Using Math in Physics - Overview
Using Math in Physics - Overview
Edward F. Redish
Abstract
The key difference between math as math and math in science is that in science we blend our physical
knowledge with our knowledge of math. This blending changes the way we put meaning to math and
even to the way we interpret mathematical equations. Learning to think about physics with math instead
of just calculating involves a number of general scientific thinking skills that are often taken for granted
(and rarely taught) in physics classes. In this paper, I give an overview of my analysis of these
additional skills. I propose specific tools for helping students develop these skills in subsequent papers.
9/24/20 1 Using math in physics: Overview Edward F. Redish, University of Maryland - emeritus,
College Park, MD The key difference between math as math and math in science is that in science we
blend our physical knowledge with our knowledge of math. This blending changes the way we put
meaning to math and even to the way we interpret mathematical equations. Learning to think about
physics with math instead of just calculating involves a number of general scientific thinking skills that
are often taken for granted (and rarely taught) in physics classes. In this paper, I give an overview of my
analysis of these additional skills. I propose specific tools for helping students develop these skills in
subsequent papers. Many of the ideas and methods I’m discussing here were developed in the context
of studying introductory physics with life science students — first, in algebra-based physics and then in
NEXUS/Physics, an introductory physics course designed specifically for life science majors. Students
in these classes often struggle with the idea that symbolic quantities in science represent physical
measurements rather than numbers and that equations represent relationships rather than ways to
calculate. Math in science is different from math in math. In science, symbols stand for a blend — a
mental combination of physical knowledge with knowledge of how a mathematical element such as a
variable or constant behaves. This changes the way we think about and use equations. For example,
when we define the electric field as ■ = ■/■ we have in mind that ■ is not just an arbitrary variable but
the specific electric force felt by the test charge ■, a conceptual blend of physics and math. In math, we
would include the q-dependence explicitly in our label. In physics, we do not. Rather, we expect the
viewer to interpret the symbol as something physical and therefore to realize that when ■ changes, so
does ■. As a result, when ■ changes, ■ does not change, surprising students. ● Math in math classes
tends to be about numbers. Math in science is not. Math in science blends physics conceptual
knowledge with mathematical symbols. Math in science is about relations among physical quantities
that are transformed into numbers by measurement. As a result, quantities in science tend to have
dimensions and units. These have to be treated differently from ordinary numbers. Unlike ordinary
numbers, different kinds of quantities can’t be equated. Students wonder why equations like ■ = ■ (and
3 cm = 3 seconds) are forbidden but the equation 2.54 cm = 1 inch is allowed. I’ll discuss this in detail in
the paper in this series on Dimensional Analysis.1. Students don’t usually learn to do this blending in
math classes, and most students in introductory physics have no experience with it.2 This blending has
a lot of structure and results in differences in the ways we use symbols in math and science. ● Math in
math classes tends to use a small number of symbols in constrained ways. Math in physics uses lots of
symbols in different ways - and the same symbol may have different meanings. In a typical algebra or
calculus book, you will find very few equations with more than one or two symbols and they tend to
follow a predictable convention — x, y, z, and t will be variables; f, g, and h will be functions; a, b, and c
will be constants. In a typical physics book, you will rarely find an equation with fewer than 3 symbols
and you will often find ones with 6 or more. And they won't follow the math conventions. This makes the
equations we use in physics look unfamiliar to students and raises their level of discomfort. ● The
symbols in science classes often carry meaning that changes the way we interpret the quantity. In pure
math it doesn't matter what we call something; in science it does. In science, we choose a symbol for a
variable or constant to give us a hint as to what kind of quantity we are talking about. We use m for a
mass and t for a time — never the other way round. Even more confusing is the fact that we use the
same symbol to mean different things. In my class, the symbol ■ can stand for heat, electric charge, or
volumetric flow. ■ can stand for a tension, a temperature, or the period of an oscillation. You might say,
“Well, sure. But the interpretation depends on the context. Then it’s obvious what you mean.” True. But
looking for the context means that you are already blending your knowledge of what the symbols mean
physically with your mathematical knowledge. Equations in physics not only represent quantitative
knowledge of the physical world. Through the blend, they codify both physical conceptual knowledge
and functional dependence. I discuss these issues
9/24/20 2 in more detail in the papers in this series on Anchor Equations3 and Functional
Dependence.4 ● In introductory math, symbols tend to stand for either variables or constants. In
science, we have lots of different kinds of symbols and they may shift from constant to variable,
depending on what we want to do. Math in math seems so clean. A variable is a variable. A constant is
a constant. In physics, our constants can be universal constants, parameters, initial conditions; and we
might choose to differentiate with respect to them.5 ● In introductory math, equations are almost
always about solving and calculating. In physics it’s often about explaining. Every semester, I have one
or two students whose comments go something like, “He doesn’t explain enough. He spends too much
time doing algebra on the board.” These students haven’t picked up on something I try to make explicit
(but obviously don’t succeed in for all students): A derivation of an equation is an explanation if you see
the equations as carrying conceptual meaning. This is something that is not obvious and is not easy to
learn, especially when their other science classes are not using math in this way. These “student
difficulties” are different from the usual student ones we might worry about. They’re not just lack of
knowledge, like forgetting how to divide by a fraction. These are more complex and “meta” — another
level, overlaying everything the students do. A lot of the literature in physics education is about helping
students better understand physics concepts. A focus on concepts is sometimes looked at as getting
away from the math. But how can we think about student thinking when the concept to be learned is
fundamentally mathematical as well as physical? Am I being unfair to math? I know some mathematical
physicists (and perhaps even some mathematicians) are going to complain that I’ve made math into a
straw man. Many of the things I say that math doesn’t do, it of course does — in more advanced
classes. In introductory physics, there’s some interesting “hidden” advanced math.6 We use some very
sophisticated mathematical structures in an introductory class because we expect our students to
interpret them not using fancy math but through the blend with common physical knowledge. For
example, the fact that the dimensions of an equation have to match can be seen as a group theoretical
statement: since the measurement scales are arbitrary, the equations must transform by the same
representation of the product of scaling groups.7 Defining a vector field mathematically correctly
requires that students think about placing a vector space at every point in space. This requires what’s
known as describing space as a manifold and creating a tangent bundle. Yikes! Physicists of course
don’t need that fancy math and we don’t teach it even in majors’ classes. It’s obvious that it makes no
sense to equate a distance and a time (unless you assume a fixed speed of light). It’s obvious what it
means to have a vector at every point in space. It’s like a weather map of wind speed. True. But the
critical element in being able to do a unit check or define an E field without the fancy math is building
the blend — mentally combining physical knowledge with mathematical representations. That blending
is neither obvious nor easy and needs to be taught. Am I asking too much? As an experienced
instructor in introductory physics, you may be feeling some distress at this point. “My curriculum is
already packed to the gills! I don’t have time to teach a whole bunch of new content!” Agreed. But I am
not suggesting adding new content. Rather, I am saying that if we feel that it is important for students to
learn to use math in science effectively then we have to teach the content that we teach in a different
way. These new learning goals don’t add to the content of the class; they appear in all contents,
identifying strategies that have general utility. They are threads, a way-of-thinking that crosses the
content that runs throughout the class, tying it together with technique and modes of thought, like the
warp and weft in a weave (Fig. 1). Figure 1. The interleaving of content (weft) with general strategy
learning (warp) Later in the paper, I will present a brief list of some of the tools I use to teach
mathematical thinking in multiple contexts. But first, we need a deeper understanding of the barriers to
students learning these skills.
9/24/20 3 Analyzing how students think When we ask students to do the kind of “thinking with math”
that I’m describing, we often not only see them struggle to do it, we often find strong resistance. In a
series of interviews with life science students in an introductory physics class, Watkins and Elby8
documented one student's views of math in science. Ashlyn: I don't like to think of biology in terms of
numbers and variables. I feel like that's what physics and calculus are for. So, I mean, come time for
the exam, obviously I’m gonna look at those equations and figure them out and memorize them, but I
just really don't like them. Ashlyn expresses considerable discomfort with trying to use the equations for
anything more than calculating. On the other hand, in another context, she expresses delight in learning
in her biology class (with models and math) that the functional dependence of volume on size explains
the reason we can’t have giant ants that she had previously seen in a Bill Nye episode. Ashlyn: I knew
that it doesn't work when you make little things big, but I never had anyone explain to me that there's a
mathematical relationship between that, and that was really helpful to just my general understanding of
the world. It was, like, mind-boggling…. It was really, like, it blew my mind. I’ve seen both of Ashlyn’s
reactions from many of my students; resistance to using math to think with and yet delight when the
math lets them understand something they knew but didn’t understand why it was so. To understand
these complexities of student responses, we need to seek the root causes of students’ resistance. I
draw on the language of the resources theoretical framework, but a detailed knowledge of the
framework is not necessary to follow my analysis. I’ll give references for those interested in more detail
in “Digging deeper” below. The key idea is that knowledge comes in basic pieces learned from
experience in everyday life as well as through schooling. These bits and pieces of knowledge are
dynamically activated in the brain in response to both external and internal stimuli. Some of the
differences between math in math and math in science that I’ve listed above are about expectations
about the nature of physics knowledge — epistemology — and some are about the kind of things we
are talking about — ontology. Knowledge about knowledge — epistemology: In thinking about student
difficulties with math in physics, it helps to think about student’s expectations about the nature of the
knowledge they are learning. These are internal stimuli that guide and constrain how students respond
to learning in our classes. These expectations may include ideas like, “I know this class is about
memorizing equations. I just have to find which equation has the right symbol in it.” or “I know I have
bad intuition about physics so I have to trust my math even if the result looks crazy.” I refer to this kind
of expectation as epistemology — knowledge about knowledge. Students’ epistemological expectations
can have profound effects on what they hear and how they think about what they’re learning. I often ask
a short essay question on my exams. This helps me get an idea of how the students are thinking
beyond “right or wrong”. Once, in my early days teaching algebra-based physics, at the end of the first
semester (Newtonian mechanics), I asked this on the final exam: “What do you think is the most
important equation you learned in this class?” To my embarrassment, the most common answer was
■=1/2 ■■!. Newton’s 2nd law was rarely mentioned. Clearly I needed to change the way I taught about
equations. My students were seeing equations as purely calculational tools, not as ways to help them
think about physics or to organize their conceptual knowledge. I totally changed my presentation to
focus on Newton’s laws as a framework for modeling. I discuss this in detail in the papers in this series
on Anchor Equations and Toy Models. A useful way to think about students’ epistemological
expectations is to consider the basic ways that they decide they know something: their epistemological
resources. These can be things they learned as infants (“I know because someone I trusted told me”)
or that they learned in school (“I know because I solved the equation and got this answer.”) Some
epistemological resources we want our students to learn in physics include: ● Symbolic manipulation
can be trusted — Algorithmic transformational steps starting from an application equation lead to a
trustable result. ● Physical meaning can be mapped to math — A mathematical symbolic
representation faithfully characterizes some feature of the physical or geometric system it is intended to
represent. ● If the math is the same, the analogy is good — Mathematics has a regularity and reliability
that is consistent across different applications. ● Toy models give insight — Highly simplified examples
can yield insight into complex mathematical representation. ● Consistency is crucial — When you look
at a problem in different ways you should get the same result. This is particularly valuable when a
physical and mathematical perspective can be brought independently, confirming an answer in the
blend. Note that epistemological resources, like resources about physical knowledge, can contradict
each other. “More means more” can correctly imply “a bigger object has more inertia and is harder to
move”, but “Closer is stronger” implies that
9/24/20 4 less distance produces a bigger effect such as “closer to a fire is hotter,” so in this case, “less
is more.” The trick to using resources in solving problems is building coherent coordinated collections of
them and developing an understanding of the contexts in which each is appropriate. Knowledge about
things — ontology: A second issue that is helpful in thinking about student difficulties with math in
physics is ontology — their knowledge about what kind of things we are talking about. ● Many of our
concepts in physics divide something that physically feels like a single concept into two mathematical
representations. For example, students often treat “motion” as a single thing, failing to distinguish
velocity from acceleration. While they have good physical experience with both motion and acceleration
(catching a ball, feeling a backward push when a vehicle accelerates), building the connection to rates
of change is not automatic. ● Some concepts in physics don’t match simple everyday ontologies (e.g.,
matter or process) but require blends. Nobody promised us that physics was going to be just common
sense codified! Quantum physics is the most blatant example, where our description involves
characteristics that make objects look both like a particle (localized emission and absorption,
momentum conservation in collisions, …) and a wave (interference, uncertainty principle, …). In fact,
there are many examples of this, some of them explicit — like treating light as rays, waves, or photons
— and some implicit — like considering energy in its matterlike aspects (conserved, has to be positive)
and in its representational aspects (can be negative, treat like a location on a graph).9 ● Some of our
concepts in physics are defined mathematically and may not have an obvious physical match. Particle
physicists will be familiar with the fact that fundamental fields (or “elementary particles”) are specified
as to “what they are” by specifying how they respond mathematically to various transformations — the
rotation group (What’s its spin?), particle exchange (Is it a fermion or a boson?), and the group of the
Standard Model, U(1)xSU(2)xSU(3) (What specific particle is it?) This same sort of “ontology as
mathematics” happens in introductory physics as well. We just tend not to notice it. It becomes obvious
when we try to explain what an electric field is without discussing vector fields; or when we try to explain
why crossed linear polarizers let light through when an angled linear polarizer is inserted between them
without talking about vectors and their decomposition. You might be able to do this (I can’t), but it feels
like trying to play charades with your hands tied behind your back. A math-in-science toolbelt This
analysis of the difficulties students have blending math with science raises a lot of questions.
Epistemological and ontological issues are meta — they run through much of the specific content topics
we teach. When we only focus on the list of physics topics we are “covering”, we may miss the more
general skills that we want students to develop along the way. Physics majors manage to learn these
skills, but often over many years (or even decades). Understanding these deeper issues about the
nature of physics knowledge and concepts is even more important to our non-major physics students
than any specific content we might choose to teach. But our “I-only-have-to-take-one-year-of-physics”
students tend to be focused on “just making it through” and, if they are pre-meds, making sure they get
a good score on the exams. Very few will make the effort to think deeply about what they are learning. If
we value learning to use math as a scientist, we have to find ways to explicitly teach it to our students.
The key is to teach introductory physics students to make the transition from math as purely about
numbers to math as a tool to think about physics. To do this, I’ve developed a set of general purpose
strategies I call epistemic games or e-games for short: specific approaches that can be brought to bear
in a variety of problems. I describe learning to do these as developing your mathematical toolbelt. I not
only teach these methods explicitly, but each method has a specific tool icon. Every time I use a tool in
class, its icon appears on the slide. Every time it’s used in our text (a free web-based wiki10) the icon
appears. As new e-games appear, new problems using them appear on clicker questions, quizzes, and
exams. Here are some of the e-games that my team and I have developed. In each paper in this series,
I’ll pick one, show how it relates to building an understanding of the use of math in science, and give
examples and links to resources. 1. Dimensional analysis 2. Estimation 3. Anchor equations 4. Toy
models 5. Functional dependence 6. Reading the physics in a graph 7. Telling the story Some of the
icons used in the NEXUS/Physics materials for these e-games are shown in figure 2. Instructional
resources Many of the ideas for this series of paper were developed in the context of studying physics
learning in a class for life-science majors. Materials from this project for delivering
9/24/20 5 instruction on the use of math in physics are available at the Living Physics Portal,11 search
“Using math in physics.” Figure 2. Some e-game icons from NEXUS/Physics: (a) Dimensional analysis,
(b) toy models, and (c) anchor equations. Digging deeper: Research resources If you’re interested in
digging into the physics education research literature a bit to see how the issues in this paper are
studied, take a look at Redish12 or Redish & Kuo.13 (Ref 14 discusses student surprising responses to
the equation ■ = ■/■ discussed at the beginning of the paper.) The knowledge-in-pieces idea that led
to the resources theoretical framework comes from diSessa’s phenomenological primitives.14 The
basic principles of the Resources Framework are outlined in Hammer,15 my Fermi Summer School
lecture16 (available as a 1 E. Redish, Using math in physics - 1. Dimensional analysis, preprint. 2 This
is especially true since word problems were purged from the elementary school mathematics
curriculum. 3 E. Redish, Using math in physics - 3. Anchor equations, preprint. 4 E. Redish, Using math
in physics - 5. Functional dependence and scaling, preprint. 5 Even my physics graduate students
sometimes get queasy when asked to differentiate with respect to a universal constant (like ■, as in the
Feynman-Hellman theorem in a graduate quantum class). 6 Even introductory math requires a blending
of every-day sense with symbol, but in a more abstract and context-independent way. See B. Sherin,
How students understand physics equations. Cognition and Instruction, 19 (2001) 479–541. 7 This is
really what’s going on with unit checks. I’ll explain this in the dimensional analysis paper, ref. . 8 J.
Watkins and A. Elby, Context dependence of students' views about the role of equations in
understanding biology, Cell Biology Education - Life Science Education 12 (June 3, 2013) 274-286.
doi:10.1187/cbe.12-11-0185. 9 B. Dreyfus, A. Gupta, and E. Redish, Applying Conceptual Blending to
Model Coordinated Use of Multiple Ontological Metaphors, Int. J. Sci. Ed. 37:5-6 (2015) 812-838.
preprint on ArXiv), and Hammer et al.17 The paper introducing the idea of epistemological resources is
Hammer & Elby.18 The idea of epistemic games was introduced by Collins and Ferguson.19 To see
how epistemic games and epistemological resources are observed, see Tuminaro and Redish20 for a
study at the algebra-based level, or Bing and Redish for a study at the advanced physics level. For
some papers on the ontological issues, see Gupta, Hammer, and Redish21 or Dreyfus et al. The
Feynman-Hellman theorem example is discussed in detail in Bing and Redish.22 The general theory of
meaning making through blending comes out of the cognitive linguistics literature23 and is discussed in
Dreyfus et al. loc. cit. Acknowledgements I would like to thank the members of the UMd PERG over the
last two decades for many discussions on these issues, especially Mark Eichenlaub, Ayush Gupta,
David Hammer, and Deborah Hemingway. The work has been supported in part by a grant from the
Howard Hughes Medical Institute and NSF grants 1504366 and 1624478. 10 The NEXUS/Physics wiki,
https://www.compadre.org/nexusph/ 11 The Living Physics Portal, https://www.livingphysicsportal.org/
12 E. Redish, Analysing the Competency of Mathematical Modelling in Physics. In: T. Greczy■o & E.
D■bowska (eds) Key Competences in Physics Teaching and Learning, Springer Proceedings in
Physics, vol 190 (2018). 13 E. Redish and E. Kuo, Language of physics, language of math: Disciplinary
culture and dynamic epistemology, Science & Education, 24:5-6 (2015-03-14) 561-590.
doi:10.1007/s11191-015-9749-7 14 A. diSessa, Towards an epistemology of physics. Cognition and
Instruction, 10:2-3 (1993) 105-225; 15 D. Hammer, Student resources for learning introductory physics,
PER Supplement to the Am. J. Phys., 68 (2000) S52-S59; 16 E. Redish, A Theoretical Framework for
Physics Education Research: Modeling student thinking, in Proceedings of the International School of
Physics, "Enrico Fermi" Course CLVI, Varenna, Italy, August 2003, E.Redish & M. Vicentini (eds.) (IOS
Press, 2004). 17 D. Hammer, A. Elby, R. Scherr, & E. Redish, Resources, framing, and transfer, in J.
Mestre (ed.), Transfer of Learning: Research and Perspectives, (Information Age Publishing, 2004). 18
D. Hammer & A. Elby, On the form of a personal epistemology. In B. Hofer & P. Pintrich (eds.),
Personal
9/24/20 6 Epistemology: The Psychology of Beliefs about Knowledge and Knowing (Lawrence
Erlbaum, 2003) 169-190. 19 A. Collins and W. Ferguson, “Epistemic forms and epistemic games:
Structures and strategies to guide inquiry,” Educational Psychologist, 28(1) 25-42 (1993). 20 J. .
Tuminaro and E. F. Redish, Elements of a Cognitive Model of Physics Problem Solving: Epistemic
Games, Phys. Rev. STPER, 3, 020101 (2007). 22 pages 21 A. Gupta, D. Hammer, and E. Redish, The
Case for Dynamic Models of Learners' Ontologies in Physics, J. of the Learning Sciences, 19:3,
285-321 (2010); JLS 20:1, 151-162 (2011); JLS 20:1, 163-168 (2011). 22 T. J. Bing and E. F. Redish,
Epistemic complexity and the journeyman-expert transition, Phys. Rev. ST Phys. Educ. Res., Vol. 8
(Feb 2012), 010105. doi:10.1103/PhysRevSTPER.8.010105. 23 G. Lakoff & M. Johnston, Metaphors
We Live By (U. Chicago Press, 1980/2003); G. Fauconnier & M. Turner, The way we think: Conceptual
blending and the mind's hidden complexities (Basic Books, 2003).