BİM122 Lecture Note 4
BİM122 Lecture Note 4
Copyright © McGraw-Hill Education. All rights reserved. No reproduction or distribution without the prior written consent of McGraw-Hill Education.
1
Summary
Valid Arguments and Rules of Inference
Proof Methods
2
Section 1.6
3
Section Summary
Valid Arguments
Inference Rules for Propositional Logic
Using Rules of Inference to Build Arguments
Rules of Inference for Quantified Statements
Building Arguments for Quantified Statements
4
Revisiting the Socrates Example
We have the two premises:
“All men are mortal.”
“Socrates is a man.”
And the conclusion:
“Socrates is mortal.”
How do we get the conclusion from the premises?
5
The Argument
We can express the premises (above the line) and the
conclusion (below the line) in predicate logic as an
argument:
6
Valid Arguments
We will show how to construct valid arguments in
two stages; first for propositional logic and then for
predicate logic. The rules of inference are the
essential building block in the construction of valid
arguments.
1. Propositional Logic
Inference Rules
2. Predicate Logic
Inference rules for propositional logic plus additional inference
rules to handle variables and quantifiers.
7
Arguments in Propositional Logic
A argument in propositional logic is a sequence of propositions.
All but the final proposition are called premises. The last
statement is the conclusion.
The argument is valid if the premises imply the conclusion. An
argument form is an argument that is valid no matter what
propositions are substituted into its propositional variables.
If the premises are 1 2 n and the conclusion is then
( 1 2 n) is a tautology.
Inference rules are all argument simple argument forms that will
be used to construct more complex argument forms.
8
Rules of Inference for Propositional
Logic: Modus Ponens
Corresponding Tautology:
(p
Example:
Let p be “It is snowing.”
Let q be “I will study discrete math.”
9
Modus Tollens
Corresponding Tautology:
( q
Example:
Let p be “it is snowing.”
Let q be “I will study discrete math.”
Example:
Let p be “it snows.”
Let q be “I will study discrete math.”
Let r be “I will get an A.”
Example:
Let p be “I will study discrete math.”
Let q be “I will study English literature.”
12
Addition
Corresponding Tautology:
p
Example:
Let p be “I will study discrete math.”
Let q be “I will visit Las Vegas.”
13
Simplification
Corresponding Tautology:
(p
Example:
Let p be “I will study discrete math.”
Let q be “I will study English literature.”
14
Conjunction
Corresponding Tautology:
( p)
Example:
Let p be “I will study discrete math.”
Let q be “I will study English literature.”
Corresponding Tautology:
(( p
Example:
Let p be “I will study discrete math.”
Let r be “I will study English literature.”
Let q be “I will study databases.”
17
Valid Arguments
Example : From the single proposition
18
Valid Arguments
Example 2:
With these hypotheses:
“It is not sunny this afternoon and it is colder than yesterday.”
“We will go swimming only if it is sunny.”
“If we do not go swimming, then we will take a canoe trip.”
“If we take a canoe trip, then we will be home by sunset.”
Using the inference rules, construct a valid argument for the conclusion:
“We will be home by sunset.”
Solution:
1. Choose propositional variables:
p : “It is sunny this afternoon.” r : “We will go swimming.” t : “We will be home by sunset.”
q : “It is colder than yesterday.” s : “We will take a canoe trip.”
2. Translation into propositional logic:
20
Handling Quantified Statements
Valid arguments for quantified statements are a
sequence of statements. Each statement is either a
premise or follows from previous statements by rules
of inference which include:
Rules of Inference for Propositional Logic
Rules of Inference for Quantified Statements
The rules of inference for quantified statements are
introduced in the next several slides.
21
Universal Instantiation (UI)
Example:
22
Universal Generalization (UG)
23
Existential Instantiation (EI)
Example:
24
Existential Generalization (EG)
Example:
25
Using Rules of Inference
Example : Using the rules of inference, construct a valid
argument to show that
“John Smith has two legs”
is a consequence of the premises:
“Every man has two legs.” “John Smith is a man.”
Solution: Let M(x) denote “x is a man” and L(x) “ x has two legs”
and let John Smith be a member of the domain.
Valid Argument:
26
Using Rules of Inference
Example : Use the rules of inference to construct a valid argument
showing that the conclusion
“Someone who passed the first exam has not read the book.”
follows from the premises
“A student in this class has not read the book.”
“Everyone in this class passed the first exam.”
Solution: Let C(x) denote “x is in this class,” B(x) denote “ x has read
the book,” and P(x) denote “x passed the first exam.”
First we translate the
premises and conclusion
into symbolic form.
28
Returning to the Socrates Example
29
Solution for Socrates Example
Valid Argument
30
Universal Modus Ponens
Universal Modus Ponens combines universal
instantiation and modus ponens into one rule.
33
Section Summary
Mathematical Proofs
Forms of Theorems
Direct Proofs
Indirect Proofs
Proof of the Contrapositive
Proof by Contradiction
34
Proofs of Mathematical Statements
A proof is a valid argument that establishes the truth of a
statement.
In math, CS, and other disciplines, informal proofs which are
generally shorter, are generally used.
More than one rule of inference are often used in a step.
Steps may be skipped.
The rules of inference used are not explicitly stated.
Easier for to understand and to explain to people.
But it is also easier to introduce errors.
Proofs have many practical applications:
verification that computer programs are correct
establishing that operating systems are secure
enabling programs to make inferences in artificial intelligence
showing that system specifications are consistent
35
Definitions
A theorem is a statement that can be shown to be true using:
definitions
other theorems
axioms (statements which are given as true)
rules of inference
A lemma is a ‘helping theorem’ or a result which is needed to
prove a theorem.
A corollary is a result which follows directly from a theorem.
Less important theorems are sometimes called propositions.
A conjecture is a statement that is being proposed to be true.
Once a proof of a conjecture is found, it becomes a theorem. It
may turn out to be false.
36
Forms of Theorems
Many theorems assert that a property holds for all elements
in a domain, such as the integers, the real numbers, or
some of the discrete structures that we will study in this
class.
Often the universal quantifier (needed for a precise
statement of a theorem) is omitted by standard
mathematical convention.
For example, the statement:
“If x > y, where x and y are positive real numbers, then x2 > y2 ”
really means
“For all positive real numbers x and y, if x > y, then x2 > y2 .”
37
Proving Theorems
Many theorems have the form:
38
Proving Conditional Statements: p
Trivial Proof: If we know q is true, then
p is true as well.
[ Even though these examples seem silly, both trivial and vacuous
proofs are often used in mathematical induction, as we will see
in Chapter 5) ]
39
Even and Odd Integers
Definition: The integer n is even if there exists an
integer k such that n = k, and n is odd if there exists
an integer k, such that n = k + . Note that every
integer is either even or odd and no integer is both
even and odd.
where
=
Thus the sum is rational.
42
Proving Conditional Statements: p
Proof by Contraposition: Assume q and show is true also. This is
sometimes called an indirect proof method. If we give a direct proof of
q p
Why does this work?
Example: Prove that if n is an integer and n + is odd, then n is
odd.
Solution: Assume n is even. So, n = k for some integer k. Thus
n+ j= k+
Therefore n + is even ,
If n is an integer and n + is odd (not even) ,
then n is odd (not even).
43
Proving Conditional Statements: p
Example: Prove that for an integer n, if n is odd, then n is
odd.
Solution: Use proof by contraposition. Assume n is even
(i.e., not odd). Therefore, there exists an integer k such
that n = k. Hence,
n = k = ( k)
and n is even(i.e., not odd).
We have shown that if n is an even integer, then n is even.
Therefore by contraposition, for an integer n, if n is odd,
then n is odd.
44
Proving Conditional Statements: p
Proof by Contradiction: (AKA reductio ad absurdum).
To prove p, assume and derive a contradiction such as
p Since we have shown
that is true , it follows that the contrapositive T
45
Theorems that are Biconditional
Statements
To prove a theorem that is a biconditional statement,
that is, a statement of the form p
46
Exercises
Rules of Inference
Chapter 1.6 (7th Global Edition): 2,3, 7, 8,10, 11
Chapter 1.6 (7th Edition): 3, 5, 9, 14, 15, 16
Introduction to Proofs
Chapter 1.8 (7th Global Edition): 1, 5, 9, 14
Chapter 1.7 (7th Edition): 1, 9, 17, 23
47
References
Discrete Mathematics and Its Applications, Seventh Edition, Kenneth Rosen
48