Pizzi Necess ETRelative Conting
Pizzi Necess ETRelative Conting
Contingency
1
As stated in Humberstone [2002], “where S is a -based modal logic, SΔ is to be
its Δ + Boolean connectives fragment, thinking of Δ as having been introduced into S
by the definition of ΔA as A ∨ ¬A”(p.123). For the above quoted negative result see
especially Cresswell [1988]. Cresswell proved that, with the exception of some anomalous
normal systems (as for instance K +Verum) systems weaker than KT cannot in general
grant the definability of in terms of Δ.
(i) W = ∅
(ii) Wτ ⊆ W
Necessity and Relative Contingency 405
397
(iv) V is defined as usual for truth-functional wffs and for the other
wffs by the following two clauses:
(iv1) V(τ, x) = 1 iff x ∈ Wτ
(iv2) V(ΔA, x) = 1 iff for every y such that xRy and every y s.t. xRy ,
V(A,y) = V(A,y ).
Obviously in place of (iv2) we could have
(iv2’) V(∇A,x) = 1 iff for some y such that xRy and some y s.t. xRy ,
V(A,y) = V(A,y ).
2
After removing axiom KΔ4 we lack an axiom governing τ , so τ plays the same role of
a variable and does not add new theorem schemata to system KΔ. A KΔ-model can then
be redefined as a 4-ple W, Wτ , R, V where W, R, V are as in traditional KΔ-models,
Wτ ⊆ W but τ is not bound to the interpretation described by the condition (iv1):
V(τ, x) = 1 iff x ∈ Wτ . Every KΔτ -model may be then be considered a 4-ple which is a
special case of a KΔ-model.
406
398 C. Pizzi
3
For this approach to the semantics of KΔτ see Pizzi [2006].
Necessity and Relative Contingency 407
399
p
0
@
@
@
@
@
R
@
-
' $
τ τ
0 1
& %
@
I
@ @ @
I
@ @
@ @ @ @
@ @ @ @
@ @ @ @
@ @@
R @ @@
R
'- $
τ τ
1 0
& %
The proof of the following three theorems is easy and will be omitted:
(1) ♦τ ⊃ ( (τ ⊃ p) ⊃ ♦p) K
(2) (τ ⊃ p) ⊃ ♦p (1), ♦τ
(3) (♦p ∧ (p ∨ ¬p)) ⊃ p K
(4) (τ ⊃ p) ⊃ ((p ∨ ¬p) ⊃ p) (2), (3)
(5) (p ∨ ¬p) ⊃ ((τ ⊃ p) ⊃ p) (4), PC
(6) (♦¬τ ∧ ¬p) ⊃ ((τ ∧ ¬p) ⊃ p) K
410
402 C. Pizzi
Remark. The tableau procedure makes it easy to check that the following
are theses of both KΔτ and Kτ :
1) ∇τ ≡ ♦τ
2) τ ≡ Δτ
3) (τ ⊃ A) ≡ Δ(τ ⊃ A)
4) ♦(τ ∧ A) ≡ ∇(τ ∧ A)
The last equivalence shows that the confusion between possibility and
contingency, which is often pointed as an incongruity in Aristotle’s Organon,
is a logical truth for every A which is coinjoined with some contingent stock
of given information.
§3. We are now able to prove that the fragment of KΔτ + Def containing
no occurrences of t is exactly KD, i.e. the deontic system K + ♦T. The
proof runs in two parts:
Proof. We already know that all the theorems of K are theorems of Kτ
+ Def Δ.
♦τ ⊃ ♦T is a substitution instance of the K-theorem ♦p ⊃ ♦T. So by axiom
(Bτ ) ♦T is a theorem of Kτ + Def Δ.
Proof. Suppose there is some world x in some weakly τ -forked model which
gives value 0 to Axiom KΔτ *, which means that in x ∇τ is 0 and Δp is 0.
There are two alternatives to be considered:
1)¬∃y xRy. In this case in x Δp is vacuously true for every instance of p,
contrary to the supposition
2) ∃y1 ∃y2 ((xRy1 ∧ y1 ∈ Wτ ) ∧ (xRy2 ∧ y2 ∈ Wτ )). In this case ∇τ is true
in x, contrary to the supposition.
Remark. Theorem 12 implies that the two systems KΔτ and KΔτ w are
distinct. In fact the axiom ∇τ of KΔτ takes value 0 in weakly τ -forked
model where W = {x} and x is a dead end.
Let us consider now a system Kτ w which is K extended with the axiom
(Necτ w ) τ ≡ ¬τ .
414
406 C. Pizzi
Theorem 15. KΔτ w is complete with respect to the class of KΔτ w-models.
§5. As a final comment, we have to stress that the relation between the
modal system Kτ + DefΔ and the equivalent contingential system KΔτ
+ Def is not the same which obtains between Kτ w + Def Δ and the
equivalent contingential system KΔτ w + Def. The characteristic axiom
♦τ ∧ ♦¬τ of Kτ is the -variant of the characteristic axiom ∇τ of KΔτ ;
Necessity and Relative Contingency 417
409
4
A theorem concerning this semantic aspect of the language LΔ may be found in J.
Marcos [2005], p.203.
418
410 C. Pizzi
It appears then that there are expressive limits of the contingential lan-
guage which cannot be easily overcome by the introduction of a propositional
constant. It may be conjectured that a different definition of necessity in
terms of contingency or the introduction of stronger constrains on the propo-
sitional constant τ might allow to identify a modal system with the required
properties. The problem opened by this difficulty however lies beyond the
scope of the present paper.
References
[1] Cresswell, M. J., ‘Necessity and Contingency’, Studia Logica 47 (1988), 145–149.
[2] Hughes, G. E., and M. J. Cresswell, An Introduction to to Modal Logic, Methuen,
London, 1968.
[3] Humberstone, I. L., ‘The Logic of Non-Contingency’, Notre Dame Journal of Formal
Logic 36 (1992), 214–234.
[4] Humberstone, I. L., ‘The Modal Logic of Agreement and Non Contingency’, Notre
Dame Journal of Formal Logic 43 (2002), 95–127.
[5] Kuhn, T. S., ‘Minimal Non-contingency Logics’, Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic
36 (1995), 230–234.
[6] Marcos, J., Logics of Formal Inconsistencies, Ph.D. Thesis, UNICAMP, Campinas
University, 2005.
[7] Pizzi, C., ‘Contingency Logics and Propositional Quantification’, Manuscrito, UNI-
CAMP, Campinas University, 22, (1999), 283–303.
[8] Pizzi, C., ‘A Logic of Contingency with a Propositional Constant’, in E. Ballo and
M. Franchella (eds.), Logic and Philosophy in Italy, Polimetrica, Milano, 2006, pp.
141–151.
Claudio Pizzi
Dipartimento di Filosofia e Scienze Sociali
Università di Siena
via Roma 47 -53100 Siena
Siena, Italy
[email protected]