0% found this document useful (0 votes)
81 views30 pages

Chapter 1 P 2

This document discusses predicate logic and quantifiers. It introduces predicates, variables, quantifiers (universal and existential), and how to translate statements between English and predicate logic. Some key points: - Predicate logic uses variables, predicates, and quantifiers to represent statements about objects and their properties. - The universal quantifier ("for all") is represented by ∀ and the existential quantifier ("there exists") is represented by ∃. - Quantifiers are used to translate English statements containing "all" or "some" into logical expressions. - Negating quantified statements follows De Morgan's laws, such that ¬∀xP(x) is equivalent to ∃x
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PPTX, PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
81 views30 pages

Chapter 1 P 2

This document discusses predicate logic and quantifiers. It introduces predicates, variables, quantifiers (universal and existential), and how to translate statements between English and predicate logic. Some key points: - Predicate logic uses variables, predicates, and quantifiers to represent statements about objects and their properties. - The universal quantifier ("for all") is represented by ∀ and the existential quantifier ("there exists") is represented by ∃. - Quantifiers are used to translate English statements containing "all" or "some" into logical expressions. - Negating quantified statements follows De Morgan's laws, such that ¬∀xP(x) is equivalent to ∃x
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PPTX, PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 30

The Foundations: Logic

and Proofs
Chapter 2, Part II: Predicate Logic
Summary
Predicate Logic (First-Order Logic (FOL), Predicate
Calculus)
The Language of Quantifiers
Logical Equivalences
Translation from Predicate Logic to English
Translation from English to Predicate Logic
Predicates and Quantifiers
Section 1.4
Section Summary
Predicates
Variables
Quantifiers
Universal Quantifier
Existential Quantifier
Negating Quantifiers
De Morgan’s Laws for Quantifiers
Translating English to Logic
Logic Programming (optional)
Propositional Logic Not Enough
If we have:
“All men are mortal.”
“Socrates is a man.”
Does it follow that “Socrates is mortal?”
Can’t be represented in propositional logic. Need a
language that talks about objects, their properties, and
their relations.
Later we’ll see how to draw inferences.
Introducing Predicate Logic
Predicate logic uses the following new features:
Variables: x, y, z
Predicates: P(x), M(x)
Quantifiers (to be covered in a few slides):
Propositional functions are a generalization of
propositions.
They contain variables and a predicate, e.g., P(x)
Variables can be replaced by elements from their
domain.
Propositional Functions
Propositional functions become propositions (and have truth
values) when their variables are each replaced by a value from
the domain (or bound by a quantifier, as we will see later).
The statement P(x) is said to be the value of the propositional
function P at x.
For example, let P(x) denote “x > 0” and the domain be the
integers. Then:
P(-3) is false.
P(0) is false.
P(3) is true.
Often the domain is denoted by U. So in this example U is the
integers.
Examples of Propositional Functions
Let “x + y = z” be denoted by R(x, y, z) and U (for all three variables) be the integers.
Find these truth values:
R(2,-1,5)
Solution: F
R(3,4,7)
Solution: T
R(x, 3, z)
Solution: Not a Proposition
Now let “x - y = z” be denoted by Q(x, y, z), with U as the integers. Find these truth
values:
Q(2,-1,3)
Solution: T
Q(3,4,7)
Solution: F
Q(x, 3, z)
Solution: Not a Proposition
Compound Expressions
Connectives from propositional logic carry over to predicate logic.
If P(x) denotes “x > 0,” find these truth values:
P(3) ∨ P(-1) Solution: T
P(3) ∧ P(-1) Solution: F
P(3) → P(-1) Solution: F
P(3) → ¬P(-1) Solution: T
Expressions with variables are not propositions and therefore do
not have truth values. For example,
P(3) ∧ P(y)
P(x) → P(y)
When used with quantifiers (to be introduced next), these
expressions (propositional functions) become propositions.
Quantifiers
We need quantifiers to express the meaning of English words
including all and some:
“All men are Mortal.”
“Some cats do not have fur.”
The two most important quantifiers are:
Universal Quantifier, “For all,” symbol: 
Existential Quantifier, “There exists,” symbol: 
We write as in x P(x) and x P(x).
x P(x) asserts P(x) is true for every x in the domain.
x P(x) asserts P(x) is true for some x in the domain.
The quantifiers are said to bind the variable x in these expressions.
Universal Quantifier
x P(x) is read as “For all x, P(x)” or “For every x, P(x)”
Examples:
1) If P(x) denotes “x > 0” and U is the integers, then x P(x) is
false.
2) If P(x) denotes “x > 0” and U is the positive integers, then
x P(x) is true.
3) If P(x) denotes “x is even” and U is the integers, then  x
P(x) is false.
Existential Quantifier
x P(x) is read as “For some x, P(x)”, or as “There is an
x such that P(x),” or “For at least one x, P(x).”
Examples:
1. If P(x) denotes “x > 0” and U is the integers, then x P(x) is
true. It is also true if U is the positive integers.
2. If P(x) denotes “x < 0” and U is the positive integers, then
x P(x) is false.
3. If P(x) denotes “x is even” and U is the integers, then x
P(x) is true.
Thinking about Quantifiers
When the domain of discourse is finite, we can think of
quantification as looping through the elements of the domain.
To evaluate x P(x) loop through all x in the domain.
If at every step P(x) is true, then x P(x) is true.
If at a step P(x) is false, then x P(x) is false and the loop terminates.
To evaluate x P(x) loop through all x in the domain.
If at some step, P(x) is true, then x P(x) is true and the loop
terminates.
If the loop ends without finding an x for which P(x) is true, then x
P(x) is false.
Even if the domains are infinite, we can still think of the quantifiers
this fashion, but the loops will not terminate in some cases.
Properties of Quantifiers
The truth value of x P(x) and  x P(x) depend on both
the propositional function P(x) and on the domain U.
Examples:
1. If U is the positive integers and P(x) is the statement
“x < 2”, then x P(x) is true, but  x P(x) is false.
2. If U is the negative integers and P(x) is the statement
“x < 2”, then both x P(x) and  x P(x) are true.
3. If U consists of 3, 4, and 5, and P(x) is the statement
“x > 2”, then both x P(x) and  x P(x) are true. But
if P(x) is the statement “x < 2”, then both x P(x) and
 x P(x) are false.
Precedence of Quantifiers
The quantifiers  and  have higher precedence than
all the logical operators.
For example, x P(x) ∨ Q(x) means (x P(x))∨ Q(x)
x (P(x) ∨ Q(x)) means something different.
Unfortunately, often people write x P(x) ∨ Q(x)
when they mean  x (P(x) ∨ Q(x)).
Translating from English to Logic
Example 1: Translate the following sentence into predicate
logic: “Every student in this class has taken a course in Java.”
Solution:
First decide on the domain U.
Solution 1: If U is all students in this class, define a
propositional function J(x) denoting “x has taken a course in
Java” and translate as x J(x).
Solution 2: But if U is all people, also define a propositional
function S(x) denoting “x is a student in this class” and
translate as x (S(x)→ J(x)).
x (S(x) ∧ J(x)) is not correct. What does it mean?
Translating from English to Logic
Example 2: Translate the following sentence into
predicate logic: “Some student in this class has taken a
course in Java.”
Solution:
First decide on the domain U.
Solution 1: If U is all students in this class, translate as
x J(x)
Solution 2: But if U is all people, then translate as
x (S(x) ∧ J(x))
x (S(x)→ J(x)) is not correct. What does it mean?
Returning to the Socrates Example
Introduce the propositional functions Man(x)
denoting “x is a man” and Mortal(x) denoting “x is
mortal.” Specify the domain as all people.
The two premises are:

The conclusion is:

Later we will show how to prove that the conclusion


follows from the premises.
Equivalences in Predicate Logic
Statements involving predicates and quantifiers are
logically equivalent if and only if they have the same
truth value
for every predicate substituted into these statements
and
for every domain of discourse used for the variables in
the expressions.
The notation S ≡T indicates that S and T are logically
equivalent.
Example: x ¬¬S(x) ≡ x S(x)
Thinking about Quantifiers as Conjunctions
and Disjunctions
If the domain is finite, a universally quantified proposition is equivalent
to a conjunction of propositions without quantifiers and an existentially
quantified proposition is equivalent to a disjunction of propositions
without quantifiers.
If U consists of the integers 1,2, and 3:

Even if the domains are infinite, you can still think of the quantifiers in
this fashion, but the equivalent expressions without quantifiers will be
infinitely long.
Negating Quantified Expressions
Consider x J(x)
“Every student in your class has taken a course in Java.”
Here J(x) is “x has taken a course in Java” and
the domain is students in your class.
Negating the original statement gives “It is not the
case that every student in your class has taken Java.”
This implies that “There is a student in your class who
has not taken Java.”
Symbolically ¬x J(x) and x ¬J(x) are equivalent
Negating Quantified Expressions (continued)
Now Consider  x J(x)
“There is a student in this class who has taken a course in
Java.”
Where J(x) is “x has taken a course in Java.”
Negating the original statement gives “It is not the
case that there is a student in this class who has taken
Java.” This implies that “Every student in this class has
not taken Java”
Symbolically ¬ x J(x) and  x ¬J(x) are equivalent
De Morgan’s Laws for Quantifiers
The rules for negating quantifiers are:

The reasoning in the table shows that:

These are important. You will use these.


Translation from English to Logic
Examples:
1. “Some student in this class has visited Mexico.”
Solution: Let M(x) denote “x has visited Mexico” and
S(x) denote “x is a student in this class,” and U be all
people.
x (S(x) ∧ M(x))
2. “Every student in this class has visited Canada or
Mexico.”
Solution: Add C(x) denoting “x has visited Canada.”
x (S(x)→ (M(x)∨C(x)))
Some Fun with Translating from English into
Logical Expressions
U = {fleegles, snurds, thingamabobs}
F(x): x is a fleegle
S(x): x is a snurd
T(x): x is a thingamabob
Translate “Everything is a fleegle”

Solution: x F(x)
Translation (cont)
U = {fleegles, snurds, thingamabobs}
F(x): x is a fleegle
S(x): x is a snurd
T(x): x is a thingamabob
“Nothing is a snurd.”

Solution: ¬x S(x) What is this equivalent to?


Solution: x ¬ S(x)
Translation (cont)
U = {fleegles, snurds, thingamabobs}
F(x): x is a fleegle
S(x): x is a snurd
T(x): x is a thingamabob
“All fleegles are snurds.”

Solution: x (F(x)→ S(x))


Translation (cont)
U = {fleegles, snurds, thingamabobs}
F(x): x is a fleegle
S(x): x is a snurd
T(x): x is a thingamabob
“Some fleegles are thingamabobs.”

Solution: x (F(x) ∧ T(x))


Translation (cont)
U = {fleegles, snurds, thingamabobs}
F(x): x is a fleegle
S(x): x is a snurd
T(x): x is a thingamabob
“No snurd is a thingamabob.”

Solution: ¬x (S(x) ∧ T(x)) What is this equivalent


to?
Solution: x (¬S(x) ∨ ¬T(x))
Translation (cont)
U = {fleegles, snurds, thingamabobs}
F(x): x is a fleegle
S(x): x is a snurd
T(x): x is a thingamabob
“If any fleegle is a snurd then it is also a thingamabob.”

Solution: x ((F(x) ∧ S(x))→ T(x))

You might also like