Lecture 6-Signalling Games
Lecture 6-Signalling Games
Mohammad Vesal
Graduate School of Management and Economics
Sharif University of Technology
44706
Spring 2025
1 / 53
Dynamic games
2 / 53
Outline
Introduction
Reputation game
Reference: Fudenberg and Tirole Ch 8 (sec.1 & 2), MWG Ch 9.C (partly),
Ch 13.C (partly)
3 / 53
Outline
Introduction
Reputation game
4 / 53
Basic signaling game
• Player 1 (sender)
observes θ ∈ Θ
selects a1 ∈ A1
• Player 2 (receiver)
observes a1
selects a2 ∈ A2
• Payoffs
u1 (a1 , a2 , θ) u2 (a1 , a2 , θ)
• Common knowledge about prior distribution of θ
• Upon observing action a1 , receiver asks, what type of
player 1 is more likely to take this course of action.
Update his belief about player 1’s type
5 / 53
Strategies and beliefs
• Mixed strategy for sender
σ1 (a1 | θ)
µ(θ | a1 ) = Pr (θ | a1 )
σ2 (a2 | a1 )
p(θ)σ1∗ (a∗1 | θ)
µ(θ | a∗1 ) = P 0 ∗ ∗ 0
θ0 ∈Θ p(θ )σ1 (a1 | θ )
7 / 53
PBE discussion
8 / 53
Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium: more general
Pr (x | σ)
µ(x) = ∀x ∈ H
Pr (H | σ)
• Note: the consistency requirement only restricts beliefs on
the equilibrium path.
Players could have arbitrary beliefs on nodes in information
sets that are not reached on the equilibrium path.
9 / 53
Two examples of signaling games
• Reputation games
P1: Incumbent chooses fight/accommodate
P2: Entrant chooses to stay/exit
• Spence’s (1973) job market’s signaling
P1: worker observes productivity and chooses education
P2: employer observes education but not productivity and
chooses wage offer
10 / 53
Taxonomy of PBEs
• Separating equilibrium
understands P1’s type from observing P1’s action.
• Semi-separating equilibrium
Only sometimes P1’s action reveals his true type.
• Pooling equilibrium
All P1 types play the same strategy, no information is
revealed.
11 / 53
Outline
Introduction
Reputation game
Separating equilibrium
Semi-Separating equilibrium
Pooling equilibrium
12 / 53
Reputation game
Two firms: Incumbent and entrant
1. Incumbent observes θ ∈{sane,crazy}
Chooses a1 ∈{Fight,Accommodate}
prior: Pr(sane)= p
2. Entrant observes a1
Chooses a2 ∈{Stay,Exit}
Ent. Ent.
sane S E crazy S E
F (P1 , P2 ) (M1 , 0) F (K1 , K2 ) (M1 , 0)
Inc. Inc.
A (D1 , D2 ) (M1 , 0) A (D1 , D2 ) (M1 , 0)
13 / 53
Reduced form of a entry deterrence game
14 / 53
What are the PBEs of this game?
a∗1 (crazy) = F
15 / 53
Taxonomy of equilibria
16 / 53
Separating equilibrium
17 / 53
Entrant’s belief when α = 0
p(θ)σ1∗ (a∗1 | θ)
µ(θ | a∗1 ) = P 0 ∗ ∗ 0
θ0 ∈Θ p(θ )σ1 (a1 | θ )
18 / 53
Entrant’s optimal strategy
• ∀a1 , ∀a∗2 (a1 ) such that σ2∗ (a∗2 (a1 ) | a1 ) > 0
( )
X
∗
a2 (a1 ) ∈ arg max µ(θ | a1 )u2 (a1 , a2 , θ)
a2
θ∈Θ
• If a1 = F, entrant’s expected payoff is
X
µ(θ | a1 = F)u2 (a1 = F, a2 , θ) = u2 (F, a2 , crazy)
θ∈Θ
• Entrant’s optimal strategy is exit because
u2 (F, a2 = E, crazy) > u2 (F, a2 = S, crazy)
0 > K2
• If a1 = A, entrant’s optimal strategy is stay because
u2 (A, a2 = E, sane) < u2 (A, a2 = S, sane)
0 < D2
19 / 53
Incumbent’s optimal strategy
• Entrant’s optimal strategy was to stay if a1 = A and to exit
if a1 = F
• Now incumbent’s optimal strategy is
∀θ, ∀a∗1 such that σ1∗ (a∗1 | θ) > 0
X
a∗1 ∈ arg max σ2∗ (a2 | a1 )u1 (a1 , a2 , θ)
a1
a2 ∈A2
21 / 53
Semi-separating equilibrium
22 / 53
Entrant’s belief given α ∈ (0, 1)
µ(θ = sane | a1 = A) = 1
pα
µ(θ = sane | a1 = F) =
pα + 1 − p
• Are there any out-of-equilibrium beliefs?
23 / 53
Entrant’s optimal strategy
• Entrant’s expected payoff is
X
µ(θ | a1 )u2 (a1 , a2 , θ) =
θ∈Θ
µ(sane | a1 )u2 (a1 , a2 , sane) + (1 − µ(sane | a1 ))u2 (a1 , a2 , crazy)
• If a1 = A, entrant’s optimal strategy is stay because 0 < D2
• If a1 = F and entrant stays
pα pα
P2 + (1 − )K2
pα + 1 − p pα + 1 − p
If he exits he gets zero
• Stay is optimal iff
pα pα
P2 + (1 − )K2 ≥ 0
pα + 1 − p pα + 1 − p
⇔ pαP2 ≥ −(1 − p)K2
24 / 53
Entrant’s optimal strategy
25 / 53
Incumbent’s optimal strategy
βP1 + (1 − β)M1
• If β = M 1 −D1
M1 −P1 then the sane incumbent will be indifferent
and we can assume he mixes with the α we derived above!
26 / 53
Pooling equilibrium
27 / 53
Entrant’s beliefs given α = 1
why?
• Are there any out-of-equilibrium beliefs?
Let γ = µ(θ = sane | a∗1 = A) ∈ [0, 1]
accommodate is played with zero probability, entrant could
have any beliefs!
• We have to examine all possible γ to rule out existence of
pooling equilibrium.
28 / 53
Entrant’s optimal strategy
29 / 53
Incumbent’s optimal strategy
P1 < D1
30 / 53
Discussion
31 / 53
Summary of reputation game equilibria
32 / 53
Outline
Introduction
Reputation game
33 / 53
Job market signaling
• Payoffs
a
uw = w − uf = θ − w
θ
34 / 53
Simplify the game
δ(a) = µ(θH | a)
35 / 53
Separating equilibria
δ(a(θL )) = 0 δ(a(θH )) = 1
δ(a) ∈ [0, 1] ∀a ∈
/ {a(θL ), a(θH )}
36 / 53
Low type’s incentive compatibility
• Low type should not have an incentive to deviate
a(θL ) a
θL − ≥ θL + δ(a) (θH − θL ) − ∀a
θL θL
• This implies a(θL ) = 0 [prove by contradiction]
• Therefore
a
≥ δ(a) ∀a (1)
θL (θH − θL )
• Low type should not have an incentive to pretend as high
type
a(θH )
θL ≥ θL + (θH − θL ) −
θL
⇔ a(θH ) ≥ θL (θH − θL ) (2)
37 / 53
High type’s incentive compatibility
a(θH ) a
θH − ≥ θL + δ(a) (θH − θL ) − ∀a
θH θH
a(θH ) − a
⇔1− ≥ δ(a) ∀a (3)
θH (θH − θL )
• High type should not want to pretend as low type
a(θH )
θH − ≥ θL
θH
⇔ θH (θH − θL ) ≥ a(θH ) (4)
38 / 53
Results so far
39 / 53
Satisfying the belief condition
• Discontinuous beliefs
(
0 if a < a(θH )
δ(a) =
1 if a ≥ a(θH )
why?
40 / 53
Numerical example: Separating equilibria
• Let θL = 1, θH = 2, the belief and education conditions are
a(θH ) − a
δ(a) ≤ min 1 − ,a ∀a
2
2 ≥ a(θH ) ≥ 1
• For every â ∈ [1, 2] there exists a separating equilibrium in
which
a(θL ) = 0 a(θH ) = â
(
0 if a < â
δ(a) =
1 if a ≥ â
• There are multiple separating equilibria.
In all of them the firms have consistent beliefs
on-the-equilibrium path and specified beliefs
off-the-equilibrium.
Education level of workers are such that they do not have
an incentive to deviate to any level of education given firms
beliefs.
41 / 53
Pooling equilibria
w = θL + γ (θH − θL )
42 / 53
Low type’s incentive compatibility
• No incentive to deviate
a a
θL + γ (θH − θL ) − ≥ θL + δ(a) (θH − θL ) − ∀a
θL θL
• No incentive to deviate to zero education
a
γ (θH − θL ) − ≥ δ(0) (θH − θL )
θL
⇒ a ≤ (γ − δ(0)) θL (θH − θL )
43 / 53
High type’s incentive compatibility
• No incentive to deviate
a a
θL + γ (θH − θL ) − ≥ θL + δ(a) (θH − θL ) − ∀a
θH θH
• No incentive to deviate to zero education
a
γ (θH − θL ) − ≥ δ(0) (θH − θL )
θH
⇒ a ≤ (γ − δ(0)) θH (θH − θL )
44 / 53
Summary of conditions for pooling equilibria
• The two IC constraints for deviation to zero give
together with
a ≤ γ (θH − θL ) θL
• You can confirm that all the conditions for a pooling
equilibrium are satisfied.
• Notice the beliefs specified above is not the only possible
beliefs system that could support the pooling equilibria.
Could you give another beliefs system that supports the
same equilibria?
• But in any pooling equilibria a must satisfy the condition
above. Why?
46 / 53
Multiplicity of equilibria
47 / 53
Intuitive Criterion
48 / 53
Applying the intuitive criterion
49 / 53
Separating equilibria
• Take a separating equilibrium with
â
θL + δ̂(â) (θH − θL ) − ≤ θL
θL
⇔ δ̂(â) ≤ 1
50 / 53
Pooling equilibria
• Take a pooling equilibrium with a ≤ γ(θH − θL )θL and
consider a deviation to
â = a + (1 − γ) (θH − θL ) θL
• θH gets strictly higher utility if employer’s belief is δ(â) = 1
because
a â
θL + γ (θH − θL ) − < θH −
θH θH
θL
⇔ (1 − γ) (θH − θL ) > (1 − γ) (θH − θL )
θH
⇔ θH > θ L
• θL does not get strictly higher utility by deviating to â for
any belief δ̂(â) ∈ [0, 1] because
â a
θL + δ̂(â) (θH − θL ) − ≤ θL + γ (θH − θL ) −
θL θL
⇔ δ̂(â) ≤ 1
51 / 53
Two stories about education
52 / 53
Summary
53 / 53