Giambattista Vico, an influential philosopher from Naples, emphasized the importance of human creativity in understanding truth and history, challenging Cartesian views. His major work, The New Science, posits that history is shaped by human consciousness and societal constructs. Vico's ideas laid the groundwork for later thinkers like Hegel, Ranke, Croce, and Collingwood, who further explored the relationship between history, philosophy, and human agency.
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0 ratings0% found this document useful (0 votes)
21 views25 pages
Meth Ods
Giambattista Vico, an influential philosopher from Naples, emphasized the importance of human creativity in understanding truth and history, challenging Cartesian views. His major work, The New Science, posits that history is shaped by human consciousness and societal constructs. Vico's ideas laid the groundwork for later thinkers like Hegel, Ranke, Croce, and Collingwood, who further explored the relationship between history, philosophy, and human agency.
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 25
Giambattista Vico was born in Naples, Italy,
to a bookseller and the daughter of a
carriage maker. Due to poor health and dissatisfaction with Jesuit education, he was home-schooled. After recovering from typhus in 1686, he worked as a tutor in Vatolla for nine years. In 1699, he married Teresa Destito and became a professor of rhetoric at the University of Naples. Despite his ambition, he never secured a chair in jurisprudence. In 1734, he was appointed royal historiographer by King Charles III, receiving a higher salary. He held his rhetoric position until retiring in 1741 due to illness. On the Study Methods of Our Time (1709) – educational and philosophical tract On the Most Ancient Wisdom of the Italians (1711) – philosophical investigation The Deeds of Antonio Carafa (1716) – historical biography Universal Right (1722) – study of Roman law The New Science (Scienza Nuova, 1725) – his most influential work; revised in 1730 and 1744 Autobiography (1728) – narrative of his intellectual life Vico's verum factum principle, introduced in 1710, asserts that truth is known through creation or invention, not merely through observation, challenging Descartes’ view. He claimed, “the true is the made,” meaning we truly understand something only if we have made it. This idea became central in his major work The New Science (1725), where he argued that human society and history, like mathematics, are constructed by human beings and can thus be truly understood. Humanist and Pedagogic Concerns Role as Royal Professor of Latin Eloquence Critique of Modern Rhetoric Vico’s Rhetorical Framework The Orator’s Role Influence of Classical Tradition Vico argued that the realms of verifiable truth and human concerns only overlap slightly, but reasoning is essential in both. He criticized the application of Cartesian method to practical life, likening it to trying to apply rigid rules of reason to the complexities of human affairs, which are governed by chance, opportunity, and unpredictability. He also contended that applying Cartesian principles to political speech would strip it of depth, reducing it to dull arguments. Establishes the “principles of humanity” and a theory of societal origins and evolution. Proposes an ideal eternal history of nations, emphasizing the human consciousness as the driving force of history. Argues that history is shaped by human consciousness, with its certainty linked to the creator of events narrating them. Influenced Croce and Collingwood, who viewed historiography as reenacting historical actions. Inspired Marx, who appreciated Vico’s focus on collective mentalities and the role of shared beliefs in history. Vico’s emphasis on creativity and narrative in historiography deeply influenced the way historians approach the past. Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel (1770–1831) was a German philosopher central to German Idealism, whose work significantly shaped European philosophy, Continental philosophy, and Marxism. His philosophy is based on absolute idealism, where mind or spirit evolves through contradictions and oppositions that are reconciled. Key concepts like dialectics, Geist (spirit), negativity, sublation, and the Master/Slave dialectic have influenced thinkers such as Marx, Nietzsche, phenomenologists, and existentialists. Hegel's work remains a major influence on contemporary philosophy, with philosophers like Michel Foucault recognizing his impact. Hegel's interest in history, influenced by his classical education, the French Revolution, and German Idealism, led him to develop a nuanced analysis of historical events, particularly the French Revolution. While he supported the ideals of the Revolution, he opposed its excesses, especially the terror. In his Phenomenology and Lectures on the Philosophy of History, Hegel examines the Revolution through the lens of Enlightenment thought, emphasizing the conflict between faith and reason, and the tension between individual and universal consciousness. Hegel’s Philosophy of History presents a unique perspective on historiography, in which he outlines different forms of history writing: Original Historiography: Contemporary accounts written by historians who were witnesses to the events they describe. Reflective Historiography: Focuses on the past, divided into: Universal Historiography: Synthesizes the history of a people, country, or the world. Pragmatic Historiography: Unifies historical events through a general idea. Critical or Scientific Historiography: Evaluates the authenticity and credibility of historical narratives. Specialized Historiography: Focuses on a particular perspective or area, such as art, law, or religion. Philosophical Historiography: Applies thought to history, viewing history as a rational process governed by reason. Hegel's approach to history builds on Aristotle's idea that human action is goal-directed (teleological) and rational. He contends that history, as the record of human actions, is rational and can be understood. However, history is not transparent. It involves both reason and passion, with ordinary individuals pursuing personal aims, while world-historical individuals are driven by deeper, universal goals. Hegel introduces the "cunning of reason," where these individuals, though pursuing personal passions, unknowingly contribute to broader historical ends. Hegel's philosophy of knowledge centers on the idea that knowledge is historical, evolving through human practices within social contexts. Building on Kant’s constructivism, Hegel argues that knowledge arises not from representing a mind-independent world but from understanding the world as it is experienced. He views knowledge as a process of trial and error, where concepts are compared to experience, and theories are revised when discrepancies arise. In his Phenomenology of Spirit, Hegel rejects the notion of directly grasping an objective reality, focusing instead on how knowledge evolves through historical processes and changing conceptual frameworks. Leopold Ranke is considered the founder of modern scientific historiography, emphasizing the critical study of sources to uncover the true history and discredit distortions. His work focused on European history from the sixteenth to eighteenth centuries, and he established the “historical seminar” to train students in his method. Ranke opposed speculative philosophers like Hegel, who saw history as a rational process to be understood philosophically, instead seeking to determine "what really had happened" through factual evidence. His scientific approach to history emphasized four key principles: objectivity, the primacy of facts, the uniqueness of historical events, and the centrality of politics. Objectivity: Historians should avoid moralizing or instructing the present; their role is to show "what actually happened" without subjective interference. Primacy of facts: Historians must focus on presenting events as they occurred, based on evidence, and avoid abstract theories or philosophical speculation. Uniqueness of historical events: Each historical event, epoch, or process is unique and should be understood in its own context, without being subordinated to larger philosophical narratives like progress. Centrality of politics: Ranke's historiography primarily focused on politics and states, viewing them as the central units of historical analysis, though social and economic factors were also considered in their political context. Leopold Ranke's historiography rejected the philosophical systems of Hegel and Fichte, focusing instead on understanding what truly happened in history, without moral or philosophical judgments. He emphasized the uniqueness of each historical event and figure, opposing the idea of reducing history to rational patterns or laws. Ranke's approach was grounded in source analysis but also acknowledged a divine purpose in history, although less systematically than the philosophers. Later in life, he became more open to the idea of a developmental totality in history, viewing past and present as interconnected, with divine governance shaping human destiny. His philosophy of history was evolving and not systematic, reflecting his views on history's continuity and purpose. Ranke saw history’s continuity as essential both for scholarly inquiry and political stability, opposing liberal reforms that ignored historical context. He believed that history could reveal the trends and ideas of different eras, offering insights for political decisions rooted in the complexities of the past. For Ranke, historiography was a means of reconciling contradictions in human nature and society, connecting the particular with the universal. His work sought to integrate national histories with universal ones, viewing history as a continuous process. Ranke argued that historians should focus on the actual events and their spiritual significance, without applying philosophical or theoretical Benedetto Croce and Robin George Collingwood were influential philosophers who focused on history and historiography, shaping areas like moral, social, and political philosophy. They built on a tradition from thinkers like Vico, Kant, and Hegel, but uniquely placed reason in individual human actions, asserting that history is shaped by liberty and freedom. For both, historiography was not just theoretical but had practical significance, influencing present possibilities and guiding future actions. Croce saw historiography as preparing for action, while Collingwood viewed it as shaping choices and actions. Despite shared philosophical connections, their ideas should be understood separately. Viewed history as a cycle of aesthetic, logical, practical, and ethical activities of the mind. Believed historiography combines intuition from art and logic from philosophy. Emphasized that all knowledge and action are rooted in history. Advocated "absolute historicism," rejecting abstract concepts outside of history (e.g., determinism). Saw historiography as a tool to help individuals confront reality and make informed decisions. Viewed history as a product of human action and choice, with an evolving concept of mind and morality. Believed historiography was essential for understanding human actions and making rational decisions. Linked moral choices to duty, not utility or rules. Argued that historiography provides insight into the historical context of actions. Believed understanding history is crucial for self-knowledge, understanding others, and making ethical and political decisions. Saw historiography as a key tool for diagnosing moral and political issues through insight into human action. Emphasized the importance of textual interpretation and memory in historiography. Argued that "all true history is contemporary history," meaning history is always linked to the present and must resonate with the historian's mind. Believed history involves critically engaging with documents and interpreting them. Argued that moral-political action, particularly liberty, drives and shapes history, providing explanations for historical events. Believed historiography should be based on reason and inference rather than external facts. Argued that historical knowledge is gained through interpreting evidence, connecting actions, and constructing coherent narratives. Developed the theory of re-enactment, where historians recreate the thoughts and reasoning of historical agents. Emphasized reason over empathy or intuition in understanding historical actions. Stressed that historiographic narratives should explain the human past through the actions and reasoning of historical agents. Believed these narratives must be open to criticism and revision. Both thinkers connected history and historiography to contemporary concerns and political significance. Rejected formal or speculative approaches to history. Focused on history as the realm of moral acts and choices. Believed history is shaped by moral agency. Emphasized liberty as the driving force behind history, particularly in 19th-century Europe. Argued that when liberty is detached from its moral roots, it leads to misguided pursuits of power Focused on the political and social implications of liberalism and its potential distortions. Rejected the distinction between theory and practice in history. Argued that history is understood from within, as people are both the creators and subjects of history. Linked society’s development to free will, seeing civilization as a process of people coming together through common actions. Emphasized that civilization is not just about following rules but is built on free choice and understanding, especially through education and art. Believed that a society that understands its history and embraces historiographic thought can more effectively address its moral and political issues. Croce and Collingwood's philosophies of history and historiography center on the activity of reason, positioning historiography as a fundamental aspect of philosophy. Croce presented a unified account of mind with history at its core, while Collingwood developed a more critical approach, emphasizing the understanding of history both as a subject and an object. Both thinkers rejected speculative philosophies of history and moralizing approaches that treat history as a guide to ethics. Their perspectives differ from later analytical philosophies of historiography, which tend to be more theoretical and neutral in significance. Instead, Croce and Collingwood's views incorporate metaphysical and substantive elements that challenge scientism. They placed historiography at the heart of philosophical thought, contrasting with later thinkers who saw the philosophy of history as a discrete, theoretical field.