Bounding Theory
Bounding Theory
Cedric Boeckx
(Harvard University)
1. Introduction
Much research within the Minimalist Program tries to offer a better under-
standing of phenomena and generalization that research of the past 30 years
has firmly established. One such phenomenon is successive cyclic movement,
the fact that movement steps have an upper bound, that movement cannot be
"too long" (see Chomsky (1973) and much subsequent work). In this paper I
offer an argument in favor of a specific conception of successive cyclicity
within the minimalist program on the basis of considerations having to do
with lower bounds on movement steps, that is, the idea that movement cannot
be "too short." Specifically, I argue for a version of successive cyclic movement
that minimizes chain links (Takahashi 1994, Boeckx 2003, among others) be-
cause that version requires a ban on movement internal to the projection from
which movement originates. I show on the basis of data from applicative and
psych constructions that this ban on movement is superior to alternative ways
of defining lower bounds on movement.
Standard assumptions about binding tell us that the binding of the reflexive in
(la) is unproblematic since John has raised from its base position over the re-
flexive to the specifier of to appear and then subsequently raised to its surface
position. Thus we understand the reflexive to be locally bound by virtue of the
trace/copy in the intermediate position (indicated by .f). (lb), on the other
hand, is ruled out by virtue of a kind of blocking effect since Mary, by hy-
pothesis, has raised through the specifier of to appear as in (lc). Thus, typical
binding requirements could be said to rule out (lb) on the assumption that the
intermediate movement really takes place.
That A-bar movement also proceeds in short steps can be seen from exam-
ples like (2).
(2) a. [Which pictures ofhimselfi/j] does Johnj think ~ that Bi1lj bought
b. Who said that Johnj thinks that Bi1lj bought pictures of himself'i/j
Although the facts around successive cyclic movement are clear, the under-
lyjng cause is much less so. Consider McCloskey's (2002: 184-185) telling
quote:
"If locality conditions are at the heart of syntax (as increasingly seems to be the
case), then the existence of apparently unbounded dependencies like [long-distance
wh-movement] represents an anomaly. Since Chornsky (1973), it has come to be
widely believed that the apparently distant connection between antecedent and vari-
able position in such cases is mediated by a sequence of more local connections. (... )
In all variants of this core idea, the specifier of CP is one of the crucial left-peripheral
positions establishing these connections (... ) Movement is always at least this local.
(... ) A much harder question is what makes this true - what property of language-
design determines that this is how things work."
The conceptual problem posed by successive cyclicity has been around ever
since the advent of the rrrinimalist program and its insistence on movement as
last resort. Put simply, there doesn't seem to be obvious features triggering in-
termediate steps of movement.
Various featural options have been tried, but I agree with McCloskey (2002:
186) that all of them boil down to "spurious," or "pseudo-"features (Q, Op,
Wh, etc.) - movement-triggering features optionally present on intermediate
landing sites, whose presence is required neither by lexical requirements or by
considerations of interpretability.
It has sometimes been suggested (see, e.g., Hornstein (2001: 119» that the
checking of 4>-features should be implicated in the formulation of successive
cyclic movement on the basis of so-called wh-agreement phenomena in lan-
guages like Chamorro (see Chung (1998». However, this conception of wh-
agreement (agreement triggered by successive cyclic movement of the wh-
phrase) appears to rest on a factual misunderstanding (noted by various ex-
perts on the languages exhibiting overt 'wh' -agreement). As noted in Boeckx
(2003: 57), building upon observations in Chung and Georgopoulos (1988),
Georgopoulos (1991), and Chung (1988), for Palauan and Chamorro (see also
Rackowski and Richards (2003) on Tagalog, Pearson to appear on Malagasy,
and Finer (1997) on Selayarese), 'wh-agreement' is only indirectly conditioned
by overt wh-movement. That is, although wh-movement induces a morpho-
logical change on intermediate verbs (verbs along the wh-movement path), the
morphological change refers to a special kind of agreement between the verb
and the clause from which the wh-phrase has been extracted. In particular,
when overt wh-movement takes place, the verbs along the way to the ultimate
[+wh] SpecCP bears the morphology they would bear if the complement
38 Cedric Boeckx
(5) *John met someone, but I don't know who Peter said (that) John met
(6) a. John's talk about the economy was interesting, but Bill's talk about
the @conomy was boring
I I here set aside differences among the relevant languages pertaining to whether 'wh-
agreement' on intermediate verbs is obligatory (Tagalog) or optional (Chamorro) de-
pending on the nature of the moving wh-phrase (D-linked or not). I also set aside the
fact that in the relevant languages, the moving wh-phrase directly affects the morphol-
ogy of the most deeply embedded verb. The latter point is largely orthogonal to the issue
of successive cyclicity.
2 The only instance of genuine long-distance wh-agreement (where morphology co-varies
with the featural specification of the wh-word, not the clause containing it) I am aware
of is found in Kinande. As Schneider-Zioga has illustrated in a series of papers (Schnei-
der-Zioga 2000, 2002, 2004; see also Rizzi 1990: 55), the language expresses the noun
class and number of the wh-phrase on the complementizer (lfocus-marker) immediately
adjacent to the wh-phrase (i), as weH as on complementizers along the wh-path (ii) ..
(i) a. Iyond! yO Karnbale alangIra
Who.l that. 1 Kambale saw
'Who did Karnbale see'
b. AbahI Bo Kambale alangIra
Who.2 that.2 Karnbale saw
c. EkIhI kyO Karnbale alangIra
What.7 that.7 Karnbale saw
'What did Kambale see'
d. EBIhI ByO Kambale alangIra
What.8 that.8 Karnbale saw
(ii) EkIhIj kyOj Yosefu a-kabula [,mp nga-kyoj rip a-kalangira ~ ]]
what FOC J. wonders if -FOC agr.sees
'What does Yosefu wonder ifhe sees?'
To analyze Kinande in a way consistent with the claim that there is no wh-agreement triggered
on intermediate landing sites, Boeckx (2004) foHows Davies' (2003) analysis of long-
distance wh-questions in Madurese and Javenese. Davies argues that apparent long-
distance wh-movement are instances of iterative prolepsis, as schematized in (iii). (See
also McCloskey (2002: 199) for an independent argument in favoring of allowing a
strategy like (iii) based on Irish.)
(ill) Whi [Opi C .... <Opi> [Opi C ... <Opi>]]
(It is interesting to note that Kinande wh-extractions, like Madurese and Javanese wh-questions,
have a cleft-like nature.)
Some Notes on Bounding 39
On the basis of arguments of this sort I conclude that successive cyclic move-
ment steps are not feature-driven. This conclusion is also embraced by Chom-
sky in his recent writings (Chomsky 2000, 2001, 2004, 2005a-b). There, suc-
cessive-cyclic movement is forced by the PlC (11). To avoid being trapped in a
phase, an element must move from phase-edge to phase-edge. The mechanism
that ensures this is given in Chomsky (2000):
(7) At the end of phase HP, the head H may freely be assigned an EPP-
feature, forcing overt movement of a phrase into SpecHP
Takahashi claims that the Mirrimize Chain Links Principle captures the cy-
clic (local) nature of movement while avoiding the pitfalls of spurious features
posited in intermediate sites to drive successive cyclic steps.
Takahashi's core idea is that successive steps are taken not in order to check
some feature in intermediate sites, but simply due to the requirement that
chain links must be minimized (a reflex of economy). In Takahashi's (1994)
terms, each link of a chain must be as short as possible. The requirement forces
any element X undergoing movement of type Y to stop at every position of
type Y on the way to its final landing site independently of feature checking. It
is worth noting that Takahashi assumes that the relevant operation underlying
movement is Form Chain. In so doing, Last Resort is relevant only to the for-
mation of a chain, not links of a chain. In other words, formation of a chain
must have feature-checking motivation, but formation of chain links needs not
Building upon a suggestion made in Manzini (1994), Boeckx (2003: 8) modi-
fied Takahashi (1994), and argued that a moving element adjoins to the
maximal domain of each head on its way to its ultimate landing site (see also
Boskovic (2002: 186), Boskovic (2005), Fox and Lasnik (2003), Fox (2000),
Richards (2002) for similar claims; see also the percolation mechanisms in
frameworks like HPSG, or in Neeleman and van de Koot (2002)).5 The moti-
vation for this idea was twofold. First, ever since the principle of the cycle was
proposed, the number of cyclic nodes (originally restricted to S and NP) in-
creased, and just about every node became a cyclic node (see already Williams
(1974)). This strikes me as the simplest assumption. Second, the notion of
movement type (AI A-bar) has no clear status in current syntactic theorizing,
which makes it very difficult to define in a non-arbitrary way what a landing
site of the relevant type is.
property of the movement operation, and is not due to the checking of (pseudo-)features
in intermediate positions. As far as this paper is concerned, any version of successive
cyclicity that encodes this intuition and that requires a lower bound on movement will do.
Here I rely on Takahashi's version because it is fairly we11-known, and because the need
for a lower bound on movement once we adopt Takahashi's version has been fleshed out
in the literature (Boskovic 1994).
5 One may say that under Boeckx's version of successive cyclic movement every maximal
projection is a phase (as argued for in Epstein and Seely (2002) and Boskovic (2005)),
but it is important to note that were one to do so, one would be using a very different no-
tion of phase from the one used by Chomsky. For Chomsky, every phase induces a PLC
effect. If every projection were a phase, no extraction would be possible, as the comple-
ment of any phrase would have to move to the edge of that phrase/phase, a movement
step that would count as too local under the version of 'anti-locality' that I entertain in
this paper. For this reason I refrain from using the term 'phase' in connection with the
conception of successive cyclicity argued for here.
Some Notes on Bounding 41
Based on such facts, Lasnik and Saito (1992) conclude that movement from
within one projection, more precisely for them, movement from SpecIP to the
IP-adjoined position, must be disallowed. To explain this, Murasugi and Saito
(1995) propose (8), which they argue is reducible to an economy guideline, viz.
the ban on superfluous steps (possibly related to Chomsky's (1986b) ban on
vacuous projections).
Boskovic (1994) (see also Boskovic (1997: 184, n28» argues that (8) has con-
siderable motivation. In particular, he notes that (8) rules out adjunction of X
to its own XP and substitution of X to SpecXP (situations that Chomsky
(1995: 321) referred to as 'self-attachment').
More recently, Kayne (2005) has independently proposed to rule out
movement of the complement of X to the specifier position of XP, and sug-
gests that this condition could be derived in feature-checking terms if upon
42 Cedric Boeckx
The desired result can be deduced from (8) if we take the label of X to be a
copy of X (Chomsky 2001, Har1ey 2004, Boeckx 2004). Accordingly, (8)
would forbid movement of V to I in (12a), since a copy of V (VP) is already in
a local relation with I (it is the complement of 1). By contrast, no such local
relation exists prior to V-movement in (12b), due to the presence of XP, which
renders movement possible.
In a similar vein, Abels (2003) notes that, though mobile in general, IFs may
not move and strand their selecting CPs.
(13) *Frank saw a play that «a play> was long and boring> yesterday
<a play> was long and boring
Likewise, Abels shows that, though mobile in principle (in some languages),
VPs never strand VD. Based on this, Abels proposes the following principle:
Given the requirement that domains called phases only allow movement of
their specifiers (not their complements) (see Chomsky (2000); the PlC in (7)
above), (16) in effect amounts to a version of (8); i.e., no phrase can be both
specifier and complement of the same head (Always: *[aP l3i [a ti]].
In sum, there seems to be good reasons to adopt some version of (8). Impor-
tantly, those reasons are independent of the fact that something like (8) is
needed to guarantee the adequacy of any version of a Takahashi-style ap-
Some Notes on Bounding 43
6 Grohmann embeds his ban on movement that is too short (lower bounds on movement) into a
theory of locality. This is clearly the most desirable move: bounding and locality should go hand
in hand.
7 Grohmann notes that just like movement that is "too long" can be "salvaged" (impressionisti-
cal1y speaking) by resumption (i), movement that is too short can, too. For justification of the
derivations in (ii), see Grohmann's own work.
(i) ? Which woman did you claim that Peter met the man who saw <whlch 'l.~ her
(ii) a. John [yp<John> likes-<Jelm> -+ himself]
b. [xpDiesen Mann, [xp <diesefl: MaBfl> -+ den kenne ich nicht] German
This.acc man that-one. ace know I not]
'This man, I don't know him'
For alternative views on resumption (including reflexivity) that don't require Grohmann's spe-
cific version of Anti-locality, but instead rely in agreement and case, see Boeckx (2003) and
Hornstein (2001), respectively.
44 Cedric Boeckx
5.1. Applicatives
The latter line of research has reached a conclusion that is puzzling at first.
McGinnis (2001) in particular has provided compelling empirical evidence
suggesting that languages employing the structure in (19) correspond to what
previous research had called symmetric languages, that is, languages that treat
both objects alike for a variety of syntactic purposes such as passivization, cli-
ticization, etc. British English is often described as one such language, on the
basis of (20).
(2004)); 10 always start off higher than DO, i.e., closer to T". What remains to
be explained is how DO can circumvent the intervening 10.
Ura (1996), McGinnis (1998, 2001) and Anagnostopoulou (2003) converge
on the idea that passivization of DO is rendered possible as a result of DO
moving to the edge of the projection hosting 10. Once that movement step has
taken place, DO is higher than 10 and can be passivized.
Note that this movement step must be blocked in so-called asymmetric lan-
guages, since these languages lack DO-passivization. J-E Lee (2004) (see also
Y Jeong (2004)) suggests an interesting way of doing precisely that. She as-
sumes that Ura, McGinnis, and Anagnostopoulou are correct in saying that
passivization of DO in a language that adopts (19) allows movement of DO to
the edge of the VP hosting 10. At that point, DO is higher than 10 and can be
passivized, as schematized in (22).
To prevent this derivation in languages making use of (18), J-E Lee appeals to
anti-locality to block movement of DO to the edge of the VP hosting 10. The
key factor here is that the VP hosting 10 also hosts DO. Since 'anti-locality'
considerations rule out movement of the complement of X to the specifier of
XP, DO cannot become higher than 10. Therefore, only 10 can be passivized,
as illustrated in (23)-(24).
Notice that J-E Lee's reasoning only goes through if anti-locality only applies
within one projection, not within a given domain, such as VP / vP, as in Groh-
mann (2000, 2003). If movement within vP (the thematic domain) were
banned, one would not be able to distinguish between symmetric and asym-
metric languages. In fact, Grohmann predicts all languages to be of the
asymmetric type, since the movement step that obviates minimality, 'Leap-
frogging' in McGinnis' terms, would violate Grohmann's notion of anti-
locality.
An argument similar to J-E Lee's can be made on the basis of psych verb
data, although this time, we'll see that the intervention-obviating step is fea-
ture-driven.
As is well-known, Belletti and Rizzi (1988) distinguish among three types of
46 Cedric Boeckx
The three verb classes are Subject Experiencer NP verbs like temere ('fear');
Object Experiencer verbs like preoccupare ('worry'), and verbs like piacere
('please'), which allow PP-Experiencer subjects.
Much attention has been devoted to ·Object-Experiencer verbs, in particular
to the backward binding facts like (28).
To account for such facts, Belletti and Rizzi argued that the subjects of object-
experiencer psych verbs start off as complements of V. This assumption al-
lowed for a straightforward account of "backward binding" facts. If (surface)
subjects of object-experiencer psych verbs start off as complements of V, the
(surface) object experiencer is able to bind the subject prior to movement (al-
ternatively, backward binding can be treated as a result of reconstruc-
tion/interpretation of the copy of the subject left by movement). The basic
derivation is given in (29).
(29) hP [rumors about herself]i T" fxp worrie<1j [ypMary [;, ti]]]]
To this day, Belletti and Rizzi's analysis of backward binding remains the con-
ceptually most appealing. 8
8 It has sometimes been suggested that the importance of the backward binding facts has
been overestimated. For example, Landau (2003) suggests that the binding examples are
instances of logophoric binding, which do not require the strict licensing conditions that
regular binding does. Landau's point may be correct for examples like (28a) (picture-NP
cases more generally), but it is hard to see how logophoricity could be involved in in-
stances of binding by universal or negative quantifiers (28b-c).
Some Notes on Bounding 47
Despite its conceptual appeal, Belletti and Rizzi's analysis was heavily criti-
cized, especially by Pesetsky (1995). The major criticism raised by Pesetsky is
that there are good reasons to believe that object experiencer psych-verbs are
not to be represented as unaccusative structures. The gist of Pesetsky's analysis
is that the surface subjects of object experiencer psych verbs behave themati-
cally like external arguments (causers).
Pesetsky offers several arguments in favor of this conclusion. Perhaps the
most compelling one is the fact that in contrast ot unaccusatives (30), Object
Experiencer verbs passivize (31).
According to (32), the surface subject starts off as the complement of V (where
it receives the target theta-role; see Pesetsky (1995: 58», a position that will
allow a Belletti-Rizzi style account of backward binding. On its way to SpecTP,
the subject stops by SpecvP and collects an external theta-role, which allows
Hornstein and Motomura to capture Pesetsky's results. (Horlli!tein and Mo-
tomura assume that the specifier and complement of the same projection are
equidistant, which allows rumors about herself to cross Mary on its way to
SpecvP without violating Minimality.)
A derivation like (32) is possible as soon as one allows for movement into
theta-position, an assumption that I will simply adopt here (for extensive dis-
cussion, see Hornstein (1999), Boeckx and Hornstein (2004) and references
therein).
As Hornstein and Motomura note, the intermediate step of movement tar-
geting SpecvP obviates the intervention effect of the experiencer for movement
to SpecTP. But the question now arises as to why the experiencer doesn't
block movement of the innermost object to SpecvP. (This question did not
48 Cedric Boeckx
9 Similarly, if we assume that PPs don't (match in features, hence don't) intervene (witness John
seems to Mary [t to be smart}]), movement of the innermost object in piacere class could proceed in
one fell swoop, as in (i).
(i) h1' DDi T" [~ V'- V; [vp PP-ID [~t;llJ]
This would explain why in the piacere verb class no agentivity is detected.
(I assume that when the PP-experiencer is in subject position, we are actually dealing not with a
genuine Pp, but with an NP associated with an overt case-marker. Put differently, the optionality
witnessed in the context of piacere-type verbs is the result of the ambiguous full preposition/case-
marker status of the a associated with the experiencer.)
Some Notes on Bounding 49
6. Conclusion
The double object and psych verbs data demand a notion of anti-locality
that confines the effect of the condition to a single projection (as opposed to
involving the notion of 'domam), something like (33).
Equivalently:
References
Boskovic, Zeljko. (1994). D-structure, 8-criterion, and movement into 8-positions. Lin-
guistic Analysis 24, 247-286.
Boskovic, Ze1jko. (1997). The Syntax of Non-finite Comp!ementation: An Economy Approach.
Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Boskovic, Zeljko. (2002). A-movement and the EPP. Syntax 5, 167-218.
Boskovic, Zeljko. (2005). On the locality of move and agree. Ms., University of Con-
necticut.
CastilIo, Juan Carlos, John Drury, and Kleanthes K. Grohmann. (1998). Merge-over-
move and the EPP. In University of Maryland Working Papers in Linguistics 8, 63-103.
University of Maryland, College Park.
Chomsky, Noam. (1973). Conditions on transformations. In AfestschrififOr Morris Halle, S.
Anderson and P. Kiparsky, eds., 232-286. New York: Holt, Rinehart, and Wmston.
Chomsky, Noam. (1986). Barriers. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Chomsky, Noam. (1995). The Minimalist Program. Cambridge, Mass.: MlT Press.
Chomsky, Noam. (2000). Minimalist inquiries: the framework. In Step by Step, R. Mar-
tin, D. Michaels and J. Uriagereka, eds., 89-155. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Chomsky, Noam. (2001). Derivation by phase. In Ken Hale: A Life in Language, M.
Kenstowicz, ed., 1-52. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Chomsky, Noam. (2004). Beyond explanatory adequacy. In Structures and Beyond, A.
Belletti, ed., 31. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Chomsky, Noam. (2005a). Three factors in language design. Linguistic Inquiry 36, 1-22.
Chomsky, Noam. (200Sb). On phases. Ms., MlT.
Chomsky, Noam and Howard Lasnik. (1993). Principles and parameters theory. In
Syntax: An International Handbook of Contemporary Research, J. Jacobs, A. von Ste-
chow, W Stemefeld and T. Vennemann, eds., 506-569. Berlin: de Gruyter.
Chung, Sandra and Carol Georgopoulos. (1988). Agreement with gaps in Chamorro
and Palauan. In Agreement in Natural Language: Approaches, Theories, and Description,
M. Barlowand C. A. Ferguson, eds., 251-267. Stanford, CaIi£: CSLI.
Davies, William. (2003). Extreme locality in Madurese wh-questions. Syntax 6, 237-259.
Finer, Dan L. (1997). Contrasting A-bar dependencies in Selayarese. Natural Language
and Linguistic Theory 15, 677-728.
Fox, Danny. (2000). Economy and Semantic Interpretation. Cambridge, Mass.: MlT Press.
Fox, Danny and Howard Lasnik. (2003). Successive-cyclic movement and island repair:
The difference between sluicing and VP-ellipsis. Linguistic Inquiry 34, 143-154.
Georgopoulos, Carol. (1991). Syntactic Variables: Resumptive Pronouns and Binding in Pa-
lauan. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Grohmann, Kleanthes K. (2000). Prolific Peripheries: A Radical View from the Left. Doc-
toral dissertation, University of Maryland.
Grohmann, Kleanthes K. (2003). Prolific Domains. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Harley, Heidy. (2004). Merge, conflation, and head movement: The first sister principle
revisited. In Proceedings of NELS 34, K. Moulton and M. Wolf, eds., University of
Massachusetts, Amherst: GLSA.
Some Notes on Bounding 51
Cedric Boeckx
Department of Linguistics
Boylston Hall, Thlrd Floor
Harvard University
Cambridge, MA 02138
USA
E-mail: [email protected]