Allendoerfer, C. - Mathematics For Parents
Allendoerfer, C. - Mathematics For Parents
-CARL i ALLENDOERFER
Ss
a
Bece me TES)
mii MU EUnein,.
COU
| ai
a
Se
ae
a
a
See
a
Sn
ee
eas
ana
/
Be
are the easy-impf rae
MCE rey us
ATMS Cte 00
LEU Gc See
| UT a
c help ap HUTT Rest) SUT
— ><“MATHEMATICS
“FOR
lL, PARENTS
CARL B. ALLENDOERFER
PROFESSOR OF MATHEMATICS
UNIVERSITY OF WASHINGTON
This book has been written to answer the many questions about
the “new mathematics” which come to me as I move about in public.
When I have lunch in the Faculty Club my colleagues ask me
about this “base 7” business their children are being exposed to;
when I meet someone at a summer resort he is likely to turn out to
be a member of a school board who wants the real truth about
SMSG; and when I go out in the evening my friends blame me for
all the troubles their children are having in school with mathe-
matics that even father never saw before. Although I am a mathema-
tician by profession, I sometimes like to talk about other things.
So this little volume is meant to get me off the hook, for hereafter
when I see a mathematical gleam in the eye of an approaching
parent I can say: “I know what you are about to ask. I have it all
written up in my new book.” And with a reference to my publishers,
I shall turn on my heel and look for some nonmathematical non-
parent who is still willing to talk about the Yankees, taxes, the
weather, or the Russians.
The book is really divided into two parts. The first four chapters
describe the nature of the current revolution in mathematics and
make suggestions for parents who are interested in the best mathe-
matical education of their children. Very little technical mathe-
Vv
vi PREFACE
PREFACE
https://archive.org/details/mathematicsforoa0000unse
CHAPTER | THE NATURE OF
= MATHEMATICS
Before you can make sense of the current recommendations for the
reform of mathematics teaching, you must have an understanding
of the nature of mathematics. To many of you mathematics probably
means ordinary arithmetic with its set rules for computation. Others
may remember algebra as a collection of special procedures which,
by some sort of magic, can be used to get the answer in the book.
And geometry is a mysterious subject full of theorems to memorize
and outrageous tricks by means of which we prove the truth of
perfectly obvious relationships in nature. It is no wonder that parents
ask me, ‘‘How can there be anything new in mathematics? Are the
old formulas not still true?” So that you can fit your present recol-
lection of mathematics into the whole picture as a mathematician
sees it, I shall begin with a description of the nature of our subject.
Later we shall discuss the details of its separate branches.
Let me begin by describing the structure of a mathematical
theory in a mature form. In other words, let me show you how a
piece of mathematics looks when it has been completed and polished
and written up (or is it ‘“embalmed”’?) in textbooks. As we shall see,
1
2 MATHEMATICS FOR PARENTS
Mathematical
Applications
model
Nature Nature
the quantitative aspects of their domains. Then they join with math-
ematicians to build what is currently called a mathematical model of
their portion of nature. This model is incomplete in many ways, for
first it contains only the quantitative and geometric aspects of nature,
and, moreover, like all models it is only an imperfect copy and not
the real thing. Extant models differ in their degree of excellence;
they are remarkably exact for the physical sciences, but are just
emerging in hesitant form in the social sciences. But whatever the
value of the model, it is the beginning of a mathematical theory.
Let us examine the character of such a model. In the first place,
it is necessary to settle upon a technical vocabulary to describe the
observed phenomena. It is surprising to most nonmathematicians to
§
“
The Nature of Mathematics 3
ends and the middle and only after decades of effort bring forth the
beautiful, logical, and polished gems which we dangle before our
students.
More often we follow a different path. Beginning with nature
as before, we seek to find as many relationships within it as we can.
If we can systematize these we do so, but a lack of organization of
our material does not keep us from pushing forward. On the basis of
what we have observed, we guess theorems and use these to derive
other theorems. Immediately we rush to apply these back again to
nature and proceed headlong if our predictions are successful. Ax-
ioms, logic, and rigor are thrown to the winds, and we become in-
toxicated with our success and open to dreadful errors.
This process is called zntuztron, and its nature is in no way under-
stood. Several great mathematicians have written accounts of their
experiences in this phase of mathematical discovery, but the psy-
chologists are baffled by their testimony. The successful unraveling
of this process should be a major contribution to the understanding
of the human mind. But explained or not, it is by this means that
the great majority of mathematical theorems are first discovered.
One of my teachers in graduate school was good for about one hun-
dred such discoveries a week, with an average of only about one
which stood up under careful analysis. Yet those that were correct
made him one of the great mathematicians of the past generation.
The procedure is then as in Fig. 2. By means of intuition we
guess theorems, test them against applications, organize those that
survive, find axioms on the basis of which they can be proved and
thus build our mathematical model. A little-known trade secret is
that in this process theorems come first and axioms second. A good
example of this is the re-examination of Euclidean geometry in the
past century. It was discovered that many-of Euclid’s theorems
could not be proved from his axioms. Yet we all believed these
theorems to be true, and a number of different systems of axioms
were developed which had these theorems as their consequences.
This process of justifying a belief by trying to find premises from
which it can be deduced is shockingly similar to much reasoning in
our daily lives, and I am embarrassed to have to let you know that
mathematicians are experts at this art.
After the model has been constructed in this way we then prove
theorems by deduction and finally seek for applications to nature.
The Nature of Mathematics 7
There are, then, four key words in the process of constructing a math-
ematical theory:
Intuition
Organization
Deduction
Application
We shall see that this same pattern applies to the learning of math-
ematics, and that any good course in our subject must include all
four of these features.
Theorems
Axioms Logical deduction Rules
Organization
Intuition Applications
Nature Nature
Fig. 2. Structure of mathematics—as it is discovered.
and in fact Euclidean geometry was given the aura of absolute truth
commonly associated with the Bible.
In the early part of the nineteenth century attempts were made
to prove this axiom by the method of contradiction. In conformity
with this method mathematicians assumed that the axiom was false
and hoped to deduce conclusions which contradicted at least one of
the remaining axioms. In particular the two alternative axioms were
investigated: (1) there is no such parallel, and (2) there are at least
two such parallels. Although these mathematicians worked diligently
and imaginatively, they were frustrated in that they found no such
contradictions. It is reported that Gauss was the first to have arrived
at this awkward impasse and that he considered the possibility that
Let us return to Fig. 1 of the first chapter and look at it in the light
of the traditional curriculum in mathematics. Most of you will find
that your experience with mathematics was confined to the right
side of the figure. You were shown a set of rules and given practice
in applying these to a variety of more or less artificial situations.
Only rarely (especially in geometry) were you given any idea of the
reasons behind the rules or of how you might have invented them
yourself. An extreme version of a traditional mathematics textbook
might well look like that of Fig. 4.
On the left hand page we have a rule, usually printed in color,
and often imperfectly stated. Under this are several worked examples
illustrating the application of the rule. On the opposite right hand
page there are fifty or one hundred problems to which the rule is to
be applied. The student memorizes the rule, works a selection of the
problems, and then turns the page. There he finds exactly the same
thing, although with a different rule. Consecutive rules may have
some relationship, but this is infrequently explained in detail. After
a series of some five or ten episodes of this kind, the student is tested
10
How Things Are Changing 11
on his proficiency, and then proceeds to more rules. All too often the
earlier procedures are forgotten, and mathematics appears to the
youngster as a collection of rather stupid, isolated tricks which he is
supposed to learn by rote.
page 32 page 33
| Problems to which
Rule the rule is to be
(in color) applied
51.
52s
Dos
ILLUSTRATIVE
Examples
vard, and Yale universities. In this text the students studied pounds,
shillings, and pence—for we had only recently adopted the decimal
system in our currency. They were taught, for instance, to find one-
third of 4 pounds, 12 shillings, and 5 pence. Later in the course they
were taught not only how to take square root but also cube root,
fourth root, and fifth root. These topics have fortunately disappeared
from modern arithmetics, but undoubtedly there were head shakers
among the old-timers when these changes were made.
The most important trends of this kind at present have to do
with the techniques of computation and with solid geometry. Until
the 1920’s there were only two available methods for accurate com-
putation: longhand and logarithms. Early forms of the desk calcu-
lator were available, but these were not in widespread use; and some
forward-looking engineers were using slide rules. But most people
had to rely on pencils or logarithm tables for their work. Mathemat-
ical instruction was geared for this, and students were taught appro-
priate methods for handling their problems by these means.
Since then we have seen the widespread use of the desk calcula-
tor in business and technology, and the universal adoption of the
slide rule for approximate calculations by scientists and engineers.
Moreover, we are now in the midst of a major new development
resulting from the invention of the high-speed electronic computing
machine. Methods of handling problems which were designed for
efficient hand or logarithmic calculation are now replaced with those
which are most appropriate for the use of modern computing equip-
ment. For instance, the old, long method of taking square roots and
the logarithmic solution of triangles (in trigonometry) are now obso-
lete. There is no reason to teach such things to our children just
because they were essential tools for our own parents.
The situation concerning solid geometry is somewhat different.
This course used to require a semester, usually in the twelfth grade.
The purpose was twofold: (1) to reteach the axiomatic method previ-
ously taught in the tenth grade, and (2) to train the students in
three-dimensional perception. The first of these objectives can now
be met in other ways, particularly through the use of axioms in
algebra. Perception of relationships in space remains an important
objective in the total educational picture, but it is important that it
be taught at a much earlier age. For these reasons the formal course
in solid geometry has largely disappeared. Some schools have missed
14 MATHEMATICS FOR PARENTS
New Language
Acceleration
trained teachers and able students, the results have been excellent.
Freshmen entering universities are far better prepared than their
counterparts of a few years ago. Teachers and students are enthu-
siastic, and there is much acclaim.
Some weaknesses, however, have appeared. The new materials
are too hard for the less than average student, and so new versions
are being written for these pupils. Some schools swung too far on
the pendulum and forgot to teach skills as well as ideas. They have
learned and are moving back toward a well-balanced position.
There has, however, been some outspoken opposition. Part of
this comes from congenital conservatives who oppose change of
any kind; part comes from those who are too lazy to change; part
comes from the uniformed (who have not read this book!); and
there is a small group of mathematicians who think that extremists
have taken over the movement and are leading it into dangerous
territory. Any revolution has its extreme fringe, and I agree that
our extremists have gone too far. The opposition, however, is badly
mistaken in its belief that these extremists represent the views of
the great body of mathematics teachers. Judged by the published
work of its responsible leaders, the revolution is on firm ground,
and its success will bring tremendous benefits to the American
people.
CHAPTER 3 WHAT YOUR
2 SCHOOL CAN DO
ing what would happen to these children when they entered a high
school which disapproved of acceleration. Decisions of this kind must
be system-wide and not piecemeal by schools.
The parents also need to be brought into the picture in advance.
For there can be a bad reaction from home when Johnny shows off
his algebra book, which is full of words and problems that father
never learned about in school. Some school people take the view
that telling parents anything is asking for trouble, but I strongly
disagree. Parents are entitled to know what is going on in their
schools, and if they are not informed they are quite unlikely to
approve the special taxes needed to support the schools.
makes mathematics his special project for the year, and says, for
example: ‘“‘Put SMSG into every classroom in the schools, beginning
at 9 o’clock tomorrow.” Perhaps no such person exists, but I have
met some that come mighty close. A good school curriculum in
mathematics must be developed gradually; it should be watched
constantly and improved and extended every year. A crash program
which intends to do everything at once (and then get on with some-
thing “important” such as the new stadium) is sure to fail.
that, by the single act of buying rods, they have done all that is
needed to reform their arithmetic teaching. This is indeed an excel-
lent first step, but it must be followed up by a change in the method
of instruction as well.
2. TEACHING MACHINES. The past few years have seen the com-
mercial exploitatio n of Professor B. F. Skinner’s research on pro-
gramed learning and teaching machines. The basic idea is very
simple: students learn easily if they progress by very short steps,
and if they are told immediatel y after each step whether their action
was right or wrong. The questions which comprise these steps can
be presented to the student as “frames” in a specially designed
textbook, as films which he views in a teaching machine, or in
many other ways.
The advantages claimed for this method are that students can
proceed at their own pace independent of the rates of learning of
their classmates, that learning is more rapid than in an ordinary
class, that bad habits are stopped before they become ingrained,
and that teachers are relieved from routine paper grading and hence
are available to do more actual teaching. No one claims that the
method is cheaper than the usual one, or that teachers will be any
less important.
I am impressed with the probable usefulness of programed
learning in many teaching situations, but I deplore the excesses
of the commercial promoters of teaching machines. No matter how
good the basic idea of programed learning may be, it cannot be
proved in practice until some first-rate programs are written and
tested experimentally. The construction of a program requires the
collaboration of an experienced teacher and writer with a psycholo-
gist who is an expert in learning theory. Too often programs have
been thrown together by less competent persons so that they could
be available to promote the sale of teaching machines. The results
have been unfortunate in many cases, and the reaction of mathe-
matics teachers is quite mixed. Fortunately good programs follow-
ing modern curricula in mathematics are now becoming available,
and soon a better judgment can be made.
Moral: Do not rush into the purchase of teaching machines
until you are sure that well-tested, modern programs are available
for use in them. Consider programed textbooks quite carefully, but
What Your School Can Do 25
English 4 years
Mathematics 4 years
Foreign language 3-4 years
Social science 3 years
Natural science 2 years
Nonacademic subjects 4 years
Total 20-21 years
Careers as a Mathematician
=
a
33
MATHEMATICS FOR PARENTS
34
ways of repre-
Even in our system of numerals, we have many
can write “‘five’ as
senting the same number. For instance we
5,1 +4,2+3,7 — 2, 1%, V/28, ete.
Decimal Notation
that it is based
A striking feature of our system of numerals is
of us are born with
upon the number 10, apparently because most
notation is called the
ten fingers, which we use for counting. This
have made many
decimal system, and we shall see that we could
m is devis ed to use only the symbols
other choices. The decimal syste
retati ons depen d upon the place
Op le2 se Oo, DULY their interp
give this inter preta tion we choose
in which they are used. In order to
choos e ten. We define 101 =10,
a base for our system, and in this case
etc., and now are ready to
102 = 10 X 10, 10? = 10 X 10 X 10,
as 724. By defini tion:
define what is meant by a numeral such
724 = (7 X 10°) + (2 X 101) + 4,
8216 = (8 X 10%) + (2 X 10?) + (1 xX 10') + 6,
il
57.3 I 6 x10) +) + (8x z),
1 1 1
2.458 24 (+xit)+(5x ih) + (8xa)
Al3seven = (4 x ) al ql x 7) + 3,
In a similar fashion,
Al 8seven= (4 X 77)
+ (1X7) +3 = 196 +743
==> 206ten-
Also,
2164 seven = (2 X 75) + (1 X 72) + (6 X 7) +4
= 686 + 49 + 42 + 4
= 78 lten.
lol 3 «7 2 1 6 4 7
a 14, 105 777
4 29 206 2eegloe Liesl
The steps are these: Write down the base seven digits leaving
spaces between them. Bring down the first of these to the bottom
line unchanged. Multiply this by 7, and add the product to the
second digit. Continue, moving to the right. The final sum is the
appropriate numeral to base ten.
In order to proceed in the opposite direction, it is convenient
to have a table of powers of seven available:
ete
7? = 49,
73 = 348,
74 = 2401.
MATHEMATICS FOR PARENTS
36
l
Now let us find the expression to base seven of the numera
power of seven which goes
1954 ten. We divide 1954 by the largest
into it, namely, 7* = 343, and obtain
1954°= (5% 7) = 239:
can
We can do arithmetic to the base seven just as easily as we
to base ten, provided that we rememb er what we are doing. Addi-
tion depends on the table:
Now let us add the following where all numerals are to the
base seven:
45
+26
one seven plus four. We write the four and carry the one into the
second column:
1
45
+26
4
We add the second column and get 4 + 2 = 6 and 6+ 1 = 10.
So we have, finally,
45
+26
104
It is a good exercise to convert all these numerals to base ten and
check this answer. [Result: 33 + 20 = 53ten.]
Similarly, we can do multiplication to base seven. The multi-
plication table is as shown.
0
6
15
24
33
42
51
Daperen x a onevont
I om tire
Zten 10two
Sten deve
Aten 100two
Oten Oe
Bten LEO ire
iikvern is
Sten 1000 two
+) (Oe el en Oe?
OF 0 ie 0;90 O
Litt oLO Teed
110
101
110
000
110
11110
Numbers 39
Negative Numbers
1+ (-1) = 0,
2 (= 2) a 0,
3 + (—3) = 0,
etc.
Rational Numbers
Real Numbers
that there is no rational number whose square is 2, that is, that ~/2
must be irrational. In order to make room for such numbers, we
again expand the number system by including nonrepeating as well
repeating decimal expansions. The collection of all such numbers is
called the real number system.
The adjective real is quite misleading here, but is so well im-
bedded in usage that it cannot be replaced. The real numbers are
high-order abstractions from nature, and are far from “real” in the
customary sense of this word. The word “‘real’’ is used to distinguish
these from another system of numbers which our ancestors called
imaginary. Imaginary numbers arose because of the problem of
introducing +/ —1 into algebra. Since there is no real number whose
square is negative, ~/ —1 was completely excluded from considera-
tion for many centuries. Then it began to creep in as an zmaginary
number. We are now so used to it that we treat it like any other
abstract number, but the traditional names have stayed with us.
In order to complete our number system, finally we introduce
complex numbers of the form a + 62, where a and 6 are real and 7 isa
symbol that stands for ~/—1. As before, the word “complex” is a
misnomer derived from our ancestors; it is an inappropriate name,
but we are now stuck with it. We add and subtract these numbers
as in the illustrations:
(3 + 5i) X (4
+2%) = (8 X 4) + (3 X 2a) + (Si X 4) + (Si X 21)
12 + 61 + 202 + 102?
12 + 267 + 1022
12 + 26¢ + 10(—1)
2 + 261.
ax? ++ br +c = 0.
You might think that we would have to introduce fancier and fancier
kinds of numbers to solve equations of higher degree such as
Con
ae lee),
or
BEA 4 eG eae
It is remarkable, indeed, that complex numbers still do the job, so
that we need not introduce further systems of numbers for such
purposes. ,
The use of the terms real, imaginary, and complex is an illustra-
tion of how mathematical terminology differs from ordinary English.
These and only these words are proper mathematical language for
the ideas involved, and common English synonyms cannot be sub-
stituted for them. One of the more amusing but frustrating con-
fusions of this type occurred several years ago in connection with a
mathematical manuscript. This was being edited by a professional
editor for publication as a book. The editor found the use of “‘real”’
Numbers 43
PROBLEMS
1. Write the following in base ten notation. (a) 456seven; (b) 5623seven}
(c) 20Gsecons
2. Write the following in base seven notation. (a) 2196ten; (b) 4503 ten;
(c) 7208ten-
z?—4r+ 13 =0
Problems 12-15 are not covered in the text, but if you think hard you
should be able to solve them.
12. Write the following in base ten notation: (a) 35.2seven} (b) 21.13 seven}
(ey 10. (yl 10N te
13. Carry out the following operations on the understanding that all
numerals are expressed to base seven. Check as directed in Probs. 3
and 6.
(a) 6/66 (d) 45]1353
(b) 21|630 (e) 3426
re —1645
(c) 16/643 (f) 1536
a — 642
14. Express in the form a/b (all numerals are to base ten):
(a) 0.44444 ... Hint: Letz = 0.4444... ;
then 10z = 4.4444... ,
S010 c— 04, OOO0R me
T= Fi;
(D0 7777) eric),
0,121210 een end lecags oeee
3441 | BoP 4 a2 te 1 + 22
15. (a) +
24 Hint:
v T ry ie x b
pgm vtCerra
a+ ib godt bd) + i(be — ad)
16. Show that ———
c+ id c+ d?
ANSWERS
19ten
io i} Mal Oia d eee
15. ern a) a
CHAPTER © SETS, FUNCTIONS,
! > AND RELATIONS
Sets
(1) {1, 6, 15} is the set whose elements are the numbers 1, 6,
and 15. We use braces { } to represent sets in this way.
(2) {1, 2, 3,4, . . .} is the set of all natural numbers.
(3) {Bob, Jim, Bill} is a set of boys whose last name is
Allendoerfer.
(4) {z|z? = 1}. This notation is to be read “The set of num-
bers x such that x? = 1.”’ The vertical bar stands for “such that’’.
This set can also be written {—1, 1}.
(5) &, the empty set which contains no elements. An example
of such a set is the set of men born in 1700 who are still alive.
(6) {x|az? — 52 + 6 = O}, the set of solutions of the equation
aor | 6 = 0, namely, {2, 3}.
(7) [a, b], a special notation for the set of all real numbers which
lie between a and 6 inclusive, that is, those which satisfy the inequal-
ities a < x < b. This set is called a closed interval.
(8) Ja, b[, a special notation for the set of real numbers satisfy-
ing a < x < b. This set is called an open interval.
(9) {(a, y)|8a — 4y + 12 = 0}. This notation requires some
further explanation. The symbol (z, y) stands for a pair of numbers,
x and y; moreover, it is understood that the pair (x, y) is to be dis-
tinguished from the pair (y, x)—that is, the order of the two num-
bers in the pair is of importance to us. For this reason we call (z, y)
an ordered pair of numbers. The set defined above is, therefore, the
set of those ordered pairs (x, y) whose components x and y satisfy
the equation 3x — 4y + 12 = 0. Examples of elements of this set
are (—4, 0), (0, 3), (8, 9); there are in fact infinitely many such pairs,
and so we can never write down a complete list of them.
(10) {(2, y, 2)|Ba — 4y + 62 + 12 = 0}. By analogy with (9)
we call (x, y, z) an ordered triple. The elements of this set are those
ordered triples whose components satisfy the given equation.
Examples (9) and (10) raise a special problem in that it is not
possible to give a complete list of the elements of the given sets or to
use a notation such as in (2) to suggest what these elements are.
Thus we must invent another technique to help us see what the set
is; namely, we construct the graph of the set. To do this we draw two
perpendicular lines in the plane, as in Fig. 5, which we label the
X-axis and the Y-axis. We plot the point P as the graph of the
ordered pair (x, y) by measuring z units along the X-axis and y units
50 MATHEMATICS FOR PARENTS
Yi
(x, y) which satisfy the given equation. Second, we have the set of
points in the plane which lie along the graph we have plotted. These
two sets are closely related in that to each pair (a, y) there cor-
responds a unique point, and to each point there corresponds a
unique pair (x, y). Situations like this occur in many other places in
mathematics, and so it is worth while for us to give a name to such
a correspondence.
32 MATHEMATICS FOR PARENTS
corresponds to one and only one b and each b corresponds to one and
only one a. We write such correspondences in several ways. For
example,
John Jim _ Jerry
J 1 if
Bill Bob Bert
GQ) A
Gy B
the set of blue-eyed girls. Then A ()/ B is the set of red-headed girls
who also have blue eyes. As another example, if A = {1, 6, 9, 12},
Be 1Ont? a1> pethen:
AB = (9, 12}.
Now let us apply these ideas to. some familiar problems in math-
ematics. You are used to questions such as ‘“‘What is the solution of
x? + 7x +12 = 0?” but before attempting an answer we must
understand the problem. In the first place we call x a variable, and
we need to say what “variable”? means.
Es . @
(a) (b) (Cc)
Fig. 9. Intersection of two sets.
8. TRUTH SET. The truth set of an open sentence is the set of ele-
ments in U whose substitution for the variable in the open sentence
Sets, Functions, and Relations 57
ta ee oO
Thus the notion of a truth set includes the familiar idea of the solu-
tion of an equation, but it is a broader concept. It applies to inequal-
ities and to open sentences in two or more variables, such as
{alz? + 7x + 12 = 0}.
22+ 3y = —1,
z—-y=2.
tt) = Be 2a 1.
A B
Real number x The real number x? — 2x + 7
A letter The postage required to send this letter by
airmail
A positive real number x The logarithm of x
A telephone subscriber His phone number
A college student His age
A circle The length of its radius
A town The dot on a map which represents this town
We get an infinite collection of pairs such as (1, 1), (0, 2), (3, —1l),
(114, 14), ete. The set of all such ordered pairs is the relation so
defined.
Another relation is the set of ordered pairs whose elements sat-
isfy the inequality: a? + b? < 16. Particular elements of this set are
( Ly d, 2), ae 3), (2, iD) (2,2), etc.
These two relations differ in one important respect. In the rela-
tion defined by b = 2 — a, each value of a determines a unique
value of b. Hence this is an example of a function. On the other hand,
in the relation defined by a? + b? < 16, there are infinitely many
values of b that can be associated with a = 1. Indeed any b such that
b2 < 15 will work. Thus this relation is not an example of a function.
So that we may identify those relations which actually are functions,
we shall define a function as a special case of a relation.
Definition. Consider a relation which is a subset of the Cartesian
Product A X B. This relation is a function if and only if no two |
ordered pairs (a, b) which are elements of this relation have the same
first element, a.
From this point of view a function is a set of ordered pairs,
PROBLEMS
ANSWERS
whereas
(ey(uaecas)
GS Or)
Since
Gay
this type of multiplication is not commutative.
3. ASSOCIATIVE LAWS. The addition and multiplication tables tell
us how to add or multiply a pazr of real numbers. But there is nothing
in these tables that helps us with the sum 2 + 5 + 9 or the product
4 X 6 X 2. The sums and products of triples of numbers need to be
defined, and similar problems occur when we deal with quadruples
and larger sets of numbers.
If this matter bothered you when you were in school, you have
undoubtedly forgotten about it by now, but the situation is more
serious for your young children. What shall we do about 2 + 5 + 9?
There are at least two possibilities. First, you might add 2 to 5 and
get 7, and then add 7 to 9 and get 16. We write this as
OPER eee Jer het Osa G,
On the other hand, you might add 5 to 9 and get 14, and then add
2 to 14 and get 16. We write this as 2 + (5 + 9) = 16. From this
example we observe that
(2cteap eat Oo) 2-5 (5 9).
After some experience we realize that, for every triple of real num-
bers, a, b, c,
(a+b)+c=a+(b+ 0).
66 MATHEMATICS FOR PARENTS
This is the Associative Law for Addition. The parallel law for mul-
tiplication is
(dix Dy Ge = 08x sO c)-
every a
G@ <i=jixXG=a
These six laws contain all the necessary information about the
algebra of real numbers—apart from their order properties to be
discussed in Chapter 9. They therefore form the basis of algebra, and
every theorem and rule of algebra is implicit in them.
Fields
Theorem 1. ~(-a) = a.
Proof:
eed) eo) — a0). (Axiom 5)
Now add a to both sides. You get:
2. (Ca) ++ Ca)) + o=.0 + a,
or
3. —(a) + [Ca) + a] =a. (Axioms 2 and 4)
4, ~(Ca) +0 =a. (Axiom 5)
Don (a) star (Axiom 4)
The Laws of Algebra 69
a+ a = bd.
Dee “+ ty, = b.
ae V1 F~ Xo.
Then from 1 and 2 it follows that
4. a+t+a=a-+ xo.
Add ~a to each side; the result is:
». —“a+ 2] ([=-a+ a+ [a+ xl,
or
6. [(-a) +a] + 21 = [Ca) +a] 4+ a2. (Axiom 2)
7% O+%,=0+4+ 22. (Axiom 5)
ae (Axiom 4)
Step 8, however, contradicts step 3. This means that the assump-
tions 1, 2, and 3 cannot all be true and hence that there is only one x
with the required property.
70 MATHEMATICS FOR PARENTS
Examples of Fields
I have already described how the real numbers form afield, and
you may properly ask: Are there other number systems which are
also examples of fields? Yes, indeed. There are just lots and lots of
fields lying around in mathematics. Two of the most familiar are the
fields of rational numbers and of complex numbers. But these behave
so much like real numbers that they are not particularly worth
looking at here. I should prefer to show you some fields that are
quite different from any that would easily occur to you. These are
called finite fields or modular fields.
As an introduction to such matters let me ask you the
question:
“Tf it is now 9 o’clock, what time will it be seven hours from
now?” I hope you give the correct answer, ‘4 o’clock’’, but the
important question is ‘How did you do the problem?” One sys-
tematic way of handling such questions is to add 7 to 9 and then
subtract 12: 7 +9 —12= 4. Try this method to answer the
question:
“Tf it is now 3 o’clock, what time will it be fifteen hours from
now?” Answer ‘6 o’clock”’. A slightly harder question is:
“If it is now 5 o’clock, what time will it be thirty hours from
now?” To solve this we compute 5 + 30 — 2(12) = 11 o’clock.
In this way we can construct a new kind of addition which is
the same as ordinary addition, except that from the ordinary an-
swer we subtract that multiple of twelve which will leave a remainder
between 0 and 11 inclusive. Arithmetic of this kind is called modular
arithmetic, the modulus in this example being 12.
I chose 12 as an example because of its practical use in figuring
time, but it is too complicated for the rest of what I wish to do. Let
me then carry on from here using 5 as a modulus. To see how to add
in this system, let me write down the addition table.
The Laws of Algebra 71
se (yah ae
©
mwhdor
©
re
Bmwhwo
COoFW
Ne aH
bd
Ww
Pe
Oo Nor
oF
& Of,
OnrF
(1) The sum of any pair of numbers chosen from the set
10, 1, 2, 3, 4} is another number in this set. Hence addition is closed.
(2) To test the associative law is tedious; let us check a few
cases:
24(+4)=24+2=4 (243)4+4=04+4=4,
Mea 2) el tla?) (1 $4) +2204 2=2.
Others work the same way.
(3) The commutative law certainly holds, for
2+3=0, 3+2=0,
and so forth. Indeed, the whole table is symmetrical about the diag-
onal running from upper left to lower right.
(4) From the first line it follows that, for any a,
O+a=a.
(5) The additive inverses can be computed from the table. They
are:
ata=b
8+2=1.
-3+(8+4+2) =3+4+1.
2+(3+2) =2+1,
or
or
0+2=3,
or
x= 3.
Pm
© eS= ©
SS
woNWr a No
©
Ww
PR
PwOnNWF Ke
©
ke
wow
In ordinary algebra you would now divide by 3 and get x = 44; but
here this is nonsense since 44 is not one of our numbers. Instead we
multiply both sides by 3’ = 2:
(253)eo 4s
or
re.
or
x= 3.
If, finally, we check the distributive law, we see that the integers
with modulus 5 satisfy all the axioms of a field. Thus there are some,
strange looking “‘fields’’.
You may indeed wonder if there are any familiar systems of
numbers which are not fields. By all means! The positive integers:
74 MATHEMATICS FOR PARENTS
PROBLEMS
ax =b where a0.
4. Prove: There exists one and only one solution of the equation
ax+b=c where a= 0;
ANSWERS
4. A solution is: 2 = ~~". To prove this is unique, suppose there are two
a
different solutions x; and x» with x, ¥ x». Then
which is a contradiction.
mipGel 2 3 0} oO O O ©
ieee 3 0 Tt Polos
mie 3 0 1 Ze Oe Oe
Sao 1 2 St |O momo mel
No. 2 does not have a multiplicative inverse.
.. No. There is no solution since 2’ does not exist.
. Write the addition and multiplication tables. They are
Ore a2 a0 ale,
ORO 1 2 OREO 0
ie 2° 0 PS U0 Sol ee
ana) O° 1 2|0 1
Now check the axioms:
I have saved the Distributive Law for a chapter of its own because of
its very great importance. Something like one-half of the manipula-
tions of algebra depend upon this law, and much of the trouble
students have with algebra results from their ignorance of it.
The essential idea behind this law is that it establishes a con-
nection between multiplication and addition. You will observe that
all the other laws deal separately with these two operations, so that
without the distributive law much that is familiar could not be
established.
The intuitive idea behind this law is that for positive integers
multiplication is repeated addition. For example,
3X4=34+34+3+43
=44444.
Notice that this definition of multiplication does not make sense in
other cases such as 4 X 34, for how can we multiply 34 by itself
one-half time? There are similar difficulties with (—2) * (—6), and
76
The Distributive Law 77
aX (b+c+d)=(aXb)+(Xc)+
(aX a).
I can give many easy applications of this law. First let me apply
it to positive integers, and use it to show that, for these, multiplica-
tion is in fact repeated addition. I assume that it has already been
established, for instance, that
4=1+14+1¢41.
Then
aha —l| 3% Ue 1 it)
eto, eka Lais
by the distributive law. In other words, 3 times 4 is the sum of four
three’s. Similarly,
Brena.
4X3=4xX[1l+1+41,
=44444,
or 4 times 3 is the sum of three four’s.
To make the situation doubly clear, I remind you that there
are two statements to be considered:
(1) The Distributive Law.
(2) Multiplication is Repeated Addition.
For positive integers these two are equivalent. For various other
types of products, however, (2) is meaningless whereas (1) continues
to make sense. It is, therefore, wise to use (1) in all circumstances
and to de-emphasize (2).
As another illustration of the use of the distributive law,
78 MATHEMATICS FOR PARENTS
consider
2X (4+7) =(22X4+ (2X7)
Sera
= 22.
24 X 56 = 24 xX (50 4 6)
(24 X 50) + (24 X 6)
1200 + 144
1344.
24 24
X56 or X56
“144 “144
1200 120
1344 1344
Less well understood is the use of this law from right to left in
the process of factoring. That is,
(aXb)+(aXxXc) =aX4+0).
In numbers, we can therefore write
39 + 75 (5 X 7) + (5 X 15)
5X (7+ 15)
5 X 22
= 110.
The idea is to do most of the steps mentally, and to write down only
the answer.
The distributive law is observed to hold for positive integers,
but there is no way of testing its validity for situations where any
of a, b, or c is zero, negative, or fractional. Since such numbers are
creatures of our own minds we are free to give them any properties
we wish. Because the distributive law is so useful for positive in-
tegers, we assume that it is to be true for all real numbers. This
assumption has several very important consequences.
First, let us prove that for any real number a
a0. 0)
You doubtless believe this already, and wonder what the point of
this is. Remember that zero is defined by its properties of addition
(a + 0 = a) and that nothing was said about multiplication. You
cannot go from addition to multiplication without consulting the
distributive law. So why is a X 0 = 0?
Well:
0+ 0= 0,
aX(0+0)=axXQ0,
(aX0)+(@xX0)=ax0O, (Distributive law)
ax 0 = 0. (Adding —(a X 0) to each side)
. 12-458) = 12 = 12),
or
4% (—3) = —12.
Thus we see that a positive number times a negative number is
negative without having to rely upon some arbitrary rule handed
down by the teacher as something to be memorized or else!
Can you prove now that (—3) X (—4) = 12? I leave the prob-
lem to you, but suggest that you start with
oe = 5(r+ 5)
= (144)(2z) + (4)(5)
=x -+ (54).
Students have been known to think that the correct answer is x + 5;
they have merely cancelled the 2’s.
Using this idea we can see why it is true that an integer is
The Distributive Law
81
0 Te
Since ae is an integer (actually it is zero), 396 is divisible
by 11.
What, then, is the general rule? It is ‘An integer is divisible by
eleven if and only if the sum of its number of units, minus its number
82 MATHEMATICS FOR PARENTS
PROBLEMS
ANSWERS
4 (—4) = 0,
og) tah et) eas) <0,
ees eral oes) (4) — 0,
pei MO) K—-4)] =O,
ar (14) + i{—3) X(—4)] = 124 0,
(—3) X (—4) = 12.
b+ (—b) =0,
afb + (-—b)]=a X0 =0,
—ab + ab + [a X (—b)] = —ab +0,
a X (—b) = —ab.
84 MATHEMATICS FOR PARENTS
Ne “ a+ (—a) = 0,
la (—@)| X= 2) = 0 (0),
a(—b) + [(—a) X (—d)| = 0.
From Prob. 6, a(—b) = —ab, so
—ab + [(—a) X (—b)] = 0,
ab — ab + [(—a) X (—)b)] = ab +0,
(—a) X (—b) = ab.
8. Only (b).
9. (a) and (c).
10. If a number has a representation to base seven with 0 as the last digit,
it is of the form:
j=
Qo
Moreover, each number belongs in one and only one of these subsets.
This means, for instance, that no number is simultaneously positive
and negative.
This observation permits me to define inequality as follows:
Definition. For two real numbers a and b, the statement a > b (read
“a is greater than b’’) is equivalent to the statement a — b is positive.
Similarly, a < b (read “a is less than b’’) is equivalent to the statement
a — b is negative.
We can interpret this geometrically as follows. Arrange the real
numbers on the number line in the usual way with positive numbers
to the right and negative numbers to the left. Then ‘“‘greater than”
means “‘to the right of” and ‘‘less than” means “‘to the left of”’.
Since a — bis either positive, zero, or negative, we can conclude
that: Given any two real numbers a and b, precisely one of the following
as true:
a> b, a = 6}, a<b.
Basic Theorems
(a+c)—(b+d) = (@—b)
+ ( — ad).
Since by hypothesis a — 6 and c — d are both positive, [(a + c) —
(b + d)] is positive and the proof is complete.
Applications
3a +4
> 1.
The graph is given in Fig. 10. The open circle above —1 indi-
cates that. —1 is not to be included in the shaded region.
IIL
ee X
=I 0
Fig. 10. Graph of x > —1.
At eee el
This is equivalent to
—2x4 > —4,
or to
22 < 4,
or
Ea 2)
BLE ee
0 1 2
Fig. 12. Graph ofx < 2.
This is equivalent to
v?— d54+6> 0,
or to
(x — 2)(a2 — 3) > 0.
90 MATHEMATICS FOR PARENTS
+ = +
SX
0 1 2 3
Fig. 13. Sign pattern for (x — 2)(a% — 38).
This process depended upon our ability to factor the given quad-
ratic. If we are unable to do so by elementary means, we can rely on
the quadratic formula. This says that the roots of
av? ++ ba +c¢=0
Inequalities 91
are
iad —b+ Vb? — 4ac
oa 2a
This gives two values of x which are real if b2 — 4ac > 0, but which
are not real otherwise. Thus when b? — 4ac > 0, the process shown
will solve our problem.
What if, on the other hand, b? — 4ac < 0? Then az? + br + c
is not zero for any real x. Hence it cannot change sign as x moves
from — © to + ~, that is, it is definitely positive for all x or negative
for all x. Let us try an example:
Find the solution set of 22 +2+1> 0. Since b? — 4ac =
1 — 4 = —8, we know that x? + x + 1 is either positive or nega-
tive for all x. To find out which it is, try x = 0. Atz = 0,22 +a+
1 = 1, so x? + 2+ 1is positive for all x. The solution set is the
entire X-axis.
If, however, our problem had been to find the solution set of
x* + x +1 < 0, our answer would have been ‘‘The empty set.’
A frequent use of inequalities involves the notion of absolute
value. By the absolute value of a real number we mean the distance
of the number from 0, taken positively along the number line. The
symbol |a| is used to denote the absolute value of a. For example
Now what do we mean by stating that |x| < 4? This says that
the distance of x from 0is less than 4, or that x is between —4 and
+4. A convenient notation for this is
—4<24<4.
Similarly,
lx + 2| <6
is equivalent to
= Octet 2a 0
or to
—8 <2 < 4.
Finally,
lx —a| <b
is equivalent to
—b<x-—a<b,
92 MATHEMATICS FOR PARENTS
or
a—b<2z2<a-+b.
GM = VarXa,X
°°Xa
The remarkable inequality to which I refer is that
GM < AM
GM = Vam, AM = a,
From simple algebra it follows that
(a1 = a»)?
G10. < A
or that
a2 = 8, we have
——— 2+8
+
oS Sao CLASS:
For a; = 5, a2 = 5, we have
5+5
V5xX5< ; or aon
It never fails!
Further we can ask: When does equality hold in the statement
GM < AM? In our proof above for n = 2, it is clear that we obtain
inequality if (a1 — a2)? > 0 and equality if (a; — a2)? = 0. Hence
equality holds if and only if a; = a2. The conclusion is still valid for
the general case, that is, equality holds if and only if a1, a2. . . » An
are all equal.
PROBLEMS
10. Prove: If a > 6, and if a and bare positive, then a? > 6’.
11. Show that, among all rectangles with a fixed perimeter, it is the square
which has maximum area.
Inequalities 95
ANSWERS
2. (a) (ie
(b) ee.
(c) (th)
(d) Gy) <<a
(e) Gia:
3. (a) (Ha
(b) (g) =.
(c) (h) >.
(d) Ga.
(e) VAVYAA
VAAY
AVYAAY Ca
408) eS 2. () << %.
2777777777777
ee
0 2 01/2
(222227777777
4 777Pw _LLZZZZZZZZAL
LYLADD PRL
01p 0 6
ary
96 MATHEMATICS FOR PARENTS
—<———
AZZ
+ i) -72 0 13/
(os) =<
we<< &. (g) —5 <2 <1.
___FPFAAERA EAL
ey 0 5 =5 Ome
a
eens
WINDS CE CIMA Was
__
PATA© 0
-5 9
-2 0 4
Gi) SA sx PS il
G)) Sa <q a s<
___ 5}AAG 0 2
a es
3 0 3
(3 @) oS Sore
<< =e (d) cx>2orz
< —3.
CZZZ7ZAD | | 777777 L777 77ZRY || CV
=} 0 3 et 0 Zz
L777 py 4 | | Vs PEP A,
=o 0 5 150 5
ls (a) |x
— 4| < 6. (d) |x — 3] > |r + 4].
(b) jx — 2| > 5. (e) |x — 1] + |x — 3] > 10.
(c) jz — 2| = dla — 6].
. (a) (d) The empty set.
L277 77AY 4 V7 77773,
20 4 (e)
(c)
a
-5 01
3 + 27
may \/3 X 27 < cae (8) << 115),
2
2+5 + 100
(b) V2
5 X 100 < or 10 < 35%.
Vay <==!
or that
Graph of 3x
— 4y + 12 = 0
Figure 16
them. Join them with the line. Now test any point not on the line;
we choose O because the arithmetic is easiest for this point. At O,
2x + 5y —10 = 0+ 0-— 10 < 0. Hence the half-plane below the
line is the wrong one for our problem, and so the upper half-plane
gives us the solution. Just to be sure we check that at (3, 3), 2e+
5y — 10 = 64+ 15 — 10 = 11 > 0. We now shade the upper half-
plane.
Inequalities in the Plane 101
Graph
of : —-2x + 3y-6=0
Figure 17
LZ e (3,3)
Figure 18
The home team naturally wishes to win, but also thinks it wise
to mix up its offenses as much as possible. What possibilities are
open to them?
Let p be the number of pattern plays the home team uses and
r the number of running plays, so that the home team has a total of
p + r plays. Assume that after each shot the ball changes hands, so
Y
2x + 5y-—-10>0
x-y<l
Figure 19
that the opponents will also have p + r plays. We must assume, also,
that there are no penalties, and no miscues which cause the ball to
change hands except after a shot.
Then we look at the time required. We see that
30p + 15r + 15(p + r) < (1014)(60) = 630 (seconds)
Dividing by 15 we simplify this to
ip ir) <42
ap ina
104 MATHEMATICS FOR PARENTS
or
3p + 2r < 42.
With regard to the score, if the home team is to win we must have
Dexa piesa Pat eae
This simplifies to
p—T> ¥.
Our system of inequalities is therefore:
3p + 2r < 42, Deza0:
p—r>9, r= 0:
Their graph is as shown in Fig. 20. The two lines intersect at
(3, 12), and the set which satisfies all the inequalities is shaded in
3p + 2r < 42
(Sh 4)) p=1r>9
p20
Te)
Figure 20
the figure. The home team can then play any combination (r, p) of
offenses which lies in the shaded region. The possibilities are:
r 0 1 py
Dp 9 to 14 11 to 13 12
Inequalities in the Plane 105
In other words, the home team can afford to use at most two
running plays. Perhaps they would do better to use the pattern
offense for the whole time, but the team will have to decide this on
the basis of other information than that stated in this problem.
For a true problem in Linear Programing we should put the
question somewhat differently. Suppose we had said: Given 1014
minutes to play and the times and accuracies stated above, how
Pp
3p + 2r < 42
Figure 21
should the running and pattern plays be distributed so that the home
team would have the largest net gain in score?
The mathematical formulation then becomes: For what values
of p and r is the function (the net gain in score) p — r a maximum
when p and r are subject to the conditions
3p + 2r < 42, He) mage eeOt
The graph of these simultaneous inequalities is shown in Fig. 21. A
theorem says that this maximum will be achieved at one of the
vertices of this triangle. Let us check them.
AL (21, 0);
p—?r=0 —2h= —21,
106 MATHEMATICS FOR PARENTS
At (0, 0),
p—r=0.
At (0, 14),
p—r= 14.
The conclusion is that, for the largest net score, all plays should be
pattern plays. This conclusion was probably obvious to you without
all these calculations, but that is inevitable if I give you such a
simple problem. The point is that methods of this kind can solve
maximization problems of much greater difficulty for which the solu-
tions are far from obvious. Let me illustrate the method by a second
example.
A 100 50 0
B 200 10 ve 30
The units for protein and fat are arbitrary and need not be specified.
Let us also suppose that the minimum daily requirements for an
active man are:
Calories: 2500.
Protein: 350.
Fat: 150.
PROBLEM 2. Let us assume all the above information plus the fact
that food A costs 10 cents per ounce and food B costs 20 cents per
ounce, Then what combination of A and B should be used to provide
an adequate diet at least cost?
IE
(0,35)
(0, 12/2)
pa
maeC (7,0) (25,0)
a
a+ 2b225
Graph of Sa + eae
a2z0
Figure 22
At R,
a= 15, be=s5: cost = 250 cents.
Thus Q and R are equally good solutions, and in fact any point
on
the segment QR is also a solution.
PROBLEMS
Running 3 30
Pass 12 9
Also suppose that there are 36 yards to go for a touchdown and that
138 seconds remain in the game. Ignore the requirement of having
to
make 10 yards in four downs and other considerations of score
and
strategy. Problem: What combinations of running and pass plays
will
secure a touchdown in the allotted time?
6. In the football problem (Prob. 5 above) suppose that on
the average
there is one injury in each five running plays and one injury
in each
ten pass plays. Then what combination of plays should the quarter-
back call to secure the touchdown in the allotted time with the minimu
m
risk of injuries?
MATHEMATICS FOR PARENTS
110
into
7. The Minneapolis and Seattle Lumber Company can convert logs
a given week the mill can turn out 500 units
either lumber or pulp. In
are
of production, of which 100 units of lumber and 200 units of pulp
and
required by regular customers. The profit on a unit of lumber is $15
on a unit of pulp is $18. Problem: How many units of lumber and pulp
should the mill produce (totaling 500) in order to maximize the total
profit?
ANSWERS
1. (a) (b)
he <
( ih 0)
Inequalities in the Plane 11
r+ 4p > 12,
10r + 3p < 46,
p = 0,
i Uy
The graph is shown below. The shaded triangle is the solution set. The
P
C (0, 15Y3)
A (0, 3)
(4.6, 0)
r 0 1 2 3 4
p 3 to 15 3 to 12 3 to 8 3 to 5 2
From among these possibilities the quarterback can choose his plays
according to his judgment of appropriate strategy.
112 MATHEMATICS FOR PARENTS
At 6, r = 0, p = 15%; I = 4% = 1.538.
I is minimized at A, so the quarterback calls three pass plays and no
running plays.
7. Let L = units of lumber, P = units of pulp.
The conditions are:
L+P = 500, TOO ee 200:
Profit = 15L + 18P. Draw the graph. From the two inequalities the
mill must operate in the shaded portion of the plane. Moreover, it must
operate along the diagonal line. Hence its operations must lie on the
segment AB. "
JS
Oo
113
114 MATHEMATICS FOR PARENTS
A and B, on aline (see Fig. 23), we wish to speak of the segment AB.
The natural definition of this segment is that it consists of the
points A and B and all points on the line between them. The trouble
is that Euclid’s axioms give us no grounds for deciding what between
should mean. Of course, we know what we mean from the figure, but
this is not enough—it must be in the axioms. By straightening out
Se
A B
Figure 23
Figure 24
(3) The set II (the points on the other side of the line) such that
(See Fig. 25a and b):
(a) A segment PQ lies in I (or II) if and only if the points P and
Q are in region I (or II).
(a) (b)
Fig. 25. Division of a plane byaline.
> aq
Analytic Geometry
Intuitive Geometry
Solid Geometry
It is a paradox that in the space age the teaching of the geom-
etry of space has gone to pieces. But so it is, and the fault is due to
both neglect and misunderstanding. Everyone agreed that the old
twelfth-grade course in solid geometry had failed to meet its objec-
tives, but there was no agreement on the remedy. Students have a
serious need for an understanding of space relationships, for knowl-
edge of the facts about lines and planes in space, and for information
about the geometry of the sphere (for is our globe not a sphere?).
The deductive method of approaching these ideas was too compli-
cated and tiresome, and seemed to bog down in details while missing
the main ideas. For this reason it was recommended that the course
be abandoned, and that the material on space geometry be taught
intuitively in the junior high school and in the tenth grade. This has
been partially accomplished, but much more must be done. Too
often space geometry is taught nowhere in the school, and our chil-
dren are the worse for our neglect.
A Recommendation
My own preference for the geometry curriculum is the fol-
lowing:
Junior High. Intuitive geometry in two and three dimensions.
Emphasize ideas; no proof.
Tenth Grade. Modernized deductive geometry of the plane.
Ideas of solid geometry introduced where appropriate. A few weeks
only of analytic geometry.
Twelfth Grade. One semester of plane and solid analytic geom-
etry. A few weeks on the geometry of the sphere.
If this program is followed in addition to a proper curriculum
in algebra and trigonometry, the student will be well prepared for
his calculus course when he goes to college. It is very foolish to teach
calculus to anyone who has not first completed such a curriculum.
A Theorem on Intersections
Let us now get down to some details. First I shall show you an
application of the axiom on the division of the plane which I stated
earlier in the chapter.
120 MATHEMATICS FOR PARENTS
B Q
P
Figure 28
any of the vertices and to count the number of sides which it crosses.
Regardless of how you draw PQ this number will be even if P is
outside and odd ifP is inside. Try a few positions for PQ, and check
this for yourself. Of course, this result requires proof, but since the
proof is complicated I shall leave it out. The idea, however, is most
important. Did you ever run across it when you were in school?
Figure 29
Euler’s Theorem
Tetrahedron: WN = 2.
122 MATHEMATICS FOR PARENTS
Figure 30
Next do the same for a cube (see Fig. 32): We find that V = 8,
E = 12, F = 6,sothatN= V —EH+ F= 2.
Cube: WN = 2.
Finally let us do it for an octahedron (Fig. 33). We find that
V = 6, FE= 12, F = 8,sothatN= V —E+F = 2.
Octahedron: WN = 2.
Perhaps this is getting monotonous; we seem to get N = 2 no
matter what solid figure we consider. As I shall show you, this is not
necessarily the case, so we need to state some property of a solid
Geometry 123
Tetrahedron
Figure 31
Cube
Figure 32
124 MATHEMATICS FOR PARENTS
Octahedron
Figure 33
Again, I must omit the proof, but let us try some experiments.
First take any spherical object (say an orange or a billiard ball) and
draw a network of curves on it. Mark all the intersections and call
these ‘vertices’. Between each pair of vertices there should be one
and only one curved segment—call this an “‘edge’’. Call the open
spaces ‘‘faces’”. Now compute V — EF + F; if you have followed the
instructions this number should be N = 2. Thus you have verified
Euler’s Theorem.
As the next experiment I suggest that you do the same thing on
the surface of a doughnut. I know that it is hard to draw on a
Geometry 125
Regular Solids
Let me return to Euler’s Theorem as it applies to solids whose
surface can be blown up into the surface of a sphere. Remember that
in this case
ae ieee
A solid is called regular if and only if each face has the same number
of edges, and if each vertex is met by the same number of edges.
The question now is: What regular solids exist?
Let n represent the number of edges to a face and m represent
the number of edges meeting at a vertex. Then the three solids
mentioned above are regular with the following values of n and m:
m n
Tetrahedron 3 3
Cube 3 4
Octahedron 4 3
3 3 6 4 4| Tetrahedron
3 4 8 6| Cube
3 5 SOM mel 12 | Dodecahedron
3 6 — | — | — |Impossible since 1g + 146 = 14
3 of — | — | — |Impossible since 44 + 4% < 14
4 3 12 6 8| Octahedron
4 4 — | — | — |Impossible since 14 + 14 = 14
4 5 — | — | — |Impossible since 14 + 14 < 14
5 3 30 12 | 20 | Icosahedron
5 4 — | — | — |Impossible since 14 + 14 < 14
ee
Icosahedron Dodecahedron
Figure 34
Geometry 127
opment of his philosophy. Hence, the five regular solids are often
called the ‘“‘Platonic Solids’”’. It is a beautiful theorem, but of little
practical importance. Students of mathematics, however, should see
such theorems in order to be convinced that mathematics has aes-
thetic as well as practical values.
PROBLEMS
1. Find the flaw in the following proof that: All triangles are isosceles.
B B
(a) Given triangle ABC, construct the angle bisector BD at angle B and
the perpendicular bisector DH of side AC. Unless AB = BC, these
lines are distinct and meet in a point D. So far as we know at present,
D may lie inside or outside the triangle, so we draw the two corre-
sponding figures.
(b) Draw AD and DC.
(c) From D draw MD LAB and NDL BC.
(d) AADE= ACDE (right triangles with equal bases and altitudes).
(e) AD = DC (corresponding parts of congruent triangles).
(f) ABMD = ABND (right triangles with equal angles at B and equal
sides BD).
(g) MD = ND and BM = BN (corresponding parts of congruent
triangles).
(h) AADM = ACDN (right triangles with two pairs of equal sides).
(i) AM = CN (corresponding parts of congruent triangles).
(j) In the first figure above, In the second figure above,
BM = BN, BM = BN,
Mies ONG AM =CN.
Adding: AB = BC. Subtracting: AB = BC.
128 MATHEMATICS FOR PARENTS
ANSWERS
1. D must lie outside the triangle, for it lies on the circumscribed circle.
Even so, the figures above are incorrect. Hither MJ lies on segment AB
or N lies on segment BC, but not both. So on one side we should sub-
tract and on the other side we should add.
Geometry 129
This fallacy illustrates the point that we should never argue from a
figure. In order to handle this problem we need the concept of the order
of points on a line, phrased in a way such that we can prove results with-
out the use of a figure. The modern treatment of geometry permits this;
Euclid’s does not.
2. V =16; EF = 32:F =16:N=V—E+F =0.
Seve 240 = 48: Ff = 32)N =V=B+F= —2,
4. N =2 — 2¢.
SSS]
CHAPTER 12 TRIGONOMETRY
Oo
i
Oo
a/c. Similarly, the cosine of A is b/c. (See Fig. 35.) We write these
for short:
sin A = G/c,
cos A = b/c.
c a
A Cc
b
Figure 35
f(a) =x? — 42 + 7,
or
g(x) = logio x,
Figure 36
Figure 37
134 MATHEMATICS FOR PARENTS
z positive
Figure 38
that in Fig. 38. The point Q will then lie on the circle and has coor-
dinates x and y. We then define
sin2 = y,
COs 2 = &,
tive we wrap the segment of length |z| around the circle in a clock-
wise direction and thus find the position of point Q (Fig. 39).
From such a figure we can immediately compute the values of
these functions for certain convenient values of z.
Vv
z negative
Figure 39
Q(0, 1)
3
|
Figure 40
Applications
Mf
Figure 41
wave motion. The graph of y = sinz is the basis of this and has the
form shown in Fig. 42. This can be modified hy inserting coefficients
to read
y = Asin Bz.
The factor A is called the amplitude and controls the height of the
maximum and the depth of the minimum of the curve. The factor
B is related to the frequency of the curve, and tells us how many
138 MATHEMATICS FOR PARENTS
Figure 42
Amplitude Modulation
Figure 43
Logarithms
MUU MA
VV VVVVVVVY WY VV VWI
Carrier wave Transmitted wave
Frequency Modulation
Figure 44
n is given
grams to decay into A/2 grams. The graph of this functio
in Fig. 45.
tation
Another use for logarithms occurs in the graphical presen
stock market and
of percentage change. Suppose that you play the
You may well plot
wish to chart the behavior of your favorite stock.
in Fig. 46.
the price against time and obtain a graph like that shown
x
Radioactive Decay
Figure 45
78
77
76
Price74
73
72
71
70
Time
Figure 46
Trigonometry 141
log 90
log 80
log 70
log 60
(logarithmic
Price
scale)
log 50
log 40
Time
Logarithmic Rulers
Figure 48
Now plot log y against log x. The result is a straight line. The easiest
way to do this is to use “log-log” graph paper on which both the
vertical and horizontal scales are logarithmic. (See Fig. 49.)
It is for applications like these that logarithms need to be taught;
let us leave computing to the machines.
log 100
log 30
log 20
(log 2, log 16)
log 10
log 5
log 3
log 2 (log
1,log 2)
log 1
log 1 log2 log3 log4
Figure 49
PROBLEMS
Ey con (i)sin(- -
Sea . 2
(e) sin 5 (j) cos(- *)
144 MATHEMATICS FOR PARENTS
dollars after t years. How much interest at 4 per cent per annum would
be paid on a deposit of $100 during the first year? How much would the
first year’s interest have been if it had been compounded quarterly?
7. For small values of z, a good approximation to sin z is
; ae
Sa = o> ==
6
Compute sin (0.1) to four decimal places, and compare your result with
its value in a published table. You will need to consult a table which
gives the sine of an angle of 0.1 radians, for published tables have not
caught up with the times.
8. From the definition show that sin (2r + 2) =sinz. Hence using
the result of Prob. 7 compute sin 6.38.
9. Give an example to show that in general
ANSWERS
sin? z + cos? z = 1.
logy=x log,)2
0.0 ~1+1.
10. The end point of the are corresponding to (—z) is directly below that
corresponding to z. Since the figure is symmetrical relative to the
X-axis, sin (—z) = —sin z.
ae
CHAPTER 13 LOGIC
oO
ste es
oO
Some open sentences are true for every value of the variable; these
are called identities. Examples are
Similarly, some open sentences are true for no value of the variable.
Examples are
ge tA and (a — 2)(x4 — 3) = 0.
True False
CONJUNCTION
Pz Qx De IN Gz
HeaHHA Sd
DISJUNCTION
Pr Ux Dz V Qe
a ly a
Hl F a
F fi a
F F F
Definition. Two open sentences are equivalent if and only if they have
identical truth sets.
EQUIVALENCE
Pe dx Pr x
Miwaeg
ke Sey
Pz —~DPxz
NEGATION
Dx pe
ay F
F cD
Implication
The great bulk of mathematical theorems are of the form: Ii pay
then q:. For example:
If x is an even number, then x + 1 is an odd number.
There is, moreover, a subtlety here that is all too frequently ignored.
In our example above, we really mean:
For all integers «: If x is an even number, then x + | isan
odd number.
Let p, be a? = 4, gz be (x — 2)(x% — 3) = 0.
Then we have
Values of x Pz dx Dz — Qz
2 ue oi
—2 cl F To be
3 F eli defined
Any other x F F
IMPLICATION
Dz a Pz dx
elacia
eolae| ea
In our example above we see that p,— q; is true for all values
of x except « = —2, and that it is false for c = —2. Hence it is not
true for all x, and the statement
Values of x De
2 a
—2 EF
Any other x F
Figure 50
circles P and Q may lie, there are just two which correspond to the
statement that V, (p:— q,) is true, namely, the situations when P
lies inside Q or is identical with Q (Fig. 51).
P Pand Q
(a) (b)
Figure 51
Figure 52
In our example
Forally:ii a= 2, then?’ = 4
the figure looks like Fig. 52. The large circle includes points where
x? = 4, namely, x = —2 and xz = 2. The small circle contains x = 2
154 MATHEMATICS FOR PARENTS
Figure 53
true for all these values of x. If it is, the statement is true. If, how-
ever, there is a single x for which p, is true and qz is false, the state-
ment is false.
HHAmaH
We Deed) Vx(9,—>
(a) (b)
Figure 54
Direct Proof
The most common type of mathematical proof is a direct proof
involving a chain of implications which have previously been shown
to be true. Suppose that we are given that the following are true:
O | coy (0)
Figure 55
Logic Wa 74
Figure 56
Proof:
1. For all z: If x is odd, then 2 = 2a + 1. (Given)
2. Forall x: If c = 2a+ 1, then 2? = 4a? +4a+1. (Algebra)
3. 402+ 4a+1 = 2(2a2 + 2a) +1 =2b+1, where 6b is an
integer. (Algebra)
4. For all x: If « = 2a +1, then 2? = 26+ 1, where b is an
integer. (Substitution)
5. For all a: If 22 = 2b + 1, where b is an integer, then x? is odd.
(Given)
6. For all a: If x is odd, then 2? is odd. (From 1, 4, and 5)
Indirect Proof
That is, some point inside the P circle must be outside the Q circle.
Let us try an example:
Prove: For all integers x: If x? is even, then x is even.
Proof: Weassume that the given implication is false, namely, that:
For some x: 2? is even and x is odd (not even).
From our previous proof, above, however, we know that it is impos-
sible for x to be odd and x? to be even. Hence we have arrived at a
Logic 159
Disproof
There is a natural procedure: find one value of x for which the open
sentence is false. Such an z is called a counterexample. In the above
example xz = 0 will do the job.
Conclusion
This has been a very brief and informal discussion of logic and
methods of proof and disproof, but I hope that you have some idea
of these topics. The construction of a proof often involves ingenuity
of a high order, and this takes time to develop even if the brain
power is adequate. It is nowhere nearly so difficult to recognize a
correct proof when you see one, and I hope that this discussion will
help you find your way through some of the modern textbooks your
children are using.
PROBLEMS
1. Using truth tables show that (p.) V (~pz) is true for all values Ofeas
Hint; Fill in the right-hand column of the table:
Dx ~Dz (pz) V (~Pz)
© F
F T
2. Using truth tables show that ~[(p:) A (~pz)] is true for all values of x.
oo.Using truth tables show that p, — qz is equivalent to ~[(pz) A (~¢4z)]-
4. In order to treat the inverse and contrapositive of Vz (pz — 2) in our
diagrammatic fashion, we draw a square to represent the universal set
consisting of all values of x. The circle P inside this square contains
those values of x for which p; is true. The remainder of the square con-
160 MATHEMATICS FOR PARENTS
tains those x for which p, is false (figure below) that is, for which
>
(~pz) is true. Using this idea show that V. (pz — qr) and Vz [(~qz)
(~p,)] are equivalent.
ea 267)
(6) e272) — g?.
(7) q? is even.
(8) gis even, so q = 2s.
(9) p and q have 2 as a common factor.
(10) Step 9 contradicts step 2.
(11) Therefore, the assumption in step 1 is incorrect and the theorem
is proved true.
12. Is the following a correct indirect proof?
Prove: For all 2: If z > 3, then 2? > 9.
Proof:
(1) Assume: For all x: If e< 3, then 2? < 9.
(2) Let x = —5. Then —5 < 3, but (—5)? = 25 and is not <9. Thus
z = —5 is counterexample to step 1, and step 1 is false.
(3) Since the assumption in step 1 is false, the theorem is true.
13. Some theorems in mathematics cannot be written conveniently in the
form Vz (pz — gz), but indirect proof can still be applied to them. Con-
sider the theorem:
There exist an infinite number of primes.
Recall that a prime is a positive integer which has no integral divisors
except itself and 1. To prove this theorem we proceed as follows:
(1) Assume that the theorem is false, that is, assume that: There are
only n prime numbers, where n is a (finite) positive integer.
(2) Then we can make alist of these primes, say, Pi, Pa, + + + 5 Pn
(3) Consider P = pi X p2 X ++ * X Pn +1. We wish to produce a
contradiction by showing that P is a prime not in the above list of
all primes.
(4) First, P is not equal to any of pi, . . . , Dn, for it is clearly larger
than any of them.
(5) Second, P is a prime (prove it).
(6) Hence there is a contradiction with our assumption in step 1 and
the theorem is true.
ANSWERS
oy F ali
F el iL
i. F F ar
F L F fi
MATHEMATICS FOR PARENTS
~qa
(pz) \ (~q@) ~[(pz) A (~9az)] (Dz — qz)
————$_$———_——— SCT
Logic 163
Hence the region where ~; is true is included in the region where ~qz
is true, or Vz [(~pz) — (~qz)] is true. Now reverse the process.
. There can be no proof, for z = —2 is a counterexample to the conclu-
sion.
. Proof:
(1) For all x: If ct = 16, then 2? = 4. (Given)
(2) For all x: If xz is other than z = —2, 2, then 2? # 4. (Given)
(3) For all 2: If 2? = 4, thenz = —2or2. (Contrapositive of step 2)
(4) For all x: If x! = 16, then x = —2 or 2. (From steps 1 and 3)
. Proof:
(1) For all x: If z is even, then « = 2a where a is an integer. (Given)
(2) For all x: If x = 2a, then x? = 4a’. (Algebra)
(3) 4a? = 2(2a?)= 2b, where 6is an integer. (Algebra)
(4) For all x: If = 2a, then x? = 28, where 0 is an integer.
(Substitution)
(5) For all x: If x? = 2b, where bis an integer, then x? iseven. (Given)
(6) For all x: If z is even, then 2? is even. (From steps 1, 4, and 5)
NEroor:
(1) Assume that, for some z, x? is odd and zis even.
(2) This contradicts the result of Prob. 8.
(3) Hence the assumption is incorrect and the theorem is true.
10. False. Let a = 2, b = 1, c = 3, d= 10. The na
> b and c <d. But
a+ec=5andd+4+d = 11. Hence it is false thata +e > 6 +d.
on This is correct. It shows that there is no rational number a/b whose
square is 2, or that / 2 is irrational.
12. This is incorrect. The assumption in step 1 is the wrong one if you wish
to assert that the theorem is false. Actually the implication in step 1 is
the inverse of the given implication, which has nothing to do with the
case! The correct assumption to make is: For some z:z > 3 and 2? < 9.
This does not lead to any reasonably evident contradiction, and so the
method of indirect proof is not suitable for this theorem.
We can give a simple direct proof as follows: Consider x? — 9.
We know that x? —9 = (rx+ 3)(c4 — 3). Now x > 3; sor+3>0
and (x — 3) > 0. Hence (x + 3)(x — 2 9.
3) =>0, or 2?
13. To prove that P is a prime, we use indirect proof again. Assume that P
is not a prime. Then P must be divisible by at least one of the existing
pened, py, =: . , Pa. Sin ce
P = p, XP2X~"* +1, this is a
X pn
contradiction. Hence P is a prime.
CONCLUSION
mm (1 Between, 114
Absolute value, 91 Binary system, 39
Abstraction, 3
Acceleration, 15 Calculus, 14
Actuary, 31 Careers, 31
Addition, repeated, 77 Cartesian product, 59
Advanced Placement Examination, 16 Closure, 64
Advice to school districts, 19 Commercial aids, 22
Algebra, laws of, 63 Commission on Mathematics, 17
“All triangles are isosceles’, 127 Commutative law, 64
Analytic geometry, 14, 118 Complement of a set, 55
Angle, 117 Complex numbers, 41
interior of, 117 Compound interest, 144
Applied mathematics, 5 Computation, 13
Associative law, 65 Conjunction, 147
Audio-visual aids, 22 Contrapositive, 154
Axioms, 3 Converse, 154
in geometry, 4 Coordinate system, three dimensional,
in physics, 4 52
two dimensional, 50
Base seven, 35 Cosine of, acute angle, 132
ten, 34 real number, 134
two, 38 Counterexample, 159
165
166 Index
Number, 33 Sets, 48
base seven, 35 Cartesian product of, 59
ten, 34 complement of, 55
two, 38 identical, 54
complex, 41 intersection of, 55
imaginary, 41 truth, 56
natural, 33 union of, 55
negative, 39 universal, 55
rational, 40 Sine of acute angle, 131
real, 40 Sine of real number, 134
Numeral, 33 Sine wave, 137
amplitude, 137
Octahedron, 122, 124 frequency, 137
One to one correspondence, 52 Skinner, B. F., 24
Open sentence, 56, 147 SMSG, 17
compound, 147 Solid geometry, 13, 119
equivalent, 149 Solids, regular, 125
Operations Research, 27 Square root of 2 is not rational, 160
Opposition, 18 Structure of mathematics, 2, 7
Order on a line, 85, 114 Subset, 54
Subtraction, 67
Percentage change, 140 Sum of three numbers, 66
Place value, 34 Support, types needed, 20
Plato, 126
Primes, infinitude of, 161 Teacher training, 21
Probability, 14 Teaching machines, 24
Programed learning, 24 Tetrahedron, 121, 123
Projectors, overhead, 25 “Three’’, 3
Proof, direct, 156 Topics, old and new, 12
indirect, 158 Transitive Law, 88
Triangle, interior of, 117
Quadratic formula, 91 Trichotomy, Law of, 86
Quadratic inequalities, 89 Trigonometry, 130
Truth, 5
Rational numbers, 40 set, 56
Real numbers, 40 table, 148
Reference materials, 20, 31
Regular solids, 125
UICSM, 17
Relation, 60
Undefined terms, 3
Understanding, teaching with, 11
Scientific Revolution, 26
Union of two sets, 55
Semilog graph paper, 142
Universal set, 55
Sentences, 146
open, 56, 147
Separation of the plane by aline, 115 Variable, 56
~'ee
a“
» j
. - 7
.
.
’
na ibbdpry
7 won ive 2 iow
A 5) oeM- a, ;
‘
DATE DUE
2)
SEC 6
Y
B®)
9
3
fiz
” oOo wo
Oo
0
ray
Allendoerfer, Carl Barnett
QA
a:
~A558 Mathematics for parents.
SCIENCE
QH
From the preface...
"This book has been written to answer
the many questions about the ‘new
mathematics' ... my colleagues ask me
about this 'base 7' business their children
are being exposed to; when I meet someone
at a summer resort he is likely to turn
out to be a member of a school board who
wants the real truth about SMSG; and when
I go out in the evening my friends blame
me for all the troubles their children are
having in school with mathematics that
even father never saw before. ... This
book is designed to get me off the hook,
for hereafter I can say: I know what
you are about to ask. I have it
all written up in my new book."
IH
evident in his recent television series on the ‘
math” permeates this book. Professor of Mi
matics at the University of Washington a
|
former president of the Mathematical As ~ELIBRARY. 253
||
8212
ation of America, he is the author of widely
textbooks.