Art and Beauty
Art and Beauty
Art and Beauty
Gordon Graham
INTRODUCTION
• To have reached this point is not necessarily to have put the concept
of pleasure behind us, because some philosophers have thought that
what is special about art is a distinctive kind of pleasure –
‘aesthetic pleasure’.
• The Polish philosopher Roman Ingarden, for instance, urges us to
recognize that aesthetic pleasures ‘have a special character of their
own and exist in a different manner from the pleasures deriving from
a good meal or fresh air or a good bath’ (Ingarden 1972: 43).
• What could this pleasure be? One obvious
answer is – the pleasure that accompanies
beauty.
• Colour words are like this.
• Whereas we can apply colour words like red
and green without committing ourselves to a
favourable estimation of the things we apply
them to, we automatically praise something
when we call it beautiful, and criticize it when
we describe it as ugly.
• What is the connection between a purely
descriptive term like ‘red’ or ‘green’ and the
evaluative term ‘beautiful’?
• There are two possibilities that philosophers have discussed at great
length. The first is that the connection is purely subjective.
• The term ‘beautiful’ says something about the person who uses it. This is
the view embodied in the familiar saying that “Beauty lies in the eye of
the beholder,” which is where Hume started his argument
• two principal objections to such a view:
1. If saying ‘This is a beautiful red apple’ means ‘I
like/love/value/prefer this red apple’, why don’t I just say that? Why
cast my opinion in such a misleadingly objective form, as though it
were about the apple, when in fact it is about me, and my feelings
towards it?
2. If judgments of beauty are purely subjective, why does anyone
bother to argue about them?
KANT ON BEAUTY
• Between subjectivist and objectivist accounts
of beauty there is a stand-off.
• Some aspects of the way we talk and act
support a subjectivist interpretation, and
others support an objectivist interpretation.
• How then are we to judge between them?
• This was the motivation behind most of
Kant’s philosophy—to resolve certain
fundamental antinomies about art.
But Kant came to the view that the aesthetic is a special kind of pleasure precisely
because it in some sense transcends mere individual preference.
Aesthetic pleasure, or pleasure in the beautiful, is something we can expect others to
experience at the same time as ourselves.
It means that pleasure in the beautiful is a pleasure it is proper to commend to
others.
Kant’s Critique:
1. The Critique of Pure Reason, is concerned with how
human minds can have knowledge of the world outside
them, how science is possible if you like.
2. Critique of Practical Reason, is an attempt to
discern the principles that make action rational
and morality possible.
3. The Critique of Judgement accounts for the aesthetic
by locating it in relation to these other two.
http://www.niagarafallsstatepark.com/img/bg_hero_ArialView_1.png
Caernarfon Castle, Wales
http://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/8/88/Caernafon_Kings_Gate.jpg
1969 Liberace Show plaing Tchaikovsky
http://www.hurvitz.org/Photos/Switzerland/Schaffhausen/Schaffhausen-20020628-093908.JPG
• So too, when we stand beneath the
raging cataract, we set aside any
question of how we are to
negotiate a crossing or harness its
power for the purpose of
generating electricity.
• But more importantly from the
point of view of appreciating its
sublimity, we also detach ourselves
from it emotionally.
We apprehend its fearfulness,
certainly, but without actually
feeling the sort of fear that would
make us run away; we savour its
power without any anxiety that we
might be swept away.
• It is the sort of apprehension brilliantly expressed in
William Blake’s famous poem:
http://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/6/6a/Mona_Lisa.jpg
In this way Gadamer forges a plausible connection between art and the
aesthetic.
Q: what special value attaches to art above natural beauty?
A: Gadamer’s answer is that the deliberate creations of the artist provide
‘the experiences that best fulfill the ideal of “free” and “disinterested”
delight’ (Gadamer 1986: 20). What is the mark of ‘best’ here? We must
look, he thinks, at ‘the anthropological basis of our experience of art’, the
way that art connects with our fundamental nature.
This connection, it turns out, is to be found in
play.
By nature children engage in those activities
essential to physical survival . But they also play.
In thinking about play, we usually contrast it with
work and for this reason generally accept that
play can be characterized as activity without
purpose. But, as Gadamer points out, it is a deep
http://generalhowitzer.hubpages.com/hub/Filipino-Kids-Play-Plaything-and-Playground#slide2346708
mistake to suppose on the strength of this
characterization that play is trivial activity and
work is serious. This is a different contrast.
Play is not ‘mere diversion’ because activity
without a purpose need not be pointless.
Viewed extrinsically – from the outside – play amounts to nothing
of any consequence and has no value. This is the sense in which
the game is purposeless.
But viewed intrinsically, that is within the terms of the game itself,
the ball crossing the line is an achievement, namely a goal.
Within the game of soccer scoring
goals is what lends focus and
point to the rules of play and calls
for the skill that may be exhibited in
it.
Play can be serious, not in the sense
that it is professionalized, but in the
sense that it demands, solely for its
own purposes, the best
temperaments and the finest skills of
which human beings are capable.
Now Gadamer thinks that art is a kind of play, in which together artist
and audience join.
What is distinctive about great art is the challenge it presents to the
viewer to discern a meaning within it.
This is not a meaning that can be conceptualized or explicated in
language (to this extent Gadamer follows Kant closely) but is rather
symbolic. The challenge is to realize fully in our own imaginations
the constructs of the artist’s imagination and these constructs are
symbolic – the picture of happiness, for example, rather than a
photographic record of a happy occasion.
The artist’s task is to engage the audience in a creative free play of
images whereby symbolic representation is realized
• the symbolic IS central to art
• Gadamer :the realization of symbol is a communal activity . It requires
cooperative activity, and this activity – of play – is something in which all and any may
engage. (This is Gadamer’s interpretation of Kant’s sensus communis.)
But why should we value this special kind of play? His explanation is novel and
interesting.
We discover in art the same kind of universality we discover in festivals, and the important
thing about festivals, according to Gadamer, is that they punctuate the flow of time.
One familiar suggestion is that art communicates emotion, and this is the idea we
examine next.