Topic 2 - Freedom and Morality
Topic 2 - Freedom and Morality
Topic 2 - Freedom and Morality
Morality
Freedom and
Moral Acts
Introduction
• In Kant philosophy, freedom is defined as a concept which is involved
in the moral domain, at the question: what should I do?
• In summary, Kant says that the moral law is only that I know myself as
a free person. Kantian freedom is closely linked to the notion of
autonomy, which means law itself: thus, freedom falls obedience to a
law that I created myself. It is therefore, respect its commitment to
compliance with oneself.
Kant's Morality and
Freedom
• To act freely is to act autonomously. To act autonomously is to act
according to a law I give myself. Whenever I act according to the laws of
nature, demands of social convention, when I pursue pleasure and
comfort, I am not acting freely. To act freely is not to simply choose a
means to a given end. To act freely is to choose the end itself, for its own
sake.
• This is central to Kant's notion of freedom. For Kant, acting freely
(autonomously) and acting morally are one and the same thing.
• The capacity to act autonomously in this manner gives humans that
special dignity that things and animals do not have. Respecting this
dignity requires us to treat others not as means to an end, but as ends in
themselves.
• To arrive at a proper understanding of Kant's notion of moral law and the
connection between morality, freedom and reason, let's examine these
contrasts:
Kant's Morality and
Freedom
1. Duty vs. Inclination (morality) — Only the motive of duty, acting
according to the law I give myself confers moral worth to an action. Any
other motive, while possibly commendable, cannot give an action moral
worth.
2. Autonomy vs. Heteronomy (freedom) - I am only free when my will is
determined autonomously, governed by the law I give myself. Being part
of nature, I am not exempt from its laws and I'm inclined or compelled to
act according to those laws. My capacity for reason opens another
possibility, that of acting according to laws other than the laws of nature:
the laws I give myself. This reason, "pure practical reason", legislates a
priori - regardless of all empirical ends.
3. Categorical vs. Hypothetical Imperatives (reason) — Kant
acknowledges two ways in which reason can command the will, two
imperatives. Hypothetical Imperative uses instrumental reason: If I want
X, I must do Y. (If I want to stay out of jail, I must be a good citizen and
not rob banks). Hypothetical imperative is always conditional.
What is Categorical
Imperative?
This question can be answered from the idea of a law that binds us as rational
beings regardless of any particular ends.
1. Act only on that maxim whereby you can at the same time will that it
should become a universal law. "Maxim" is a rule, a principle that gives
reason to action. This is a "universalizing test" that checks whether my action
puts my interests and circumstances ahead of everyone else's. My action will
fail the test if it results in a contradiction.
Example: I want a loan, but I know I won't have money to repay it. I'm
considering making a promise I know I can't keep. Can I make this a
universal law, the law that says "every time one needs a loan and has no
money to repay it, one should make a false promise"? Imagine everyone then
acting according to this maxim. We quickly realize that this would result in
negating the whole institution of promise-keeping. We arrive at a
contradiction.
What is Categorical
Imperative?
2. "Act in such a way that you always treat humanity, whether in your own
person or in the person of any other, never simply as a means, but always at
the same time as an end."