How Dogs Think
How Dogs Think
How Dogs Think
Wynne The American Journal of Psychology, Vol. 118, No. 4 (Winter, 2005), pp. 660-666 Published by: University of Illinois Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/30039094 . Accessed: 07/06/2012 11:01
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
University of Illinois Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The American Journal of Psychology.
http://www.jstor.org
660
I have already stated that my bias is toward the belief that animals (at least most mammals) have conscious thinking ability to some extent, although generally less than that of humans. I also believe that if you find one behavior that cannot be the case has been proven, whereas explained in the absence of consciousness, Wynne seems to have set for himself the nearly impossible task of asserting the negative. Nonetheless, despite the different conclusions that we reach (based in
part on the different datasets we consider), it is still true that this book is worth reading and considering seriously. It does provide a good picture of certain aspects of animal behavior that are not well known, and it offers a number of cautions and questions that should be considered in the analysis of animal cognition. Perhaps the final word on the controversy should be left to Wynne himself, who notes, "It's not their like-us-ness that makes animals important; It's their not-like-us-ness that is the better reason to cherish them. You may disagree. I respect that. Thoughtful people can in good faith reach different conclusions on these problems.... Go peacefully-and may your dog go with you" (p. 244). Stanley Coren
Department of Psychology University of British Columbia 2136 West Mall Vancouve BC, Canada V6T 1Z4
What Dogs Do
How Dogs Think: Understanding the Canine Mind
By Stanley Coren. New York: Free Press, 2004. 351 pp. Cloth, $26.00. The first scientific paper on dog behavior was published in 1884 by Charles Darwin's neighbor, Sir John Lubbock. Lubbock, governor of the Bank of England and inventor of British public holidays, was a keen amateur contributor to several
BOOK REVIEWS
661
branches of science. Lubbock thought that the standard method of training dogs to understand human commands underestimated dogs' communicative abilities because it offered no line of communication from dog to human. He had an original idea to get over this problem. He wrote the names of things he thought his poodle, Van, might like on large cards, which he then spread out on the ground. Whatever Van selected he received, and whatever Van received he accepted with delight. Lubbock was greatly impressed by the frequency with which Van learned to bring him the card with "FOOD" written on it: "No one who sees him can doubt that he understands the act of bringing the card with the word 'Food' on it as a request for something to eat" (Lubbock, 1884, p. 216). Lubbock clearly believed that he had made a great breakthrough in understanding dog minds. Modern readers, especially those trained in psychology, will readily recognize the fallacy of Lubbock's reasoning. Van's behavior can be more parsimoniously accounted for as the expression of Edward Thorndike's (1911) Law of Effect, the principle that actions that produce desired consequences will be repeated. Van was rewarded by food whenever he brought the card with that word written on it; consequently, the action of bringing that card was reinforced and came to be repeated in the future. There is no need to suppose that Van was communicating any "thoughts," and with parsimony being a basic principle of science, we should not assume that he was.
662
In How Dogs Think Coren revels in debunking the cynicism of skeptics with well-documented accounts of dog abilities that were previously dismissed as romantic anthropomorphism. Dogs do learn by imitation, for example. They also understand more of the intentions of people around them than they have been given credit for. Being proven wrong is the lot of the skeptic. However, it does not invalidate a skeptical attitude in science in general and with regard to animal minds in particular. The problem with lifting a prohibition on a skeptical attitude toward animal minds is not that skeptics are not sometimes (perhaps often) wrong; it is that excessive enthusiasm can never be proven wrong. If I insist that fairies dance in my garden at night after everyone is asleep and never leave a trace of their presence, I am never going to be proven wrong. My sanity may be doubted for believing something not supported by any evidence, but no amount of negative evidence regarding these immaterial spirits can ever contradict my assertion. This argument is not new; indeed, it is the one rehearsed by William of Occam in the 14th century when he concluded, "Pluralitas non est ponenda sine neccesitate," or "Plurality should not be posited without necessity."
BOOK REVIEWS
663
people are intimately related to other life forms, Darwin (1882) argued that all human mental powers differed only in degree, not in kind, from those of other species. It is interesting that Darwin chose to quote a reverend to support his point: "But man, as a highly competent judge, Archbishop Whately remarks, 'is not the only animal that can make use of language to express what is passing in his mind, and can understand, more or less, what is so expressed by another'" (Darwin, 1882, p. 84). When we look at the examples Darwin mustered, however, we see that they concern the expression of emotions, not thoughts. For example, Darwin mentioned cebus monkeys that can communicate emotions through the use of "at least six distinct sounds" and dogs that "bark in at least four or five distinct tones" (Darwin, 1882, p. 84). He went on to argue that human language could have evolved from the inarticulate emotional cries of other species. Most scientists now side with Darwin against Descartes in believing that linguistic thought must be the result of evolutionary processes rather than the direct intervention of a deity. Fewer commentators, I believe, would argue in support of Darwin's contention that "the lower animals differ from man solely in his almost infinitely larger power of associating together the most diversified sounds and ideas; and this obviously depends on the high development of his mental powers" (Darwin, 1882, pp. 85-86). In his desire to shore up as much evidence as possible in favor of mental continuity between human and animal, Darwin failed to see that emotional cries, which indeed people share with many other species, are not what makes language interesting. It is the decoupling of communication from emotion that has made human language so powerful and does indeed appear to be a uniquely human adaptation (Anderson, 2004; Wynne, 2004). Although my shrieks of distress as I am attacked by a dog probably would be as well understood by other dogs in the neighborhood as by my human neighbors, my verbal account of how the dog came to bite me would make sense only to my human friends. On this point Descartes was closer to the truth than Darwin. Although we know very little about Descartes's private life, there is at least one point of commonality between Descartes and Darwin: They were both fond of dogs. Descartes experimented on dogs, but he also had a pet dog, Monsieur Grat (Mister Scratch), of whom he was very fond (Watson, 2002). Darwin's love of dogs was famous, if not infamous. In his autobiography he quoted his father of him as a schoolboy, 'You care for nothing but shooting, dogs, and rat-catching, and you will be a disgrace to yourself and all your family" (Darwin, 1927, p. 7). Stanley Coren clearly shares with Descartes and Darwin a great love of dogs. HowDogs Thinkis full of happy anecdotes of the richness of life shared with canine companions. But what are we to make of this contentment that dogs can bring into a home? Could one animal have evolved solely for the well-being of another? There is a side of dog ownership that Coren chooses not to go into: the costs. In The TruthAboutDogs (2000) Stephen Budiansky wittily ponders the expense side of the dog-keeping ledger. He points out that if visitors from outer space observed members of one species cleaning up the poop of another they would surely make certain assumptions about which of these species was the dominant and which the subordinate. And yet we love them so. The solution to the apparent paradox of the costs of doggy companionship and our fondness for them lies in our shared evolutionary history. DNA evidence
664
suggests that modern dogs evolved from wolves more than 100,000 years ago (Vila et al., 1997), and some argue that people have been associating with dogs since those early times. If true, this means that dogs started associating with people when we were still Neanderthals. More certain is archeological evidence such as a burial site in Israel from 13,500 years ago that contains the bodies of an old woman with her puppy (Tacon & Pardoe, 2002), clear evidence of a very intense relationship.
BOOK REVIEWS
665
& Fischer, 2004) found a border collie, Rico, who knew the names of more than 200 objects. Rico could be ordered into a room to collect a named item from among nine other items with which he was also familiar. Rico must have been responding based just on the name of the item because owner and experimenter remained in one room while the dog went into the other to make his selection. More remarkable than just his vocabulary was Rico's ability to learn new words. As in the first test, the experimenters ordered Rico into the other room to collect an item. This time, however, they used a word that was not familiar to Rico and sent him into a room that contained eight items. Seven of these objects were familiar to the dog, but the eighth item was new to him. In 7 out of 10 tests with novel words Rico appropriately retrieved a different novel item each time.
666
ability in an animal is rather exciting and satisfying. However, each such incident does not shake my faith in skepticism as the proper method of science. I remain convinced that dogs do not act consciously, at least as we understand that term when we apply it to each other. They do not read our minds; rather, they read our behavior. Millennia of natural selection and a few centuries of artificial selection have led to animals that have an uncanny ability to understand what we are doing and predict where we are going next. They can also manipulate us to their designs. But they do not know they are doing this. They are not conscious. That does not mean we cannot love them. Sentimental it may be, but, asJames Serpell rightly pointed out in In the CompanyofAnimals (Serpell, 1996) many of our lives' richest moments are beset with sentimentality. And they are none the worse for that.
Clive D. L. Wynne Department ofPsychology University of Florida Gainesville, FL 32611 E-mail: [email protected]
References
Anderson, S. (2004). DoctorDolittle'sdelusion:Animals and the uniqueness of human language. New Haven, CT:Yale University Press. Budiansky, S. (2000). The truthabout dogs.New York: Viking. Coppinger, R., & Coppinger, L. (2002). Dogs: A new understanding of canine origin, behavior, and evolution. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Curio, E., Ernst, E., & Vieth, W. (1978). Cultural transmission of enemy recognition: One function of mobbing. Science,202, 899-901. Darwin, C. (1882). Thedescentof man and selectionin relationto sex (2nd ed. revised and augmented). London: John Murray. Darwin, C. (1927). Theautobiography CharlesDarwin. London: Watts & Co. of Descartes, R. (1976). Animals are machines. In T. Regan & P. Singer (Eds.), Animal rights and human obligations(pp. 60-66). Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall. (Original work published 1637) Descartes, R. (1980). Letter to the Marquis of Newcastle, 23 Nov 1646. Reprinted in Descartes:Philosophical Letters(trans. A. Kenny) (p. 207). Oxford: Blackwell. (Original work published 1646) Kaminsky,J., Call, J., & Fischer, J. (2004). Word learning in a domestic dog: Evidence for "fast mapping." Science,5677, 1682-1683. Lubbock,J. (1884). Teaching animals to converse. Nature, 29, 547-548. Serpell, J. (1996). In the companyof animals: A study of human-animal relationships(2nd ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Tacon, P. S. C., & Pardoe, C. (2002). Dogs make us human. Nature Australia, 27, 52. Thorndike, E. L. (1911). Animal intelligence: Experimentalstudies. New York: Macmillan. Turing, A. M. (1950). Computing machinery and intelligence. Mind, 59, 433-460. Vila, C., Savolainen, P., Maldonado,J. E., Amorim, I. R., Rice,J. E., Honeycutt, R. L., Crandall, K. A., Lundeberg,J., & Wayne, R. K. (1997). Multiple and ancient origins of the domestic dogs. Science,276, 1687-1689. Watson, R. (2002). Cogito,ergosum: The life ofRend Descartes.Jaffrey,NH: David Godine. Wynne, C. D. L. (2004). Do animals think?Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.