Aristotle, an ancient Greek philosopher, viewed the state as a natural institution essential for human life, arguing that it is the highest form of community that enables citizens to achieve their potential. He defined citizenship as the privilege of the ruling class, excluding women, slaves, and aliens from participation in political life, and emphasized the importance of education and moral character in governance. Aristotle's political philosophy also included a justification for slavery and a hierarchical view of society, asserting the superiority of men over women and Greeks over non-Greeks.
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0 ratings0% found this document useful (0 votes)
11 views24 pages
Aristotle
Aristotle, an ancient Greek philosopher, viewed the state as a natural institution essential for human life, arguing that it is the highest form of community that enables citizens to achieve their potential. He defined citizenship as the privilege of the ruling class, excluding women, slaves, and aliens from participation in political life, and emphasized the importance of education and moral character in governance. Aristotle's political philosophy also included a justification for slavery and a hierarchical view of society, asserting the superiority of men over women and Greeks over non-Greeks.
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 24
Aristotle (384-322 B.C.
) was an ancient Greek
philosopher who is regarded the father of the science of politics. He was the illustrious disciple of Plato (427-347 B.C.) and the tutor of Alexander the Great (356-323-B.C.). In any case, Aristotle's own thought shares many concerns with Plato. Both saw instability of the state as the major problem of the Greek city-states and held moral anarchy responsible for this state of affairs. Both held the view that the state comes into existence for the sake of life and continues for the sake of good life. Both accepted the need for proper education of citizens as well as rulers and wanted to pass the burden of manual labour to the slaves. However, Aristotle sought to build his philosophy on scientific foundation while Plato had largely relied on speculative method.
Aristotle on State
Aristotle believed that the state, or polis, was the
highest form of community and the best place for humans to live. He thought that the state's purpose was to help its citizens live well and fulfill their potential.
How Aristotle viewed the state
The state is a natural outcome of other forms of
association, such as families and villages.
The state should have a distinct identity, such as
rivers and mountains.
The state's population should be just large
enough to achieve self-sufficiency.
The state should be ruled by one, a few, or the
many.
The state should be governed for the general
good.
The state should provide economic opportunities
to help citizens enhance their well-being
How Aristotle viewed government
Monarchy is government by a single person for
the general good. Tyranny is government by a single person for private benefit. Aristocracy is government by a minority that aims for the state's best interest. Oligarchy is government by a minority that benefits only the ruling minority. Polity is popular government in the common interest. Democracy is anarchic mob rule.
STATE AS A NATURAL INSTITUTION
For Aristotle state is necessary as well as natural
for human beings. He argues that a lonely person is unable to sustain himself. Man and woman join together to set up a family or household. The expansion of family into many branches leads to the formation of a village community. A combination of several village communities results in the formation of city or state. In ancient Greece, city and state were conterminous. Aristotle observes that with the formation of the state, human community becomes self-dependent. Thus the process of social organization begins with an attempt to fulfil ordinary needs of life and culminates in laying the foundations of good life. State is as natural an association as a family or village community. Other associations are imperfect as they provide for one or the other aspect of good life, but the state is meant to secure all aspects of good life.
For Aristotle, living in a state is'as natural for a
man as to be a human being. In other words, a man is like any other animal until he lives in a state. The urge for leading a good life is the distinctive characteristic of human being which necessitates formation of the state. You cannot think of a human being as different from other animals without thinking of the state. Thus Aristotle postulates: State is prior to man. Historically the state appears after the appearance of man. But from the point of view of logic, the idea of state comes before the idea of man, as the idea of 'full' comes before the idea of its 'part'. You cannot think of a 'hand' or a 'foot' without thinking of the body of which it is a part. If a hand is separated from the body, it becomes redundant. So a man outside the state loses his identity as a human being. Politics is an essential part of human character, That is why Aristotle postulates: Man is by nature a political animal. He who does not live in a state or who does not need a state is either a beast (subhuman) or a god (superhuman).
Other living beings, such as bees and elephants
may live in groups; so they may be regarded as 'social animals' (or 'gregarious animals' in modern terminology); but they have no aim in life beyond mere survival; they have no idea of good life. But man is always interested in pursuing good life; so he lives in a state which is the indispensable instrument of good life. That is why in Aristotle's view, man is not merely a 'social animal', but he is by nature a 'political animal'.
Aristotle's notion of politics is different from its
present-day notion in this context also. In the present age, conflicting demands and pressures are considered to be the common characteristics of politics. The state is expected to evolve such policies and decisions which could be made acceptable to the conflicting parties, at least for the time being. Such a notion of politics was alien to Aristotle's political philosophy.
(Aristotle treated the state as a moral as well as a
natural institution. He upheld organic theory of the state and maintained that the relation between individual and the state was similar to that between an 'organ' and the 'organism', that is the body. As different organs of the body perform different functions according to their differential capacities, so different individuals in society have different status and function. The division of labour among different groups of individuals benefits all of them by making use of their different faculties of mind and body. This gives rise to the sense of responsibility, mutual regard and cooperation and strengthens their moral character.
FAMILY, PRIVATE PROPERTY AND SLAVERY
Family is the first institution to provide for good
life. Aristotle pays due attention to household management which included family, property and slaves. He concedes that family is the cradle of virtue. Property is an essential ingredient of household. Ownership of property gives a sense of security and an urge to increase one's wealth. It is an instrument of hospitality, generosity, friendship and affection. So Aristotle defends private ownership of property and ridicules Plato's scheme of common ownership of property among the guardians. Aristotle holds that while property should be held under private ownership, its owners should make it available for common use. He hopes that proper education will inculcate this type of generosity among citizens.
Extending the analogy of organic theory to the
realm of human relations, Aristotle maintained that as some organs of the body are superior to others, so some individuals are superior to others. He argued that men were superior to women, freemen were superior to slaves, and Greeks were superior to barbarians. He likened the relation between man and woman to that between master and slave. He held that men were fit for command and women for obedience. He rejected Plato's plea for equality between men and women within the guardian class as it was not based on experience.
Aristotle argued that woman is weak of will, and
therefore incapable of independence of character or position; her best place is a quiet home life. While she is ruled by man in her external relations, she may reign supreme in domestic affairs. No attempt should be made to obliterate the natural difference between man and woman: "The courage of a man and that of a woman are not, as Socrates supposed, the same. the courage of a man is shown in commanding; that of a woman in obeying... As the poet says, 'Silence is a woman's glory." Thus woman's role should be confined to the sphere of family which is a natural institution; it caters to the good of woman as well as man.(Aristotle seeks to exclude women from the domain of citizenship on this ground. Again, men differ widely in their intellectual capabilities. The great majority of men are natural dunces and sluggards; in any system whatever these men will sink to the bottom. These people must be ruled in politics and directed in industry, with their consent if possible, without it if necessary: "From the hour of their birth some are marked out for subjection and others for rule." Those who are proficient in mental work are by nature intended to be masters or lords; and those capable of physical work are by nature meant to be slaves. It is better for all inferiors that they should be placed under the rule of their superiors. (Ancient Greek philosophers considered physical labour always inferior to intellectual work, Aristotle argued that those capable of intellectual work were fit to be masters, and those capable of physical labour were by nature fit to be slaves. He even refused to recognize the slave as a full-fledged human being, and compared him to a 'living tool which was a part of the property of his master. As a poor man kept oxen to do physical labour, so a rich man kept slaves for the similar work. Thus a slave was at best a tool or the counterpart of a domestic animal)
(Aristotle even declared the slave to be incapable
of virtue or moral excellence. He argues that manual or physical labour blunts one's mind and renders one incapable for performing political function which requires high calibre. It is therefore the prerogative of a freeman who alone is capable of virtue. Moreover, a freeman needs 'leisure' for the exercise of virtue which is created by assigning all physical work to the slave. The slave could get the benefit of virtue only through serving his master. So slavery was beneficial for the master as well as the slave. While Aristotle wanted the slave to be dutiful, he also advised the master to be kind to his slaves.
In this context, 'leisure' does not mean the escape
from work. It simply means the freedom from physical labour to enable a person to devote himself fully to the study. contemplation and pursuit of art. Those who work to fulfil material needs of society do not need 'leisure' in this sense. Hence mechanics, labourers, peasants and salves are not fit to rule. They are not entitled to the status of citizens..
Here Aristotle uses the term 'slave' in a wider
sense. Even merchants and financiers are thought to be slaves in this sense. However, Aristotle concedes that learning the theory of finance is not unworthy of philosophy, but to be engaged in finance or in money-making is unworthy of a free man. A free man is constantly devoted to intellectual work the way to actualization of good life which is an end-in-itself. On the other hand, anybody who is required to do a fixed job, and repeat it everytime, is not fit to be a citizen.
(Aristotle further believed that only the Greeks
had the ability lity to do intellectual work, hence they were fit to be free men. On the other hand, barbarians were able to do physical labour only. Hence they were fit to be slaves. On the whole, Aristotle stands for supremacy of men over women, of freemen over slaves, and of Greeks over barbarians. It is therefore rightly said that Aristotle was a spokesman of patriarchal society, institution of slavery and the supremacy of the Greeks.
Aristotle's justification of slavery was designed
only to defend the interests of the Greeks who were mainly freemen. His assumption regarding the differences of capacity of virtue or moral excellence between different categories of persons was not based on any scientific evidence or sound logic. He even recommended different scales of punishment for master and slave in the case of a similar offence. He tried to justify this recommendation on the flimsy ground that the slave was less sensitive to pain!
In short, Aristotle's defence of patriarchy and
slavery can best be understood only in terms of his political realism and expediency rather than on the basis of a sound logic. The Greek economy during those days was founded on household organization and its productivity was largely dependent on slave labour. In any case, Aristotle's defence of slavery was based on the false assumption of inherent qualitative differences between different races. This argument was widely used in early modern times by colonial powers in order to justify their exploitative rule in a large part of the world. They claimed to spread enlightenment among the allegedly ignorant people of non-white races. CONCEPT OF CITIZENSHIP
DEFINITION OF THE CITIZEN
In the Book I of his classic work Politics, Aristotle
dwelled on the importance of households and village communities and defined the state as an 'association of associations'. But in Book III thereof he described the state as an 'association of freemen'. In this sense, constitution of a state is an attempt at determining the status of its residents in a specific way. Here Aristotle conceded that the state is made of individuals It is therefore necessary to examine the status of different individuals in the state. We must likewise identify as to who are citizens of a state, and who are not so.
(According to Aristotle, all the residents of a state
are not its citizens. In ancient Greek city-states women, slaves and aliens were not regarded as citizens. In those days there was no scope of development of the concept of citizenship in the sense which developed in England after the Glorious Revolution (1688) and which reached its logical conclusion in the concept of welfare state
In short, Aristotle recognized 'citizenship' as the
privilege of the ruling class. In his times, the right to participate in public decisions was confined to the citizens. So Aristotle equated citizenship with effective participation in the exercise of power. Aristotle regarded this privilege of the ruling class as its duty and insisted on its performance. He held that when all members of the ruling class would fulfil this duty, they will be able to secure good life for all the members of the political community (that is the citizens as well as non-citizens).
The peculiar conditions prevailing in ancient
Greek city-states were responsible for drawing special attention to the problem of citizenship, Internally these small states were inflicted by the conflict between the rich and the poor, externally they were threatened by the attacks of their neighbouring states. Under the circumstances. maintenance of peace and stability in the state was the chief concern of political philosophers. Would it be safe to vest all power in the hands of the few or should it be dispersed among large numbers? Should they allow the aliens to acquire citizenship easily? Athenians had the harrowing experience of the regime of "Thirty Tyrants", and they had not yet forgotten the experience of a slack democracy which did not hesitate them pronouncing a death sentence for Socrates - the wisest man of Cireece. Pur had proposed to set up the rule of 'philosopher-kings' to deal with this situation. But Aristotle felt that this scheme was far-removed from ground reality. So he focused on the problem of citizenship in order to solve the problems of the city-states.
stration
Politics
Aristotle argued that mere residence in a city or a
state cannot be treated as a qualification for becoming a citizen thereof. For example, slaves or resident aliens cannot be treated as citizens. Nobody becomes a citizen of a state by virtue of being entitled to certain legal rights because such rights can ensue from a commercial contract or a treaty. Then the criterion of birth, too, cannot be accepted as the basis of citizenship because the question of citizenship of parents, grandparents and to be decided. It will be better if citizenship is defined so on will still remain on the basis of one's function. Accordingly, political rights alone can be treated as a qualification of a citizen. These include the right to share in the administration of justice and the right to share in political office. Aristotle believed that only those members of a state can be regarded its citizens who are entitled to 'take part in deliberative or judicial office. It is not necessary that each citizen should be actually holding a political office for the time being. For example, where people are chosen as members of a jury by rotation, all those eligible for election shall be considered as citizens.
STATUS OF THE CITIZEN
According to Aristotle, the nature of political
authority is different from all other types of authority. Political authority stands for the authority used by political office-holders over other citizens. This authority is used according to the rules of the prevalent constitution. In other words, the relation between the ruler and other citizens in a state is determined by the prevalent form of government. Thus different patterns of relations between the ruler and other citizens may be found under different types of constitutions of the state. For example, citizens under a despotic rule would not enjoy the same privileges as those under a monarchical role.
In spite of conceding these variations in the
nature of political authority under different constitutions, Aristotle also dwells on the distinctive features of political authority as such. In what sense political authority is different from other types of authority? Aristotle argues that husband's authority over wife or master's authority over slave is derived from the law of nature because nature has made woman inferior to man, and slave inferior to master. But in the political sphere, nature has not made any citizen inferior to the ruler. Then master's authority over slave is essentially despotic in nature, because slave's life is entirely at the disposal of his master. But ruler's authority over citizens cannot be allowed to follow this pattern.
FUNCTIONS OF THE CITIZEN
Aristotle is now convinced that ruler's authority over citizens cannot be regarded to be despotic. He argues that in the eye of law, all citizens are equal-whether one is rich or poor, whether one is holding a political office or one is an ordinary citizen. It would be worthwhile to extend citizenship to all those entitled to be citizens of a state, but those enjoying the right to vote should be adequately rich so that they are not tempted to grab others' wealth by means of their political power.
Aristotle sought to make a clear distinction
between a 'good man' and a 'good citizen, It is important to note that in his classification of various forms of government, Aristotle drew distinction between 'normal' and 'perverted forms of Under 'normal' or ideal form of government, rulers were devoted to good of the government. state. Under this form of government, there was no conflict between the demands of individual righteousness and the demands of political righteousness. In other words, in the ideal polis (i.e. city-state) there was no clash between the roles of a good man and a good citizen. itizen. However, under 'perverted form of government, rulers were devoted to self-interest at the expense of the state. Under this form of government, the requirements of good citizenship ntight run counter to the requirements of individual righteousness. For example, under aristocracy which is a normal form of government, a good citizen would prove to be a good man by obeying the commands of the state. But under oligarchy which is a perverted form of government, a good citizen, obeying the commands of the state cheerfully, will not be able to uphold the good of the state, he will not be able to remain a good man. Thus Aristotle was aware of the dilemma of a good man living in a bad polis, but he did not elaborate his obligations in detail. This problem was relegated to the background for centuries together until T.H. Green (1836-82), brilliant English philosopher, sought to tackle it effectively.
Aristotle endeavoured to show that citizenship
did not imply mere subjection to political rule. The citizen himself should play an active role in shaping that rule. The function of citizenship can be properly performed only by those who have the competence to analyse political problems thoroughly and who have sufficient 'leisure' at. their disposal. According to Aristotle, only the Greeks were endowed with this competence. There was little scope of evolution of citizenship in the very cold regions of Persia and the North. The people in those regions could hardly manage the means of their survival. So for them, there was no scope of engaging in politics. On the other hand, the people of hot regions were very indolent. They would accept the despotic rule in order to escape from hard work. So the idea of citizenship could not flourish in those regions.
Again, a city with a very large population no
longer remains a state in the proper sense of the term. If a city's population of active citizens exceeds ten thousand, they fail to evolve personal acquaintance. Consequently they become unable to develop friendship among themselves which is essential for maintaining citizenship. Thus the Greek city-states of those days alone were fit for evolving an effective citizenship; no other country would qualify for its practice. Citizenship was an exclusive quality of the Greeks; it was an exclusive prerogative of the 'freemen' among them. Labourers, peasants and women were not eligible for citizenship, not to speak of slaves! CONCEPT OF JUSTICE
In Aristotle's view, justice is concerned with the
regulation of human relations. He identified three types of justice: (a) Distributive Justice; (b) Retributive (also called Corrective, Rectificatory or Remedial) Justice; and (c) Commutative Justice. The legislator should be concerned with distributive justice whereas the judge should be concerned with retributive and commutative justice. Distributive justice deals with the allocation of honours and wealth. Its basic principle is 'treating equals equally and unequals unequally'. Aristotle preferred to rely on the prevailing custom and customary law for deciding as to who were equals or unequals.
Retributive justice deals with imposition of
punishment and payment of damages.
It requires full restoration of any loss involuntarily
sustained in the course of transactions between individual members of the community. Finally, commutative justice seeks to determine the amount of one sort of goods or services to be rendered in return for another sort in voluntary transaction of buying and selling, or letting and hiring. Its guiding principle should be full equivalence.
SEARCH FOR A STABLE CONSTITUTION
CLASSIFICATION OF CONSTITUTIONS
Aristotle sought to evolve empirical method of
studying politics and to combine it with the comparative method. He was particularly perturbed by the prevailing instability of government in his contemporary Greek city-states. So he sought to develop a model constitution that would ensure political stability. He sent his disciples to various places for the purpose of preparing case histories of their constitutions. In this process, 158 case histories of various city-states were prepared which were examined by Aristotle himself. On this basis he produced his famous classification of constitutions. Unfortunately these case histories, except that of Athens, have been lost. But Aristotle's observations regarding the various forms of government, the causes of their instability and the steps required to overcome this instability are still accessible to us.
(Aristotle's classification of constitutions focused
on two factors: (a) Whether a state is ruled by one, the few or many persons; and (b) Whether the ruler is devoted to interest of the state (the normal form of constitution) or to his self-interest (the perverted or deviant form). From this perspective, the following classification was derived.
This classification indicates only the predominant
features of different types of rule because none of them is found in pure form. For example, a single government may embrace some democratic features (if all citizens are eligible for jury service) and some monarchical features (if the military forces are under the control of one man). Aristotle observed that none of these forms of government was stable for want of proper checks on the power of the ruler. Monarchy was good under normal conditions. But in the absence of any effective control over the absolute power of monarch, it degenerated into tyranny because 'power and virtue cannot coexist'. Tyranny was followed by a rebellion by the chosen few who overthrew it and set up aristocracy in its place. In the absence of any effective curbs on their power, aristocracy degenerated into oligarchy. In due course the larger numbers rose against it and replaced it by polity. This again degenerated into democracy (the rule of the larger numbers seeking self-interest). This was eventually overthrown by a single virtuous man who set up monarchy in its place. This marked the beginning of a new cycle of change. CAUSES AND REMEDIES OF REVOLUTION
Aristotle realized that the political instability of the
Greek city-states was the outcome of frequent revolutions in those states. So he proceeded to inquire into the causes and remedies of revolution.
While Plato in his 'Republic' had proposed a
radical solution of the problem of political instability by postulating the rule of philosopher-kings and communism of wives and property for the guardian class, Aristotle took a conservative stand. He rejected these proposals as they contradicted the experience of the hitherto society. He
argued that politics cannot remake human nature;
it should be accepted as it was.
Analysing the causes of revolution, Aristotle
observed that dissatisfaction with the existing distribution of power and prestige gave rise to rebellion. Dissatisfaction may be widespread or limited to a small group. It erupts in violent form. Hence sedition is the first step to revolution. If revolt is suppressed, it fails; if it succeeds, it results in the overthrow of the existing regime. In this process power passes from one party to another whether constitution is changed or not.
What is the source of dissatisfaction that leads to
revolution? Aristotle observes that the seed of revolution grows in the mind of the people. The sense of injustice is the source of all dissatisfaction. When some people feel that they have been deprived of power and honour which they deserved, they feel dissatisfied and start organizing themselves to fight for their rights. Thus signs of conflict appear in society and the sense of unity disappears.
Un Aristotle's view dissatisfaction chiefly stems
from the desire for power and honour rather than wealth. However, he does not ignore the impact of economic inequality altogether. He observes that faster the division of society into the rich and the poor, greater the chances of revolution. The poor would never tolerate the luxurious ways of living of the rich. However, if a large and strong middle class exists to maintain balance between the two, the probability of revolution would be minimized.,
The first and foremost remedy of revolution lies in
preventing dissatisfaction in any section of the community. If a constitution is founded on consent of all the citizens and it is enforced impartially, it would prevent the growth of 'sense of injustice'. If consent of all the citizens cannot be obtained, it should be based on the consent of the large majority but the minorities should not be cheated. No individual or class should be allowed to become too powerful, and political office should not be allowed to become a source of personal gain.. Secondly, political stability can be secured by educating the people in accordance with the spirit of the constitution. State sponsored educational system can induce the people to make their property available for the common use. This would give rise to mutual understanding, goodwill and cooperation. It will make the people law-abiding. Younger generation can be taught discipline and respect for law so that all their acts tend to raise the dignity of the state.
Finally, the statesmen should be sensitive even to
the minor changes. No constitution should be allowed to take an extreme form. Here Aristotle invokes his ethical principle of 'the golden mean'. Accordingly, all extremes should be avoided and a middle path should be adopted between mutually opposite properties. Thus a middle course between aristocracy and democracy will prevent the feeling of injustice among the rich and the poor. Aristotle's concept of the 'mixed constitution' is precisely based on this principle.
CONCEPT OF THE MIXED CONSTITUTION
in social, der in which verthrows he tion of on, S
strength progress modern tariat to in order
Since no form of government was found to be
stable under the existing conditions, Aristotle sought to consider whether a judicious mixture of any two forms was likely to prove stable. This idea was consistent with his doctrine of 'the golden mean' which held that virtue or excellence lies in the middle of the two extremes which would otherwise turn out to be vices. Earlier, Plato (427-347 B.C.), in his Laws, had observed that a combination of monarchy and democracy could provide for a stable political system. However, Aristotle drew his conclusions from his own style of logic independently. He observed that since you cannot find perfect men on earth, as Plato had imagined, it was imperative that the state should be placed under the rule of laws. In that case, rulers would be obliged to enforce the laws which had existed since time immemorial, and which had stood the test of time. As an adherent of conservatism, Aristotle argued that it was unwise to change the existing laws in the hope of bringing about a better political order. He warned: "Characters are not so easily changed as laws." He firmly asserted: "Political science does not make men, but must take them as they come from nature." Aristotle's notion of the rule of law may be regarded as a precursor to the modern concept of rule of law.
Now each form of government was ruled by its
own law. We must examine its merits and demerits before considering its claim for mixing it with any other form in order to prepare a judicious mixture of two forms that would serve our purpose. At the outset, Aristotle observed that monarchy involved the exercise of absolute power, hence it was more prone to be corrupted. Aristocracy was preferable because it allowed for some dispersal of power. But in the absence of effective control on its power, this too was corruptible. Let us consider whether this tendency can be prevented by combining it with democracy.
(Aristotle identified democracy as 'the rule of the
many', that is the more numerous members of the community, particularly the poor ones. In his classification of governments into normal and perverted forms, Aristotle placed democracy among perverted forms since it referred to the rule of mediocres seeking to serve their selfish interests rather than the interest of the state. Here Aristotle makes very interesting observations about the merits and demerits of democracy: This rule by the poor has some advantages. The people, though individually they may be worse judges than those who have special knowledge, are collectively as good. Moreover, there are some artists whose works are best judged not by themselves alone but by those who do not possess the art; for example, the user or master of a house will be better judge of it than the builder... and the guest will be a better judge of a feast than the cook.
Again, the involvement of larger numbers in the
process of governance has its own advantages. As Aristotle observes:
(The many are more incorruptible than the few;
they are like the greater quantity of water which is less easily spoiled than a little
Moreover, the larger number are less likely to be
swayed by anger or passion. Hence their judgement is likely to prove more sound than that of one or the few persons. But the demerits of democracy were no less striking. Aristotle argued that democracy is based on a false assumption of equality. It arises out of the notion that those who are equal in one respect (such as in respect of law) are equal in all respects; those who are equally free, claim to be absolutely equal. The upshot is that ability is sacrificed to numbers, while numbers are manipulated by trickery. Because the people are so easily misled, and so fickle in their views, the ballot should be limited to the intelligent. Proceeding on this line of argument, Aristotle comes to the conclusion that a judicious mixture of aristocracy and democracy, described as the mixed constitution, would prove to be the best form of government.)
In a nutshell, under the mixed constitution
authority to rule will be confined to the rich, educated, cultured and competent persons. In this sense, it will retain the prominent feature of aristocracy. But the ruling class will not be allowed to exercise absolute powers, because its decisions will be subject to approval of the ordinary citizens. In this sense, it will adopt an important feature of democracy. So it will represent 'the golden mean' between aristocracy and democracy.
CONCLUSION
e or the fo argued the notion the all-respect at
ability the peop ited to th lusion the nstitution
As a champion of the rule of law, Aristotle was
more concerned with political stability than progress. He sought to prevent the causes of revolution by stressing the virtues of the prevailing inequalities. His belief in differential levels of moral excellence not only between master and slave (the racial factor) but also between man and woman (the gender factor) was not based on sound logic; it cannot be accepted in the modern times.
However, his idea of the mixed constitution can
be considered worth adopting in the modern age, with necessary modifications. For our purpose, aristocracy as a component of the mixed constitution should be redefined as a group of those with high character and competence rather than the rich and the high-born; and democracy should be redefined as the provision of equal political rights of all citizens without discrimination (e.g. between freemen and slaves which was conceded by Aristotle). The people should not only approve the policies proposed by the rulers but should choose the rulers themselves. The rulers would be chosen from the general body of the people on the basis of competence and high character. This would mean the adoption of the existing model of liberal democracy with the proviso that duly qualified and tested persons should be eligible to hold political office. Aristotle is right when he says that the ordinary people should have the right to approve public policy as 'the wearer knows where the shoe pinches'. But the responsibility of its implementation should rest with the specialists who have given substantial proof of their competence and character.
Although Aristotle deprecated democracy in its
raw form, yet his definition of democracy as 'the rule of the poor' cannot be set aside as totally irrelevant in modern times. C.B. Macpherson (1911-87), contemporary Western political philosopher, has pleaded for the revival of the classical concept of democracy (which roughly corresponds to Aristotle's view). Macpherson (Democratic Theory: Essays_in Retrieval; 1973) argued that the truly classical concept of democracy saw democracy as the cry of the oppressed, their claim for recognition as equally human beings; a means by which, or a society in which all men could enjoy and develop their human capacities.
In a nutshell, Aristotle's definition of democracy
may be recast as 'the empowerment of the poor' in order to convert it into 'substantive democracy'.