Unit 3 Ai - Imsc
Unit 3 Ai - Imsc
SYLLABUS
UNIT 3
67
Functions, which are a subset of relations where there is only one “value” for any given
“input”
First-order Predicate logic (FOPL) provides
Constants: a, b, dog33. Name a specific object.
Variables: X, Y. Refer to an object without naming it.
Functions: Mapping from objects to objects.
Terms: Refer to objects
Atomic Sentences: in(dad-of(X), food6) Can be true or false, Correspond to propositional
symbols P, Q.
A well-formed formula (wff) is a sentence containing no “free” variables. So, That is, all
variables are “bound” by universal or existential quantifiers.
(∀x)P(x, y) has x bound as a universally quantified variable, but y is free.
Quantifiers
Universal quantification
(∀x)P(x) means that P holds for all values of x in the domain associated with that variable
E.g., (∀x) dolphin(x) → mammal(x)
Existential quantification
(∃ x)P(x) means that P holds for some value of x in the domain associated with that
variable
E.g., (∃ x) mammal(x) 𝖠 lays-eggs(x)
Also, Consider the following example that shows the use of predicate logic as a way of
representing knowledge.
1. Marcus was a man.
2. Marcus was a Pompeian.
3. All Pompeians were Romans.
4. Caesar was a ruler.
5. Also, All Pompeians were either loyal to Caesar or hated him.
6. Everyone is loyal to someone.
7. People only try to assassinate rulers they are not loyal to.
8. Marcus tried to assassinate Caesar.
The facts described by these sentences can be represented as a set of well-formed formulas (wffs)
as follows:
1. Marcus was a man.
man(Marcus)
2. Marcus was a Pompeian.
Pompeian(Marcus)
3. All Pompeians were Romans.
∀x: Pompeian(x) → Roman(x)
4. Caesar was a ruler.
ruler(Caesar)
5. All Pompeians were either loyal to Caesar or hated him.
inclusive-or
∀x: Roman(x) → loyalto(x, Caesar) ∨ hate(x, Caesar)
exclusive-or
∀x: Roman(x) → (loyalto(x, Caesar) 𝖠¬ hate(x, Caesar)) ∨
(¬loyalto(x, Caesar) 𝖠 hate(x, Caesar))
68
6. Everyone is loyal to someone.
∀x: ∃y: loyalto(x, y)
7. People only try to assassinate rulers they are not loyal to.
∀x: ∀y: person(x) 𝖠 ruler(y) 𝖠 tryassassinate(x, y)
→¬loyalto(x, y)
8. Marcus tried to assassinate Caesar.
tryassassinate(Marcus, Caesar)
Now suppose if we want to use these statements to answer the question: Was Marcus loyal to
Caesar?
Also, Now let’s try to produce a formal proof, reasoning backward from the desired goal: ¬
Ioyalto(Marcus, Caesar)
In order to prove the goal, we need to use the rules of inference to transform it into another goal
(or possibly a set of goals) that can, in turn, transformed, and so on, until there are no unsatisfied
goals remaining.
69
Representing Instance and ISA Relationships
Specific attributes instance and isa play an important role particularly in a useful form of
reasoning called property inheritance.
The predicates instance and isa explicitly captured the relationships they used to express,
namely class membership and class inclusion.
4.2 shows the first five sentences of the last section represented in logic in three different
ways.
The first part of the figure contains the representations we have already discussed. In
these representations, class membership represented with unary predicates (such as
Roman), each of which corresponds to a class.
Asserting that P(x) is true is equivalent to asserting that x is an instance (or element) of P.
The second part of the figure contains representations that use the instance predicate
explicitly.
70
Computable Functions and Predicates
To express simple facts, such as the following greater-than and less-than relationships:
gt(1,O) It(0,1) gt(2,1) It(1,2) gt(3,2) It( 2,3)
It is often also useful to have computable functions as well as computable predicates.
Thus we might want to be able to evaluate the truth of gt(2 + 3,1)
To do so requires that we first compute the value of the plus function given the arguments
2 and 3, and then send the arguments 5 and 1 to gt.
Consider the following set of facts, again involving Marcus:
1) Marcus was a man.
man(Marcus)
2) Marcus was a Pompeian.
Pompeian(Marcus)
3) Marcus was born in 40 A.D.
born(Marcus, 40)
4) All men are mortal.
x: man(x) → mortal(x)
5) All Pompeians died when the volcano erupted in 79 A.D.
erupted(volcano, 79) 𝖠 ∀ x : [Pompeian(x) → died(x, 79)]
6) No mortal lives longer than 150 years.
x: t1: At2: mortal(x) born(x, t1) gt(t2 – t1,150) → died(x, t2)
7) It is now 1991.
now = 1991
So, Above example shows how these ideas of computable functions and predicates can be useful.
It also makes use of the notion of equality and allows equal objects to be substituted for each
other whenever it appears helpful to do so during a proof.
So, Now suppose we want to answer the question “Is Marcus alive?”
The statements suggested here, there may be two ways of deducing an answer.
Either we can show that Marcus is dead because he was killed by the volcano or we can
show that he must be dead because he would otherwise be more than 150 years old,
which we know is not possible.
Also, As soon as we attempt to follow either of those paths rigorously, however, we
discover, just as we did in the last example, that we need some additional knowledge. For
example, our statements talk about dying, but they say nothing that relates to being alive,
which is what the question is asking.
So we add the following facts:
8) Alive means not dead.
x: t: [alive(x, t) → ¬ dead(x, t)] [¬ dead(x, t) → alive(x, t)]
9) If someone dies, then he is dead at all later times.
x: t1: At2: died(x, t1) gt(t2, t1) → dead(x, t2)
So, Now let’s attempt to answer the question “Is Marcus alive?” by proving: ¬ alive(Marcus,
now)
71
Resolution
Propositional Resolution
1. Convert all the propositions of F to clause form.
2. Negate P and convert the result to clause form. Add it to the set of clauses obtained in
step 1.
3. Repeat until either a contradiction is found or no progress can be made:
1. Select two clauses. Call these the parent clauses.
2. Resolve them together. The resulting clause, called the resolvent, will be the
disjunction of all of the literals of both of the parent clauses with the following
exception: If there are any pairs of literals L and ¬ L such that one of the parent
clauses contains L and the other contains ¬L, then select one such pair and
eliminate both L and ¬ L from the resolvent.
3. If the resolvent is the empty clause, then a contradiction has been found. If it is
not, then add it to the set of classes available to the procedure.
The Unification Algorithm
In propositional logic, it is easy to determine that two literals cannot both be true at the
same time.
Simply look for L and ¬L in predicate logic, this matching process is more complicated
since the arguments of the predicates must be considered.
For example, man(John) and ¬man(John) is a contradiction, while the man(John) and
¬man(Spot) is not.
Thus, in order to determine contradictions, we need a matching procedure that compares
two literals and discovers whether there exists a set of substitutions that makes them
identical.
There is a straightforward recursive procedure, called the unification algorithm, that does
it.
Algorithm: Unify(L1, L2)
1. If L1 or L2 are both variables or constants, then:
1. If L1 and L2 are identical, then return NIL.
2. Else if L1 is a variable, then if L1 occurs in L2 then return {FAIL}, else return
(L2/L1).
3. Also, Else if L2 is a variable, then if L2 occurs in L1 then return {FAIL}, else
return (L1/L2). d. Else return {FAIL}.
2. If the initial predicate symbols in L1 and L2 are not identical, then return {FAIL}.
3. If LI and L2 have a different number of arguments, then return {FAIL}.
4. Set SUBST to NIL. (At the end of this procedure, SUBST will contain all the
substitutions used to unify L1 and L2.)
5. For I ← 1 to the number of arguments in L1 :
1. Call Unify with the ith argument of L1 and the ith argument of L2, putting the
result in S.
2. If S contains FAIL then return {FAIL}.
3. If S is not equal to NIL then:
2. Apply S to the remainder of both L1 and L2.
3. SUBST: = APPEND(S, SUBST).
6. Return SUBST.
72
Resolution in Predicate Logic
We can now state the resolution algorithm for predicate logic as follows, assuming a set of given
statements F and a statement to be proved P:
Algorithm: Resolution
1. Convert all the statements of F to clause form.
2. Negate P and convert the result to clause form. Add it to the set of clauses obtained in 1.
3. Repeat until a contradiction found, no progress can make, or a predetermined amount of
effort has expanded.
1. Select two clauses. Call these the parent clauses.
2. Resolve them together. The resolvent will the disjunction of all the literals of both
parent clauses with appropriate substitutions performed and with the following
exception: If there is one pair of literals T1 and ¬T2 such that one of the parent
clauses contains T2 and the other contains T1 and if T1 and T2 are unifiable, then
neither T1 nor T2 should appear in the resolvent. We call T1 and T2
Complementary literals. Use the substitution produced by the unification to create
the resolvent. If there is more than one pair of complementary literals, only one
pair should omit from the resolvent.
3. If the resolvent is an empty clause, then a contradiction has found. Moreover, If it
is not, then add it to the set of classes available to the procedure.
Resolution Procedure
Resolution is a procedure, which gains its efficiency from the fact that it operates on
statements that have been converted to a very convenient standard form.
Resolution produces proofs by refutation.
In other words, to prove a statement (i.e., to show that it is valid), resolution attempts to
show that the negation of the statement produces a contradiction with the known
statements (i.e., that it is unsatisfiable).
The resolution procedure is a simple iterative process: at each step, two clauses, called
the parent clauses, are compared (resolved), resulting in a new clause that has inferred
from them. The new clause represents ways that the two parent clauses interact with each
other. Suppose that there are two clauses in the system:
winter V summer
¬ winter V cold
Now we observe that precisely one of winter and ¬ winter will be true at any point.
If winter is true, then cold must be true to guarantee the truth of the second clause. If ¬
winter is true, then summer must be true to guarantee the truth of the first clause.
Thus we see that from these two clauses we can deduce summer V cold
This is the deduction that the resolution procedure will make.
Resolution operates by taking two clauses that each contains the same literal, in this
example, winter.
Moreover, The literal must occur in the positive form in one clause and in negative form
in the other. The resolvent obtained by combining all of the literals of the two parent
clauses except the ones that cancel.
If the clause that produced is the empty clause, then a contradiction has found.
For example, the two clauses
winter
73
¬ winter
will produce the empty clause.
Rule for T
The simplest introduction rule is the one for T. It is called "unit". Because it has no premises, this
rule is an axiom: something that can start a proof.
(unit)
T
Rules for Implication
In natural deduction, to prove an implication of the form P ⇒ Q, we assume P, then reason under
that assumption to try to derive Q. If we are successful, then we can conclude that P ⇒ Q.
In a proof, we are always allowed to introduce a new assumption P, then reason under that
assumption. We must give the assumption a name; we have used the name x in the example
below. Each distinct assumption must have a different name.
(assum)
[x : P]
74
Because it has no premises, this rule can also start a proof. It can be used as if the proposition P
were proved. The name of the assumption is also indicated here.
However, you do not get to make assumptions for free! To get a complete proof, all assumptions
must be eventually discharged. This is done in the implication introduction rule. This rule
introduces an implication P ⇒ Q by discharging a prior assumption [x : P]. Intuitively, if Q can
be proved under the assumption P, then the implication P ⇒ Q holds without any assumptions.
We write x in the rule name to show which assumption is discharged. This rule and modus
ponens are the introduction and elimination rules for implications.
[x : P]
⋮ P P⇒Q
(⇒-elim, modus ponens)
Q Q
P ⇒ Q (⇒-intro/x)
A proof is valid only if every assumption is eventually discharged. This must happen in the proof
tree below the assumption. The same assumption can be used more than once.
Rules for Disjunction
P (∨-intro- Q (∨-intro- P∨Q P⇒R Q ⇒ R (∨-
76
For example, here is a proof of the proposition (A ⇒ B ⇒ C) ⇒ (A 𝖠 B ⇒ C).
A proposition that has a complete proof in a deductive system is called a theorem of that system.
Soundness and Completeness
A measure of a deductive system's power is whether it is powerful enough to prove all true
statements. A deductive system is said to be complete if all true statements are theorems (have
proofs in the system). For propositional logic and natural deduction, this means that all
tautologies must have natural deduction proofs. Conversely, a deductive system is
called sound if all theorems are true. The proof rules we have given above are in fact sound and
complete for propositional logic: every theorem is a tautology, and every tautology is a theorem.
Finding a proof for a given tautology can be difficult. But once the proof is found, checking that
it is indeed a proof is completely mechanical, requiring no intelligence or insight whatsoever. It
is therefore a very strong argument that the thing proved is in fact true.
We can also make writing proofs less tedious by adding more rules that provide reasoning
shortcuts. These rules are sound if there is a way to convert a proof using them into a proof using
the original rules. Such added rules are called admissible.
77
A representation in which the control information that is necessary to use the knowledge
is embedded in the knowledge itself for e.g. computer programs, directions, and recipes;
these indicate specific use or implementation;
The real difference between declarative and procedural views of knowledge lies in where
control information reside.
For example, consider the following
Man (Marcus)
Man (Caesar)
Person (Cleopatra)
∀x: Man(x) → Person(x)
Now, try to answer the question. ?Person(y)
The knowledge base justifies any of the following answers.
Y=Marcus
Y=Caesar
Y=Cleopatra
We get more than one value that satisfies the predicate.
If only one value needed, then the answer to the question will depend on the order in
which the assertions examined during the search for a response.
If the assertions declarative then they do not themselves say anything about how they will
be examined. In case of procedural representation, they say how they will examine.
Declarative Knowledge
A statement in which knowledge specified, but the use to which that knowledge is to be
put is not given.
For example, laws, people’s name; these are the facts which can stand alone, not
dependent on other knowledge;
So to use declarative representation, we must have a program that explains what is to do
with the knowledge and how.
For example, a set of logical assertions can combine with a resolution theorem prover to
give a complete program for solving problems but in some cases, the logical assertions
can view as a program rather than data to a program.
Hence the implication statements define the legitimate reasoning paths and automatic
assertions provide the starting points of those paths.
These paths define the execution paths which is similar to the ‘if then else “in traditional
programming.
So logical assertions can view as a procedural representation of knowledge.
78