Linguistic
Linguistic
assignment
WORD FORMATION
Verb To Noun
To hope Hope
To cover Cover
To increase Increase
To attack Attack
4. COMPOUNDING
‘Compounding’ is a word-formation process that
allows words to combine to make a new word.
•Compounding words can also be formed as two words
joined with a hyphen.
• EXAMPLES:
Words Compounding Words
Class+room Classroom
Note+book Notebook
Break+up Breakup
Brother+in+law Brother in law
5.CLIPPING
‘Clipping’ reduces or shortens a word without
changing the exact meaning.
In contrast to the back-formation process, it reserves
the original meaning.
Clipping is divided into four types. They are:
1. Back Clipping
2. Fore Clipping
3. Middle Clipping
4.Complex Clipping
•Back Clipping removes the end part of a word
•Fore Clipping removes the beginning part of a word
• Middle Clipping reserves the middle position
•Complex Clipping removes multiple pieces from
multiple words.
•Examples
Words Clippings
Advertisement Ad
Photograph Photo
Telephone Phone
Influenza Flu
Cable telegram Cablegram
6.BLENDING
In the ‘Blending word-formation method, the parts of
two or more words combine to form a new word.
• EXAMPLES:
Words Blendings
Breakfast+lunch Brunch
Biographical+picture Biopic
Motor+hotel Motel
Spanish+English Spanglish
Telephone+marathon Telethon
7.ABBREVIATION
Abbreviation’ is another famous and widely used
word-formation method used to shorten a word or
phrase.
•EXAMPLES:
Words/Phrases Abbreviation
Junior Jr.
Mister Mr.
Mistress Mrs.
Doctor Dr.
Department Dept.
Bachelor of Arts B.A
Master of Arts M.A
Master of Business MBA
Administration
8.ACRONYMS
An Acronym is a popular word-formation process in
which an initialism is pronounced as a word.
It forms from the first letter of each word in a phrase,
and the newly formed letters create a new word that
helps us speedy communication.
For example, ‘PIN’ is an initialism for Personal Identification
Number used as the word ‘pin.’
• EXAMPLES:
Acronyms Words/Phrases
HIV Human Immunodeficiency Virus
AIDS Acquired Immunodeficiency Syndrome
NASA National Aeronautics and Space
Administration
ASAP As Soon As Possible
AWOL Absent Without Leave
9.BORROWING
‘Borrowing’ is another word-formation process in
which a word from one language is borrowed directly
into another language.
EXAMPLES:
Words Borrowed from
Algebra Arabic
Cherub Hebrew
Murder French
Pizza Italian
Tamale Spanish
SEMANTICS
Semantics is the study of meaning in language. It can be
applied to entire texts or to single words. In linguistics,
semantics is the subfield that studies meaning. Semantics can
address meaning at the levels of words, phrases, sentences,
or larger units of discourse. One of the crucial questions which
unites different approaches to linguistic semantics is that of
the relationship between form and meaning.
Semantics involves the deconstruction of words, signals, and
sentence structure. It influences our reading comprehension
as well as our comprehension of other people‟s words in
everyday conversation. Semantics play a large part in our daily
communication, understanding, and language learning
without us even realizing it. For example, in everyday use, a
child might make use of semantics to understand a mom‟s
directive to “do your chores” as, “do your chores whenever
you feel like it.” However, the mother was probably saying,
“do your chores right now.”
Semantics is the study of meaning, but what do we mean by
„meaning‟? Meaning has been given different definitions in
the past. Meaning equals connotation. The meaning is simply
the set of associations that a word evokes, and it is the
meaning of a word defined by the images that its users
connect to it. So „winter‟ might mean „snow‟, „sledging‟ and
„mulled wine‟. But what about someone living in the
amazon? Their „winter‟ is still wet and hot, so its original
meaning is lost. Because the associations of a word don‟t
always apply, it was decided that this couldn‟t be the whole
story .
It has also been suggested that the meaning of a word is
simply the entity in the World which that word refers to. This
makes perfect sense for proper nouns like „New York‟ and
„the Eiffel Tower‟, but there are lots of words like „sing‟ and
„altruism‟ that don‟t have a solid thing in the world that they
are connected to. So meaning cannot be entirely denotation
either. So meaning, in Semantics, is defined as being
Extension: The thing in the world that the word/phrase refers
to, plus Intension: The concepts/mental images that the
word/phrase evokes.
Thus, semantics is interested in how meaning works in
language: The study of semantics looks at how meaning works
in language, and because of this it often uses native speaker
intuitions about the meaning of words and phrases to base
research on. We all understand semantics already on a
subconscious level, it‟s how we understand each other when
we speak. How the way in which words are put together
creates meaning is one of the things that semantics looks at,
and is based on, how the meaning of speech is not just
derived from the meanings of the individual words all put
together. The principle of compositionality says that the
meaning of speech is the sum of the meanings of the
individual words plus the way in which they are arranged into
a structure. Likewise, semantics also looks at the ways in
which the meanings of words can be related to each other.
2. Sense Relations
Here are a few of the ways in which words can be
semantically related 1. Synonymy – Words are synonymous/
synonyms when they can be used to mean the same thing (at
least in some contexts – words are rarely fully identical in all
contexts). Begin and start, Big and large, Youth and
adolescent 2. Antonymy Words are antonyms of one another
when they have opposite meanings (again, at least in some
contexts). Big and small, Come and go, Up and down.
3. Polysemy – A word is polysemous when it has two or more
related meanings. In this case the word takes one form but
can be used to mean two different things. In the case of
polysemy, these two meanings must be related in some way,
and not be two completely unrelated meanings of the word.
Bright (shining) and bright (intelligent). Mouse (animal) and
mouse (computer hardware).
4. Homophony – Homophony is similar to polysemy in that it
refers to a single form of word with two meanings, however a
word is a homophone when the two meanings are entirely
unrelated. Bat (flying mammal) and bat (sports equipment).
Pen (writing instrument) and pen (small cage) (Betti, and
Yaseen, 2020: 61). (Al-Seady, 1995: 77)
SEMANTICS THEORIES
Behaviourist semantics
B.F. Skinner
B.F. Skinner, 1971.
In an effort to render linguistic meaning public and the study
of linguistic meaning more “scientific,” the American
psychologist B.F. Skinner (1904–90) proposed that the correct
semantics for a natural language is behaviouristic: the
meaning of an expression, as uttered on a particular occasion,
is either (1) the behavioral stimulus that produces the
utterance, (2) the behavioral response that the utterance
produces, or (3) a combination of both. Thus, the meaning of
fire! as uttered on a particular occasion might include running
or calling for help. But even on a single occasion it is possible
that not everyone who hears fire! will respond by running or
calling for help. Suppose, for example, that the hearers of the
utterance include a firefighter, a pyromaniac, and a person
who happens to know that the speaker is a pathological liar.
The behaviourist account seems committed to the implausible
view that the meaning of fire! for those people is different
from the meaning of fire! for others who run or call for help.
The behaviourist account, like the ideational one, is also
vulnerable to the objection based on compositionality.
Suppose that a person’s body recoils when he hears brown
cow but not when he hears either brown or cow alone. The
meaning of brown cow, which includes recoiling, is therefore
not determined by or predictable from the meanings of
brown and cow.
Referential semantics
As noted above, reference is an apparent relation between a
word and the world. Russell, following the 19th-century
British philosopher John Stuart Mill, pursued the intuition that
linguistic expressions are signs of something other than
themselves. He suggested that the meaning of an expression
is whatever that expression applies to, thus removing
meaning from the minds of its users and placing it squarely in
the world. According to a referential semantics, all that one
learns when one learns the meaning of tomato is that it
applies to tomatoes and to nothing else. One advantage of a
referential semantics is that it respects compositionality: the
meaning of red tomato is a function of the meanings of red
and tomato, because red tomato will apply to anything that is
both red and a tomato.
But what about expressions that apparently refer to nothing
at all, such as unicorn? A referential semantics would appear
to be committed to the view that expressions such as unicorn,
Santa Claus, and Sherlock Holmes are meaningless. Another
problem, first pointed out by Frege, is that two expressions
may have the same referent without having the same
meaning. The morning star and the evening star, for example,
refer to the same object, the planet Venus, but they are not
synonymous. As Frege noted, it is possible to believe that the
morning star and the evening star are not identical without
being irrational (indeed, the identity of the morning star and
the evening star was a scientific discovery).
Such examples have led some philosophers, including Mill
himself and Saul Kripke, to conclude that proper names lack
meaning. But the problem also affects common nouns,
including definite descriptions. The descriptions the first
president of the United States and the husband of Martha
Washington apply to the same individual but are not
synonymous. It is possible to understand both without
recognizing that they refer to the same person. It follows that
meaning cannot be the same as reference.
Fregean semantics
According to Frege, the meaning of an expression consists of
two elements: a referent and what he called a “sense.” Both
the referent and the sense of an expression contribute
systematically to the truth or falsehood (the “truth value”) of
the sentences in which the expression occurs.
As noted above, Frege pointed out that the substitution of
coreferring expressions in a sentence does not always
preserve truth value: if Smith does not know that George
Washington was the first president of the United States, then
Smith believes that George Washington chopped down a
cherry tree can be true while Smith believes that the first
president of the United States chopped down a cherry tree is
false. Frege’s explanation of the phenomenon was that, in
such sentences, truth value is determined not only by
reference but also by sense. The sense of an expression,
roughly speaking, is not the thing the expression refers to but
the way in which it refers to that thing. The sense of an
expression determines what the expression refers to.
Although each sense determines a single referent, a single
referent may be determined by more than one sense. Thus,
George Washington and the first president of the United
States have the same referent but different senses. The two
belief sentences can differ in truth value because, although
both are about the same individual, the expressions referring
to that individual pick him out in different ways.
Verificationist semantics
Frege did not address the problem of how linguistic
expressions come to have the meanings they do. A natural,
albeit vague, answer is that expressions mean what they do
because of what speakers do with them. An example of that
approach is provided by the school of logical positivism, which
was developed by members of the Vienna Circle discussion
group in the 1920s and ’30s. According to the logical
positivists, the meaning of a sentence is given by an account
of the experiences on the basis of which the sentence could
be verified. Sentences that are unverifiable through any
possible experience (including many ethical, religious, and
metaphysical sentences) are literally meaningless.
The basic idea underlying verificationism is that meaning
results from links between language and experience: some
sentences have meaning because they are definable in terms
of other sentences, but ultimately there must be certain basic
sentences, what the logical positivists called “observation
sentences,” whose meaning derives from their direct
connection with experience and specifically from the fact that
they are reports of experience. The meaning of an expression
smaller than a sentence is similarly dependent on experience.
Roughly speaking, the meaning of an expression is given by an
account of the experiences on the basis of which one could
verify that the expression applies to one thing or another.
Although the circumstances in which triangular and trilateral
apply are the same, speakers go about verifying those
applications in different ways.