Breaking The Definitional Circle: Four Theories of Meaning
Breaking The Definitional Circle: Four Theories of Meaning
DEFINITIONAL CIRCLE
Four Theories of Meaning
Explanations of meaning in terms of
meanings are circular ………….
Def.: Expressions actually mean the concept or idea associated with them. Any
particular sound image is psychologically associated with a particular concept.
[chair]→{chair}(signifier vs signified)
Merits: The classification of objects in the world, for example, need not be natural or
universal, but only conceptual. So it solves the concrete and abstract ideas.
Demerits: Yet still not the functional word classes in language such as and or but.
Meaning as Ideas
Initially developed by John Locke (1632-1704)
Current proponents include Noam Chomsky (1928- )
and Jerry Fodor (1935 - ), and many other cognitive
scientists and other cognitive semanticists.
The basic idea is that meaning = idea. What a word
or sentence means is the idea in my head that I am
trying to convey with that word or sentence.
Locke’s view was that an idea was an (visual) image.
The Idea Theory of Meaning
So, when I use the word, e.g., “Santa” I form an
image in my mind, and the meaning of the word just
is that image or idea.
If you want to know what I mean by a word you
need to identify the ideas that I associate with them.
The Idea Theory of Meaning
Some problems:
How does this theory fare with respect to mass terms
(or abstract terms, as George Berkeley (`1685-1753)
refers to them? E.g., what idea do I associate with
“dog”?
“Dog” is a term that denotes all dogs, so the meaning must
be general enough to encompass all of them—but we can
only form ideas of particular things! I.e., we cannot have an
idea of a general dog.
The Idea Theory of Meaning
Some problems:
Another major problem with this view is that since we cannot
access someone’s ideas or mental images, we can never be
sure that we know what their words mean.
When you say “The flower is yellow”, how do I know that
our words “yellow” mean the same thing? I know what my
word means since I have access to my mental images, but I
don’t have access to yours. Hence, how can I be sure that
we mean the same thing?
Meaning as Brain States
Whatever is occurring, it must be represented
through our mind consequently through our brains.
So why to look here or there in search of
meaning???
Lets look into brain and find the meaning their.
But there are certain problems and serious ones!!!
The Problem of Synonymy
The brain is just physical matter; it makes as little sense
to say that a state of brain matter is the opposite of, or
synonymous with, another as it does to say the same of
the state of the electrons in my computer at any one
time. It therefore seems that meanings have a property
which prevents them from being completely identified
with brain states. (Reimer, 2010)
Problems: the practical stimulus S is not always obvious, so how to identify it?
Meaning as Use
Another version of USE theory developed by (the
later) Wittgenstein (1889-1951) and J. L. Austin
(1911-1960).
The basic idea is that meaning = use.
On this view, if we want to know what a particular
word or sentence means, we are to ask what that
word or sentence is used for. What is the speaker
trying to accomplish by using those words or
sentences?
Meaning as Use
On this view, it makes no sense to ask for the
meaning of a word in isolation.
We first need to look at the role it plays in the
sentence, and then determine what the sentence is
being used for.
Meaning as Use
Context is essential in determining use (= meaning)
Important contextual features include:
Social setting
Speaker’s personal goals
Gestures
Meaning as Use
Examples
(a) Hold it. (What does “hold” mean here? “It”?)
(b) The queen is in a vulnerable position. (What does
“queen” mean?)
(c) The President has been shot and died a few minutes
ago.
(d) Let me go. (“Me”? “Go”?)
Meaning as Use
Some Problems: this theory is not immune from
problems
In particular, knowing how a word or sentence is being used
in a particular context is sometimes a function of the
meaning of the words themselves.
E.g., if I say: “You are a son of a stickleback fish” there are
really two questions here:
What are you using that sentence for? (to insult someone, maybe)
What do those words mean? (a stickleback is a species of
Gasterosteidae, found in northern temperate climates)
Conclusion
We do not have to categorically choose between
these theories. Instead, recognizing that the
notion of meaning in linguistics is a way of
talking about the factors which explain language use,
we can see referents, concepts, brain states and
uses as all relevant to this task. (Reimer: 2010)