PHIL201 Lec1
PHIL201 Lec1
WSU-Tricities
What is Logic?
1
Arguments
The Building Blocks of Arguments
2
We can break this argument down into it’s discrete claims.
3
Propositions
4
You may not know whether a particular proposition is true or false,
but it still is either true or false, you just don’t know what it’s truth
value is.
Some propositions with unknown truth values
5
Propositions are often referred to as statements by some logicians,
and these terms will be used interchangeably in this course.
When you make some statement, you assert (or negate) some claim.
The claim you assert or negate may be true or false.
6
Questions, Commands, and Exclamations
7
Command or Imperatives such as ”Duck!”, ”Stop!” or ”Come quickly!”
also do not assert or negate any claims so they are not propositions.
• ”Duck!”
8
Compound Propositions
• Conjunctive
• Disjunctive
• Conditional
9
Conjuctive Propositions
10
Conjuctive Propositions
11
Our original proposition is equivalent to
12
Figure 1: Conjuctive, because all of the components are linked together
13
Conjuctive Proposition Example
What are the component propositions? Are they true or false? Is the
entire proposition true or false?
14
Disjunctive Propositions
• It is raining outside
• It is sunny
15
However, unlike in the case of a conjuctive proposition, in this
proposition, the truth of the compound proposition does not
depend on the truth of all of the component propositions, but on
any one of them.
A compound proposition that is true if any one of it’s component
propositions is true is known as a disjunctive proposition.
Each component proposition stands alone and is able to make the
entire proposition true.
16
Disjunctive Proposition Example
What are the component propositions? Are they true or false? Is the
entire proposition true or false?
17
Conditional Propositions
• It is raining
• I should not bike to work
18
Conisder the proposition
19
Building an argument
20
The Structure of an Argument
21
• Based on our experience and knowledge of what rain does to
roadways, we can infer from the fact that it is raining that the
roads will be slippery.
• Based on our knowledge of slippery roads, we can infer that
biking is dangerous.
• Based on our knowledge of whether or not we should do
dangerous things, we can infer we should not bike
Inference Inference
It is raining −−−−−→ The roads will be slippery −−−−−→
Inference
Biking is dangerous on slippery roads −−−−−→ I should not bike
| {z }
Argument
22
Implied Propositions
23
There is an implied proposition here, which we do not include
because we believe everyone would agree with it unquestionably.
24
Consider the alternative argument
Inference
It is raining −−−−−→ The roads will not be slippery →
Biking is safe on non-slippery roads → I should bike to campus
| {z }
Argument
25
Consider the alternative argument
Inference
It is raining −−−−−→ The roads will not be slippery →
Biking is safe on non-slippery roads → I should bike to campus
| {z }
Argument
26
Consider the alternative argument
27
Figure 2: Me arguing about politics
28
When formulating an argument, there is typically some final
proposition that you wish to reach; a decision to be reached, a point
to be made. This proposition is the conclusion of your argument.
In the previous example, I was trying to decide whether or not to
bike to work. I should not bike was my conclusion.
The propositions which I use to build up to that conclusion, either by
asserting them prima facie or by affirming them through other
propositions and inferences are known as premises
29
The premises of my previous argument were
• It is raining
• The road is slippery when raining
• Biking is dangerous on slippery roads
30
Generic Argument Structure
Premises
z }| { z }|
Conclusion
{
Inf Inf Inf
Proposition 1 −→ Proposition 2 −→ Proposition 3 −→ Proposition 4
| {z }
Argument
31
Analyzing and using arguments
32
We’re going to start our with analyzing the form and structure of
arguments.
Subsequently, we’ll look at the quality of the argument to see if the
claimed conclusion is in fact warranted based on the argument.
33
Basic Arguments
Premise Conclusion
z }| { Inf z }| {
Proposition 1 −→ Proposition 2
| {z }
Argument
34
Each proposition can make an appearance as it’s own sentence
35
Alternatively, the propositions can be bound together in a single
sentence.
Since it turns out that all humans are descended from a
small number of African ancestors in our recent
evolutionary past, believing in profound differences between
the races is as ridiculous as believing in a flat earth.
36
An Essay as an argument
37
Much like the sentence breakdown of an argument, the order in
which the premises appear in a text is not importantly in gauging the
qualitiy or validity of the argument. Often times, a conclusion will
precede a premise or set of premises.
In the simplest form this could look something like
38
Arguments vs Propositions
39
Now consider
A state aims to be a society composed of equals, and
therefore a state that is based on the middle class is bound
to be the best constituted.
40
Arguments vs Collection of Propositions
41
Arguments vs Collection of Propositions
42
Identify Premises and Conclusions: Example
43
• Edmund Hillary completed an impossible task (Premise)
• Sherpa’s helped him complete this task (Premise)
• Those who do not forget their helpers are heroes (Premise)
• Hillary did not forget the Sherpas who helped him (Premise)
• Edmund Hillary is a Hero (Conclusion)
44
The Argument Clinic
45
Recognizing Arguments
Indicators
46
Conclusion Indicators
• Therefore
• Hence
• Thus
• So
• It follows that
• From which we can infer
• Consequently
47
Premise Indicators
• Since
• Because
• following from
• as shown by
• may be inferred from
• in view of the fact
48
Indicator Warning
49
The wonderful world of context
50
We could make essentially an identical argument paraphrased as
51
The original quote’s argument can be paraphrased out as (unstated
premises in grey)
52
Premises or Conclusions not in Declarative Form
53
Rhetorical Questions
54
The proposition being asserted is essentially;
The author asks it as a question, but they don’t want you to answer
it; Clearly you couldn’t answer him if you wanted to. Instead, they are
asserting the answer to that question is No.
55
The coin-conscious writer continues
Wouldn’t honoring women who have served as governors,
Supreme Court justices, or legislators be a more fitting
tribute to this nation’s womens than coins featuring ”First
Spouses”?
56
Danger of Rhetorical Questions
57
Additionally, rhetorical questions can be used in a somewhat
specious and dishonest way; to assert something with having to
carry the responsibility of asserting something. Consider this
statement made by Congressmen Steve King last week.
In the context of the interview which this statement was made, his
not asking because he is genuinely curious about the answer. He’s
asking to make the point that it is not offensive. Yet, if he were to
come out and say that directly, there would uproar about his
comment.
As a rhetorical question, he can avoid taking responsibility for his
argument and instead fall back on the defense that his is ”just
asking questions”.
58
Figure 3: Give it up for rhetorical questions, ladies and gentleman.
59
Betteridges Law of Headlines
60
Commands
61
But it is making an argument; one that could be written more
explicitly as:
62
Unstated Propositions
The unstated proposition ”you should not do evil things”, is taken for
granted.
An argument that appears incomplete because one or more
propositions is taken as assumed is called an enthymeme.
63
Arguments vs Explanations
64
An argument is a series of connected statements to establish the
truth of a proposition (your conclusion).
In this case, we’re not trying to establish what your grade was, or
whether or not your grade is 70%, but merely provide you with the
reasoning why your grade was 70%
If some fact is known to be true, and several propositions are used
to explicate the why of that truth, those connected propositions form
not an argument, but an explanation.
65
Determining Arguments vs Explanations
P because Q
The general rule for determining if something is an argument or an
explanation is.
66
Explanation vs Proposition Example
67
1. This is an explanation; no one argues about the color of the
daytime sky on a clear day; the question is not open for
discussion. Everyone knows the answer, and here we are
explaining that is the particular case.
2. This is an argument; the so-called ”star light problem” used to
argue against young Earth creation theorists. There is some
pushback about the notion that the universe is 13.4 billion years
old. So it’s an argument against a 6,000 year old universe.
Needless to say, this hasn’t ended the controversy.
68
Inductive and Deductive
Arguments
Types of Reasoning
69
Deductive Argument Examples
70
Validity
71
Validity Example
72
Validity Example
So once again, we assume all the premises are true, and see if the
conclusion must be true because of them.
Could there be other reasons Jan isn’t getting paid (unpaid leave)?
So does Jan not getting paid necessitate that the government must
be shut down?
It doesn’t; the conclusion does not necessarily follows from the
premise; this is a invalid deductive argument.
73
All deductive arguments either succeed if all the premises is true, or
they fail if all the premises are true, thus, every deductive argument
is either valid or invalid.
We will discuss at length, the varieties of valid and invalid deductive
arguments, and how to analyze them.
In chapters 5,6 and 7, we’ll use Classical, Aristotlean logic to analyze
and determine the validity of arguments.
In chapters 8,9,10, we’ll use modern, symbolic logic to determine
validity.
74
Why you as a computer scientist should care
75
This is equivalent to the argument.
76
Shape 1
Figure 4: A square
77
Shape 2
Figure 5: A rectangle
78
Shape 3
Figure 6: A rhombus
79
Shape 4
80
If you want you code to run correctly, all your logical statements
must be composed of or reducible to valid deductive arguments.
If you want your code to behave correctly, all your premises must
be true.
81
Inductive arguments
82
Inductive vs Deductive argument example
83
Inductive Reasoning
84
There are numerous ways to analyze inductive arguments, but
because they do not make claims with certainty, the notions of
validitiy and invalidity do not apply to inductive arguments, as they
do to deductive arguments.
If we have time at the end of the semester, we’ll look at a method of
formalizing inductive reasioning mathematically to assign
probabilities to certain conclusions, through the use of Bayesian
Statistics.
85
Validity and Truth
86
Invalid Argument Table
87
Invalid Argument: True Premises, True Conclusions
88
Invalid Argument: True Premises, False Conclusions
If Bill Gates owned all the gold in Fort Knox, then Bill Gates
would be wealthy. Bill Gates does not own all the gold in
Fort Knox. Therefore, Bill Gates is not wealthy.
89
Valid Argument Table
On the other hand, if you know the premises of a valid argument are
true, you know immediately that the conclusion is true. This follows
from the definition of a valid argument.
90
Valid Argument: True Premises, True Conclusion
91
Valid Argument: False Premises, False Conclusions
All for legged creatures have wings, all spiders have exactly
4 legs, therefore all spiders have wings.
All fish are mammals, all whales are fish, therefore all
whales are mammals.
92
Then, you see if the premises being true forces the conclusion to be
true.
None of this depends on the actual truth of the
premises/conclusionsRemember, when gauging the validity of an
argument; you assume all premises are true.
Then, you see if the premises being true forces the conclusion to be
true.
None of this depends on the actual truth of the
premises/conclusions
93