Bounded Rationality and Political Science
Bounded Rationality and Political Science
ABSTRACT
By 1958, a model of human behavior capable of serving as the microlevel foundation for
organizational and policy studies was in place. The scientific soundness of that model is un-
questioned, yet the fundamentals of that behavioral model of choice have not yet been in-
corporated into political science. Much analysis relies on models of rational maximization
despite the availability of a more scientifically sound behavioral base. In this article I exam-
ine the reasons for and ramifications of this neglect of sound science in political science,
focusing primarily on public policy and public administration. While neither approach can lay
claim to major successes in prediction, the behavioral model of choice predicts distributions
of organizational and policy outputs in a superior fashion.
Most people who study politics and government care little about the fine details of the
specifics of human cognition; they are quite content to leave that to biologists, psychologists,
and cognitive scientists. What they cannot escape, however, is the need for some firm foun-
dation that can link human behavior to macropolitics. That foundation must fulfill three cri-
teria: First, it must do no harm (it should not mislead); second, it must allow movement be-
tween individual-level processes and organizational processes in a more or less seamless
manner; and third, it should be efficient in that it does not drag in specifics of human be-
havior that are not needed to understand the policy-making process.
I will show how the model of bounded rationality, as initially articulated by Herbert A.
Simon, a political scientist, (and then expanded by Simon, organizational theorists such as
James A. March, and cognitive scientists such as Allen Newell) fulfills these criteria. This
foundation has been available since 1958.1 I will show that the common alternative as-
sumption, comprehensive rationality, fails to produce satisfactory scientific predictability
and that bounded rationality is a superior mechanism. It is superior in two respects: It per-
forms better in linking the procedures of human choice with the organizational and policy
processes, and it performs better in predicting organizational and policy outcomes in a very
important class of collective behaviors. Neither approach does very well in “point predic-
tion” (predicting precise events), but bounded rationality makes distributional predictions in
1 This paper draws heavily from Jones 2003 and Jones 2002. I appreciated comments from Frank Baumgartner,
Steve Brown, Jon Mercer, Tracy Sulkin, and Jim True.
DOI: 10.1093/jopart/mug028
Journal of Public Administration Research and Theory, Vol. 13, no. 4, pp. 395–412
© 2003 Journal of Public Administration Research and Theory, Inc.
396 Journal of Public Administration Research and Theory
a manner not matched by assumptions of full rationality. Finally, I examine studies in pub-
lic administration and public policy that have relied on comprehensive rationality as an un-
derpinning, showing how they reach an impasse when prediction fails and how they lead to
overinvestment in one aspect of the complexities of public organizations.
1. Behavioral choice. In 1957, Simon published a collection of his papers under the
title Models of Man. The volume included his 1955 paper “A Behavioral Model
of Rational Choice,” which appeared in the Quarterly Journal of Economics
(Simon 1955). (Simon received the Nobel Prize in Economics in 1978 for this
paper.) With this work, bounded rationality became a positive theory of choice,
not solely a critique of comprehensive rationality.
2. Cognitive psychology. The field of psychology during the 1950s was in the grips
of Skinnerism: To be scientific, it was claimed, one could not rely on the
artificial and unobservable constructs of mental processing. In 1958, Allen
Newell and Herbert Simon published “Elements of a Theory of Human Problem-
Solving” in the Psychological Review. This article formed the basis for modern
cognitive psychology, which gets “inside the heads” of people to examine how
they think and reason (Newell and Simon 1958).
3. Artificial intelligence. In 1957, Newell, Simon, and Clifford Shaw published a
joint paper, “Empirical Implication of the Logic Theory Machine,” which argued
that computers could be used to model human thought; this was a breakthrough
in the field of artificial intelligence (Newell, Shaw, and Simon 1957; Newell and
Simon 1956).
4. Behavioral organization theory. In 1958, March and Simon published
Organizations, a tour de force that established the field of behavioral organization
theory. The work linked organizations and the newly developed behavioral theory
of choice. Behavioral organization theory “gets inside the organization” to examine
the role of organizational processes in determining bureau or firm outputs in a man-
ner analogous to the way that behavioral decision theory does for the individual.
Jones Bounded Rationality and Political Science 397
By 1958, then, all the elements of a scientifically sound model of human choice and the ca-
pacity to expand that model downward into psychological processes and upward into organ-
izations and political and economic institutions were in place. It is fascinating to note how lit-
tle of the stream of research in economics and political science actually made use of the model.
In political science, much time was spent fighting Simon’s approach as “too scientific” for
the humanistic study of politics; later the public choice approach simply ignored the model.
Economists “went on counting angels on the heads of neoclassical pins” (Simon 1999, 113).
It is no accident that the behavioral model of choice came more or less directly from
the behavioral discipline of political science. Simon credited his participation as a student
in Charles Merriam’s behavioral revolution at the University of Chicago in the 1930s for this
influence (Simon 1996a). The scientific tenets of political behavioralism were strong on ob-
servation and quantification and not as strong on theory; the movement had a clearly in-
ductive flavor. It demanded real-world observation—Merriam wanted to make a difference
in the conduct of public policy as well as in the conduct of scientific inquiry.
The notion of bounded rationality has been confused with a lack of calculational abil-
ity. Lupia, McCubbins, and Popkin recently claimed that “Herbert Simon argued that, unlike
homo economicus, people are not omniscient calculators—they do not do all of the calcula-
tions all of the time” (2000, 9). Simon, March, and Newell all stressed that calculations were
a minimal part of the difficulty and were easily solved using notepads, calculating machines,
or a bureau of accountants. Simon did write extensively, however, about attention, emotion,
habit, and memory, and he explored the functionality and dysfunctionality of these aspects of
the architecture of human cognition. It is true that a prime component of the behavioral model
of choice is difficulty in planning and executing long behavioral sequences (Jones 2001, 61),
but this aspect of the model should not be confused with calculational difficulties.
Principle of Adaptation
The principle of adaptation stems most directly from the studies of Newell and Simon on
human problem solving and is best stated in Simon’s The Sciences of the Artificial (1996b).
He claimed that most human behavior is explained by the nature of the “task environment.”
Given enough time, human thought takes on the shape of the tasks facing it—that is, human
thought is adaptive and basically rational. Simon stated that “there are only a few ‘intrinsic’
characteristics of the inner environment of thinking beings that limit the adaptation of
thought to the shape of the problem environment. All else in thinking and problem-solving
behavior . . . is learned and is subject to improvement” (1996b, 54). From this principle
comes the inference that, in general, the more time a decision maker spends on a problem,
the more likely his or her understanding of the problem will approximate the actual task
environment and the limitations of human cognitive architecture fades (Newell 1990).
Psychologists today tend to stress the distinction between central and peripheral men-
tal processing (Fiske and Taylor 1991, 475–80). Kuklinski and Quirk put it this way: “In
central processing, used when attention and motivation are high, people employ more men-
tal resources, think more systematically, and allow data to shape inferences. In peripheral
processing, used when attention and motivation are low, they employ fewer resources, rely
on simple heuristics, and use top-down, stereotypic inferences” (2000, 163).
Principle of Uncertainty
One of the major strategies of the rational choice approach in social science has been to un-
derstand uncertainty in light of the calculus of probabilities. It is possible now to speak of
“expected utility” and think of outcomes as following a probability distribution. Unfortu-
nately, this undeniable improvement does not come close to telling the entire story of human
decision making. Students of human choice in the real world or in laboratory situations re-
peatedly find that people have great difficulties in working with probabilities, assessing risk,
and making inferences when uncertainty is involved. Indeed, a whole field has emerged
that studies the factors responsible for perceptions of risk; clearly these perceptions are not
just rooted in “nature” but also involve human psychology.
An underlying tenet of bounded rationality from its early years centered on how human
cognitive architecture interacted with an uncertain world; bounded rationalists saw uncer-
tainty as far more fundamental to choice than the probability calculus implied (March 1994).
If one’s understanding of the causal factors involved in a problem is hazy or ambiguous,
then the uncertainty is not contained but reverberates through the entire thought process. If
one is uncertain about how to specify outcomes, then one must also be uncertain about how
to specify one’s utility function. I am not referring to probabilities associated with well-
Jones Bounded Rationality and Political Science 399
specified outcomes; the probability calculus easily handles that. Simon termed this difficulty
“the design problem” to denote the fundamental nature of specifying a space within which
to solve problems. Addressing this reverberation and its impacts on organizational decision
making is perhaps the key contribution of James March’s work.
Principle of Trade-Offs
It became evident very early in the study of human choice that people have a difficult time
trading off one goal against another when making a choice (Slovak 1990; Tetlock 2000). The
classical economic model depicts trade-offs as smooth indifference curves, and modern
rational choice theory offers little new in the theoretical study of trade-offs. The first be-
havioral tool for understanding trade-offs was Simon’s notion of satisficing. His idea that a
person within an organization chooses alternatives that are “good enough” led critics to
claim that the notion was just a poverty-stricken version of maximization. Recently, for ex-
ample, Lupia, McCubbins, and Popkin claimed that bounded rationality was consistent with
maximizing behavior. They cited with approval Jensen and Meckling, who wrote that the
use of the term satisficing “undoubtedly contributed to this confusion because it suggests re-
jection of maximizing behavior rather than maximization subject to costs of information
and decision making” (2000, 9).
If one adds information and decision-making cost constraints to choice, this will not
cause bounded rationality to dissolve into maximizing behavior. The reason is that satisficing
describes the cognitive difficulties people have with trade-offs. As a consequence, satisficing
has little to do with some sort of second-rate maximization approach. Because of limited at-
tention spans, people generally work on goals sequentially. As a consequence, trade-offs
among goals are very difficult. The response, argued Simon, was for people to set aspiration
levels for the goals they wish to achieve. If a choice was good enough (that is, if it exceeded
aspiration levels) for all goals, then it was chosen.
Other models of choice among multiple goals have been developed, including the lex-
icographic strategy (choose the strategy that maximizes gain on the most salient goal and ig-
nore the rest) and elimination by aspects (use a lexicographic strategy unless there is a tie
among alternatives; then and only then use a second goal to break the tie). People have con-
siderable difficulty in trading off benefits against losses, which is something that standard
utility maximization theory recognizes as straightforward (Kahneman and Tversky 1979).
1988, 1992) because of their single-minded focus on experimental design and their rejection
of various tenets of expected utility. Several political scientists have criticized experimen-
tal psychology and behavioral economics literature for their seeming ad hoc nature—they
build findings experimental effect by experimental effect. They noted correctly that exper-
imentation was a very soft foundation from which to study institutions and macropolitics.
From another perspective, David Laitin (1999) properly noted that in everyday actions peo-
ple were adaptive and avoided many of the traps set for them in experiments. But rather
than explore the ramifications of this observation empirically, he jumped to the wholly un-
warranted conclusion that people must be comprehensively rational.
There is no support for these and related lines of argument because the behavioral
model of choice has been available since the late 1950s. It avoids the anomalies problem, is
parsimonious, and, as I shall argue, yields more accurate predictions on aggregates than
comprehensive rationality does.
Bounded rationality points to the limits of rational adaptation; behavioral choice the-
ory provides a body of literature that shows how human choice works. As I noted above,
bounded rationality and the associated behavioral theory of choice is open ended; we do
not know everything about human choice, but we learn more every year. We do know enough
to specify the outlines of what aspects of human cognition must be incorporated to formu-
late a general theory of human choice. I would cite the following:
Clearly these six aspects of human cognition do not tell the whole story. For example, in
many cases in which attention and emotion are aroused, people may insist on following old
rules. But these aspects cover much ground and lay the basis for a general behavioral the-
ory of choice in organizations and institutions.
While organizations clearly free people by extending their capacities to achieve goals,
they can also fall prey to aspects of human cognitive architecture in predictable ways. Major
Jones Bounded Rationality and Political Science 401
aspects of the behavioral theory of organization mirror major facets of the behavioral the-
ory of human choice.
The relationships between organizational decision making and individual decision making
are causal, not metaphorical (Jones 2001). One cannot really understand how organizations
operate without a strong sense of how individuals process information and make decisions.
As a consequence, a firm scientific foundation for policy studies must be rooted in a be-
havioral approach to organizations (see Green and Thompson 2001).
extent to which the model in question can be used to understand and predict collective
choices.
4 Wildavsky 1964 relied in part on data from Fenno, later published in 1966. In his introduction (1966, xxiv),
Fenno described all of the major organizational changes that were eliminated from his data set. Incorporating these
changes implies a far different budgeting process.
Jones Bounded Rationality and Political Science 403
The problem is that public budgets are not incremental, at least when viewed from a
long-enough time span or in a broad-enough sample (True 2000; Jones, Baumgartner, and
True 1996). The processes underlying incremental budgeting may have been misspecified
(Padgett 1980, 1981). Indeed, new budgetary studies, based on outcome predictions but
reliant on a proper appreciation of organizational processes, pointed to a glaring omission
in earlier budget studies. Focused as they were on organizational procedures that stabilize
and make predictable a potentially chaotic environment, earlier studies missed how organ-
izations cope with unexpected change.
There are times when organizations must adjust their standard operating procedures
to address signals from the environment that simply cannot be placed within preexisting
categories. Padgett’s (1980, 1981) examination of federal budget routines found that se-
quential search for acceptable alternatives under conditions of changing political constraints
would yield punctuated change.5 Carpenter (1996) showed that federal agencies often ignore
the budgetary signals sent by Congress unless those signals are sent repeatedly. The first
attempt to cope with a radically changing environment seems to be to use the preexisting set
of rules; only when it becomes clear that the signals cannot be ignored will an agency re-
spond (at the cost of considerable disruption to internal procedures).
Similarly, the FDA’s shift from a priority of protecting public health to one of pro-
moting as well as protecting health had characteristics of a punctuated equilibrium (Cec-
coli 2003). In any case, a smooth response to the problem was not possible because old
decision-rules had to be abandoned and replaced by new ones. This leads to episodic, dis-
jointed behavior.
While the early budget studies had much of the budgeting process right, they didn’t
properly appreciate the role of shifting attention. The allocation of attention is a critical
component of agenda-setting studies (Cohen, March, and Olsen 1972; Kingdon 1996; Baum-
gartner and Jones 1993). Attention shifts in policy making imply changes in standard oper-
ating procedures, which in turn predict major punctuations in policy outcomes. So policy
outcomes should be characterized by periods of stability or incremental adjustment that are
punctuated by periods of rapid change. Further, both stability and change should be more
pronounced than the information coming in to the organization (or, more generally, the pol-
icy subsystem); that is, whatever the information flow, a model of organizational processes
based in bounded rationality predicts a more episodic process in outcomes. Both individu-
als and organizations are disproportionate information processors when they ignore many
signals in the environment until they must overreact (Jones 2001).
5 Padgett’s work on budgeting was based in organizational processes and developed a decisional mechanism that
implied not solely incremental budgetary outputs. These insights did not result in further understanding of the bounded
rationality base of budgeting for a decade and a half, testimony to the lags in adaptation in the research enterprise.
404 Journal of Public Administration Research and Theory
Principal-Agency
The modern literature on public administration indicates that the primary problem—perhaps
the only problem—for the study of bureaucracy is control. Bureaucrats seem to spend their
lives avoiding doing what superiors want them to do. The primary theoretical vehicle for this
extensive line of research is the principal-agent model. This model is based on asymmetric
information—an agent has more information than a principal in his or her area of expertise
and will invariably use that information to cheat the principal unless formal incentives are
in place to make sure that this does not happen.
The model was developed for such situations as when a company hired an accountant,
but it has been adapted enthusiastically to the study of legislative-bureau relationships.
Strangely enough, the model seems to have been more popular in the United States, where
the separation of powers makes the model problematic, than in parliamentary systems, where
it may well be more relevant. There are two major problems with this model: (1) it is based
on an antiquated model of human behavior (basically Skinnerian psychology), and (2) its in-
credible popularity has led to a vast overinvestment of scholarly resources in the study of
control to the exclusion of other worthy topics.
The adoption of an antiquated (or incorrect) model of human behavior has led to truly
strange circumstances in the field. Models based on principal-agency have big problems in
confirmation (see Brehm and Gates 1997; Balla 1998; Carpenter 1996; Balla and Wright
2001). Most interesting is Brehm and Gates’s commentary that “the primary contribution
is . . . our finding of the overwhelming importance of attributes of the organizational culture
in determining subordinates’ levels of compliance” (1993, 578). This is surprising (as Brehm
and Gates are well aware) only if one begins with a bad model. Organizational culture is no
longer some sort of residual variable but a powerful component of properly formulated
analyses (Miller 1992).
What does one do if one finds a general lack of confirmation of the purest principal-
agent models in government agencies? The “as if ” school of thought requires disconfirmation.
6 It is ironic that Skinner’s study of pigeons and mice and the comprehensive rationality of economics both lead
to the same impoverished model of human choice: Only formal incentives matter.
Jones Bounded Rationality and Political Science 405
What do we disconfirm? That control in organizations is not relevant? That the principal-
agent distinction is not valid? That asymmetric information does not occur in bureaucracies?
All of these would be silly but are required by followers of Milton Friedman. What is not
valid is the outmoded model of human behavior that the principal-agent model is based on.
Get rid of the antiquated assumption, and a better perspective on the role of control in bu-
reaucracies emerges.
Administrative Procedures
Perhaps in no other area of public administration has more effort been directed in an inef-
ficient fashion than in the “deck stacking” thesis of McCubbins, Noll, and Weingast (1987).
This theory even comes with its own pet name: “McNollgast.” As is usual in principal-
agent–based theorizing, Congress is obsessed with the control of bureaucrats and sets up ad-
ministrative procedures to empower interests comprising the majority coalition. Yet key
components of the Administrative Procedures Act of 1946 require “notice and comment” be-
fore the issuance of regulations.
On the face of it, this looks more like issuing rules to stabilize an uncertain environ-
ment, maybe even solving the problem of every debate about regulations being appealed to
Congress.7 Organizational routines focus attention toward certain aspects of the environ-
ment and exclude others, and these routines also regularize the responses to environmental
stimuli. It has always been assumed that such rules may carry a bias, but the empirical doc-
umentation of such bias (outside of the questionable bias of allowing the interested the op-
portunity to participate in a democracy) has been difficult. 8 In any case, good science would
have required the explicit exclusion on theoretical or empirical grounds before leaping to an
overhead control model.
If McNollgast was poor science, at least it was a compelling and innovative hypothe-
sis. One wonders why, given the extraordinary attention this piece received, no scholar
pointed out its inconsistencies or the inconsistencies of other hypotheses from behavioral
organization theory.
1. Isolating out one motive from a panoply of those that drive congressional behavior.
If members of Congress are focused fundamentally on reelection, then the right
question is how they balance (or trade off) the various means that could lead to
that goal. One way could be controlling bureaucratic behavior. The behavioral
model of choice would insist that this balancing is accomplished via attentional
mechanisms. How various means to goals get activated is a critical component of
choice, but this is completely ignored in the congressional literature.
against charges that they were violating central office policy. If central control were pursued
to the exclusion of anticipatory problem solving, punishing those showing initiative, soon
the agency would devolve into a pathological one, incapable of responding to changing cir-
cumstances. In effect, most managers do not really want control. They want adaptive in-
formation processing.9
In his study of municipal budgeting, John Crecine (1969) noted that city agencies devel-
oped attention rules, which indicated what aspects of the environment ought to be monitored
for indicators of change that could need addressing. These rules did not tell the agency what
to do, only what to attend to. Similarly Jones (1985) found in a study of Chicago building-
code enforcement that informal norms generally supplanted the complexities of the code,
but that supervisors occasionally sent out signals to field inspectors that all violations were
to be recorded in potentially hot cases. These cases, usually when there was party, neighbor-
hood group, or media interest, simply generated better code enforcement than the bulk of
cases. Differential code enforcement resulted as a consequence of these attention rules.
Research by Armstrong, Carpenter, and Hojnacki (2003) indicates that media atten-
tion to disease is not simply related to mortality and morbidity. This attention seems to me-
diate output indicators, such as investment in cures and related science. The designation of
a hot disease has characteristics of a disjointed response to objective disease characteristics.
Attention is different from any other resource type variable because one cannot allocate
it proportionally to one’s priorities at any one time. Attention is selective; select one aspect
of an environment for study and inattention must be paid to the rest of the environment. At-
tention is partially under the control of a decision maker, but cognitively that decision maker
possesses no comprehensive system for monitoring when enough attention has been de-
voted to a topic. As a consequence, shifts in attentiveness are in large part due to emotional
arousal. Attention shifts are governed by emotion, so they are unavoidably disrupted. Past
decisions are a residue of past allocations of attention because, in many cases, the devotion
of other resources follows attention. Decisions may or may not be consistent—great incon-
sistencies in choices are a result of the level of attention.
9 This example is based on an undergraduate student paper. Interestingly, the SSA refused to allow the develop-
ment of this example into an extended paper for publication.
408 Journal of Public Administration Research and Theory
They avoid punctuated outputs except where inputs are disjointed and episodic. Organiza-
tions composed of rational participants respond directly and efficiently to information dis-
counted by costs. Organizations composed of boundedly rational participants cannot avoid
punctuated outputs because they cannot adjust their behaviors to incoming information of
any degree of complexity.
CONCLUDING COMMENTS
In his commentary for the fiftieth-anniversary celebration of the signing of the Declaration
of Independence, John Adams wrote that the United States was “destined in future history
to form the brightest or blackest page, according to the use and abuse of those political in-
stitutions by which they shall in time come to be shaped by the human mind” (quoted in
Ellis 2000, 247). To Adams there were no guarantees of good government in the design of
institutions. Human history was messy and contingent, and the human mind creative.
Science similarly is not neat, no matter how much the formalists would like to pretend
differently. Formalistic analyses based in an anachronistic model of human behavior, such
as rational maximization in economics and other social sciences, fail in the most important
standard: satisfactory prediction. Only an incomplete and immature science can rest on an
unrealistic microfoundation, as rational analysis requires. Imagine a physicist interested in
the mathematics of subatomic particles but uninterested in finding empirical evidence of
them, or a biologist uninterested in observing genes. That is what the “as if ” school of analy-
sis in effect asks us to do.
Simon was a crucial figure in the development of a sound basis for the study of human
choice; by 1958 the outlines of this model were fundamentally complete.10 We have made
great progress in understanding human choice and its implications for the study of public
policy and public administration since then, but the “rational choice controversy” continues
to plague social science. As Simon did from 1945 until his death in 2001, I continue to ad-
vocate a solid behavioral base for the analysis of political and economic systems. This per-
spective leads invariably to a public administration and public policy oriented more toward
the dynamics of information processing and away from a fascination with control.
REFERENCES
Armstrong, Elizabeth M., Dan Carpenter, and Marie E. Hojnacki. 2003. Whose deaths matter?: Attention
to disease in the public arena. Paper presented at the Conference on the Politics of Biomedical
Research, March, Woodrow Wilson School of Public and International Affairs, Princeton
University.
Balla, Steven J. 1998. Administrative procedures and political control of the bureaucracy 1998.
American Political Science Review 92:663–73.
Balla, Steven J., and John R. Wright. 2001. Interest groups, advisory committees, and congressional
oversight. American Journal of Political Science 45799–812.
Baumgartner, Frank R., and Bryan D. Jones. 1993. Agendas and instability in American politics.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Brehm, John, and Scott Gates. 1993. Donut shops and speed traps: Evaluating models of supervision on
police behavior. American Journal of Political Science 37:555–81.
———. 1997. Working, shirking, and sabotage. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.
10 To the end of his life, Simon insisted that he was a “member of the tribe”; see Simon 1999.
410 Journal of Public Administration Research and Theory
Brown, Steven R. 2001. Structural and functional information: A cautionary note to Fernandes and
Simon. Paper presented at the annual meeting of the Society for the Policy Sciences, New Haven,
Conn.
Camerer, Colin F. 1998. Behavioral economics and nonrational organizational decision making. In
Debating rationality: Nonrational aspects of organizational decision making, edited by Jennifer J.
Halpern and Robert N. Stern.. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.
Camerer, Colin F., and Richard F. Thaler. 1995. Ultimatums, dictators, and manners. Journal of
Economic Perspectives 9:209–19.
Carpenter, Daniel. 1996. Adaptive signal processing, hierarchy, and budgetary control in federal
regulation. American Political Science Review 90:283–302.
Ceccoli, Stephen. 2003. Policy punctuations and regulatory drug review. Journal of Policy History
15:158–91.
Cohen, Michael, James G. March, and Johann Olsen. 1972. A garbage can model of organizational
choice. Administrative Science Quarterly 17:1–25.
Crecine, John. 1969. Government problem solving. Chicago: Rand-McNally.
Ellis, Joseph. 2000. Founding brothers. New York: Vintage.
Fenno, Richard. 1966. The power of the purse. Boston: Little, Brown.
Fernandes, Ronald, and Herbert A. Simon. 1999. A study of how individuals solve complex and ill-
structured problems. Policy Sciences 32:225– 45.
Fiske, Susan, and Shelly Taylor. 1991. Social cognition. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Friedman, Jeffrey. 1996. Introduction: Economic approaches to politics. In The rational choice
controversy: Economic models of politics reconsidered, edited by Jeffrey Friedman. New Haven,
Conn.: Yale University Press.
Frolich, Norman, and Joe Oppenheimer. 2000. How people reason about ethics. In Elements of reason:
Cognition, choice, and the bounds of rationality, edited by Arthur Lupia, Mathew D. McCubbins,
and Samuel L. Popkin.. Cambridge, Mass.: Cambridge University Press.
Green, Mart T., and Fred Thompson. 2001. Organizational process models of budgeting. In Research in
public administration: Evolving theories of budgeting, edited by John Bartle. San Francisco: JAI
Press.
Hammond, Thomas, and Gary J. Miller. 1987. The core of the constitution. American Political Science
Review 81:1155–74.
John, Peter, Helen Margetts, and Daniel Gilbert. 2001. Rollercoaster budgeting in the U.K.: Fluctuations
and equilibria in U.K. central government programme expenditures since 1945. Paper presented to
the European Consortium for Political Research, Kent, U.K.
Jones, Bryan D. 1980. Service delivery in the city: Citizen demand and bureaucratic response. New
York: Longman.
———. 1985. Governing buildings and building governement: A new perspective on the old party.
Tuscaloosa: University of Alabama Press, 1985.
———. 1994. Reconceiving decision making in democratic politics. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
———. 2001. Politics and the architecture of choice. Chicago: University of Chicago.
———. 2002. Bounded rationality and public policy: Herbert A. Simon and the decisional foundation of
collective choice. Policy Sciences 35:269–84.
———. 2003. Attention-driven choice and the behavioral foundations of public administration. Paper
presented to the Midwest Caucus of Public Administration, April, Chicago, Illinois.
Jones, Bryan D., and Lynn W. Bachelor. 1993. The sustaining hand. 2d ed., rev. Lawrence, Kans.:
University Press of Kansas.
Jones, Bryan D., Frank R. Baumgartner, and James L. True. 1996. The shape of change: Punctuations
and stability in U.S. budgeting, 1947–94. Paper presented at the annual meeting of The Midwest
Political Science Association, Chicago, Illinois.
Jones, Bryan D., Tracy Sulkin, and Heather Larsen. 2003. Punctuations in political institutions.
American Political Science Review 97:151–69.
Jordan, Meaghan. Forthcoming. Punctuations and priorities: Local government expenditures. Journal of
Policy Analysis and Management.
Jones Bounded Rationality and Political Science 411
Kahneman, Daniel, and Amos Tversky. 1979. Prospect theory: An analysis of decision making under
risk. Econometrica 47:263–91.
Kingdon, John. 1996. Agendas, Alternatives, and Public Policies. 2d ed. Boston: Little, Brown.
Krause, George. 2003. Coping with uncertainty: Analyzing risk propensities of SEC budgetary decisions,
1949–97. American Political Science Review 97:171–88.
Kuklinski, James, and Paul Quirk. 2000. Reconsidering the rational public: Cognition, heuristics, and
mass opinion. In Elements of reason: Cognition, choice, and the bounds of rationality, edited by
Arthur Lupia, Mathew D. McCubbins, and Samuel L. Popkin. Cambridge, Mass.: Cambridge
University Press.
Laitin, David. 1999. Identity choice under conditions of uncertainty: Reflections on Selten’s dualist
methodology. In Competition and cooperation: Conversations with Nobelists about economics and
political science, edited by James Alt, Margaret Levi, and Elinor Ostrom. New York: Russell Sage.
Linberry, Robert. 1977. Equality and public policy: The distribution of municipal public services.
Beverly Hills, Calif.: Sage.
Lupia, Arthur, Mathew D. McCubbins, and Samuel L. Popkin. 2000. Beyond rationality: Reason and the
study of politics. In Elements of reason: Cognition, choice, and the bounds of rationality, edited by
Arthur Lupia, Mathew D. McCubbins, and Samuel L. Popkin. Cambridge, Mass.: Cambridge
University Press. March, James. 1994. A primer on decision making. New York: Free Press.
March, James. 1994. A primer on decision-making. New York: Free Press.
March, James, and Herbert A. Simon. 1958. Organizations. New York: John Wiley.
McCubbins, Mathew, Roger Noll, and Barry Weingast. 1987. Administrative Procedures As Instrument
of Political Control. Law, Economics, and Organization 3:243–77.
Miller, Gary. 1992. Managerial dilemmas: The political economy of heirarchy. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Mladenka, Kenneth. 1978. Rules, service equity, and distributional decisions. Social Science Quarterly
59:192–202.
Newell, Allen. 1990. Unified theories of cognition. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Newell, Allen, and Herbert A. Simon. 1956. The logic theory machine. IRE Transactions on Information
Theory 3:61–79.
———. 1958. Elements of a theory of human problem solving. Psychological Review 65:151–66.
———. 1972. Human problem solving. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall.
Newell, Allen, J.C. Shaw, and Herbert A. Simon. 1957. Empirical explorations of the logic theory
machine. Proceedings of the Western Joint Computer Conference 7:101–8.
Padgett, John F. 1980. Bounded rationality in budgetary research. American Political Science Review
74:354–72.
———. 1981. Hierarchy and ecological control in federal budgetary decision making. American Journal
of Sociology 87:75–128.
Pareto, Vilfredo. 1935. Trattato di sociologia generale (Mind and society). Ed. Arthur Livingston. New
York: Harcourt, Brace.
Robinson, Scott. 2003. Punctuated equilibrium, bureaucratization, and budgetary changes in schools.
Paper presented at the Midwest Political Science Association, 4–6, April, Chicago, Illinois..
Simon, Herbert A. 1947. Administrative behavior: A study of decision-making processes in
administrative organization. New York: Macmillan.
———. 1955. A behavioral model of rational choice. Quarterly Journal of Economics 6:99–118.
———. 1957. Models of man. New York: Wiley.
———. 1983. Reason in human affairs. Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press.
———. 1985. Human nature in politics: The dialogue of psychology with political science. American
Political Science Review 79:293–304.
———. 1996a. Models of my life. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
———. 1996b. The sciences of the artificial, 3d ed. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
———. 1999. The potlatch between political science and economics. In Conflict and cooperation:
Conversations with Nobelists about economics and political science, edited by James Alt, Margaret
Levi, and Elinor Ostrom. New York: Russell Sage.
412 Journal of Public Administration Research and Theory
Slovak, Paul. 1990. Choice. In Thinking: An invitation to cognitive science, vol. 3, edited by Daniel N.
Osherson and Edward E. Smith. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Sornette, Didier. 2000. Critical phenomena in natural sciences. Berlin: Springer.
Thaler, Richard H. 1988. Anomalies: The ultimatum game. Journal of Economic Perspectives
2:195–206.
———. 1991. Quasi rational economics. New York: Russell Sage.
———. 1992. The winner’s curse: Paradoxes and anomalies of economic life. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton
University Press.
Tetlock, Philip. 2000. Coping with trade-offs: Psychological constraints and political implications. In
Elements of reason: Cognition, choice, and the bounds of rationality, edited by Arthur Lupia,
Mathew D. McCubbins, and Samuel L. Popkin. Cambridge, Mass.: Cambridge University Press.
True, James L. 2000. Avalanches and incrementalism: Making policy and budgets in the United States.
American Review of Public Administration 30:3–18.
True, James L., Bryan D. Jones, and Frank R. Baumgartner. 1999. Punctuated equilibrium theory. In
Theories of the policy process, edited by Paul Sabatier. Boulder, Colo.: Westview.
Wildavsky, Aaron. 1964. The politics of the budgetary process. Boston: Little, Brown.