Engineering Ethics: Lecture by Md. Raihan Goni
Engineering Ethics: Lecture by Md. Raihan Goni
Engineering Ethics: Lecture by Md. Raihan Goni
Lecture by
Md. Raihan Goni
Kantian theory
• According to deontology (also known as duty ethics), an action is morally right
if it is in agreement with a moral rule (law, norm, or principle) that is
applicable in itself, independent of the consequences of that action. The most
well-known system of deontology has been developed by Immanuel Kant.
• A core notion in Kantian ethics is autonomy. In Kant’s opinion man himself
should be able to determine what is morally correct through reasoning. This
should be possible independent of external norms, such as religious norms. The
idea behind is that we should place a moral norm upon ourselves and should
obey this norm out of a sense of duty – out of respect for the moral norm. It is
only then that we are acting with good will. Since a moral norm has validity
independent of time and place, it means that a moral norm is unconditionally
applicable (or categorically applicable) to everyone in all circumstances in
Kant’s view.
• Often a norm follows the form of 'thou shalt…', such as 'thou shalt not
kill', or 'thou shalt not lie'. In contrast to a categorical norm, a
hypothetical (conditional) norm only applies under certain
circumstances. A hypothetical norm usually has the following shape:
‘if you wish to achieve this goal, then you will have to act in this
way’. An example of such a norm is 'if you do not wish to betray your
friend, then you may lie', in which the rule of behavior ('you may lie')
is not unconditional but can only be applied under certain conditions
('you do not wish to betray your friend').
• According to Kant there is one universal principle from which all moral
norms can be derived, which makes his ethics a monistic duty ethics. This
principle, which is the foundation of all moral judgments in Kant’s view,
is referred to as the categorical imperative. An imperative is a prescribed
action or an obligatory rule. By arguing reasonably, any rational person
should be capable of judging whether an optional action is morally right.
The categorical imperative was formulated by Kant in different ways.
• The first formulation of the categorical imperative, the universality
principle, is as follows: "Act only on that maxim which you can at the
same time will that it should become a universal law." A maxim is a
practical principle or proposition that prescribes some action. Kant states
that the maxim should be unconditionally good, and should be able to
serve as a general law for everyone without this giving rise to
contradiction.
• Kant gives a number of examples on how to reach such a
contradiction. His most well-known example is the example of false
promises: "Another finds himself forced by necessity to borrow
money. He knows that he will not be able to repay it, but sees also
that nothing will be lent to him unless he promises firmly to repay it
in a definite time. He desires to make this promise, but he has still so
much conscience as to ask himself: 'Is it not unlawful and inconsistent
with duty to get out of a difficulty in this way?' Suppose however that
he resolves to do so: then the maxim of his action would be expressed
thus: 'When I think myself in want of money, I will borrow money and
promise to repay it, although I know that I never can do so.'
• Now this principle of self-love or of one's own advantage may perhaps
be consistent with my whole future welfare; but the question now is,
'Is it right?' I change then the suggestion of self-love into a universal
law, and state the question thus: 'How would it be if my maxim were
a universal law?' Then I see at once that it could never hold as a
universal law of nature, but would necessarily contradict itself. For
supposing it to be a universal law that everyone in difficulty should be
able to promise whatever he pleases, with the purpose of not keeping
his promise, the promise itself would become impossible, as well as
what it is supposed to accomplish, since no one would consider that
anything was promised to him, but would ridicule all such statements
as vain pretenses." (Kant 1785)
• The second formulation of the categorical imperative, the reciprocity
principle, is as follows: "Act as to treat humanity, whether in your own person
or in that of any other, in every case as an end, never as means only."
Humanity in this version of the imperative is presented as equivalent to
‘reason’ or ‘rationality’, for humans differ from things without reason (objects
and animals) because humans can think. This imperative state that each
human must have respect for the rationality of another and that we must not
misguide the rationality of another.
• Applied to the example of false promises, Kant explains this reciprocity
principle as follows: "He who is thinking of making a lying promise to others
will see at once that he would be using another man merely as a mean,
without the latter containing at the same time the end in himself. For he
whom I propose by such a promise to use for my own purposes cannot possibly
assent to my mode of acting towards him and, therefore, cannot himself
contain the end of this action." (Kant 1785)
• Note that to treat someone as an end does not simply mean doing
what he or she wants. If a consumer argues about the purchase price
of a car, and the salesman does not want to bargain about the price,
this does not mean that the salesman treats the consumer not as an
end. If the salesman informs the consumer about the price of the car
and the condition of the car, the salesman treats the consumer as an
end.
• Two main criticism of Kant's theory are that it ignores conflicts between norms and that
it is too rigid. To cope with the first problem, William David Ross developed a pluralistic
theory of moral obligations. Ross (1930) states that good is often situated on two levels:
what seems to be good at first and that which is good once we take everything into
consideration. The norms of the first level are called prima facie norms and those of
the second level are called self-evident norms ('duties sans phrase'). Usually, the prima
facie norms are our self-evident norms, but this is not necessarily the case. An example
can illustrate this. Say you promise your students that you will check their work by the
end of next week. Later on, a good friend of yours gets into trouble and needs aid. The
fact that you have promised to check the work does not disappear. Both norms are
prima facie norms, but upon closer inspection only the norm ‘you must help your friend’
is a self-evident norm while the one ('you must keep your promise') is not.
• The second criticism is that in Kant's theory there is no such thing as bending a rule.
Kant does not allow for any exceptions in his theory. In practice, we can easily imagine
that sometimes lying could be morally acceptable (for instance, to save someone's life).
Virtue ethics
• Utilitarianism and Kantian theory both are theories about criteria concerning
action. Rather than taking action as point of departure for moral judgment,
virtue ethics focuses on the nature of the acting person. This theory indicates
which good or desirable characteristics people should have or develop and how
people can achieve this. Virtue ethics is not exclusively aimed at reason, as
the previous two theories were, but is more a mixture of ethics and psychology
with an emphasis on developing character traits. Virtue ethics is based on a
notion of humankind in which people's characters can be shaped by proper
nurture and education, and by following good examples. The central theme is
the development of persons into morally good and responsible individuals so
that they can lead good lives. To this purpose, developing good character
traits (virtues), both intellectual and personal character traits, is essential.
They not only indicate how to lead a good life but also what a good life is.
• Virtue ethics stems from a long tradition and was already popular in ancient
Greece with philosophers like Socrates, Plato and Aristotle. Aristotle was the
first to define virtue ethics as a field of inquiry in itself. According to Aristotle,
the final goal of human action is to strive for the highest good: eudaimonia.
This can be translated as 'the good life' (or as 'welfare' or 'happiness'). This
does not refer to a happy circumstance that brings pleasure (the goal of
classical utilitarians), but a state of being a good person. It means leading a
life as humans are meant to lead it; one should excel in the things that are
part of being human. The good life is an active life in agreement with the
virtues necessary to realize one’s uniquely human potential.
• Each moral virtue holds a position of equilibrium according to Aristotle. A
moral virtue is the middle course between two extremes of evil; courage is
balanced between cowardice and recklessness for example, generosity
between stinginess and being a spendthrift, and pride between subservience
and arrogance.
• People must seek a middle course, but this is not a simple matter. Aristotle
believed that people know what they want instinctively, but not what they
should do. Moreover, the middle course depends on the circumstances in a
given situation. In other words, what is good in one case is not necessarily
so in another. Unlike Plato (and, later, Kant), Aristotle argues that the good
is sometimes ambiguous. However, people are not powerless in finding the
middle course. The intellectual virtue practical wisdom is aimed at making
the right choices for action concerning what is good and useful for a
successful life. According to Aristotle, a wise man can see what he has to do
in the specific and often complex circumstances of life. Practical wisdom
implies a capacity for moral judgment, which is the middle course. Moral
virtues and the intellectual virtue go hand in hand.
• Main criticisms of virtue ethics include that it is does not tell you how to act
and that virtues are not unconditionally good.