique!
• BR(s-i): set of si that solve max ui(si , s-i)
• The definition can be written:
ŝi is a BR to s-i if sˆi  BRi (si )  argmax ui (si,
si )
si

• Best response correspondence of


i: s ➔ BR (s )
18
Nash equilibrium as a fixed point

• Game N, S iN , u


i i
• Let’s define S iN i S (set of strategy
and the
profiles) correspondence
iN  B:SS
s  B(s)  iN BRi (si )
• For a given s, B(s) is the set of strategy profiles s’
such that si’ is a BR to s-i for all i.
• A strategy profile s* is a Nash eq. iif s*  B(s* )
(just a re-writing of the definition) 19
Kakutani’s fixed point theorem

Theorem: Kakutani’s fixed point theorem


Let X be a compact convex subset of Rn and let
f : X  X be a set-valued function for which:
• for all x  X , the set f (x) is nonempty convex;
• the graph of f is closed.
Then there exists x*  X such that x*  f (x* )

20
Closed graph (upper hemicontinuity)
• Definition: f has closed graph if for all sequences (xn) and (yn)
such that yn is in f(xn) for all n, xn➔x and yn➔y, y is in f(x)
• Alternative definition: f has closed graph if for all x we have the
following property: for any open neighborhood V of f(x), there
exists a neighborhood U of x such that for all x in U, f(x) is a
subset of V.
• Examples:

21
Existence of (pure strategy) Nash
equilibrium
Theorem: Existence of pure strategy NE
Suppose that the game N, Si iN , ui iN 
• The action set S i
satisfies: of each player is a
compact
nonempty convex subset of R n

• The utility ui of each player is continuous


in s
(on S ) and concave in si (on Si )
Then, there exists a (pure strategy) Nash
equilibrium.
22
Proof
• Define B as before. B satisfies the assumptions of
Kakutani’s fixed point theorem
• Therefore B has a fixed point which by definition is a
Nash equilibrium!

• Now, we need to actually verify that B satisfies the


assumptions of Kakutani’s fixed point theorem!

23
Example: the partnership game
• N = {1, 2}
• S = [0,4]x[0,4] compact convex
• Utilities are continuous and concave
u1(s1 , s2) = ½ [4 (s1 + s2 + b s1 s2)] - s 12
u2(s1 , s2) = ½ [4 (s1 + s2 + b s1 s2)] - s 22
• Conclusion: there exists a NE!

• Ok, for this game, we already knew it!


• But the theorem is much more general and
applies to games where finding the equilibrium is
much more difficult
24
One more word on the partnership
game before we move on
• We have found (see exercises) that
– At Nash equilibrium:
s*1 = s*2 =1/(1-b)
– To maximize the sum of utilities:
sW 1 = sW =1/(1/2-b) > s*
2 1
• Sum of utilities called social welfare
• Both partners would be better off if they
worked sW1 (with social planner, contract)
• Why do they work less than efficient?

25
Externality
• At the margin, I bear the cost for the extra unit of effort
I contribute, but I’m only reaping half of the induced
profits, because of profit sharing

• This is known as an “externality”


➔ When I’m figuring out the effort I have to put I
don’t take into account that other half of profit that
goes to my partner
➔ In other words, my effort benefits my partner, not
just me

• Externalities are omnipresent: public good problems,


free riding, etc. (see more in the netecon course)
26
Outline
1. Coordination games and Pareto optimality
2. Games with continuous action sets
– Equilibrium computation and existence theorem
– Example: Cournot duopoly

27
Cournot Duopoly
• Example of application of games with continuous
action set
• This game lies between two extreme cases in
economics, in situations where firms (e.g. two
companies) are competing on the same market
– Perfect competition
– Monopoly
• We’re interested in understanding what happens
in the middle
– The game analysis will give us interesting economic
insights on the duopoly market

28
Cournot Duopoly: the game
• The players: 2 Firms, e.g., Coke and Pepsi

• Strategies: quantities players produce of identical


products: qi, q-i
– Products are perfect substitutes

• Cost of production: c * q
– Simple model of constant marginal cost

• Prices: p = a – b (q1 + q2) = a – bQ


– Market-clearing price

29
Price in the Cournot duopoly

p Demand curve
Slope: -b Tells the quantity
a demanded for a
given price

0 q1 + q2

30
Cournot Duopoly: payoffs
• The payoffs: firms aim to maximize profit

u1(q1,q2) = p * q1 – c * q1
p = a – b (q1 + q2)

► u1(q1,q2) = a * q1 – b * q2 –b*q
q –c*q
1
1
2
1

• The game is symmetric 31


Cournot Duopoly: best responses
• First order condition a  2bq1  bq2  c 
0
• Second order condition
[
 2b  0
a  c q2
➔ ˆ 
 q 1  BR1 (q2 ) 2b

 2  1
qˆ2  BR2 (q1 ) a  c q
2b 2
 32
Cournot Duopoly: best response
diagram and Nash equilibrium
q2

a
cb

BR1
a
qCournot  a  c
c2b 3
NE
b
BR2

0 a a q1
c2b cb 33
Best response at q2=0
p
• BR1(q2=0) = (a-c)/(2b)
• Interpretation:
a Demand curve monopoly quantity
Slope: -b
► marginal revenue =
Marginal revenue marginal cost
Slope: -2b

Marginal cost: c

0 a q1
c2b
34
MONOPOLY
When is BR1(q2) = 0?
p

• BR1(q2=(a-c)/b) = 0
a Demand curve • Perfect competition
Slope: -b quantity
Marginal revenue
►Demand = marginal
Slope: -2b cost
Marginal cost

0 a a q1+q1
c2b cb
If Firm 1 would produce more, the
MONOPOLY PERFECT selling price would not cover her costs 35
COMPETITIO
Cournot Duopoly: best response
diagram and Nash equilibrium
q2

a
cb

BR1

Monopoly qCournot  a  c
NE 3
b
BR2

0 a q1
Perfect
c2b competition 36
Strategic substitutes/complements
• In Cournot duopoly: the more the other player
does, the less I would do
➔ This is a game of strategic substitutes
– Note: of course the goods were substitutes
– We’re talking about strategies here
• In the partnership game, it was the opposite:
the more the other player would the more I
would do
➔ This is a game of strategic complements
37
Cournot duopoly: Market perspective
q2
• Total industry
profit
a maximized for
cb monopoly
BR1
Industry profits
are maximized
qCournot  a  c
3b
BR2

0 a q1
c2b 38
Cartel, agreement
q2 • How could the
firms set an
agreement to
a
cb
increase profit?
• What can the
BR1
problems be
Both firms
qCournot  a  c with this
produce half 3
of the monopoly b2
BR
agreement ?
quantity

0 a q1 39
c2b
Cournot Duopoly: last observations
• How do quantities and prices we’ve
encountered so far compare?

Perfect Cournot
Monopoly QUANTITIES
Competition Quantity

a 2(a  a
cb c) 3 c2b
b
Perfect Cournot PRICES
Monopoly
Competition Quantity

40
Summary
• Coordination games
– Pareto optimal NE sometimes exist
– Scope for communication / leadership
• Games with continuous action sets (pure
strategies)
– Compute equilibrium with FOC, SOC
– Equilibrium exists under concavity and continuity
conditions
– Cournot duopoly

41

You might also like