0% found this document useful (0 votes)
206 views93 pages

Discrete Structures and Graph Theory: Unit-1

The document discusses the topics covered in the course "Discrete Structures and Graph Theory". The 6 units cover propositional logic, first order logic, relations and algebraic structures, elementary combinatorics, recurrence relations, and graph theory. Two textbooks are listed. Mathematical logic concepts like statements, connectives, truth tables, tautologies, and logical equivalences are defined and examples are provided.
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PPT, PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
206 views93 pages

Discrete Structures and Graph Theory: Unit-1

The document discusses the topics covered in the course "Discrete Structures and Graph Theory". The 6 units cover propositional logic, first order logic, relations and algebraic structures, elementary combinatorics, recurrence relations, and graph theory. Two textbooks are listed. Mathematical logic concepts like statements, connectives, truth tables, tautologies, and logical equivalences are defined and examples are provided.
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PPT, PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 93

Discrete Structures and Graph Theory

 Unit-1: Propositional logic


 Unit-2: First order Logic
 Unit-3: Relations and Algebraic Structures
 Unit-4: Elementary Combinatorics
 Unit-5: Recurrence relations
 Unit-6: Graph theory
Text Books:
Discrete Mathematical Structures With Applications to Computer Science
Jean Paul Tremblay, Rampurkar Manohar
Discrete Mathematics for Computer Scientists and Mathematicians
Joe L. Mott, Abraham Kandel, Théodore P. Baker
Mathematical logic
 Statement (Proposition) : A declarative sentence to which it is
meaningful to assign one and only one of the truth values “true” or
“false”. We call such sentences Propositions (Statements).
 Ex. London is a city. Ex. 2+3 = 4
The following sentences are not statements.
 What is your name?
 Close the door
For definiteness let us list our assumptions about propositions.
 The law of excluded middle: For every proposition p,
either p is true or p is false.
 The law of contradiction: For every proposition p, it is not the case that
p is both true and false.
Atomic and Compound statements
 Atomic statement : A statement which can not be divided further, is
called atomic statement (Simple statement or primary statement).
These statements are denoted by p,q,r,s,……
Ex. Milk is white Ex. 2+3 = 5
 Compound Statement : Two or more simple statements can be
combined to form a new statement. These new statements are called
Compound statements or Molecular Statements or Propositional
function or Statement formulas.
Ex. It is raining today and there are 20 tables in this room.
 Compound statements can be formed from atomic statements through
the use of following sentential connectives.
not, and , or , if …then and if and only if .
Connectives
 Negation: If p is a statement, then the negation of p, written as ~p
and read as “ not p ” is a statement.
Ex. p : London is a city.
~p : London is not a city.
 The truth table for not p is given below.

p ~p
T F
F T
Conjunction (and) pq
 If p and q are two propositions, then the conjunction of p and q is the
statement p  q which is read as “ p and q ”.
 The statement p  q has the truth value T whenever both p and q have
truth value T; otherwise it has the truth value false.

p q pq
F F F
F T F
T F F
T T T

Conjunctive syllogism: If p  q is false and p is true, then q is false.


Disjunction ( Or ) pq
 If p and q are two propositions, then the disjunction of p and q is the
statement p  q which is read as “ p or q”.
 The statement pq has the truth value F only when both p and q have
truth value F; otherwise it has the truth value T.

p q pq
F F F
F T T
T F T
T T T
Disjunctive syllogism: If p  q is true and p is false, then q is true.
Implication (Conditional) pq
 If p and q are two propositions, then the statement pq which is read
as “ if p, then q ” or “ p implies q “.
 The statement pq has truth value F only when p is true and q is
false; otherwise it has a truth value T.
p q pq
F F T
F T T
T F F
T T T
 A false antecedent p implies any proposition q.
 A true consequent q is implied by any proposition q
Biconditional (if and only if) pq
 Biconditional : If p and q are two propositions, then the statement
pq, which is read as “p if and only if q” is called a biconditional
statement.
 The statement pq has the truth value T whenever both p and q have
identical truth values.

p q pq
F F T
F T F
T F F
T T T
More on Implication
 The opposite of pq is p  q
 The converse of pq is qp
 The contra positive of pq is q  p
 Note : pq is logically equivalent to q  p
i.e., pq  q  p
or pq  q  p
* Ex. p: Today is Sunday
q: Today is Holiday
p  q : If today is Sunday, then today is Holiday
q  p : If today is not Holiday, then today is not Sunday
 If pq is true then it’s converse q  p need not be true.
 If pq is true then it’s opposite p  q need not be true.
Well formed formulas
 A well formed formula can be generated by the following rules.
1. A statement variable standing alone is a well formed formula.
2. If P is a well formed formula, then ~P is a well formed formula.
3. If P and Q are well formed formulas, then (PQ) , (PQ) , (PQ)
and (PQ) are well formed formulas.
4. A string of symbols containing the statement variables,connectives
and parenthesis is a well formed formula, iff it can be obtained by
finitely many applications of the rules 1,2 and 3.
 Ex. (PQ) , (PQ) , (P (PQ) ) , (P (Q R)) and
(PQ) (PQ) are well formed formulas.
 Ex. PQ , (PQ )Q ) and (P Q )  (Q) are not well formed
formulas.
Truth tables
 Our basic concern is to determine the truth value of a statement
formula for each possible combination of the truth values of the
component statements.
 A table showing all such truth values is called the truth table of the
formula.
 Ex.1 Construct truth table for the statement formula P  Q

P Q Q P  Q
F F T T
F T F F
T F T T
T T F T
Truth tables - Examples

Ex : 2 Construct the truth table for (PQ)  P

P Q PQ P (PQ)  P

F F F T T
F T T T T
T F T F T
T T T F T
Truth tables - Examples
Ex.3 Construct the truth table for (PQ)  (QP)

P Q PQ QP (PQ)  (QP)

F F T T T
F T T F F
T F F T F
T T T T T

Note:
(PQ)  {(PQ)  (QP)}
Tautology and Contradiction
 Tautology : A propositional function (Statement formula) whose value
is true for all possible values of the propositional variables is called a
Tautology ( A Universally valid formula or a logical truth).
Ex: P  P is a tautology.
Ex. ( P  P )  Q is a tautology.
 Contradiction (Absurdity): A propositional function whose truth value
is always false is called a Contradiction
Ex. P  P is a Contradiction .
Ex. ( P  P )  Q is a Contradiction
 Contingency: A propositional function that is neither a tautology nor a
contradiction is called a Contingency.
Ex. P  Q , P  Q , P Q, ….
Logical Equivalence & Tautological Implication
 Two propositional functions P and Q are logically equivalent, if they
have same truth tables. Then we write
P  Q or P  Q
Ex: (P )  P
Ex: ( P  Q )  ( P  Q ).
Note : The symbol  is not a connective
 A Statement P is said to tautologically imply a Statement Q if and only
if PQ is a tautology.We shall denote this as P  Q.
 Here, P and Q are related to the extent that, Whenever P has the truth
value T then so does Q.
 Every logical implication is an implication, but all implications are not
logical implications.
More on Implications
 If P  Q and Q  P , then PQ.
 If PQ then PQ is a tautology.
 Ex: Show that ( P Q )  ( P  Q )

P Q PQ P PQ
F F T T T
F T T T T
T F F F F
T T T F T

 Since columns 3 and 5 are identical, The result follows


Ex.Construct truth table for [(pq) (r)]  p]
 The truth table is given below

p q r pq r (pq) (r) [(pq) (r)] p]


F F F F T T F
F F T F F F T
F T F F T T F
F T T F F F T
T F F F T T T
T F T F F F F
T T F T T T T
T T T T F T T
Ex. Show that (PQ)  (Q  P)
 Let us prove the result using truth table.

P Q PQ Q P (Q P)


F F T T T T
F T T F T T
T F F T F F
T T T F F T
Ex. Using truth tables, show that ( P  Q )  (Q)
is a tautology

 The truth table is given below.

P Q PQ ( P  Q ) Q ( P  Q )  (Q)

F F T F T T
F T T F F T
T F F T T T
T T T F F T
Equivalences
Commutative laws:
 PQQP
 PQQP
Asociative laws:
 (PQ)RP(QR)
 (PQ)RP(QR)
Distributive laws:
 P(QR)(PQ)(PR)
 P(QR)(PQ)(PR)
Demorgan’s laws:
  ( P  Q)   P   Q
  ( P  Q)   P   Q
More Equivalences
  ( P )  P (Double negation)
 P P  P
 PP  P
 PPT
 PPF
 R(PP)R
 R(PP)R
 R(PP)T
 R(PP)F
 P  Q  ( P  Q)
 ( P  Q )  (P   Q)
 P  Q  ( Q   P )
More Equivalences
• PFP
• PTT
• PFF
• PTP
• P  ( Q  R)  ( P  Q )  R
•  ( P  Q )  (P   Q)
• (P  Q )  [( P  Q)  ( Q  P )]
• ( P  Q )  [( P  Q)  ( P   Q )]
• Absorption laws
• P(PQ)P
• P(PQ)P
Ex. Without using truth tables, Show that
P  ( Q  R)  ( P  Q )  R

 Proof:
L.H.S = P  (Q  R)
 P  (Q  R) (Since A  B  ( A  B))
 P  (Q  R)
 (P  Q)  R (By associative property)
 ( P  Q )  R (By demorgan’s law)
 (PQ)R
= R.H.S
Ex. Without using truth tables, Show that
( P  Q )  P is a tautology.
Proof:
Consider, ( P  Q )  P
 ( Q  P )  P ( By commutative law )
 Q  (P  P ) ( By associative property)
 Q  T
 T
 ( P  Q )  P is a tautology.
Ex. Show that the Statement formula
( P  Q )  (PQ)  P is a tautology.
 Proof : Consider,
 {( P  Q )  (PQ)}  P (Associative law)
 {(P  Q )  (PQ)}  P ( Demorgan’s law)
  {P  (Q  Q)}  P (Distributive law)
  {P  T }  P
  {P }  P
  T
  ( P  Q )  (PQ)  P is a tautology
Ex. Show that [{( P  Q )  ( P  Q )}  R ]  R

 Proof: L.H.S = {( P  Q )  ( P  Q )}  R
  {T}R (Since P  Q  ( P  Q))
  R
 = R.H.S

 Ex. Show that {( P  Q )  ( P  Q )} is a Contradiction.


 Proof : Let P  Q = R
 Consider, {( P  Q )  ( P  Q )}
  { R  R }
  F
  { ( P  Q )  ( P  Q )} is a contradiction.
Ex. Show that (P  (Q  R))  ( Q  R )  (P  R)  R

 Proof : Consider,
 {P  (Q  R)}  ( Q  R )  (P  R)
  {(P  Q)  R}  {( Q  R )  (P  R)}, By associative law
  { (P  Q)  R}  {(Q  P )  R} , By distributive law
  {(P  Q)  R}  {(Q  P )  R} , By Demorgan’s law
  {(P  Q)  (Q  P ) } R, By distributive law
  {T } R (Since, A  A  T)
  R
Ex. S.T. ((P  Q)  (P  (Q  R)))  ( P  Q)  (P   R) is a

tautology.

 Consider,
 [(P  Q)  {P  (Q  R)}]  {(P  Q)  (P  R)}
 [(P  Q)  {P  (Q  R)}]  {(P  Q)  (P  R)}
(By De morgan’s laws)
 [(P  Q)  {P  (Q  R)}]  {(P  Q)  (P  R)}
(By De morgan’s laws)
 [(P  Q)  {P  Q) (P  R)}]  {(P  Q)  (P  R)}
(By Distributive law)
  {(P  Q)  (P  R)}  {(P  Q)  (P  R)}
(Since A  A  A)
  T ( Since A  A T)
Implications ,Arguments,Inferences
 Inference (Argument): From a set of premises (called Hypotheses) {H1,
H2, …., Hn } a conclusion C follows logically
iff H1  H2  ….  Hn  C.
• The rules of inference are criteria for determining the validity of an
argument.
• Any conclusion which is arrived at by following these rules is called a
valid conclusion, and the argument is called a valid argument.
• The following statements are equivalent.
• 1. {H1 , H2 , …. , Hn }  C is a logical implication.
• 2. ( H1  H2  ….  Hn) C is a tautology.
• 3. {H1 , H2 ,…. , Hn }  C is a valid argument.
Rules of Inference (Logical Implications)
1) Simplification rules:
 a) (P  Q)  P
(P  Q)  P is a tautology.
P logically follows from (P  Q)

 b) (P  Q)  Q
(P  Q)  Q is a tautology.
Q logically follows from (P  Q)
Contd.,
2) Addition rules:
• a) P  (P  Q)
P  (P  Q) is a tautology
(P  Q) logically follows from P

 b) Q  ( P  Q )
Q  (P  Q) is a tautology
(P  Q) logically follows from Q
Rules of Inference (contd.,)
 3) P (P  Q)
P (P  Q) is a tautology
(P  Q) logically follows from P

 4) Q  ( P  Q)
Q (P  Q) is a tautology
(P  Q) logically follows from Q
Contd.,
 5) (P  Q)  P
(P  Q)  P is a tautology (or)
P follows from (P  Q)

 6) (P  Q )  (Q)
(P  Q )  (Q) is a tautology
Q logically follows from (P  Q)
Rules of Inference (Contd.,)
7) Disjunctive syllogism
{P, P  Q}  Q

{P  ( P  Q)}  Q is a tautology.

The inference PQ


P
Q is valid
Contd.,
8) Conjunctive syllogism
{(P  Q) , P}  Q

{(P  Q)  P }  Q is a tautology.

The inference (P  Q)


P
 Q is valid
Contd.,
 8) Modus ponens (Rule of detachment)
 { P , PQ }  Q
 { P  (PQ) }  Q is a Tautology
 The argument
PQ
P
 Q is valid
Contd.,
 Ex: The following argument is valid.
A) If today is a Sunday then today is a Holiday
B) Today is Sunday
C : Hence, Today is Holiday
9) Modus tollens
 { PQ, Q }  P
 { (PQ)  Q}  (P) is a Tautology
 The argument
PQ
Q
------------
 P is valid
 Ex: The following argument is valid.
A) If today is a Sunday then today is a Holiday
B) Today is not Holiday
C : Hence, Today is not Sunday
Rule of Transitivity (Hypothetical Syllogism)
 { PQ, QR }  (PR)
 { (PQ)  (QR}  (PR) is a Tautology
 The argument
PQ
QR
------------
 PR is valid
 Ex: The following argument is valid.
A) If I Study well, then I will get distinction.
B) If I get distinction, then I will get a Good Job.
C:  If I Study well, then I will get a good job
Dilemma
 The Inference
PQ
PR
QR
------------
R is a valid Inference.

 {P  Q, PR, QR }  R is a logical implication.

 {(PQ)  (PR}  (QR) }  R is a Tautology


Constructive dilemma
 The Inference
PQ
PR
QS
------------
 R  S is a valid Inference.

 {P  Q, PR, QS }  ( R  S ) is a logical implication.

 {(PQ)  (PR}  (QS) }  (R  S) is a Tautology


Destructive Dilemma
 The Inference
PR
QS
R  S
----------------
 P  Q is a valid Inference.

 { PR, QS, R  S }  (P  Q ) is a logical implication.

 {(PR)  (QS)  (R  S )}  (P  Q) is a Tautology


Conjunction and Conjunctive Syllogism
 Conjunction
P, Q
----------
 (PQ)
 Conjunctive Syllogism:
 {(PQ), P }  Q
 {(PQ) P } Q is a tautology.
 (PQ)
P
--------
Q
Fallacies
 1. The fallacy of affirming the Consequent (or affirming the converse):
PQ
Q
_________
P Fallacy
Ex: Consider, the following argument
If today is Mahatma Gandhi’s Birth day, then today is October 2nd.
Today is October 2nd.
 Today is Mahatma Gandhi’s Birth day.
The argument is not valid
2. Fallacy of denying the antecedent
( Or Assuming the opposite)
 Consider the following
PQ
P
_________
Q Fallacy
 Ex: Consider the following argument:
H1 : If today is Sunday, then today is Holiday
H2 : Today is not Sunday
C :  Today is not Holiday
The argument is not Valid.This is the fallacy of assuming the opposite.
The non sequitur fallacy
 P,Q
---------
 R is a fallacy.
Ex: Consider the following argument:
1. India’s Capital is New Delhi
2. Milk is White
C:  Sun rises in the East.
The conclusion does not follow from the premises.
Hence, the argument is invalid.
Ex: Show that R follows logically from the premises
PQ, QR, P

 Proof: Consider the premises,


PQ -----(1)
QR -----(2)
P ------(3)
From (1) and (2), By the rule of transitivity,we have
PR --------(4)
From (3) and (4), By the rule of Modus ponens,
R follows.
 R logically follows from the given premises
Ex: Show that P follows logically from the premises
PQ, QR, R
 Proof: Consider the premises,
PQ -----(1)
QR -----(2)
R ------(3)
From (1) and (2), By the rule of transitivity,we have
PR --------(4)
From (3) and (4), By the rule of Modus tollens,
P follows.
 P logically follows from the given premises
Ex: Show that R follows logically from the premises
PQ, QR, PM, M
 Proof: Consider the premises,
P  Q -----(1)
Q  R -----(2)
P  M -----(3)
M ------(4)
From (3) and (4), By the rule of Modus tollens, we have
P --------(5)
From (1) and (5), By the rule of Disjunctive Syllogism,we have
Q --------(4)
From (2) and (4), By the rule of Modus ponens,
R follows.
Ex: Show that (R  S) follows logically from the premises
C  D, (C  D) H, H (A B), (A B)  (R  S )
 Proof: Consider the premises,
(C  D) -----(1)
(C  D)  H -----(2)
H  (A B) -----(3)
(A B)  (R  S ) ------(4)

From (2),(3) and (4), By the rule of Transitivity, we have


(C  D)  (R  S ) --------(5)

From (1) and (5), By the rule of Modus ponens,


(R  S) follows.
Ex: Show that S follows logically from the premises
P  (R S), RP, P
 Proof: Consider the premises,
P  (R S) -----(1)
R  P -----(2)
P -----(3)
From (1) and (3), By the rule of Modus ponens, we have
(R S) ------(4)
From (2), By Contra positive equivalence, we have
PR -------(5)
(3) and (5), By the rule of Modus ponens, we have
R --------(6)
From (4) and (6), By the rule of Modus ponens, S follows.
Ex: Show that W follows logically from the premises
TR, S, T  W, R  S.
 Proof: Consider the premises,
T  R ------(1)
S -----(2)
TW -----(3)
RS -----(4)
From (1), By Contra positive equivalence, we have
RT -------(5)
From, (5) and (3), By the rule of Transitivity, we have
R W --------(6)
From (4) and (2), By the rule of Disjunctive syllogism,we have
R ---------- (7)
 From(6)and (7), By the rule of Modus ponens, W follows
Ex: Show that TP follows logically from the premises
R(ST), R  W, P S, W
 Proof: Consider the premises,
R(ST) ------(1)
R  W -----(2)
P S -----(3)
W -----(4)
From (2) and (4), By the rule of Disjunctive syllogism,we have
R ---------(5)
From(1)and (5), By the rule of Modus ponens, we have
S T ---------(6)
From, (3) and (6), By the rule of Transitivity, we have
P  T ---------(7)
 ( T P ) (By Contra positive equivalence)
Conditional Proof (CP rule)
 Theorem: If {H1, H2, …., Hn } and P imply Q, then
{H1, H2, …., Hn } imply (PQ).

 Proof: From our assumption we have,


(H1 H2  ….  Hn  P)  Q
This assumption means (H1 H2  ….  Hn  P)  Q is a tautology.
Using the equivalence P (Q R)  (P  Q)  R
We can say that (H1 H2  ….  Hn)  ( PQ ) is a tautology.
Hence the theorem.
 Rule CP : If we can derive Q from P and a set of premises,then we can
derive PQ from the set of premises alone
Ex:Show that RS can be derived from the premises
p (Q S), RP, Q

 Solution: Instead of deriving RS, we shall include R as an


additional premise and show S first.
p (Q S) …..(1)
RP …..(2)
Q ……(3)
R …….(4)
From (2) and (4), By the rule of Disjunctive syllogism,we have
P ---------(5)
From(1)and (5), By the rule of Modus ponens, we have
Q S ………….(6)
From(3)and (6), By the rule of Modus ponens, S follows
 By CP rule, RS follows from the given premises.
Consistency, Inconsistency and Proof by Contradiction
 A set of formulas {H1, H2, …., Hn} is said to be consistent, if their
conjunction has truth value T for some assignment of the truth values
to the atomic variables appearing in H1, H2, …., Hn .
 A set of formulas {H1, H2, …., Hn} is said to be inconsistent, if their
conjunction implies a contradiction. that is
(H1 H2  ….  Hn )  (R  R) where R is any formula.
 Proof by Contradiction :
In order to show that,a conclusion C logically follows from the premises
H1, H2, …., Hn ,We assume that C is false and Consider C as additional
premise.
If the new set of premises is inconsistent, then our assumption is
wrong. Hence C follows.
Ex: Show that the following set of premises are inconsistent.
P Q, P R, Q  R, P
 Proof: Consider the premises,
PQ ------(1)
PR -----(2)
Q R -----(3)
P ----(4)
From (1) and (3), By the rule of transitivity, we have
P R …….(5)
From(2)and (4), By the rule of Modus ponens, R follows
From(4)and (5), By the rule of Modus ponens, R follows
But, R and R cannot be simultaneously true (Contradiction). Hence, the
given premises are inconsistent.
Ex: Show that the following set of premises are inconsistent.
R  M, R  S, M, S
 Proof: Consider the premises,
RM ------(1)
R  S ----(2)
M -----(3)
S ----------(4)
From (1) and (3), By the rule of Disjunctive Syllogism,we have
R ……….(5)
From(2)and (4), By the rule of Disjunctive Syllogism, We have
R ………..(6)
But, R and R cannot be simultaneously true (Contradiction). Hence, the
given premises are inconsistent.
Ex: Show that (PQ) follows from (P  Q)
 Solution: Let us introduce (PQ) as an additional premise and show
that this leads to contradiction.
(PQ) ….(1)
Which is equivalent to
(PQ) ….(2)
From (2), P follows
Given that, (P  Q) …..(3)
From (3), P follows
But, P and P cannot be simultaneously true (Contradiction).
 Our assumption is false.
Hence (PQ) follows from (P  Q)
Ex: Show that P follows from the premises PQ, (P  Q)
 Solution: Let us introduce P as an additional premise and show that
this leads to contradiction.
P ….(1)
PQ …..(2)
(PQ) ….(3)
From (1) and (2), By the rule of Moden ponens, we have
Q …….(4)
From (1) and (4), We have
( PQ) …….(5)
But, (3) and (5) cannot be simultaneously true (Contradiction).
 Our assumption is false.
Hence, P follows from the premises PQ, (P  Q)
Ex: Verify that the following argument is valid by using the rules of inference
(Here, H1 , H2 , …. are premises and C is conclusion) :
H1 : If Joe is a Mathematician, then he is ambitious.
H2 : If Joe is an early riser, then he does not like oat meal.
H3 : If Joe is ambitious, then he is an early riser
C : Hence, if Joe is a Mathematician, then he does not like oat meal.
 Solution: Let us make the following representations
p : Joe is a Mathematician.
q : Joe is ambitious
r : Joe is an early riser
s : Joe likes oat meal
The symbolic form of the given argument is
Contd.,
H1 : pq ….(1)
H2 : rs ….(2)
H3 : qr …..(3)
From (1) and (3), By the rule of transitivity, we have
pr ……(4)
From (4) and (2), By the rule of transitivity, we have
p  s ……(5)
i.e., if Joe is a Mathematician, then he does not like oat meal.
 The conclusion logically follows from the premises.
Hence, the argument is valid
Ex: Verify that the following argument is valid by using the rules of inference
(Here, H1 , H2 , …. are premises and C is conclusion) :
H1 : If Cliffton does not live in France, then he does not
speak French.
H2 : Cliffton does not drive a Datsun.
H3 : If Cliffton lives in France, then he rides a Bicycle.
H4 : Either Cliffton speaks French,or he drives a Datsun.
C : Hence, Cliffton drives a bicycle.
 Solution: Let us make the following representations
p : Cliffton lives in France.
q : Cliffton speaks French.
r : Cliffton drives a Datsun.
s : Cliffton drives a Bicycle.
The symbolic form of the given argument is
Contd.,
 H1 : p q …..(1)
H2 : r …..(2)
H3 : p  s …..(3)
H4 : q  r …….(4)
From (2) and (4), By the rule of Disjunctive Syllogism,we have
q ……..(5)
(1)  q  p …….(6)
From (5) and (6), By the rule of Modus ponens, we have
P ……(7)
From (3) and (7), By the rule of Modus ponens, s follows
 The conclusion logically follows from the premises.
Hence, the argument is valid
Ex:Using Symbolic logic, Show that the following premises are
inconsistent
1. If Jack misses many classes through illness,then he fails high school.
2. If Jack fails high school, then he is uneducated.
3. If Jack reads a lot of books, then he is not uneducated.
4. Jack misses many classes through illness and reads a lot of books.
 Solution: Let us make the following representations
p : Jack misses many classes through illness
q : Jack fails high school
r : Jack is uneducated
s : Jack reads a lot of books
Now, the given premises can be represented as
Contd.,
p  q …..(1) q  r …..(2)
s  r …..(3) p  s …..(4)
From (1) and (2), By transitivity, p r …..(5)
From(3), By Contra positive equivalence, r  s ….. (6)
From (5) and (6), By transitivity, we have
p s …..(7)
From(4), we have
p …..(8)
From (7) and (8), By the rule of modus ponens, s follows
From (4), s follows
But, s and s cannot be simultaneously true (Contradiction).
Hence, the given premises are inconsistent
Ex:Using Symbolic logic,prove the following argument

If A works hard, then either B or C will enjoy themselves.


If B enjoys himself, then A will not work hard.
If D enjoys himself, then C will not enjoy himself.
Therefore, If A works hard, then D will not enjoy himself .
 Solution: Let us use the following representations.
A : A works hard.
B : B will enjoy himself.
C : C will enjoy himself.
D : D will enjoy himself.
Now, we have to show that, A  D follows from
A (B  C) , B  A and D  C
Contd.,
A (B  C) ….(1) B  A ….(2)
D  C ….(3) A …. (4) ( Additional premise)
From, (1) and (4), By modus ponens, We have
(B  C) ……(5)
(2)  A  B …. (6)
From, (4) and (6), By modus ponens, B ….(7) follows.
From (5) and (7), By the rule of Disjunctive Syllogism, we have
C ….(8)
(3)  C D …. (9)
From (8) and (9), By modus ponens, D follows
Hence, By CP rule, A  D follows
Properties of operations on implication
(P  Q)  ((~P)  Q)
(P  Q)  (~Q  ~P)
(P  Q)  ((P  Q)  (Q  P))
~(P  Q)  (P  ~Q)
~(P  Q)  ((P  ~Q)  (Q  ~P))
P Q  (P  Q)  (~P  ~Q)
Normal forms
 Elementary product:A product of the variables and their negations in a
formula is called an Elementary product.
Ex: P, PQ, PQ, PQ R
 Elementary Sum: A Sum of the variables and their negations in a
formula is called an Elementary Sum.
Ex: P, P  Q, P  Q, P Q R
 Disjunctive normal form: A formula which is equivalent to a given
formula and which consists of a sum of elementary products is called a
disjunctive normal form.
 Ex: (P )  ( PQ )  (PQ).
 Ex: ( PQ )  (PQ)  (PQ R ).
Normal forms (contd.,)
 Conjunctive normal form: A formula which is equivalent to a given
formula and which consists of a product of elementary sums is called a
conjunctive normal form.
Ex: (P )  ( P  Q ) (P  Q).
Ex: ( P  Q )  (P  Q) (P  Q  R ).
Disjunctive Normal Forms
A formula equivalent to a given formula and consists of a sum of
elementary products of the given formula.

Examples
1. Obtain Disjunctive Normal Form of P  (P  Q).
P  (P  Q)  P  (~P  Q)
 (P  ~P)  (P  Q)
2.Obtain Disjunctive Normal Form of ~(P  Q)  (P  Q).
~(P  Q)  (P  Q)
 (~(P  Q)  (P  Q))  ((P  Q)  ~(P  Q))
since [R  S  (R  S)  (~R  ~S)]
~(P  Q)  (P  Q)
 (~P  ~Q  P  Q)  ((P  Q)  (~P  ~Q)

 (~P  ~Q  P  Q)  ((P  Q)  (~P  ~Q))

 (~P  ~Q  P  Q)  ((P  Q)  ~P)


 ((P  Q)  ~Q)

 (~P  ~Q  P  Q)  (P  ~P)  (Q  ~P)


 (P  ~Q)  (Q  ~Q)
Conjunctive Normal Forms
A formula equivalent to a given formula and consists of a product of
elementary sums of the given formula.

Examples
1. Obtain Conjunctive Normal Form of P  (P  Q).
P  (P  Q)  P  (~P  Q)
2.Obtain Conjunctive Normal Form of ~(P  Q)  (P  Q).
~(P  Q)  (P  Q)
 (~(P  Q)  (P  Q))  ((P  Q)  ~(P  Q))
since [R  S  (R  S)  (S  R)]

~(P  Q)  (P  Q)
 ((P  Q)  (P  Q))  (~(P  Q)  (~P  ~Q)

 ((P  Q  P)  (P  Q  Q))
 ((~P  ~Q)  (~P  ~Q)

 (P  Q  P)  (P  Q  Q)
 (~P  ~Q  ~P)  (~P  ~Q  ~Q)
3.Obtain Conjunctive Normal Form of Q  (P  ~Q)  (~P  ~Q).
Q  (P  ~Q)  (~P  ~Q)
 Q  ((P  ~P)  ~Q)

 (Q  (P  ~P))  (Q  ~Q)

 (Q  P  ~P)  (Q  ~Q)
1. P {(P Q) ~(~Q  ~ P))
2. ~{P(QR)}
3. (~P  ~ Q) (P  ~ Q)
4. (P (Q R))(~P  (~Q  ~ R))
5. (~P  ~ Q) (P  ~ Q) (CNF)
Principal Disjunctive Normal Forms
 Let P and Q be two statement variables.
 Let us construct all possible formulas which consists of conjunctions of
P or its negation and conjunctions of Q or its negation.
 None of the formulas should contain both a variable and its negation.
Ex: either P  Q or Q  P is included but not both.
 For two variables P and Q , there are 22 such formulas given by
P  Q, P  ~ Q , ~ P  Q and ~ P  ~ Q
 these formulas are called minterms.
 From the truth tables of these minterms, it is clear that no two
minterms are equivalent
 Each minterm has the truth value T for exactly one combination of the
truth values of the variables P and Q.
 For a given formula , an equivalent formula consisting of disjunction of
minterms only is known as its principal disjunctive normal form.
 Also called sum-of –products canonical form.
 Min terms: Let P and Q are two statement variables. Let us construct
all possible formulas which consist of conjunctions of P or its negation
and conjunctions of Q or its negation.
For two variables P and Q, there are 22 such formulas given by
PQ, PQ, PQ, PQ
These formulas are called ‘min terms’.
 For three variables P,Q and R, there are 23 such formulas given by
PQ R, PQ R, PQ R, PQ R,
PQ R, PQ R, PQ R, PQ R
These min terms are denoted by m0, m1 , …, m7 respectively.

 In general, there are 2n min terms for n variables.


Ex. Obtain the Principal Disjunctive normal forms of the following
PQ , P  Q, (PQ)

 Solution:
P Q PQ PQ PQ (PQ)
F F T F F T
F T T T F T
T F F T F T
T T T T T F
 PQ  (PQ)  (PQ)  (PQ)
 P  Q  (PQ)  (PQ)  (PQ)
 (PQ)  (PQ)  (PQ)  (PQ)
Ex. Obtain the Principal Disjunctive normal form of the following
P  {(PQ)  (P  Q)}

 Given formula is, [ P  {(PQ)  (P  Q)} ] = A (say)


The truth table for A is given below.

P Q PQ P  Q {(PQ)  A
(P  Q)}
F F T F F T
F T T F F T
T F F F F F
T T T T T T
 A  (PQ)  (PQ)  (PQ)
 Which is the PDNF for A .
Ex. Obtain the Principal Disjunctive normal form of the following
(P  Q)  (Q  R)  (P  R )

 Solution: Consider, (P  Q)  (Q  R)  (P  R )

  {(P  Q)  (R  R)} 
{(P  P)  (Q  R) } 
{(P  R )  (Q  Q)}

(PQ R)  (PQ R)  (PQ R) (PQ R)

Which is the PDNF for the given formula.


Ex. Obtain the Principal Disjunctive normal form of the following
(P  Q)  (P  R )
= A (say)

P Q R P  Q P (P  R) A
F F F T T F F
F F T T T T T
F T F F T F F
F T T F T T F
T F F F F T F
T F T F F T F
T T F T F T T
T T T T F T T
 A  (PQ R)  (PQ R)  (PQ R) =  (m1, m6, m7)
Principal Conjunctive normal forms (Product of
Sums canonical forms)
 Max terms: For a given number of variables, the max term consists of
disjunctions in which each variable or its negation, but not both,
appears only once.
For two variables P and Q, there are 22 such formulas given by
(P  Q), (P  Q), (P  Q), (P  Q).
These formulas are called ‘max terms’.
 For three variables P,Q and R, there are 23 such formulas given by
PQR, P  Q  R, P  Q  R, P  Q  R,
P  Q  R, P  Q  R, P  Q  R, P  Q  R
These max terms are denoted by M0, M1 , …, M7 respectively.
 In general, there are 2n Max terms for n variables.
PCNF (Contd.,)
 Mi =  mi
 M0 =  m0
= (PQ R) = (P  Q  R)
 M1 =  m1
= (PQ R) = (P  Q   R)
 M2 =  m2
= (PQ R) = (P   Q  R)
 Principal Conjunctive normal form (Product of Sums canonical
form) : For a given formula, an equivalent formula consisting of
conjunctions of max terms only is known as Principal Conjunctive
normal form.
Principal Conjunctive Normal Forms
 Let us construct all possible formulas which consists of conjunctions of
P or its negation and conjunctions of Q or its negation.
 None of the formulas should contain both a variable and its negation.
Ex: either P  Q or Q  P is included but not both.
 For two variables P and Q , there are 22 such formulas given by
P  Q, P  ~ Q , ~ P  Q and ~ P  ~ Q
 these formulas are called maxterms.
 For a given formula , an equivalent formula consisting of conjunctions
of maxterms only is known as its principal conjunctive normal form.
 Also called products-of-sums canonical form.
Ex. Obtain the Principal Conjunctive normal forms of the following
PQ , P  Q, (PQ)

P Q PQ PQ PQ (PQ)

F F T F T F
F T T F F T
T F F F F T
T T T T T F

 The PCNF’s are


 PQ  (P  Q)
 P  Q  (P  Q)  (P  Q)  (P  Q)
 (PQ)  (P  Q)  (P  Q)
EX. Obtain the Principal Conjunctive normal form of the formula given by (P
 R)  (Q  P)
 Solution: (P  R)  (Q  P)
 (P  R)  {(PQ)  (QP)}
 (P  R)  (P  Q)  (Q  P)
 { (P  R)  (Q  Q) } 
{ (P  Q)  (R  R) } 
{ (Q  P)  (R  R) }
 (P  Q  R)  (P  Q  R)  (P  Q  R) 
( P  Q  R)  (P  Q  R)
= (0,2,3,4,5)
Which is the required PCNF.
Max terms and Min terms
 *
P Q R Min terms mi Max terms Mi

F F F m0 : PQ R M0 : PQR


F F T m1 : PQ R M1 : P  Q  R
F T F m2 : PQ R M2 : P  Q  R
F T T m3 : PQ R M3 : P  Q  R
T F F m4 : PQ R M4 : P  Q  R
T F T m5 : PQ R M5 : P  Q  R
T T F m6 : PQ R M6 : P  Q  R
T T T m7 : PQ R M7 : P  Q  R
Ex. Obtain the Principal Conjunctive normal form and Principal disjunctive
normal form of A, where A = (P  Q) (P  R )
P Q R P  Q P P  R A
F F F F T F F
F F T F T T T
F T F F T F F
F T T F T T T
T F F F F F F
T F T F F F F
T T F T F F T
T T T T F F T
The PCNF of A = (0,2,4,5)
A  (P  Q  R)  (P  Q  R)  (P  Q  R) (P  Q  R)
Contd.,
The PDNF of A = (1,3,6,7)
A  (PQ R)  (PQ R)  (PQ R)  (PQ R)

You might also like