MIT14 126S16 ProblemSet 2
MIT14 126S16 ProblemSet 2
PROBLEM SET 2
MIHAI MANEA
Question 1
Consider the complete information game
α β
α θ, θ θ − c, 0
β 0, θ − c 0, 0
where c > 0 and θ is equal to some known value θˆ ∈ (0, c/2). Imagine now an email
game scenario in which there are two possible values of θ, namely θˆ and θ0 , with some prior
probabilities p and 1 − p. Player 1 knows the value of θ, and if θ = θˆ then the email exchange
takes place, where each email is lost with probability ε ∈ (0, 1). If θ = θ0 then no emails
are exchanged. For each action a ∈ {α, β}, find the range of ε for which there is some email
game (i.e. some choice of θ0 and p) in which a is the unique rationalizable action for each
type. Briefly discuss your finding.
Question 2
Let G = (N, A, u) be a finite normal-form game. Suppose the players N play an infinite
repetition of G, but instead of discounting, players care only about the maximum of the per-
period payoffs. That is, in each period t = 0, 1, 2, . . ., the stage game G is played, with each
player having observed the action profile chosen at every previous period. This gives rise
to an infinite history of action profiles (a0 , a1 , a2 , . . .) (which may be random, if the players
are mixing). For each realization of such a history, player i’s payoff in the repeated game is
1
2 MIHAI MANEA
defined to be maxt≥0 ui (at ). Prove that (a) this repeated game is in general not continuous
at infinity, but (b) the single-deviation principle still holds.
Question 3
Find all (a) Nash, (b) trembling-hand perfect, (c) proper equilibria (in pure or mixed
strategies) of the following normal-form game.
L R
U 2,2 2,2
M 3,3 1,0
D 0,0 1,1
Question 4
Give an example of a finite normal-form game G and a strategy profile σ such that for
1 2
each player i, there exists a sequence σ− i , σ−i , . . . of independent trembles of i’s opponents
k
(i.e. each σ− i specifies a full-support distribution over strategy profiles of players −i in which
the various players j 6= i mix independently of each other), converging to σ−i , such that σi
k
is a best response to σ−i for each k, but σ is not a perfect equilibrium of G.
Question 5
Is the following statement true or false? Give a proof or counterexample. Suppose G
is a finite extensive-form game with perfect recall, and hx = {x, x0 }, hy = {y, y 0 } are two
information sets, such that x is a predecessor of y, x0 is a predecessor of y 0 , and the action
taken from x along the tree toward y is the same as the action taken from x0 toward y 0 .
Then there cannot be a consistent assessment (σ, µ) such that µ(x|hx ) = 1 and µ(y|hy ) = 0.
(Note that this looks like the “no signaling what you don’t know” condition, but now we do
not require that x immediately precedes y; there may be other nodes in between.)
Question 6
Consider the following version of Rubinstein alternating offers bargaining game. There are
three players and utility of player i = 1, 2, 3 from getting fraction xi of a pie in period T is
equal to δ T xi . In the first period, player 1 proposes a partition (i.e. a vector x = (x1 , x2 , x3 )
with x1 + x2 + x3 = 1), and players 2 and 3 in turn accept or reject this proposal. If
PROBLEM SET 2 3
either of them rejects it, then play passes to the next period, in which it is player 2s turn
to propose a partition, to which players 3 and 1 in turn respond. If at least one of them
rejects the proposal, then again play passes to the next period, in which player 3 makes a
proposal, and players 1 and 2 respond. Players rotate proposals in this way until a proposal
is accepted by both responders. Show that for any division of pie x if δ > 1/2 then there is
a subgame-perfect equilibrium in which x is agreed upon immediately.
MIT OpenCourseWare
https://ocw.mit.edu
For information about citing these materials or our Terms of Use, visit: https://ocw.mit.edu/terms.