0% found this document useful (0 votes)
95 views40 pages

Chapter 1: (Part 2) : The Foundations: Logic and Proofs: Propositional Equivalence

atrdy

Uploaded by

Trilok Akhani
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PPT, PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
95 views40 pages

Chapter 1: (Part 2) : The Foundations: Logic and Proofs: Propositional Equivalence

atrdy

Uploaded by

Trilok Akhani
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PPT, PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 40

Chapter 1: (Part 2):

The Foundations: Logic and Proofs

 Propositional Equivalence
(Section 1.2)

 Predicates & Quantifiers


(Section 1.3)

© by Kenneth H. Rosen, Discrete Mathematics & its Applications, Sixth Edition, Mc Graw-Hill, 2007
1

Propositional Equivalences (1.2)

 A tautology is a proposition which is always true .


Classic Example: P V P

 A contradiction is a proposition which is always


false .
Classic Example: P  P

 A contingency is a proposition which neither a


tautology nor a contradiction.
Example: (P V Q)  R
CS 210, Ch.1 (part 2): The foundations: Logic & Proof, Sets, and Functions
2

Propositional Equivalences (1.2) (cont.)

 Two propositions P and Q are logically equivalent if


P  Q is a tautology. We write:

PQ

CS 210, Ch.1 (part 2): The foundations: Logic & Proof, Sets, and Functions
3

Propositional Equivalences (1.2) (cont.)


 Example:
(P  Q)  (Q  P)  (P  Q)

 Proof:
 The left side and the right side must have the same truth
values independent of the truth value of the component
propositions.

 To show a proposition is not a tautology: use an


abbreviated truth table
 try to find a counter example or to disprove the assertion.
 search for a case where the proposition is false

CS 210, Ch.1 (part 2): The foundations: Logic & Proof, Sets, and Functions
4

Propositional Equivalences (1.2) (cont.)

 Case 1: Try left side false, right side true

Left side false: only one of PQ or Q P need be


false.

1a. Assume PQ = F.


Then P = T , Q = F. But then right side PQ = F.
Wrong guess.

1b. Try Q P = F. Then Q = T, P = F. Then


PQ = F. Another wrong guess.
CS 210, Ch.1 (part 2): The foundations: Logic & Proof, Sets, and Functions
5

Propositional Equivalences (1.2)


 Case 2. Try left side true, right side false
If right side is false, P and Q cannot have the same truth
value.
2a. Assume P =T, Q = F.
Then PQ = F and the conjunction must be false so the left
side cannot be true in this case. Another wrong guess.
2b. Assume Q = T, P = F.
Again the left side cannot be true. We have exhausted all
possibilities and not found a counterexample. The two
propositions must be logically equivalent.

Note: Because of this equivalence, if and only if or iff is


also stated as is a necessary and sufficient condition for.
CS 210, Ch.1 (part 2): The foundations: Logic & Proof, Sets, and Functions
6
Equivalence Name
PTP Identity Laws
PVFP
PVTT Domination Laws
PFF
PVPP Idempotent Laws
PPP
 ( P)  P Double Negation
Law

PVQQVP Commutative Law


PQQP

CS 210, Ch.1 (part 2): The foundations: Logic & Proof, Sets, and Functions
7
Equivalence Name
(P V Q) V R Associative Law
 P V (Q V R)
P V (Q  R) Distributive Law
 (P V Q)  (P V R)
(P  Q)  P V Q De Morgan’s Laws
(P V Q)  P  Q
P  Q  P V Q Implication
Equivalence
P  Q  Q  P Contrapositive Law

Note: equivalent expressions can always be substituted for each other in a more
complex expression - useful for simplification.

CS 210, Ch.1 (part 2): The foundations: Logic & Proof, Sets, and Functions
8

Propositional Equivalences (1.2) (cont.)


 Normal or Canonical Forms

 Unique representations of a proposition

 Examples: Construct a simple proposition of two


variables which is true only when

 P is true and Q is false: P  Q


 P is true and Q is true: P  Q

 P is true and Q is false or P is true and Q is true:


(P  Q) V (P  Q)

CS 210, Ch.1 (part 2): The foundations: Logic & Proof, Sets, and Functions
9

Propositional Equivalences (1.2) (cont.)

 A disjunction of conjunctions where

 every variable or its negation is represented once in each


conjunction (a minterm)

 each minterms appears only once


Disjunctive Normal Form (DNF)

 Important in switching theory, simplification in the design


of circuits.

CS 210, Ch.1 (part 2): The foundations: Logic & Proof, Sets, and Functions
10

Propositional Equivalences (1.2) (cont.)

 Method: To find the minterms of the DNF.

 Use the rows of the truth table where the proposition is 1


or True

 If a zero appears under a variable, use the negation of


the propositional variable in the minterm

 If a one appears, use the propositional variable.

CS 210, Ch.1 (part 2): The foundations: Logic & Proof, Sets, and Functions
11

Propositional Equivalences (1.2) (cont.)


 Example: Find the DNF of (P V Q) R

P Q R (P V Q) R
0 0 0 1
0 0 1 1
0 1 0 1
0 1 1 0
1 0 0 1
1 0 1 0
1 1 0 1
1 1 1 0
CS 210, Ch.1 (part 2): The foundations: Logic & Proof, Sets, and Functions
12

Propositional Equivalences (1.2) (cont.)


 There are 5 cases where the proposition is true, hence 5
minterms. Rows 1,2,3, 5 and 7 produce the following
disjunction of minterms:

(P V Q) R
 (P  Q  R) V (P  Q  R) V (P  Q  R)
V (P  Q  R) V (P  Q  R)

 Note that you get a Conjunctive Normal Form (CNF) if


you negate a DNF and use DeMorgan’s Laws.

CS 210, Ch.1 (part 2): The foundations: Logic & Proof, Sets, and Functions
13

Predicates & Quantifiers (1.3)


 A generalization of propositions - propositional
functions or predicates: propositions which contain
variables

 Predicates become propositions once every variable


is bound- by

 assigning it a value from the Universe of Discourse U

or

 quantifying it
CS 210, Ch.1 (part 2): The foundations: Logic & Proof, Sets, and Functions
14

Predicates & Quantifiers (1.3) (cont.)


 Examples:

 Let U = Z, the integers = {. . . -2, -1, 0 , 1, 2, 3, . . .}

 P(x): x > 0 is the predicate. It has no truth value until the


variable x is bound.

 Examples of propositions where x is assigned a value:


 P(-3) is false,
 P(0) is false,
 P(3) is true.

 The collection of integers for which P(x) is true are the


positive integers.
CS 210, Ch.1 (part 2): The foundations: Logic & Proof, Sets, and Functions
15

Predicates & Quantifiers (1.3) (cont.)


 P(y) V P(0) is not a proposition. The variable y
has not been bound. However, P(3) V P(0) is a
proposition which is true.

 Let R be the three-variable predicate R(x, y z):


x+y=z

 Find the truth value of


R(2, -1, 5), R(3, 4, 7), R(x, 3, z)

CS 210, Ch.1 (part 2): The foundations: Logic & Proof, Sets, and Functions
16

Predicates & Quantifiers (1.3) (cont.)


 Quantifiers

 Universal

P(x) is true for every x in the universe of discourse.


Notation: universal quantifier
x P(x)

‘For all x, P(x)’, ‘For every x, P(x)’

The variable x is bound by the universal quantifier


producing a proposition.

CS 210, Ch.1 (part 2): The foundations: Logic & Proof, Sets, and Functions
17

Predicates & Quantifiers (1.3) (cont.)

 Example: U = {1, 2, 3}

x P(x)  P(1)  P(2)  P(3)

CS 210, Ch.1 (part 2): The foundations: Logic & Proof, Sets, and Functions
18

Predicates & Quantifiers (1.3) (cont.)


 Quantifiers (cont.)
 Existential

 P(x) is true for some x in the universe of discourse.


Notation: existential quantifier
x P(x)

‘There is an x such that P(x),’ ‘For some x, P(x)’, ‘For


at least one x, P(x)’, ‘I can find an x such that P(x).’

Example: U={1,2,3}
x P(x)  P(1) V P(2) V P(3)
CS 210, Ch.1 (part 2): The foundations: Logic & Proof, Sets, and Functions
19

Predicates & Quantifiers (1.3) (cont.)


 Quantifiers (cont.)

 Unique Existential

P(x) is true for one and only one x in the universe of


discourse.

Notation: unique existential quantifier


!x P(x)

‘There is a unique x such that P(x),’ ‘There is one and


only one x such that P(x),’ ‘One can find only one x
such that P(x).’
CS 210, Ch.1 (part 2): The foundations: Logic & Proof, Sets, and Functions
20

Predicates & Quantifiers (1.3) (cont.)


 Example: U = {1, 2, 3, 4}

P(1) P(2) P(3) !xP(x)

0 0 0 0
0 0 1 1
0 1 0 1
0 1 1 0
1 0 0 1 How many
1 0 1 0 minterms are
1 1 0 0 in the DNF?
1 1 1 0
CS 210, Ch.1 (part 2): The foundations: Logic & Proof, Sets, and Functions
21

Predicates & Quantifiers (1.3) (cont.)

REMEMBER!

A predicate is not a proposition until all variables


have been bound either by quantification or
assignment of a value!

CS 210, Ch.1 (part 2): The foundations: Logic & Proof, Sets, and Functions
22

Predicates & Quantifiers (1.3) (cont.)


 Equivalences involving the negation operator
(x P(x ))  x P(x)
(x P(x))  x P(x)

 Distributing a negation operator across a quantifier


changes a universal to an existential and vice
versa.

 (x P(x))  (P(x1)  P(x2)  …  P(xn))


 P(x1) V P(x2) V … V P(xn)
 x P(x)

CS 210, Ch.1 (part 2): The foundations: Logic & Proof, Sets, and Functions
23

Predicates & Quantifiers (1.3) (cont.)


 Multiple Quantifiers: read left to right . . .

 Example: Let U = R, the real numbers,


P(x,y): xy= 0
x y P(x, y)
x y P(x, y)
x y P(x, y)
x y P(x, y)

The only one that is false is the first one.


What’s about the case when P(x,y) is the predicate
x/y=1?
CS 210, Ch.1 (part 2): The foundations: Logic & Proof, Sets, and Functions
24

Predicates & Quantifiers (1.3) (cont.)


 Multiple Quantifiers: read left to right . . .
 Example: Let U = {1,2,3}. Find an expression equivalent
to x y P(x, y) where the variables are bound by
substitution instead:

Expand from inside out or outside in.

Outside in:

y P(1, y)  y P(2, y)  y P(3, y)


[P(1,1) V P(1,2) V P(1,3)] 
[P(2,1) V P(2,2) V P(2,3)] 
[P(3,1) V P(3,2) V P(3,3)]
CS 210, Ch.1 (part 2): The foundations: Logic & Proof, Sets, and Functions
25

Predicates & Quantifiers (1.3) (cont.)


 Converting from English (Can be very difficult!)

“Every student in this class has studied calculus”


transformed into:

“For every student in this class, that student has studied


calculus”

C(x): “x has studied calculus”


x C(x)

This is one way of converting from English!

CS 210, Ch.1 (part 2): The foundations: Logic & Proof, Sets, and Functions
26

Predicates & Quantifiers (1.3) (cont.)


 Multiple Quantifiers: read left to right . . . (cont.)

 Example:

F(x): x is a fleegle
S(x): x is a snurd
T(x): x is a thingamabob

U={fleegles, snurds, thingamabobs}

(Note: the equivalent form using the existential quantifier is also


given)

CS 210, Ch.1 (part 2): The foundations: Logic & Proof, Sets, and Functions
27

Predicates & Quantifiers (1.3) (cont.)

 Everything is a fleegle
x F( x)
  (x F(x))

 Nothing is a snurd.
x  S(x)
  (x S( x))

 All fleegles are snurds.


x [F(x)S(x)]
 x [F(x) V S(x)]
 x  [F(x)  S(x)]
  (x [F(x) V S(x)])
CS 210, Ch.1 (part 2): The foundations: Logic & Proof, Sets, and Functions
28

Predicates & Quantifiers (1.3) (cont.)


 Some fleegles are thingamabobs.
x [F(x)  T(x)]
 (x [F(x) V T(x)])

 No snurd is a thingamabob.
x [S(x) T(x)]
 (x [S(x )  T(x)])

 If any fleegle is a snurd then it's also a thingamabob


x [(F(x)  S(x))  T(x)]
 (x [F(x)  S(x)  T( x)])

CS 210, Ch.1 (part 2): The foundations: Logic & Proof, Sets, and Functions
29

Predicates & Quantifiers (1.3) (cont.)


 Extra Definitions:

 An assertion involving predicates is valid if it is true for


every universe of discourse.

 An assertion involving predicates is satisfiable if there is a


universe and an interpretation for which the assertion is
true. Else it is unsatisfiable.

 The scope of a quantifier is the part of an assertion in


which variables are bound by the quantifier

CS 210, Ch.1 (part 2): The foundations: Logic & Proof, Sets, and Functions
30

Predicates & Quantifiers (1.3) (cont.)


 Examples:

Valid: x S(x)  [x S( x)]

Not valid but satisfiable: x [F(x)  T(x)]

Not satisfiable: x [F(x)  F(x)]

Scope: x [F(x) V S( x)] vs. x [F(x)] V x [S(x)]

CS 210, Ch.1 (part 2): The foundations: Logic & Proof, Sets, and Functions
31

Predicates & Quantifiers (1.3) (cont.)


 Dangerous situations:

 Commutativity of quantifiers
x y P(x, y) y x P( x, y)?
YES!
x y P(x, y)  y x P(x, y)?
NO!
DIFFERENT MEANING!

 Distributivity of quantifiers over operators


x [P(x)  Q(x)]  x P( x)  x Q( x)?
YES!
x [P( x)  Q( x)] [x P(x)  x Q( x)]?
NO!
CS 210, Ch.1 (part 2): The foundations: Logic & Proof, Sets, and Functions
32

Sets (1.6)

 A set is a collection or group of objects or elements


or members. (Cantor 1895)

 A set is said to contain its elements.

 There must be an underlying universal set U, either


specifically stated or understood.

CS 210, Ch.1 (part 2): The foundations: Logic & Proof, Sets, and Functions
33

Sets (1.6) (cont.)


 Notation:

 list the elements between braces:


S = {a, b, c, d}={b, c, a, d, d}
(Note: listing an object more than once does not change the set.
Ordering means nothing.)

 specification by predicates:
S= {x| P(x)},
S contains all the elements from U which make the predicate P
true.

 brace notation with ellipses:


S = { . . . , -3, -2, -1},
the negative integers.
CS 210, Ch.1 (part 2): The foundations: Logic & Proof, Sets, and Functions
34

Sets (1.6) (cont.)


 Common Universal Sets
 R = reals
 N = natural numbers = {0,1, 2, 3, . . . }, the counting
numbers
 Z = all integers = {. . , -3, -2, -1, 0, 1, 2, 3, 4, . .}
 Z+ is the set of positive integers

 Notation:
x is a member of S or x is an element of S:
x  S.
x is not an element of S:
x  S.
CS 210, Ch.1 (part 2): The foundations: Logic & Proof, Sets, and Functions
35

Sets (1.6) (cont.)


 Subsets
 Definition: The set A is a subset of the set B, denoted
A  B, iff
x [x  A  x  B]
 Definition: The void set, the null set, the empty set,
denoted , is the set with no members.

Note: the assertion x   is always false. Hence


x [x    x  B]
is always true(vacuously). Therefore,  is a subset of
every set.

Note: A set B is always a subset of itself.


CS 210, Ch.1 (part 2): The foundations: Logic & Proof, Sets, and Functions
36

Sets (1.6) (cont.)

 Definition: If A  B but A  B the we say A is a proper


subset of B, denoted A  B (in some texts).

 Definition: The set of all subset of a set A, denoted P(A),


is called the power set of A.

 Example: If A = {a, b} then


P(A) = {, {a}, {b}, {a,b}}

CS 210, Ch.1 (part 2): The foundations: Logic & Proof, Sets, and Functions
37

Sets (1.6) (cont.)


 Definition: The number of (distinct) elements in A,
denoted |A|, is called the cardinality of A.

If the cardinality is a natural number (in N), then the


set is called finite, else infinite.

 Example: A = {a, b},


|{a, b}| = 2,
|P({a, b})| = 4.
A is finite and so is P(A).
Useful Fact: |A|=n implies |P(A)| = 2n

CS 210, Ch.1 (part 2): The foundations: Logic & Proof, Sets, and Functions
38

Sets (1.6) (cont.)


 N is infinite since |N| is not a natural number. It is called a transfinite
cardinal number.

 Note: Sets can be both members and subsets of other sets.

 Example:
A = {,{}}.
A has two elements and hence four subsets:
, {}, {{}}. {,{}}
Note that  is both a member of A and a subset of A!

 Russell's paradox: Let S be the set of all sets which are not members
of themselves. Is S a member of itself?

 Another paradox: Henry is a barber who shaves all people who do


not shave themselves. Does Henry shave himself?

CS 210, Ch.1 (part 2): The foundations: Logic & Proof, Sets, and Functions
39

Sets (1.6) (cont.)


 Definition: The Cartesian product of A with B, denoted
A x B, is the set of ordered pairs {<a, b> | a  A  b  B}
Notation: n
 Ai   a1 , a 2 ,...,a n  a i  Ai 
i 1
Note: The Cartesian product of anything with  is . (why?)

 Example:
A = {a,b}, B = {1, 2, 3}
AxB = {<a, 1>, <a, 2>, <a, 3>, <b, 1>, <b, 2>, <b, 3>}
What is BxA? AxBxA?

 If |A| = m and |B| = n, what is |AxB|?


CS 210, Ch.1 (part 2): The foundations: Logic & Proof, Sets, and Functions

You might also like