ANDERSON. Problem Solving and Learning. 1993
ANDERSON. Problem Solving and Learning. 1993
Newell and Simon (1972) provided a framework for un- computer simulation of human thought and was basically
derstanding problem solving that can provide the needed unconnected to research in animal and human learning.
bridge between learning and performance. Their analysis Research on human learning and research on prob-
of means-ends problem solving can be viewed as a general lem solving are finally meeting in the current research
characterization of the structure of human cognition. on the acquisition of cognitive skills (Anderson, 1981;
However, this framework needs to be elaborated with a Chi, Glaser, & Farr, 1988; Van Lehn, 1989). Given nearly
strength concept to account for variability in problem- a century of mutual neglect, the concepts from the two
solving behavior and improvement in problem-solving skill fields are ill prepared to relate to each other. I will argue
with practice. The ACT* theory (Anderson, 1983) is such in this article that research on human problem solving
an elaborated theory that can account for many of the would have been more profitable had it attempted to in-
results about the acquisition of problem-solving skills. Its corporate ideas from learning theory. Even more so, re-
central concept is the production rule, which plays an search on learning would have borne more fruit had
analogous role to the stimulus-response bond in earlier Thorndike not cast out problem solving.
learning theories. The theory has provided a basis for con- This article will review the basic conception of prob-
structing intelligent computer-based tutoring systems for lem solving that is the legacy of the Newell and Simon
the instruction of academic problem-solving skills. tradition. It will show how this conception solves the gen-
eral problem of the relationship between learning and
performance that has haunted learning theory. In partic-
ular, it provides a concrete realization of Tolman’s in-
Thorndike’s (1898) original learning experiments in- sights. I will also present the case for problem solving as
volved cats learning to solve the problem of getting out the structure that organizes human thought and means—
of a puzzle box. As most introductory psychology texts ends analysis as the principal realization of that structure.
recount, Thorndike concluded that his cats managed to I will argue, however, that this research has been stunted
get out of the puzzle box by a trial and error process. In because of its inability to deal with variability and change
Thorndike’s conception there was really nothing happen- in behavior.
ing that could be called problem solving. What was hap- — Then I will turn to the more recent research on ac-
pening was the gradual strengthening of successful re- quisition of cognitive skills. I will discuss the critical role
sponses. Thorndike’s research is often cited as the begin- of the production rule, a computational improvement
ning of the analysis of learning that occupied American over the stimulus-response bond, in organizing that re-
psychology for much of this century. It could also be cited search. I will show how the acquisition of complex skills
as the beginning of the neglect of problem solving as a can be accounted for by the separate acquisition of these
topic worthy of analysis. rules, thus realizing the goal of learning theory to account
Although KGhler (e.g., 1927) and the other Gestalt for complex learning in terms of the acquisition of simple
psychologists used problem-solving tasks to demonstrate units: I will close by discussing the implications of this
the inadequacies in the behaviorist conceptions of learn- analysis for education, one of Thorndike’s great concerns.
ing, they failed to offer an analysis of the problem-solving Here I will describe my own research on intelligent tu-
process. Tolman (1932) saw the critical role of goals in toring systems, which has been based on the recent in-
learning and behavior but failed to put that insight into sights into problem solving and learning. We have been
a coherent theory, leaving him vulnerable to Guthrie’s able to greatly accelerate and improve the acquisition of
(1952) famous criticism that he left his rat buried in
thought and inaction.
Problem solving finally was given a coherent pro- Donald J. Foss served as action editor for this article.
gram of analysis by Newell and Simon (1972) in a line This research was supported by National Science Foundation Grant
of research that culminated in their book Human Problem BNS-870581 i and Office of Naval Research Contract N00014-90-J-1489.
I would like to thank Allen Newell and Lynne Reder for their comments.
Solving. The basic conception of problem solving they Correspondence concerning this article should be addressed to John
set forth continues to frame research in the field. Their R. Anderson, Department of Psychology, Carnegie Mellon University.
conception had its foundation in artificial intelligence and Pittsburgh, PA 15213.
4] |.
only the fields of problem solving and learning listen to
each other.
Problem-Solving Methods
Whether one is performing operators externally or imag-
ining them, the critical issue is how to select the next
Start Finish
peg peg, ' The Tower of Hanoi task is one of a number of “toy” tasks that
Note. The goal is to move all the disks from the start peg to the finish peg. Only had an important role in the early development of ideas about problem
one disk may be moved ata time, and one cannot place a larger disk on a smaller solving. Studies of problem solving have now extended to complex and
disk. important problem-solving tasks. However, the Tower of Hanoi task and
others like it remain useful both for exposition of the basic concepts and
aS
as paradigms for studying these concepts in relative isolation.
Y
Match current state SUCCESS
Difference Subgoal: Eliminate
to goal state to find the
the difference
most important difference detected
[xo DIFFERENCES co
SUCCESS FAIL
SUCCESS
Y
Search for operator |Operator Match condition of Difference Subgoal:
relevant to reducing > operator to current > Eliminate
the difference found state to find most detected | the difference
important difference
)sove FOUND
, {xo DIFFERENCE
ward. However, if it cannot (as when a disk blocks the role in accounting for behavior in puzzles like Tower of
move of another disk in Tower of Hanoi), the problem Hanoi, academic problem solving (Larkin, McDermott,
solver sets the subgoal of eliminating the blocking con- Simon, & Simon, 1980), and everyday problem solving
dition. Thus, for instance, Neves’s subject set the subgoal (Klahr, 1978). Often because of the structure of the prob-
of removing Disk 3, which was blocking the move of Disk lem, all the aspects of the underlying means—ends method
4. The problem solver no longer is working on the original do not manifest themselves. Thus, problem solving on
goal but is working on a subgoal, which is only a means certain puzzles may look like hill climbing (e.g., Jeffries,
to the ultimate end. The three key features of means— Polson, Razran, & Atwood, 1977) because the operators
ends analysis are the focus on eliminating a single large for the problem do not have the kind of prerequisite
difference, the selection of operators by what differences structure that leads to subgoaling, and so we only see
they reduce, and the subgoaling of the preconditi6ns of difference reduction. Conversely, a problem may look like
the operator if they are not met in the current state. An- pure subgoal decomposition (Anderson, Farrell, & Sauers,
derson (1990a) can be consulted for a general analysis of 1984) because there is no similarity structure to guide
why this problem-solving method can lead to optimal the choice of subgoals.
problem solving in novel situations. It is of interest to speculate how far means-—ends
Means-ends analysis does not just apply to exotic analysis is found down the phylogenic scale and devel-
laboratory puzzles. Newell and Simon (1972) emphasized opmental scales. Klahr (1978) has argued that children
that it is found in all aspects of life. Consider, for instance, are quite capable of means—ends analysis. Their problem
their following example: solving is often ineffective because of inadequate repre-
I want to take my son to nursery school. What’s the difference sentation of the problem, and they become more effective
between what I have and what I want? One of distance. What means-ends problem solvers when their representations
changes distance? My automobile. My automobile won’t work. of the problem and the operators become sophisticated
What is needed to make it work? A new battery. What has new enough to enable means-ends problem solving to apply.
batteries? An auto repair shop. I want the repair shop to put in K6hler’s (1927) characterization of chimpanzee problem
a new battery: but the shop doesn’t know I need one. What is solving would seem to imply a means-—ends capacity for
the difficulty? One of communication. What allows communi-
them, even as his more dismal characterization of lower
cation? A telephone. . . and so on. (p. 416)
organisms would imply they do not have a means—ends
Whereas it would be incorrect to assert that all hu- capacity. There should be a very strong connection be-
man problem solving is organized by means-—ends anal- tween tool manufacture and use and means-ends problem
ysis, this problem-solving method has played the largest solving. A tool is a concrete means to an end. My own
Conclusion
T
Average
Lesson 2
I think we are beginning to see rapid and important prog-
Lesson 3 ress being made with respect to understanding how com-
plex problem-solving skills are learned. This progress has
depended on bringing together ideas from problem-solv-
ing theory and learning theory. We can understand ac-
quisition of complex problem-solving skills only when
1 2 3&4 5-8 we recognize the problem-solving structure that organizes
Opportunities
their performance while recognizing the rather simple
ES
learning that governs the acquisition and strengthening
of the individual problem-solving operators.