Article On Liberalism
Article On Liberalism
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
This content downloaded from 147.8.31.43 on Thu, 08 May 2025 21:39:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
The Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 41 No. 165
ISSN 0031-8094 $2.00
BY SIMON CANEY
Many contemporary liberals claim that the state should be neutral between
competing conceptions of the good life.' Ronald Dworkin, for example,
asserts that 'political decisions must be ... independent of any particular
conception of the good life, or of what gives value to life'.2 Similarly John
Rawls argues that 'the state is not to do anything intended to favor or
promote any particular comprehensive doctrine rather than another, nor to
give greater assistance to those who pursue it'.3 This conclusion is shared
by many other liberal political philosophers like Ackerman, Feinberg,
Gutmann, Kymlicka, Larmore, Lloyd-Thomas, Rosenblum and
Waldron.4
In this article I examine a particular type of argument that has been
given in defence of neutrality, namely consequentialist arguments. Such
arguments are not stressed by Rawls and Dworkin but they are emphasized
by many other neutralist liberals. In particular I shall consider and
reject (1) Will Kymlicka's 'competitive-evolutionary' argument; (2) Joel
Feinberg and Bruce Ackerman's 'fallibility' argument; (3) Stephen Guest's
'best judge' argument; (4) Feinberg and von Humboldt's 'character
deterioration' argument; and (5) Ackerman's 'importance of doubt'
Exceptions include Joseph Raz, The Morality of Freedom (Oxford: Clarendon Press,
1986); Vinit Haksar, Equality, Liberty and Perfectionism (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1979).
2 Ronald Dworkin, 'Liberalism', A Matter of Principle (London: Harvard University
Press, 1985), p. 191.
3 John Rawls, 'The Priority of the Right and Ideas of the Good', Philosophy and Public
Affairs, 17 (1988), p. 262.
4 Bruce Ackerman, Social Justice in the Liberal State (New Haven, Connecticut: Yale
University Press, 1980), p. 11; Joel Feinberg, The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law, Volumes
1-4 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984, 1985, 1986, 1988); Amy Gutmann, 'Commun-
itarian Critics of Liberalism', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 15 (1985), p. 313: Will Kymlicka,
Liberalism, Community and Culture (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989), pp.76-85, pp.
95-7, p. 96 n.2; Charles Larmore, Patterns of Moral Complexity (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1987), ch. 3; David Lloyd-Thomas, In Defence of Liberalism (Oxford:
Blackwell, 1988), pp. 1-2: Nancy Rosenblum, 'Introduction', Liberalism and the Moral Life.
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989); Jeremy Waldron, 'Autonomy and Perfec-
tionism in Raz's Morality of Freedom', Southern California Law Review, 62 (1989).
This content downloaded from 147.8.31.43 on Thu, 08 May 2025 21:39:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
458 SIMON CANEY
argument. In addition, I evaluate (6) Ackerman and Lloyd-Thomas's
'experimentalist-consequentialist' argument; (7) Larmore, Gutmann and
Rosenblum's modus vivendi argument; and (8) Kymlicka's 'dictatorship of
the articulate' and 'distorted dialogue' arguments. What each of these
arguments has in common is the belief that a neutral state - one that
abstains from using propositions about the good life when making policy -
has better consequences than a perfectionist state.
I. CONCEPTIONS OF NEUTRALITY
Before we appraise the consequentialist defences of the claim that the state
should be neutral between competing conceptions of the good, we should,
however, clarify what exactly is meant by neutrality. In particular it is
worth distinguishing between:
5 See for example, Ackerman, Social Justice in the Liberal State, p. 11; Dworkin
'Liberalism'; Will Kymlicka, 'Liberal Individualism and Liberal Neutrality', Ethics, 99 (1989),
pp. 883-5; J. Rawls, A Theory of ustice (London: Oxford University Press, 1971), p. 332, and
'The Priority of the Right and Ideas of the Good', p. 262. See also the references given in
footnote 4 for further evidence that neutralists are committed to justificatory neutrality.
6 '"Lopp'd and Bound": How Liberal Theory Obscures the Goods of Liberal Practices',
in R. Bruce Douglass, Gerald M. Mara and Henry S. Richardson (eds), Liberalism and the Good
(London: Routledge, 1990), p. 174.
This content downloaded from 147.8.31.43 on Thu, 08 May 2025 21:39:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
CONSEQUENTIALIST DEFENCES OF LIBERAL NEUTRALITY 459
This content downloaded from 147.8.31.43 on Thu, 08 May 2025 21:39:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
460 SIMON CANEY
The claim then is that the truth concerning what lives are worthy flourishes
in, and only in, neutralist societies. It relies upon Millean and Hayekian
claims about the preconditions of the emergence and continued existence
of worthy forms of life. Competition in the cultural marketplace, it affirms,
will lead to 'the decline of the groups that have adhered to the wrong
beliefs'.?1 Neutrality is therefore justified from a consequentialist point of
view as being maximally conducive to the emergence and persistence of
ethically valuable conceptions of the good (and the disappearance of
worthless practices).
The chief problem with this argument lies in the assumption that
valuable forms when confronted with worthless forms will prevail.
Kymlicka simply assumes that the most convincing arguments and those
that attract the most adherents are in fact the most truthful, that 'satisfying
and valuable ways of life will tend to drive out those which are
unsatisfying'." But this confidence in cultural evolution is unwarranted
and we have no reason to think that the most valuable ideals always
triumph, and that truth defeats falsity. Many factors influence the survival
and success of forms of life quite apart from their merit - the
persuasiveness of practitioners of a form of life, peer-group pressure,
manipulation, ignorance, cost - and it is simply too naive to think that the
most marketable are the most valuable. Indeed, sometimes the allure of
worthless ways of life and the strenuous nature of some worthwhile forms
of life may lead to the former driving out the latter. Kymlicka's assumption
that the worthy will triumph over the valueless appears unduly sanguine.
10 F. A. Hayek, The Constitution of Liberty (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1960), p.
36.
" Kymlicka, Contemporary Political Philosophy, p. 219.
12 This argument, it is worth noting, is inconsistent with Ackerman's espousal of a
'sceptical' argument in defence of neutrality. In making this 'fallibility' argument and in
asserting that the state might oppress worthwhile practices and might make ethical errors,
Ackerman is assuming that there are worthwhile practices and justified ethical values. This
assumption is, however, incompatible with his claim elsewhere that there is no ethical truth
(Social Justice in the Liberal State, pp. 11, 386, 369; and 'What is Neutral About Neutrality?',
Ethics, 93 (1983), p. 387).
This content downloaded from 147.8.31.43 on Thu, 08 May 2025 21:39:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
CONSEQUENTIALIST DEFENCES OF LIBERAL NEUTRALITY 461
(1) The state might make mistakes about the good life.'3 This is
because:
(a) politicians, like anyone else, are fallible. So even a
thoughtful well-intentioned statesman may promote policies
which are ethically disastrous;
(b) the experience of powers corrupts and thus politicians are
likely to be less interested in the promotion of what is good
than in their own self-aggrandizement;'4
(c) even if the politician is able to discern ethical worth and
wishes to promote ethical worth the state might still make
mistakes about the good because bureaucrats have a tendency
to influence policy to their own interest.15
(2) If the state might make mistakes about the good life, then it
should not promote any conceptions of the good life.16
(3) Therefore the state should not promote any conceptions of the
good life. It should remain neutral between competing
conceptions of the good life.1
The problem with this argument is, however, that it is too strong. It is also
true that the state might make mistakes about the right and justice: but this
does not lead neutralists to conclude that the state should not promote
justice and rights. There are a great variety of conceptions of justice
(ranging from Nozick's libertarianism to Rawls's two principles; from
Hayek's theory that the market is neither just nor unjust to Dworkin's
claim that justice demands equality of resources) and it is possible that the
state will not select the right one out of all of these. Given this diversity, the
state might make a mistake, and there seems to be no reason to think that
the state is less likely to make a mistake concerning the right as it will
concerning the good. All the factors listed in premise (1) apply to a state
that is required to institute principles of social justice. But then if this is
true, neutralists ought to conclude - if premise (2) is correct - that the state
13 Joel Feinberg, The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law, Volume 4: Harmless Wrongdoing
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1988), pp. 310-11.
14 Ackerman, Social Justice in the Liberal State, pp. 12, 362; 'What is Neutral About
Neutrality?', p. 387.
15 Ackerman, Social Justice in the Liberal State, p. 363.
16 Ackerman, Social Justice in the Liberal State, p. 369; Feinberg, The Moral Limits of the
Criminal Law, Volume 4: Harmless Wrongdoing, pp. 286, 311.
17 Ackerman Social Justice in the Liberal State, p. 369; Feinberg, The Moral Limits of the
Criminal Law, Volume 4: Harmless Wrongdoing. pp. xx, and 311.
This content downloaded from 147.8.31.43 on Thu, 08 May 2025 21:39:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
462 SIMON CANEY
should abstain from instituting principles of justice. Or, they must explain
why, on the one hand, the fact that the state might make mistakes over the
right does not entail that it should abstain from instituting the right, while,
on the other hand, that fact that the state might make mistakes over the
good does entail that it should abstain from instituting the good. Why this
asymmetry between the right and the good? Neutralists thus face a
dilemma:
either: the fact that the state might make a mistake X-ing entails that it
should not X, in which case neutralists must accept that the state should
not institute principles of justice - a wildly counterintuitive claim that no
neutralist would wish to endorse;
or: the fact that the state might make a mistake X-ing does not entail that
it should not X, in which case the fact that the state might make a mistake in
instituting principles of the good does not entail that the state should not
promote the good life.
A further problem with the 'fallibility' argument should be noted. The
argument asserts, recall, that because a perfectionist state might act in a way
which damages the well-being of its citizens, therefore the state should
eschew perfectionism. The central point is that there are costs to a state that
tries to promote worthwhile lives. But this is unpersuasive because an
analogous point may be made against a neutral state. This arises from the
fact that Ackerman and Feinberg claim only that the state might make
mistakes about the good life. In doing so they recognize the possibility that
the state might get it right. They do not say that the state will always get it
wrong - this would indeed be an unbelievably pessimistic assumption.'8
But if the state can make good decisions about the good life, then there are
clearly costs to a neutral state. In those cases where it can discern
worthwhile forms of life, and could therefore improve its citizens' lives by
promoting those valuable conceptions of the good, to take a neutral stance
clearly hampers the well-being of its citizens. The fact that a perfectionist
state might act in a way that damages the well-being of its citizens does not
therefore support a neutral state because it is true of a neutral state that it
too might act in a way that hampered the well-being of its citizens.
Feinberg and Ackerman's 'fallibility argument' against perfectionism
thus fails. It is, of course, relevant that the state might make mistakes, but
the correct conclusion is not that the state should abstain from perfectionist
policies, rather that one should guard as diligently as possible against
abuse. Moreover, Feinberg and Ackerman's point fails to engage with
perfectionists who think that the state ought to promote well-being - not
just what politicians think well-being involves. Perfectionists assert not that
the state may promote what its officials think are important conceptions of
This content downloaded from 147.8.31.43 on Thu, 08 May 2025 21:39:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
CONSEQUENTIALIST DEFENCES OF LIBERAL NEUTRALITY 463
the good (even if they are wrong), just that they should promote what is
good. So the state feared by Feinberg and Ackerman in which the state
makes calamitous decisions about the good would also be one feared by
perfectionists like Plato, Aristotle and Raz.
This content downloaded from 147.8.31.43 on Thu, 08 May 2025 21:39:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
464 SIMON CANEY
therefore, overcome the epistemological shortcomings of individuals by
subsidizing and advertising valuable ways of life which will otherwise be
overlooked. Indeed, if it is true that individuals are the best judges of their
own ethical interests - in the sense that when confronted with a valuable
option they will choose it - this supports rather than undermines such non-
coercive perfectionism. The recognition of the ability of individuals to
discern value combined with the realization that individuals often lack
adequate information thus commits us not to neutrality but to a
perfectionist state committed to introducing people to valuable modes of
life which they would not otherwise encounter.21 (If they were poor
choosers and unlikely to choose ethically worthwhile conceptions of the
good, then there would be no point in putting a valuable option before
them.)
(b) evaluative problems: second, even if we grant individuals perfect
knowledge of all worthy options, it is still questionable whether they will
always be better judges of their own interests than the state. This
contention is supported by several reasons. (i) One reason given in support
of the claim that individuals always know their ethical interests best can be
seen to be unfounded. Mill thought that individuals (given adequate
knowledge) were always the best judges of their own interests because each
individual had a unique essence, an individual quiddity utterly distinct
from others' personalities. But as communitarians have rightly reminded
us, individuals are shaped by their communities, and hence one can, by
drawing on our knowledge of the interests of others, make a reasonable
assessment of an individual's ethical interests.22 Our commonality means
that individuals do not have a privileged access to their own well-being and,
therefore, there are some occasions in which others know what is better for
them. (ii) This conclusion is strengthened by the observation that
individuals are notoriously bad at making probabilistic assessments. As
Robert Goodin notes, individuals 'are liable to all sorts of biases, in
assessing such probabilities, growing out of judgemental short-cuts that are
now well-mapped by psychologists and decision theorists. Perhaps the
most worrisome is the tendency to assume "it will never happen to me",
even when the odds are decisively against that proposition'.23 (iii) Third,
people often suffer from temporal problems and there are occasions in
which we irrationally prefer a lesser present good to a far greater future
21 Such non-coercive action is incompatible with justificatory neutrality because the state is
making policy on the basis that some conceptions of the good are superior to others. It supports some
conceptions of the good on the basis that they are valuable (reading Zola) and avoids supporting
other less valuable conceptions (like pornography say) precisely because they are less valuable.
22 For a further disucssion of this point see my 'Liberalism and Communitarianism: A
Misconceived Debate', Political Studies (1992).
23 Robert Goodin, 'Liberalism and the Best-Judge Principle', Political Studies, XXXVIII
(1990), p. 189.
This content downloaded from 147.8.31.43 on Thu, 08 May 2025 21:39:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
CONSEQUENTIALIST DEFENCES OF LIBERAL NEUTRALITY 465
24 Like those who present this argument I assume here that a person's interests can be
defined independently of his or her current conception of those interests. See Mill, On Liberty,
Collected Works, Volume XVIII (Toronto: University of Toronto, 1977) pp. 215, 261, and ch.
IV. Good reasons for doing so are given by James Griffin in Well-Being: Its Meaning,
Measurement and Moral Importance (Oxford: Clarendon, 1986), pp. 7-17.
25 They might of course suffer from a prisoner's dilemma in which case the optimal result
will also not be achieved.
This content downloaded from 147.8.31.43 on Thu, 08 May 2025 21:39:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
466 SIMON CANEY
X-ing.26 He argues that, if the state intervenes in the interest of the
individual in one area, then the individual will become increasingly
dependent on the state for guidance in other areas. He will not judge
matters for himself, will not evaluate his options, nor create new ones
because he knows that the state will come to his assistance. Thus the
consequence of any form of perfectionism is the deterioration of the
character of the individual, and perfectionism generates a tendency for
individuals to become even worse judges of their own ethical interests.
Moreover, von Humboldt argues, this is as true of non-coercive measures
as it is of coercive brands of perfectionism.27 Both undermine a person's
ability to think for himself. Thus a neutral state would have better
consequences than a perfectionist state in the sense that it will not engender
this apathy, dependence and inability to judge one's own interests.
These considerations do, I think, provide some support for a general
commitment to liberty. They do not, however, generate a wholesale
commitment to neutrality. First, von Humboldt's argument, while it has
some force against coercive perfectionism, seems implausible as a critique
of non-coercive perfectionism. It is perhaps true that, if the state judges in
one area (sexual relations, for example) that the individual's judgement is
wrong, then that individual will lack confidence in his judgement in other
areas too and will defer to the state. The ability of the state to make
judgements on behalf of the individual may, it is true, lead to a
deterioration in a person's general character. But when the state subsidizes
several forms of life on the grounds that they are worthwhile, it does not
make a judgement on the individual's behalf but makes other options
available. So a state that non-coercively promotes worthwhile activities
does not usurp the role of the individual and does not therefore lead to the
deterioration of his character. The individual still has to make a choice and
hence the state's actions are unlikely to encourage him to rely upon the
state's judgement. Non-coercive perfectionism does not make an in-
dividual's decision for him and hence von Humboldt's argument that a
perfectionist state, in making the individual's decision for him, encourages
a worsening of his deliberative powers is false.28
26 See also Mill, On Liberty, p. 305; Joel Feinberg, 'The Interest in Liberty on the Scales',
Rights, Justice and the Bounds of Liberty: Essays in Social Philosophy (Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 1980); and Feinberg, The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law, Volume 1: Harm
to Others (1984), p. 211.
27 Von Humboldt explicitly makes this point in The Sphere and Duties of Government
(London: John Chapman, 1854), pp. 18, 20-1,44-5, 65-7, 71. Thus he writes: 'however it may
accomplish this, - whether directly or indirectly by law, or by means of authority, rewards, and
other encouragements attractive to the citizen - or lastly, by merely recommending its
propositions to his attention by arguments, - it will always deviate very far from the best
method of instruction' (The Sphere and Duties of Government, p. 24).
28 Linked to this is von Humboldt's false assumption that perfectionists are necessarily
This content downloaded from 147.8.31.43 on Thu, 08 May 2025 21:39:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
CONSEQUENTIALIST DEFENCES OF LIBERAL NEUTRALITY 467
Second, it may often be the case that a neutral state rather than a
perfectionist state will lead to character deterioration. Thus one might
argue as follows:
monists who reject moral pluralism. He does not therefore distinguish between
monistic perfectionism: there is a single correct conception of the good and it is the duty of the
state to promote this good,
and
pluralistic perfectionism: there is no single correct conception of the good and there are many
worthy ways of living. It is the duty of the state to promote these various diverse ways of life.
29 See his Principles of Political Economy, Collected Works, Volumes II and III (Toronto:
University of Toronto, 1965), Book V, ch. XI, ?8.
This content downloaded from 147.8.31.43 on Thu, 08 May 2025 21:39:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
468 SIMON CANEY
A life can only go well, he claims, if individuals have the possibility of
making mistakes and this requires in turn that the state does not ban
unworthy forms of life.30 The argument at work is analogous to the
theological argument that persons were given freewill to do both good and
evil because without the possibility of evil one cannot be truly good.
Genuine goodness requires the possibility that one has the possibility to do
wrong but in fact one rejects the evil option. Similarly, Ackerman argues,
genuine ethical worth requires that one is open to doubt and that one
therefore chooses worthy options for the right reasons. This requires in
turn that the state desist from banning worthless options - hence neutrality
is justified. No form of the good life should be banned on the grounds that it
is unworthy because even unworthy conceptions of the good serve a role.
Thus the state should be neutral between conceptions of the good.
The limitations of this argument are, however, clear. First, it has no
force against a state that non-coercively promotes valuable forms of life,
and even if the existence of unworthy options serves a useful function, this
entails only that the state should allow sufficient numbers of worthless
options to exist. The argument will at most show that the state should
not ban unworthy options - it is inapplicable as an argument against
encouraging certain ways of life on the grounds that they are valuable.
Second, it does not entail a complete ban on coercive perfectionism.
What it dictates is that there should be a sufficient number of unworthy
options to contest the worthy options and that the elimination of a single
unworthy option may still leave plenty of other unworthy options.
Consider a case where an agent has the choice between worthy options, a, b,
c, d, and also the unworthy options e, f, g, h, i, j and k. Now, even if the
existence of some valueless options serves some role, it is difficult to see why
the state cannot eliminate one worthless option. After all, the agent in
question will still be able to adopt six worthless options. In other words,
even if the agent should be presented with some valueless conceptions of
the good, this does not entail that he should face an unlimited set of bad
conceptions of the good.
A more radical defect in Ackerman's argument is that the intuition
underlying the argument (and which gives the argument the plausibility it
possesses) does not seem to support Ackerman's conclusion. Ackerman and
Mill's intuition seems to be this: to live a valuable life it must be true that
(i) the actions one performs and the ideals one professes are
worthy;
30 See Ackerman 'What is Neutral About Neutrality?', p. 387; and Social Justice in the
Liberal State, pp. 365-7.
This content downloaded from 147.8.31.43 on Thu, 08 May 2025 21:39:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
CONSEQUENTIALIST DEFENCES OF LIBERAL NEUTRALITY 469
(ii) one values the ideals one performs and the ideals one professes
for the right reasons (and not simply out of habit or
socialization), where one believes something for the right
reasons when one is aware of other ideals and where one
critically evaluates them and makes one's decision on the basis
of an assessment of the comparative merits of several options.
(iii) In order to believe something for the right reasons one must be
confronted with unworthy options.
But (iii) does not follow from (ii). What follows from (ii) and the emphasis
on making a deliberated choice is that one reject other options. It does not
entail that these be unworthy. This means that the requisite deliberation
could be attained by an agent who is faced by a plurality of valuable but
incompatible and competing ideals. The existence of worthless options, as
such, is not necessary for the right-reasoned choice that Ackerman and Mill
emphasize.
Ackerman's 'necessity of error and importance of doubt' argument thus
fails to justify neutrality because (i) it is inapplicable with respect to non-
coercive perfectionism; (ii) it does not entail a complete ban on coercive
perfectionism; and (iii) the existence of unworthy options is not a
precondition of a right-reasoned choice.
This content downloaded from 147.8.31.43 on Thu, 08 May 2025 21:39:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
470 SIMON CANEY
"modes of existence".'33 Or, as Ackerman puts it, 'you can
only learn anything true about the good when you are free to
experiment'.34
(3) Therefore the state ought to ensure that the conditions for
experimenting with different forms of life exist (by (1) and (2)).
(4) Only a neutral state can ensure that the conditions for
experimentation with different forms of life are satisfied -
'liberal rights are conditions for having more reasonable views
about what activities are worth while'.35 It alone is 'favourable
to experimentation with new modes of existence'.36
(5) Therefore the state ought to be neutral between conceptions of
the good life (by (3) and (4)).37
(2a) It is true of many forms of life that we can only know if they
are good if we experiment with them.
Thus adapted, the second premise eschews the claim that experimentation
is a necessary precondition of living every good life, but recognizes that in
This content downloaded from 147.8.31.43 on Thu, 08 May 2025 21:39:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
CONSEQUENTIALIST DEFENCES OF LIBERAL NEUTRALITY 471
38 See Larmore's 'Review of Liberalism and the Limits of Justice', Journal of Philosophy, 80
This content downloaded from 147.8.31.43 on Thu, 08 May 2025 21:39:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
472 SIMON CANEY
stated the argument is as follows:
(1983), and Patterns of Moral Complexity. See too Gutmann, 'Communitarian Critics of
Liberalism', p. 313; Rosenblum, 'Introduction' to Liberalism and the Good Life (Cambridge
Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1989), p. 6. According to Chandran Kukathas the same
argument is given by Hayek (Hayek and Modern Liberalism (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1989), p. 222, and pp. 226-7).
39 Larmore, Patterns of Moral Complexity, p. 60.
0 Rosenblum, Liberalism and the Good Life, p. 6.
41 Larmore, Patterns of Moral Complexity, p. 74.
42 In Britain, for example, the state is quite clearly perfectionist and it overtly supports the
Church of England, and makes legislation on the grounds that homosexuality and lesbianism
are less valuable than heterosexuality. Moreover, the late Greater London Council and the
present London boroughs have clearly constructed policy on the basis of the worth of some
unorthodox forms of life.
43 These four countries each possesses a state which makes policy on the basis that
Catholicism is true and hence each takes a distinctively Catholic approach to issues of abortion
and divorce.
This content downloaded from 147.8.31.43 on Thu, 08 May 2025 21:39:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
CONSEQUENTIALIST DEFENCES OF LIBERAL NEUTRALITY 473
4 Recently, Larmore has assumed that a state is not perfectionist even if it promotes a
conception of the good, if that conception of the good is noncontroversial ('Political
Liberalism', Political Theory, 18 (1990), p. 358, n.3). But this definition of neutrality is
radically at odds with Rawls, Dworkin, Ackerman, Kymlicka and all other neutralists'
conception of neutrality. See for example, Ackerman, Social Justice in the Liberal State, p. 11;
Kymlicka, 'Liberal Individualism and Liberal Neutrality', pp. 883-5; Dworkin 'Liberalism';
Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 332, and 'The Priority of the Right and Ideas of the Good', p.
262. All the latter state that the state should not make policy on the basis of some conception of
the good, no matter how widely shared that good is.
This content downloaded from 147.8.31.43 on Thu, 08 May 2025 21:39:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
474 SIMON CANEY
IX: THE 'DICTATORSHIP' AND 'DIALOGUE' ARGUMENTS
Neutrality is not therefore necessary for civil peace. Before we reject all
consequentialist defences of neutrality we ought to consider two final
consequentialist arguments given by Will Kymlicka in defence of
justificatory neutrality - what might be called the 'dictatorship of the ar-
ticulate' and the 'distorted dialogue' arguments. Kymlicka relies upon
these to show that 'state perfectionism would have undesirable con-
sequences for our society'.45 His arguments are as follows:
This content downloaded from 147.8.31.43 on Thu, 08 May 2025 21:39:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
CONSEQUENTIALIST DEFENCES OF LIBERAL NEUTRALITY 475
But while this might show the problems faced by majoritarian per-
fectionists, it fails to show why one cannot have non-majoritarian
" Robert Goodin provides empirical support of how inarticulacy of certain minorities
results from unjust educational institutions and draws on the work of Paulo Freire and Basil
Bernstein. See R. Goodin, Manipulatory Politics (London: Yale University Press, 1980), pp.
77-81.
49 Kymlicka, 'Liberal Individualism and Liberal Neutrality', p. 900.
'" Kymlicka, 'Liberal Individualism and Liberal Neutrality', p. 901.
This content downloaded from 147.8.31.43 on Thu, 08 May 2025 21:39:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
476 SIMON CANEY
perfectionism. Kymlicka considers this but argues that the only other
alternative is to put policy-making power in the hands of an unaccount-
able elite - an option that is hardly attractive. But this overlooks other
possibilities which avoid the problems of unaccountable elites and
majoritarian biases. One might, for example, argue that state subsidies
devoted to supporting worthy forms of life should be allocated on a
consociational process where a decision is passed only if it is supported by
all of the cultural communities. Were state subsidies for valuable forms of
life to be allocated according to a principle of unanimity or two-thirds
majority, a dominant group would only be able to allocate money to itself
with the consent of a minority. Thus the minority will be able to bargain for
funds for its way of life. This, in fact, is the institutional system adopted in
many countries which include several minorities.51 One does not have to
enunciate the finer details of the correct institutional system required to
see, then, that there are non-majoritarian and non-elitist forms of
perfectionism which may overcome the problem of distorted dialogue.
In short, the worries Kymlicka raises are important ones and any
perfectionist should take them into account, but they do not entail a
complete repudiation of perfectionism. Caution, not abstinence, is the
conclusion entailed by Kymlicka's arguments.
X. CONCLUSION
This brings us to the end of the review of consequentialist arguments for
neutrality, and we have seen that the consequentialist project has failed to
defend neutrality. The competition between ideals in a neutral state is not
guaranteed to generate the establishment of the most valuable practices.
Nor is the fallibility of those with power itself a reason to eschew neutrality.
In addition, it is questionable whether neutrality can be justified either on
the grounds that unworthy conceptions serve an important function or on
the basis that individuals are always better judges of their interests than the
state. And it is questionable whether perfectionism leads to a withering of
our deliberative powers. Furthermore, our interest in acquiring well-
founded views about the good life, even if it requires experimentation, does
not entail neutrality and certainly does not support a ban on non-coercive
perfectionism. Finally, the more pragmatic arguments also fail to justify
51 See Arend Lijphart's Democracy in Plural Societies (London: Yale University Press,
1977), in particular pp. 25-103; Arend Lijphart, The Politics of Accommodation (Berkeley:
University of California Press, 1968); Ronald Rogowski, Rational Legitimacy: A Theory of
Political Support (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1974), pp. 77-142. In fact British
experience has shown that one can have a perfectionist state which is not biased towards
majority conceptions of the good. The Greater London Council, for example, was notorious for
subsidizing otherwise disadvantaged ways of life.
This content downloaded from 147.8.31.43 on Thu, 08 May 2025 21:39:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
CONSEQUENTIALIST DEFENCES OF LIBERAL NEUTRALITY 477
52 The first six arguments addressed in this article, recall, all claimed that a neutral state is
preferable to a perfectionist state because it best enabled individuals to lead valuable lives.
53 I would like to thank G. A. Cohen, David Miller, an anonymous referee and the Editorial
Chairman for their helpful comments.
This content downloaded from 147.8.31.43 on Thu, 08 May 2025 21:39:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms