Lesson 5
Lesson 5
ETHICS I
Ethics
Social Science Department
College of Education and Liberal Arts
Adamson University
9/3/20XX 2
NORMATIVE ETHICS I
AGENDA
What is Normative Ethics?
What is Virtue Ethics?
What is Kantian Ethics?
WHAT IS KANTIAN
ETHICS?
What is good is not equivalent to what is right
Centered in duty – deontological – deon means duty – duty to follow – based on Immanuel Kant (I.K.) – emotion is not
the basis of morality, it is our reason
3
NORMATIVE ETHICS I
Immanuel Kant (1724—
1804)
PRESENTATION TITLE
According to A – human being are only the rational animals – animals – no sense of humor = no reason
Hume’s law – one cannot derive a moral claim from fact claims
5
6
PRESENTATION TITLE
Intention of M can be good – can be good in away the money would help M in her everyday life --
however – goodness does not make the action is right
9
Kantian Ethics
• a form of deontological ethics – an ethical theory that defines right
independently of the good.
• whether or not a contemplated course of action is morally permissible
will depend on whether or not it conforms to what he terms the moral
law, the categorical imperative.
• Our duties can be understood in terms of respecting this imperative,
even if respecting the moral law leads to bad effects rather than good
ones.
Kantian Ethics (K.E.) – have reason – have duty to follow moral law
Moral law:
1. The categorical imperative – to follow – using our own reason: imperative – command/orders
Based on reason – a command based on reason
Necessary
If u follow categorical imperative – u are doing a morally action
2. Hypothetical imperative
Based on desire – do a command based on desire
Contingent – can/cannot do it – based on ur desire
11
Categorical versus Hypothetical
Imperatives
• The moral law is categorical rather than hypothetical and it is an imperative.
Imperatives are commands or orders.
• A hypothetical imperative is a contingent command, one that we ought to
follow given our desires, for example.
“Go to the doctor”
• A categorical imperative, however, binds us no matter what our desires are.
“Don’t just use someone for your own purposes”
• This is the nature of morality – obligations bind independent of our desires;
they are not based in desire but in reason.
12
Duty versus Inclination
• Kant believed that when we act well and are solely motivated by good
inclination, our actions lack moral worth.
• A person can exhibit moral worth while still experiencing
psychological conflict. What is important to moral worth is whether or
not the sense of duty is what is motivating our action.
• If a person acts rightly because of duty and not simply because he
desires the good, or had an inclination to seek it then: “…for the first
time does his conduct have real moral worth.”
13
Suppose you are visited in the
hospital by your friend Smith…
15
Duty versus Inclination
• Stocker clearly intends that we be put off by this. What we want in a friend is
someone who doesn’t regard his kindnesses to us as a matter of duty but, instead,
someone who wants to spend time with us, who is inclined to help, irrespective of
duty. Anything less than this, the thought goes, is a diminished form of friendship.
• Smith visits out of duty does not rule out a positive inclination to visit as well. The
problem is not that he is visiting out of duty, but that this seems to imply that he
is doing so grudgingly or resentfully, and that is what is disturbing. Absent those
negative feelings, however, and the case Stocker presents does not seem so
objectionable.
• Emotions such as pathological love can be very good indeed – but they have no moral
worth.
16
Duty
• Note that there is a difference between (1) following a rule and (2)
behaving in such a way that our actions happen to conform to a rule.
• Moral worth consists in following the moral law, the categorical
imperative.
17
The Categorical Imperative
• Formulation one:
Act only according to that maxim whereby you can at the
same time will that it should become a universal law.
• Formulation two:
Act in such a way that you treat humanity, whether in your
own person or in the person of another, always at the same time as an
end and never simply as a means.
18
FORMULATION
ONE
Act only according to that
maxim whereby you can at the
same time will that it should
become a universal law.
19
The case of a man who needs
to borrow money, though he
knows he cannot repay it…
21
Universal Law
22
Contradiction in Conception
• Self-contradictory or Logical contradiction: we cannot will this to be
universal because we cannot even conceive of a world in which
everyone makes lying promises successfully – universal lying would
undermine trust in communication. This is why it is termed a
contradiction in conception.
• Practical Contradiction: When this is universalized, however, people
wouldn’t be able to get loans because no one would lend them money
if they couldn’t rely on the promises– thus, the frustration of the
agent’s purposes. And therein lies the practical contradiction.
23
Suppose that Robert is
considering a donation to
charity…
26
For instance…
27
Formulation Two
• In using a person as a means, one necessarily disregards the person’s
interests; while treating them as an end, one necessarily considers the
person’s interests.
• Since having interests is essential to being a person, treating a person
as a means is tantamount to treating a person not as a person, while
treating a person as an end is tantamount to treating a person as a
person.
• Kant is not saying that we can never use another person as a means to
our own ends; he is not saying that it is always wrong to do so. As
long as they are treated with respect as autonomous, rational, beings.
28
9/3/20XX 29
PRESENTATION TITLE
THANK YOU
PRESENTATION TITLE
Summary
With PowerPoint, you can create
presentations and share your work with
others, wherever they are. Type the text
you want here to get started. You can also
add images, art, and videos on this
template. Save to OneDrive and access
your presentations from your computer,
tablet, or phone.
30