Thorstein Veblen and Socialism
Thorstein Veblen and Socialism
Geoffrey M. Hodgson
To cite this article: Geoffrey M. Hodgson (2023) Thorstein Veblen and Socialism, Journal of
Economic Issues, 57:4, 1162-1177, DOI: 10.1080/00213624.2023.2273138
To link to this article: https://doi.org/10.1080/00213624.2023.2273138
Geoffrey M. Hodgson is Emeritus professor at Loughborough University, London. The author thanks Bill Waller
and anonymous referees for helpful comments on a previous draft of this essay.
1
www.collinsdictionary.com/dictionary/english/socialism. Accessed January 16, 2022.
1162
© 2023, The Author(s). Published with license by Taylor and Francis Group, LLC.
This is an Open Access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial License
(https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0/), which permits unrestricted noncommercial use, distribution, and
reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited. The terms on which this article has been published
allow the posting of the Accepted Manuscript in a repository by the author(s) or with their consent.
Thorstein Veblen and Socialism 1163
Few other leading early American institutional economists were socialists. Many of
them, including John Maurice Clark, John R. Commons, Morris A. Copeland, Walton H.
Hamilton, and Wesley C. Mitchell, supported a regulated capitalism with a welfare state.
Veblen was an outlier on this issue. That is another reason why a more detailed excavation
and assessment of his views on socialism is overdue.
Works focusing on Veblen’s political views are relatively rare. H. J. Hodder (1956,
347) argued that “Veblen’s political and social thought can be most clearly understood and
evaluated in terms of philosophical anarchism.” But while there is plentiful evidence of
Veblen’s critical stance against traditional authority, this does not imply that he was an
anarchist. Other than his anti-authoritarianism, his qualms about state socialism and his
frequent wariness of the state, there is no clear support for this anarchist interpretation of
his politics. By contrast, in their book on Veblen’s politics, Sidney Plotkin and Rick Tilman
(2011) assumed (rightly in my view) that Veblen was a kind of socialist. But their book
includes few direct quotes from Veblen on this topic and offers little further detail on his
socialist opinions. Their volume does not mention Veblen’s (1901a, 231–232; 1904, 337–
339) criticisms of the general vagueness of socialist proposals for a future society, and it
overlooks Veblen’s (1923, 9) move away from socialism in his final years.
The following two sections assemble and discuss direct quotes from Veblen on
socialism and related issues, mostly in chronological order. These citations vary in length
and importance. He also devoted much attention to Marxist theory, but these instances are
relevant to our discussion here only insofar as they relate to the nature of socialism and its
feasibility.
Veblen was generally reluctant to reveal his normative view on socialism, and much
of his published material on this topic is descriptive or analytic. While Veblen was at the
University of Chicago in 1892–1906, and at Stanford University in 1906–1909, he taught
courses on socialism. He made his students aware of varied works, including some that are
critical of that doctrine. Joseph Dorfman (1934, 247, 253) claimed that during his courses
on socialism Veblen never revealed whether he was for or against such a system. Even in the
company of his first wife “he preserved his usual non-committal attitude towards socialism.”
This normative reticence adds to our difficulties in exhuming Veblen’s views on the topic.
But he does give us several clues about his political alignment.
In 1881, while a student at Carleton College, Veblen produced an essay on “J. S. Mill’s Theory
of the Taxation of Land.” No known copy exists, but a brief summary is available. It is clear
that Veblen then advocated a redistribution of wealth and “almost universal nationalization
of land” (Camic and Hodgson 2011, 53). This was shortly after the publication of Henry
George’s influential Progress and Poverty. George (1879) was not strictly a socialist, but he did
advocate land nationalization. It seems that Veblen followed George on that issue.
When Edward Bellamy’s (1888) novel sketching the socialist utopia of the future swept
America, Veblen and his wife read it together (Dorfman 1934, 68). But we have to wait ten
years after his essay on Mill for Veblen’s stance on socialism to be revealed in more detail. In
his article entitled “Some Neglected Points in the Theory of Socialism,” Veblen (1891, 345)
addressed Herbert Spencer’s critique of socialism. Veblen explicitly avoided the question of
the “present feasibility of any socialist scheme.” Instead, he raised “a point not adequately
1164 Geoffrey M. Hodgson
covered by Mr. Spencer’s discussion, and which has received but very scanty attention at the
hands of any other writer on either side of the socialist controversy.”
In this essay, Veblen (1891, 346–355) charged that Spencer misunderstood the drivers
behind the demand for socialism. Veblen traced this source to the modern industrial system
that “is based on the institution of private property under free competition,” and engenders
a “struggle of keep up appearances by otherwise unnecessary expenditure” on tokens of
“economic success” and shows “of luxury”—a struggle that breeds, among the poorer, some
considerable “emulation and . . . jealousy.” But “with the abolition of private property,”
socialism will end this “wasteful” process. Veblen did not consider whether much greater
economic equality within a system of private enterprise would be an adequate remedy. But
he signaled here the issues of emulation and conspicuous consumption that were to become
prominent features of his work. He also revealed some sympathy for socialism.
Veblen (1891, 357–358, 361) also rebutted Spencer’s claim that socialism meant
“compulsory cooperation . . . identified with the system of status and defined as the subjection
of man to his fellow-man.” Veblen objected that private enterprise and state compulsion were
“not logically exhaustive” as options. He claimed that socialism could instead be conjoined
with “modern constitutional government—the system of modern free institutions.”
The possibility of combining large-scale socialism with democracy has long been
controversial (Schäffle 1874; 1885; 1892; Hayek 1944; Hodgson 2019). It is not enough to
outline the logical options. The question is whether the desired combinations are feasible.
The possibility also has to be considered that a concentration of economic power would lead
unavoidably to a despotic concentration of bureaucratic and political power. If that were
the case, then widespread public ownership would undermine the countervailing politico-
economic powers required to sustain democracy. Veblen never discussed this argument.
Veblen then mentioned socialism in four book reviews, all appearing in the Journal
of Political Economy, of which he was then editor. Veblen (1893a; 1893b) briefly reviewed
two histories of socialism, without adding much further insight on his own opinions on
the subject. Veblen (1894a) reviewed a book by Karl Kautsky, where the author defended
representative and parliamentary democracy. Veblen saw Kautsky’s position as a limited
accommodation to existing institutions. Otherwise, Veblen gave little indication of his own
views. In another review, Veblen (1894c) praised a bibliographic reference work on socialism
and communism by Joseph Stammhammer.
Veblen’s (1894b) note on the “Army of the Commonweal” referred to a major protest
march of unemployed American workers in that year. It reveals a little more about Veblen’s
own views. While sympathizing with the plight and aims of the protestors, Veblen (1894b,
458) noted that their appeal was very much for the state machine to act on their behalf.
Such an outcome would be “extremely doubtful” because it would involve a “paternalism, or
socialism, on a scale that is not borne out by the experience of the past.” Veblen (1894b, 459)
noted that their appeal was “to the general government, and through the general government
to all the rest of the community, without intermediation of any lower or local body.” This
failure to consider local and other intermediate institutions reminded Veblen (1894b, 460)
of “the Socialists of the Chair, whose point of departure is the divine right of the State; whose
catch-word is: “Look to the State;” whose maxim of political wisdom is: “‘The State can do
no wrong.’ . . . It is the spirit of loyalty, petition, and submission to a vicarious providence.
This position has been euphemistically termed State Socialism, but it is, in principle, related
to socialism as the absolute monarchy is to the republic.” Here, more clearly than before,
Thorstein Veblen and Socialism 1165
Veblen distanced himself from state socialism. But he did not elaborate on the institutions
and conditions that would be necessary for socialism to be decentralized. He never provided
an institutional sketch of a decentralized socialism along these lines.2
This was a major omission. A key question is through what mechanisms the devolved,
small-scale socialist units coordinate with each other, and how resources are distributed
nationally and globally. If this is to be done by state planners, then the system becomes a
form of state socialism, despite devolutionary sentiments to the contrary. The alternative
option is to embrace markets as coordinating mechanisms, with a diminished role for the
state. Arguably, it is only with markets that small-scale socialism can remain viable (Hodgson
2019). But Veblen, like many other socialists, rejected all markets.
A further eight reviews in the Journal of Political Economy are mostly on texts about
socialism. Veblen’s (1895) review of Socialism by Robert Flint raises a number of objections
to Flint’s arguments against socialism and laments his lack of impartiality. There is also
a mention of Albert Schäffle’s (1874; 1885; 1892) work, which contain important early
arguments on the unfeasibility of democratic socialism (Hodgson 2007 and 2010).3 Veblen
(1896) then published a combined review of Marx’s Misére de la Philosophie and Enrico
Ferri’s Socialisme et Science Positive. Passing quickly over Marx’s work, Veblen devoted
more attention to Ferri’s juxtaposition of the ideas of Darwin, Spencer, and Marx. I have
argued elsewhere that this review played a significant part in Veblen’s development of his
Darwinian version of evolutionary economics (Hodgson 2004, 140ff.; Camic and Hodgson
2011, 49–50). But we focus here on the issue of socialism. Ferri defended socialism against
what he saw as Darwinian objections, including the evolutionary emphasis on competition,
struggle, differentiation and inequality. But Veblen (1896, 100–101) saw Ferri’s depiction of
Darwinism as “illegitimate.” He countered Ferri with this argument:
The struggle for existence, and therefore the fact of a selective adaptation,
is a fact inseparable from the life process, and therefore inseparable from
the life of mankind; but while its scope remains unaltered, the forms under
which it expresses itself in the life of society change as the development
of collective life proceeds. The most striking general modification . . . is
seen in transformation of this struggle for existence . . . into a struggle
for equality. . . . This struggle for equality, as is to some extent true of any
other expression of the struggle within a given society, takes the form of
a struggle between classes, and necessarily so. It is therefore a struggle for
existence on the basis of solidarity and co-operation.
Hence, by echoing the place of cooperation in Darwin’s (1871) theory of human
evolution, Veblen saw socialism and Darwinism as compatible. Veblen’s next review is
of a German text on socialism by Richard Calwer. Among other things, Veblen (1897a)
2
Veblen was writing before the rise of the guild socialist movement (Cole 1920). Elsewhere (Hodgson
2023) it is argued that Cole’s model of decentralized power with public ownership is unfeasible, and, despite his
intentions, it would lead to concentrated power at the center.
3
Notes taken by his students, including those of John G. Thompson (held in the Joseph Dorfman archive at
Columbia University), Schäffle’s The Impossibility of Social Democracy came to the attention of the students attending
Veblen’s lecture course at the University of Chicago in October-December 1903. The same book (copies of which
are extremely rare) can be found in the library at Stanford University. Note that, in Schäffle’s time, social democracy
and socialism were virtual synonyms. Schäffle’s book would be better titled today as The Impossibility of Democratic
Socialism. In the twentieth century, the term social democracy shifted in meaning, and it came to be associated with
the promotion of a mixed economy with markets, alongside a strong and redistributive welfare state. This major
change was clear in the policy declarations of the German Social Democratic Party (SPD) at its Bad Godesberg
Congress in 1959 (Hodgson 2021, 10–13).
1166 Geoffrey M. Hodgson
highlighted Calwer’s insistence that socialism should ideally come by peaceful means. The
following four relevant reviews by Veblen (1897b; 1897c; 1898a; 1898b) provide relatively
little illumination on his own views on socialism, other than by indicating his rejection of
the labor theory of value.
Veblen’s essay on “The Beginnings of Ownership” is relevant to this discussion only
insofar that its author distanced himself from the Marxist notion of primitive communism.
For Veblen (1898c, 358) “no concept of ownership, either communal or individual, applies
in the primitive community. The idea of communal ownership is of a relatively late growth.”
In a review in a politics journal, Veblen (1899a) gave socialism a very brief mention. Veblen’s
(1899b) first book, entitled the Theory of the Leisure Class mentions neither socialism nor
communism in its text.
The next significant mention of socialism is in a 1901 essay. There Veblen (1901a, 231–
232) referred near the end to “what is vaguely called socialism” and “socialist vagaries,” thus
gently chiding prominent advocates, including perhaps himself, while noting that “socialistic
thinking . . . contemplates . . . the elimination of the institution of property.” Veblen (1901b)
also noted Gustav Schmoller’s hostility to socialism, but without much further comment.
The discussion of socialism in Veblen’s The Theory of Business Enterprise (1904) is
longer than in any other of his works. There Veblen (1904, 331–356) devoted twenty-six
pages to socialism and trade unionism. But these pages are more about the causes of these
social movements, than of the nature, feasibility, or validity of socialism. Veblen (1904,
338) made it clear that his discussion addressed the “causes of the socialist disaffection; it
does not concern the profounder and more delicate point, as to the validity of the socialist
contentions.”
Nevertheless, he did make some brief revealing comments on socialist doctrines. Veblen
(1904, 337–338) noted: “[t]here is little agreement among socialists as to a programme for
the future. Their constructive proposals are ill-defined and inconsistent and almost entirely
negative. . . . Current socialism is an animus of dissent from received traditions.” In a footnote
Veblen (1904, 339n.) added that socialism “demands a reconstruction of the social fabric,
but it does not know on what lines the reconstruction is to be carried out.” These remarks
again highlight Veblen’s worry that socialists had “little to offer” beyond vague generalities.
In the same footnote he expressed another concern: “it is difficult to see how any
scheme of civil rights, more or little, can find a place in a socialistic reorganization.” This
was another vital insight, especially in the light of later revolutionary events in Russia and
elsewhere. The problem of “vagueness” of proposals concerning the nature and organization
of a socialist society, plus the concern about the compatibility of socialism with civil rights,
were some years later to be dramatized after the Bolshevik seizure of power. The Bolsheviks
found that the socialist literature offered little guidance on policies. And civil rights were
quickly eroded.
Some pages later, Veblen (1904, 355–356) made another important claim: “[t]he
political bias of this unmitigated socialism is always radically democratic . . . The state is
doomed in the socialistic view. The socialist antagonism to the state takes various forms”
and “socialist malcontents” have the conviction that “the community can best get along
without political institutions.” Here Veblen highlighted versions of socialism based on direct
community democracy, which is supposed, somehow, to eventually dispense with the state
Thorstein Veblen and Socialism 1167
and all political institutions. But Veblen offers no institutional detail on how this would
work. Here he suffered from the same “vagueness” that he found in others.
We now turn to Veblen’s (1906b; 1907) two-part essay on “The Socialist Economics of
Karl Marx and His Followers.” This important work offers a penetrating critique of Marxist
theoretical analysis, but it provides very little on the nature or feasibility of socialism. In one
important passage, Veblen (1906b, 582) attacked the teleological view of history in Marxism
with “the assumed goal of the Marxian process of class struggle, which is conceived to cease
in the classless economic structure of the socialistic final term. In Darwinism there is no
such final or perfect term, and no definitive equilibrium.” Veblen (1907, 309) added: “[i]t
is quite impossible on Darwinian ground to foretell whether the ‘proletariat’ will go on to
establish the socialistic revolution or turn aside again, and sink their force in the broader
sands of patriotism.” Hence Veblen rejected notions of socialist inevitability or proletarian
destiny. In a note on the extent of public ownership after the socialist revolution, Veblen
(1907, 309) reported that “the peasant. proprietors will not be disturbed in their holdings
by the great change. The great change is to deal with capitalistic enterprise.” In a footnote
Veblen (1906b, 578n.) referred to Schäffle’s (1874; 1885; 1892) publications (which argue
that democratic socialism is not feasible) but without any further exploration of Schäffle’s
argument. Veblen’s two-part essay on Marxism has huge strengths, but exegesis on the nature
and feasibility of socialism is not one of them.
No substantial discussion of socialism is found in any of Veblen’s works from 1908 to
1920 inclusive. Veblen’s 1921 book on The Engineers and the Price System is a collection of
papers that Veblen published previously in The Dial. There Veblen (1921a, 87–88) wrote:
“[n]o movement for the dispossession of the Vested Interests in America can hope for even
a temporary success unless it is undertaken by an organization which is competent to take
over the country’s productive industry as a whole, and to administer it from a more efficient
plan.” But it is not shown how such comprehensive planning would be compatible with the
extensive democracy that he advocated previously, or how it could avoid the state socialism
that he had warned against (Veblen 1894b, 458–460; 1904, 355–356).
Veblen (1921a, 134) added: “[t]he chances of anything like a Soviet in America, therefore,
are the chances of a Soviet of technicians” but this “is at the most remote contingency.”
Edwin Layton (1962) argued persuasively that Veblen had earlier put his radical hopes in
the engineers, but he had mis-read nature and motivation of their professional organizations
in the United States. It is also symptomatic that Veblen saw the operation of an economic
system as largely a matter of technical knowledge and efficiency, and not additionally of
devolved incentives and of the institutional processing of dispersed knowledge. The failure
of Veblen’s project to recruit and energize the engineers seems to have added to his mood of
despondency concerning the possibility of socialism after the end of the First World War.
A substantial shift in Veblen’s stance on socialism was revealed in an article he published
in a non-academic journal in 1921. In “Between Bolshevism and War” he compared the
failures of “orthodox” socialism with the success of the Bolsheviks in Russia. As in previous
works, he referred to the abolition of “absentee ownership” as the vital goal of any radical
movement aiming to improve conditions. Veblen (1934, 440–441) wrote:
In such a movement to dispossess the absentee owners the Soviet also
displaces democracy and representative government, and necessarily so,
because democracy and representative government have proved to be
1168 Geoffrey M. Hodgson
incompetent and irrelevant for any other purpose than the security and
profitable regulation of absentee ownership.
Here, in contrast to his 1891 essay on Spencer quoted above, Veblen seemed willing to sacrifice
parliamentary democracy as well. Veblen (1934, 441) tried to persuade his American readers
by assuring them that “the Soviet appears to be very closely analogous to the town-meeting
as known in New England history.” But at best the analogy is loose. Soviets were based
on the workplace and excluded non-employees. The Russian Soviets became dominated
by the Communist party-state. By contrast, New England town meetings are open to all
citizens, within a multi-party democracy. Veblen (1934, 442) returned to his comparison
between orthodox socialism and Bolshevism: “Socialism is a dead horse; whereas it appears
that Bolshevism is not . . . The Socialists had hoped to preserve the established political
organisation intact, and eventually to take it over for their own use; the Bolshevists appear to
harbor no such fancy.” Veblen (1934, 447–448) concluded his 1921 article on this climactic
note: “[t]he established order, economic and political, rests on material circumstances which
ceased to exist some time ago . . . The experience of the past few years has shown plainly
enough that the established businesslike system of ownership and control will no longer
work.”
But it is unclear whether Veblen’s brief celebration of Bolshevism was anything more
than the result of despair after the failures of orthodox socialism during and after the war,
in obvious contrast to revolutionary success in Russia. In a letter dated August 26, 1922,
to editor W. P. Noon, where he declined to review for the Political Science Quarterly two
books on socialism, Veblen wrote: “[b]ooks on socialism . . . do not interest me. [In] my
opinion Socialism is a dead issue. Too dead to be a live topic, and too lately dead for objective
historical treatment.”4
Veblen (1923, 9) briefly mentioned socialism in his book on Absentee Ownership: “[t]he
standard formalities of ‘Socialism’ and ‘Anti-socialism’ are obsolete in face of the new
alignment of economic forces. It is now not so much a question of equity in the distribution
of incomes, but rather a question of expediency as regards the absentee management of
productive industry.” Here Veblen suggested that new thinking was required that went
beyond the label of socialism itself. But again he was very unclear about the details. By that
time, Veblen was cut adrift from academia and lacking in political moorings. His excavations
of socialism had ended years before. He died in 1929.
We now turn to aspects of Veblen’s theoretical writings that may indirectly provide clues
on how he dealt with issues that related to socialism and its workability. Veblen is widely
associated with the idea that institutions come into conflict with technological development.
According to Clarence Ayres (1973, v), Veblen “made the dichotomy of technology and
ceremonialism his master principle.” Ayres (1961, 30) also saw institutions as essentially
ceremonial, and hence the “Veblenian dichotomy” between institutions and technology
entered the literature (Waller 1982 and 1994).
Veblen’s writings tell a slightly different story. His position is different from that which
Ayres attributed to him. There is no clear “dichotomy of technology and ceremonialism” in
4
In Joseph Dorfman Papers, Columbia University, quoted in Tilman (1996, 197) and in Camic (2020, 468).
Underlining as in the original.
Thorstein Veblen and Socialism 1169
Veblen’s writing. Likewise, there is not much evidence in his writings of a general dichotomy
between technology and institutions (Hodgson 2004, chap. 17). The more persistent
dichotomy in his work is between “industrial” and “pecuniary” activities, or between “industry”
and “business.” Veblen (1899c, 114; 1901a, 206) explained that this distinction between
“pecuniary” and “industrial” employments “marks the difference between workmanship
and bargaining,” or production and distribution. For Veblen, “industrial” employment
includes labor and management leading to production. “Pecuniary” employment relates to
the valuation, marketing and distribution of that which is produced.
Veblen (1899c, 113) explained that the aim of this distinction is “to indicate the
different economic value of the aptitudes and habits of thought fostered by the one and the
other class of employments.” As Veblen himself suggested, this dichotomy has its precursors
in the classical distinctions between productive and unproductive labor, and between use
value and exchange value. Veblen (1899c, 115) also referred approvingly to John Stuart
Mill’s claim that production—by contrast to distribution—is essentially a matter of the laws
of nature.5
Marx had a similar view. Gerald A. Cohen (1978, 108–111) showed that the separation
(by Mill and others) of the “natural,” “material,” or technological content of production from
its (historically specific) social form is equivalent to Marx’s distinction between “forces” and
“social relations” of production. Cohen also showed that Marx’s attempt to criticize Mill’s
account is a failure. It is possible that Mill influenced Marx on this issue. It is also possible
that Veblen took on board the dichotomy between technology and social relations from
Marx as well as from Mill.
Cohen (1978, 105) highlighted the significance for Marx of this distinction between
socio-economic form and material content, “[b]y inviting focus on the material process
operating within the capitalist economic form, it discredits capital’s pretension to being
an irreplaceable means of creating material wealth.” Veblen also thought that capitalism
was replaceable. He focused on historically specific social relations in a market economy,
including those that gave rise to pecuniary goals. Hence Veblen’s distinction between
“industrial” (material) and “pecuniary” (specific socio-economic) employments was used in
attempts to discredit markets, private property, and pecuniary motivation.
While technology was seen as subject to the laws of the natural sciences, both Marx
and Mill saw alternative arrangements concerning distribution and social organization as
possible. But they differed on what they saw as possible or desirable. Marx promoted a form
of state socialism, without markets. By contrast, Mill ([1871] 1909, 209–217, 792; [1879]
2009, 221–279) favored worker cooperatives but insisted that they should also be private
ownership and market competition. While sharing, with Mill and Marx, their separation
of “physical” productive forces from social organization and distribution, Veblen took an
unclear, third normative position. He embraced socialism but rejected both state socialism
and markets.6
According to Veblen (1899c, 114), pecuniary employments “rest on the institution
of private property” while industrial employments “rest chiefly on the physical conditions
of human life.” Similarly, Veblen (1901a, 205) suggested that while business centers on the
“higgling of the market,” industrial employments are aimed at “the shaping and guiding
5
Mill ([1871] 1909, 199) wrote: “[t]he laws and conditions of the Production of wealth partake of the
character of physical truths. There is nothing optional, or arbitrary in them.”
6
See Hodgson (2019, chap. 2) for arguments that viable decentralized socialism requires markets.
1170 Geoffrey M. Hodgson
of material things and processes.” Industry is “primarily occupied with . . . material
serviceability . . . rather than . . . exchange value” and is to be understood in terms of
“[p]hysics and the other material sciences.”
A problem with this argument, which derives from Mill and Marx, is that (physical)
industrial output depends upon and is affected by the (social) organization of the firm.
Social relations permeate industrial as well as pecuniary employments. Even if we avoid
the extremes of social constructivism, there is a large literature testifying to the interaction
and inseparability of social technology and organization.7 From this viewpoint, production
is necessarily institutional, and it cannot be reduced to physical conditions without the
inclusion of organizational and motivational matters as well.
Veblen (1901a, 205–206) admitted that pecuniary and industrial activities interact and
“business activity may . . . effect an enhancement of the aggregate material wealth of the
community, or the aggregate serviceability of the means at hand.” He acknowledged that
particular business arrangements often lead to greater industrial output. Veblen (1901a,
209–210) went as far to admit that “shrewd business management is a requisite to success
in any industry that is carried on within the scope of the market. Pecuniary failure carries
with it industrial failure . . . In this way industrial results are closely dependent upon the
presence of business ability.” Here Veblen admitted that technology was tied up with matters
of management and ability that affected its outputs.8
But this 1901 admission has two defects. First, despite his institutionalism, he accounted
for differences in output that are due to different business arrangements on output in terms
of the “business ability” of individuals. He omitted the nature or structure of organizations.
Technology is bound up with social relations and organizations as well.
Second, while assuming that it is possible, Veblen avoided the question of how industry
could be organized outside “the scope of the market” and whether a greater or lesser industrial
output would result. While he was normatively disposed towards non-market solutions, he
did not explain in detail what they are, or how they would work. Veblen (1914, 24n.) wrote
that the “all-pervading modern institution of private property appears to have . . . grown out
of the self-regarding bias of men in their oversight of the community’s material interests.”
This suggests that “the community’s material interests” are not served by private property.
But Veblen failed to give an account of how an alternative society could be organized without
private property or markets—how knowledge would be tapped and used, how decisions would
be delegated and made, how people would be incentivized to work effectively, and how the
rewards of production would be distributed. Hence the institutionalist John Maurice Clark
objected:
As for the technical processes, neither Veblen nor anyone else has ever
shown how social efficiency can be organized on a technical basis alone.
. . . Veblen’s antithesis [between business and industry], valuable as it is
as a challenge to orthodoxy, cannot serve the purposes of a constructive
search for the line of progress. This calls for an evolution of our scheme
7
See, for example, Suchman (1987), Button (1993), Star (1995), Collins and Kusch (1998).
8
In a later publication, Veblen moved slightly closer to a view that technology is inextricably entwined with
social relations. Veblen (1923, 280) wrote: “[t]he technological system is an organisation of intelligence, a structure
of intangibles and imponderables, in the nature of habits of thought. It resides in the habits of thoughts of the
community and comes to a head in the habits of thought of the technicians.”
Thorstein Veblen and Socialism 1171
of values, not for a ‘technocracy’ which ignores value. (Clarke and Bye
1925, 57)
Veblen (1921a, 100) declared: “Twentieth-century technology has outgrown the
eighteenth-century system of vested rights.” But he did not describe the system of economic
organization and coordination that was appropriate for twentieth-century technology. He
never gave a detailed picture of an alternative mode of organization of modern industrial
society, other than his vague references to a “Soviet of engineers” or an “industrial directorate”
of experts (Veblen 1921a, 144). With his insufficiently grounded presumption that private
property and markets are entirely dispensable, Veblen converged with Marxism, despite his
other analytical differences with that doctrine.
If production is inseparable from organization and motivation, then we have to face the
question of organizational and other incentives. In modern economies, are private property
and markets essential spurs to innovation, entrepreneurship and economic growth? No-one
has yet provided an adequately detailed and viable account of how a large-scale, complex,
modern economy can be organized without some private property and some markets.
Arguably incentives could be maintained in a mixed economy where the state also plays a
major role, as found in many modern economies. These questions are of course controversial.
Sadly, on such matters, Veblen is of little help. Like many socialists of his time and ours, he
simply assumed that markets are dispensable.9
Veblen had a highly sophisticated view of the role of productive knowledge, which compares
well with the views of many of his contemporary economists. Following Charles Sander
Peirce, William James, and others, Veblen stressed that all knowledge is rooted in ingrained
habits. He argued that the social complex of interacting individual habits constituted a social
stock of knowledge that could not be associated with individuals taken severally. As Veblen
(1898c, 353–354) put it:
Production takes place only in society—only through the co-operation
of an industrial community. This industrial community . . . always
comprises a group, large enough to contain and transmit the traditions,
tools, technical knowledge, and usages without which there can be no
industrial organization and no economic relation of individuals to
one another or to their environment. The isolated individual is not a
productive agent. What he can do at best is to live from season to season,
as the non-gregarious animals do. There can be no production without
technical knowledge; hence no accumulation and no wealth to be owned,
in severalty or otherwise. And there is no technical knowledge apart from
an industrial community.
Veblen (1908a, 539–540) argued that learning and experience are accumulated within a
community:
These immaterial industrial expedients are necessarily a product of the
community, the immaterial residue of the community’s experience, past
9
For further arguments and evidence on these points see Hodgson (2019).
1172 Geoffrey M. Hodgson
and present; which has no existence apart from the community’s life, and
can be transmitted only in the keeping of the community at large.
Veblen (1914, 103) repeated this point, referring to technological knowledge and its storage
in the social group:
Technological knowledge is of the nature of a common stock, held
and carried forward by the community, which is in this relation to be
conceived as a going concern. The state of the industrial arts is a fact of
group life, not of individual or private initiative or innovation. It is an
affair of the collectivity, not a creative achievement of individuals working
self-sufficiently in severalty or in isolation.
Nevertheless, he made it clear that the collective domain of knowledge devalues neither
the role of the individual, nor the fact that knowledge is always held by individuals and is a
matter of individual experience. As Veblen (1908a, 521) put it:
The complement of technological knowledge so held, used, and
transmitted in the life of the community is, of course, made up out of the
experience of individuals. Experience, experimentation, habit, knowledge,
initiative, are phenomena of individual life, and it is necessarily from this
source that the community’s common stock is all derived. The possibility
of growth lies in the feasibility of accumulating knowledge gained by
individual experience and initiative, and therefore it lies in the feasibility
of one individual’s learning from the experience of another.
The individual and the social aspects of knowledge are connected because the social
environment and its “common stock” of experience provide the means and stimulus to
individual learning. The social environment is the result of individual interactions, but
without this social environment the individual would be stultified. The above quotations
make it clear that Veblen saw the social domain as part of the storehouse of knowledge.
Veblen (1906a, 592) wrote of “habits of thought that rule in the working-out of a system of
knowledge” being “fostered by . . . the institutional structure under which the community
lives.”
With these arguments Veblen made a radical break from the view that production
is entirely a result of owned factors of production—such as land, capital, and labor—whose
owners can be remunerated according to their marginal products. Veblen (1921a, 28) argued
that production depended on a “joint stock of knowledge derived from past experience” that
itself could not become an individually owned commodity, because it involved the practices
of the whole industrial community. Producers were interdependent and it was difficult to
separate their individual contributions. This is part of Veblen’s (1908b) powerful critique of
neoclassical economics, and in particular of its theory of distribution.
But here we are concerned with the relevance of Veblen’s view of knowledge for his
theory of socialism. Friedrich Hayek’s (1944 and 1948) argument that comprehensive and
effective central planning are thwarted by the impossibility of bringing together all relevant
knowledge at the disposal of the central planners—as if in a single head—is well known. Hayek
argued that much knowledge is irretrievably dispersed. Like Michael Polanyi (1967), Hayek
(1952 and1988) stressed the importance and permanence of tacit knowledge.
Veblen’s argument is different in some respects, but it could lead to similar conclusions
about the difficulties inherent in central planning. Veblen’s argument concerning the
Thorstein Veblen and Socialism 1173
habitual nature of knowledge could be augmented by some notion of its unavoidable
tacitness. But this addition is not automatic. For example, John Dewey (1922)—who was
an influence on Veblen—also stressed that knowledge was grounded on habits. But Dewey
(1916, 401; 1927, 158, 209) argued that, in principle, knowledge could be widely shared and
made available to others. This might seem to make a nationwide system of socialist planning
possible. Sure enough, from the 1930s Dewey advocated a guild socialism that attempted
to combine some national planning with workers’ control of industry, as G. D. H. Cole
had proposed earlier (Cole 1920; Westbrook 1991, 249, 455–457). We can only speculate
whether Veblen would have taken a similar view if he had studied guild socialist writings.
Guild socialism reached its zenith in the early 1920s, after Veblen had become disillusioned
with conventional socialism.10
On deeper reflection it is difficult to reconcile Dewey’s view that knowledge is readily
transferable with his view that it is rooted in habits, which are never fully available to our
conscious mind. But that is what Dewey tried to claim. The economist Frank Knight (1936,
230) criticized Dewey’s view that much relevant knowledge could be readily shared as a
“vague mystical conception . . . a kind of intellectualized gregariousness.” There is no clear
indication whether Veblen would have followed Dewey or Knight on this issue. Given his
affinity to Dewey, we might guess the former. But any admission of the tacitness and restricted
transferability of much knowledge would have blocked the Deweyian option. According to
one analysis of the nature of tacit knowledge, its strongest and least transferable form is
associated with the complexities and ambiguities of language in the context of socialization:
“Society, which is responsible for all our collective tacit knowledge, runs on socialization and
language” (Collins 2010, 170).11 This undermines Dewey’s view of the eventual transferability
of most relevant knowledge, but chimes with Veblen’s insistence of its collective nature.
If Veblen had gone further to consider the roles of language and socialization, then his
emphasis on the collective and community-based nature of much knowledge might possibly
be used to show further difficulties in the way of central planning. But Veblen did not go
further in his writings. Yet it is possible, as a matter of conjecture, that Veblen’s apparent
(intuitive) preference for small-scale socialism, established in communities and workplaces,
may have been grounded in part on his community view of knowledge. More textual evidence
would be required to turn this conjecture into a sustainable proposition.
Conclusion
Veblen’s sympathy for socialism is clear in his writings from the 1880s to the First World
War. He was aware that socialism meant the abolition of private property, as Karl Marx
and Robert Owen had also made clear. Veblen regarded the system of private property as
“wasteful.” His reluctance to be more explicit about his normative views on the topic is
explicable in terms of the academic nature of most of his writings on this issue, and his
desire not to give more ammunition to academic authorities who had readily fired socialists
and other radicals in his time.
10
See Hodgson (2021, 15–16) for remarks on Dewey’s views on knowledge and socialism. Hodgson (2023)
shows that the guild socialists proposed nationalization rather than devolved common ownership and that their
system had an unavoidable centralizing dynamic.
11
For other views on tacit knowledge see Reber (1993), Collins (2010), Oğuz (2010), Gascoigne and
Thornton (2013).
1174 Geoffrey M. Hodgson
Several analytical themes emerge from his writings on socialism in this period. His
1891 essay on Spencer suggested that socialist public ownership could be combined with
democratic institutions. But while Veblen was aware of Schäffle’s (1874; 1885; 1892)
argument that democracy and widespread nationalization were incompatible, he did not
explicitly concur with that conclusion. Veblen did have strong qualms about state socialism
and excessive concentrations of central power. His 1894 essay on the “Army of the
Commonweal” calls for local organs of democratic representation. In 1904 he identified
socialism with direct community democracy and in a 1921 book he called for “soviets” of
engineers (Veblen 2021a). Consequently, while Veblen did not take the anarchist step of
immediately rejecting state legitimacy and power, he was concerned to build socialism on
democratic local organizations. But by the 1920s he was despondent about such possibilities.
Veblen repeatedly criticized other socialists for being unclear about the detail of their
proposals. Instead, according to him, socialists offered little explanation beyond vague
generalities. But despite this repeated criticism, Veblen himself offered no institutional
sketch of how socialism could work in detailed terms.
It is also revealing how Veblen’s views on socialism relate to other key aspects of his
thought. It is argued here that his dichotomy between “business” and “industry” (which
derives from Mill) played a role in his rejection of markets (as in the similar case of Marx).
But the view of industry that is shared by all three authors plays down its organization
character. Industry is as much about institutions and social relations as it is about the laws
of physics and chemistry.
Although Veblen had a sophisticated view of knowledge, emphasizing its embeddedness
in the community, as well as the role of individuals as its repositories, he is much less clear
on the question of its tacitness and transferability. These issues relate closely to the question
of socialism and the possibility (or otherwise) of large-scale comprehensive planning. If large
segments of knowledge relevant to planning cannot be accessed by the center, then planning
cannot adequately fulfill the socialist objectives of efficiency, fairness, and need satisfaction.
Much of Veblen’s legacy would remain if the aforementioned flaws were corrected.
His stress on institutions, his sophisticated psychological analysis, his perception of the
importance of Darwinism for social science, and his powerful criticisms of mainstream
economics and Marxism, would all endure, alongside much else of enormous value. But
the recognition that production is a social as well as a technological process, thus requiring
organizational structures and incentives, would undermine the presumed dichotomy with
“business” and the consequent blanket rejection of private property and markets. Likewise,
any emphasis on the tacitness and problematic transferability of knowledge would move
us in a similarly skeptical direction on the question of socialism (as both traditionally and
currently defined) and of its feasibility. We might become even more cautious about socialist
possibilities than Veblen was in his later years.
Disclosure Statement
No potential conflict of interest was reported by the author.
References
Ayres, Clarence E. 1961. Toward a Reasonable Society: The Values of Industrial Civilization. Austin, TX: University of
Texas Press.
Ayres, Clarence E. 1973. “Prolegomeno to Institutionalism.” Introduction to the combined reprints of Science:
The False Messiah (1927), and Holier Than Thou: The Way of the Righteous (1929). Indianapolis: Augustus M.
Kelley.
Thorstein Veblen and Socialism 1175
Bellamy, Edward. 1888. Looking Backward, 2000–1887. Boston: Ticknor.
Bestor, Arthur E., Jr. 1948. “The Evolution of the Socialist Vocabulary.” Journal of the History of Ideas 9 (3):
259–302.
Button, Graham (ed.). 1993. Technology in Working Order: Studies of Work, Interaction and Technology. London and
New York: Routledge.
Camic, Charles. 2020. Veblen: The Making of an Economist who Unmade Economics. Cambridge, MA and London,
UK: Harvard University Press.
Camic, Charles, and Geoffrey M. Hodgson (eds.). 2011. Essential Writings of Thorstein Veblen. London and New
York: Routledge.
Clark, John Maurice and Raymond T. Bye. 1925. “Problems of Economic Theory—Discussion.” The American
Economic Review 15 (1): 56–61. Available at www.jstor.org/stable/1815277.
Cohen, Gerald A. 1978. Karl Marx’s Theory of History: A Defence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Cole, G. D. H. 1920. Guild Socialism Re-Stated. London: Parsons.
Collins COBUILD Advanced Learner’s Dictionary. HarperCollins Publishers. Available at www.collinsdictionary.
com/dictionary/english/socialism. Accessed January 16, 2022.
Collins, Harry. 2010. Tacit and Explicit Knowledge. Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press.
Collins, Harry, and Martin Kusch (eds.). 1998. The Shape of Actions—What Humans and Machines Can Do.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Darwin, Charles R. 1871.The Descent of Man, and Selection in Relation to Sex, 2 vols. London: Murray; New York:
Hill.
Dewey, John. 1916. Democracy and Education: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Education. New York: Macmillan.
Dewey, John.1922. Human Nature and Conduct: An Introduction to Social Psychology (New York: Holt).
Dewey, John. 1927. The Public and its Problems: An Essay in Political Inquiry (New York: Holt).
Dorfman, Joseph. 1934. Thorstein Veblen and His America. New York: Viking Press.
Gascoigne, Neil, and Tim Thornton. 2013. Tacit Knowledge. Durham UK and Bristol CT: Acumen.
George, Henry. 1879. Progress and Poverty: An Inquiry into the Cause of Industrial Depression and Increase of Want with
Increase of Wealth. London: Kegan Paul.
Hayek, Friedrich A. 1944. The Road to Serfdom. London: George Routledge.
Hayek, Friedrich A. 1948. Individualism and Economic Order. London and Chicago: George Routledge and
University of Chicago Press.
Hayek, Friedrich A. 1952. The Sensory Order: An Inquiry into the Foundations of Theoretical Psychology. London:
Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Hayek, Friedrich A. 1988. The Fatal Conceit: The Errors of Socialism. The Collected Works of Friedrich August Hayek,
Vol. I, edited by William W. Bartley III. London: Routledge.
Hodder, H. J. 1956. “The Political Ideas of Thorstein Veblen.” Canadian Journal of Economics and Political Science
22 (3): 347–357.
Hodgson, Geoffrey M. 2004. The Evolution of Institutional Economics: Agency, Structure and Darwinism in American
Institutionalism. London and New York: Routledge.
Hodgson, Geoffrey M. 2007. “The Impossibility of Social Democracy by Albert E. F. Schäffle.” Journal of
Institutional Economics 3 (1):113–125.
Hodgson, Geoffrey M. 2010. “Albert Schäffle’s Critique of Socialism.” In Economic Theory and Economic Thought:
Essays in Honour of Ian Steedman, edited by John Vint, J. Stanley Metcalfe, Heinz D. Kurz, Neri Salvadori,
and Paul A. Samuelson, 296–315. London and New York: Routledge.
Hodgson, Geoffrey M. 2019. Is Socialism Feasible? Towards an Alternative Future. Cheltenham UK and Northampton,
MA: Edward Elgar.
Hodgson, Geoffrey M. 2021. Liberal Solidarity: The Political Economy of Social Democratic Liberalism. Cheltenham UK
and Northampton, MA: Edward Elgar.
Hodgson, Geoffrey M. 2023. “The Institutional Impossibility of Guild Socialism.” Cambridge Journal of Economics
47 (1): 21–43. doi:10.1093/cje/beac057.
Knight, Frank H. 1936. “Pragmatism and Social Action.” International Journal of Ethics 46 (2): 229–236.
Layton, Edwin. 1962. “Veblen and the Engineers.” American Quarterly 14 (1): 64–72.
Mill, John Stuart. (1871) 1909. Principles of Political Economy with Some of Their Applications to Social Philosophy, 7th
edition. Edited by William Ashley. London and New York: Longmans, Green.
Mill, John Stuart. (1879) 2009. On Liberty and Other Writings. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Oğuz, Fuat. 2010. “Hayek on Tacit Knowledge.” Journal of Institutional Economics 6 (2): 145–165.
Polanyi, Michael. 1967. The Tacit Dimension. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Plotkin, Sidney, and Rick Tilman. 2011. Political Ideas of Thorstein Veblen. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Reber, Arthur S. 1993. Implicit Learning and Tacit Knowledge: An Essay on the Cognitive Unconscious. Oxford and New
York: Oxford University Press.
Schäffle, Albert E. F. 1874. Quintessenz des Sozialismus. Gotha: Perthes.
Schäffle, Albert E. F. 1885. Die Aussichtslosigkeit der Socialdemokratie. Drei Briefe an einen Staatsmann zur Ergänzung der
“Quintessenz des Sozialismus.” Tübingen: Laupp.
1176 Geoffrey M. Hodgson
Schäffle, Albert E. F. 1892. The Impossibility of Social Democracy: Being a Supplement to “The Quintessence of Socialism,”
translated from the 4th German edition of Schäffle (1885) by A. C. Morant with a preface by Bernard
Bosanquet. London: Swan Sonnenschein and New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons.
Star, Susan Leigh (ed.) 1995. Ecologies of Knowledge: Work and Politics in Science and Technology. Albany NY: State
University of New York Press.
Suchman, Lucy A. 1987. Plans and Situated Actions: The Problem of Human-Machine Communication. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Tilman, Rick. 1996. The Intellectual Legacy of Thorstein Veblen: Unresolved Issues. Westport, CTt: Greenwood Press.
Veblen, Thorstein B. 1891. “Some Neglected Points in the Theory of Socialism.” Annals of the American Academy of
Political and Social Science 2 (November): 345–362. Reprinted in Camic and Hodgson (2011).
Veblen, Thorstein B. 1893a. Review of A History of Socialism by Thomas Kirkup, Journal of Political Economy 1 (2):
300–302.
Veblen, Thorstein B. 1893b. Review of Geschichte des Socialismus und Communismus im 19 Jahrhundert by Otto
Warschauer, Journal of Political Economy 1 (2): 302.
Veblen, Thorstein B. 1894a. Review of Der Parlamentarismus, die Volksgesetzgebung und die Socialdemokratie by Karl
Kautsky, Journal of Political Economy 2 (2): 312–314. Reprinted in Camic and Hodgson (2011).
Veblen, Thorstein B. 1894b. “The Army of the Commonweal.” Journal of Political Economy 2 (3): 456–461.
Veblen, Thorstein B. 1894c Review of Bibliographie des Socialismus und Communismus by Joseph Stammhammer,
Journal of Political Economy 2 (3): 474–475.
Veblen, Thorstein B. 1895. Review of Socialism by Robert Flint, Journal of Political Economy 3 (2): 247–252.
Reprinted in Camic and Hodgson (2011).
Veblen, Thorstein B. 1896. “Review of Misére de la Philosophie by Karl Marx and Socialisme et Science Positive by
Enrico Ferri.” Journal of Political Economy 5 (1): 97–103. Reprinted in Camic and Hodgson (2011).
Veblen, Thorstein B. 1897a. “Review of Einfuhrung in den Socialismus by Richard Calwer.”
Journal of Political Economy 5 (2): 270–272. Reprinted in Camic and Hodgson (2011).
Veblen, Thorstein B. 1897b. “Review of Essais sur la conception matérialiste de l’histoire by Antonio Labriola.” Journal
of Political Economy 5 (3): 390–391. Reprinted in Camic and Hodgson (2011).
Veblen, Thorstein B. 1897c. “Review of Die Marxistische Socialdemokratie by Max Lorenz.” Journal of Political
Economy 6 (1): 136–137. Reprinted in Camic and Hodgson (2011).
Veblen, Thorstein B. 1898a. “Review of Aristocracy and Evolution: A Study of the Rights, the Origins and the Social
Functions of the Wealthier Classes by William H. Mallock.” Journal of Political Economy 6 (June): 430–435.
Reprinted in Camic and Hodgson (2011).
Veblen, Thorstein B. 1898b. “Review of Über einige Grundfragen der Socialpolitik und der Volkswirtschaftslehre by
Gustav Schmoller.” Journal of Political Economy 6 (3): 416–419. Reprinted in Camic and Hodgson (2011).
Veblen, Thorstein B. 1898c. “The Beginnings of Ownership.” American Journal of Sociology 4 (3): 352–365.
Reprinted in Veblen (1934) and Camic and Hodgson (2011).
Veblen, Thorstein B. 1899a. “Review of The Development of English Thought: A Study in the Economic Interpretation of
History by Simon N. Patten.” Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science 14 (July): 125–131.
Reprinted in Camic and Hodgson (2011).
Veblen, Thorstein B. 1899b. The Theory of the Leisure Class: An Economic Study in the Evolution of Institutions. New
York: Macmillan.
Veblen, Thorstein B. 1899c. “Mr. Cummings’s Strictures on The Theory of the Leisure Class.” Journal of Political
Economy 8 (1): 106–117. Reprinted in Camic and Hodgson (2011).
Veblen, Thorstein B. 1901a. “Industrial and Pecuniary Employments.” Publications of the American Economic
Association, Series 3, 2 (1): 190–235. Reprinted in Camic and Hodgson (2011).
Veblen, Thorstein B. 1901b. “Gustav Schmoller’s Economics.” Quarterly Journal of Economics 16 (1): 69–93.
Reprinted in Camic and Hodgson (2011).
Veblen, Thorstein B. 1904. The Theory of Business Enterprise. New York: Charles Scribner’s.
Veblen, Thorstein B. 1906a. “The Place of Science in Modern Civilization.” American Journal of Sociology 11 (1):
585–609. Reprinted in Camic and Hodgson (2011).
Veblen, Thorstein B. 1906b. “The Socialist Economics of Karl Marx and His Followers I: The Theories of Karl
Marx.” Quarterly Journal of Economics 20 (3): 578–595. Reprinted in Camic and Hodgson (2011).
Veblen, Thorstein B. 1907. “The Socialist Economics of Karl Marx and His Followers II: The Later Marxism.”
Quarterly Journal of Economics 21 (1): 299–322. Reprinted in Camic and Hodgson (2011).
Veblen, Thorstein B. 1908a. “On the Nature of Capital I: The Productivity of Capital Goods.” Quarterly Journal of
Economics 22 (4): 517–542. Reprinted in Camic and Hodgson (2011).
Veblen, Thorstein B. 1908b. “Professor Clark’s Economics.” Quarterly Journal of Economics 22 (2): 147–195.
Reprinted in Camic and Hodgson (2011).
Veblen, Thorstein B. 1914. The Instinct of Workmanship, and the State of the Industrial Arts. New York: Macmillan.
Veblen, Thorstein B. 1921a. The Engineers and the Price System. New York: Harcourt Brace and World.
Thorstein Veblen and Socialism 1177
Veblen, Thorstein B. 1921b. “Between Bolshevism and War.” The Freeman (3) 63: 248–251. Reprinted in Veblen
(1934).
Veblen, Thorstein B. 1923. Absentee Ownership and Business Enterprise in Recent Times. New York: Huebsch.
Veblen, Thorstein B. 1934. Essays on Our Changing Order, edited by Leon Ardzrooni. New York: Viking Press.
Waller, William T., Jr. 1982. “The Evolution of the Veblenian Dichotomy: Veblen, Hamilton, Ayres, and Foster.”
Journal of Economic Issues 16 (3): 757–771.
Waller, William. 1994 “The Veblenian Dichotomy and its Critics.” In The Elgar Companion to Institutional and
Evolutionary Economics, vol. 2, edited by Geoffrey M. Hodgson, Warren J. Samuels, and Marc R. Tool,
368–372. Aldershot: Edward Elgar.
Westbrook, Robert B. 1991. John Dewey and American Democracy. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.