Lecture Notes
Lecture Notes
Emilio Espino
iii
iv CONTENTS
These notes were developed as part of the first year Graduate Macroeco-
nomic class. The main goal is to provide methodological tools for studying
macroeconomic questions.
The emphasis is on macroeconomic theory with microfoundations, i.e.,
the economy’s aggregate behavior is the result of the interaction of fully
rational economic agents (households, firms, the government, etc.) taking
as given the primitives describing the economy; i.e., consumers’ preferences,
production technologies, information, and so on.
We will concentrate on what I consider the three main frameworks used
in modern macroeconomics. First, we consider a dynamic pure exchange
economy under uncertainty. This has been the natural setting to study dif-
ferent properties of asset markets. Second, we study the celebrated neoclas-
sical growth model, the main setting used to analyze aggregate quantities in
production economies (output, consumption, investment, etc.). Finally, we
analyze a prototype overlapping generation model, which has been useful to
study different issues concerning distributional aspects.
These notes have benefited from the superb graduate students that have
worked as TA in the corresponding classes; in order: Hernan Seone, Manuel
Macera, David Kohn, Martin Beraja, Nicolas Caramp, Julian Kozlowski,
Andrés Sarto, Samuel Kaplan, Giselle Montamat, Fernando Cirelli, Alvaro
Boitier. Unfortunately, these notes are still too underground, but I plan to
revise them in the near future. Naturally, comments are welcome.
Please do NOT distribute without permission!
© by Emilio Espino.
vii
viii PREFACE
Chapter 1
Mathematical Preliminaries:
An Overview
1
2 CHAPTER 1. MATHEMATICAL PRELIMINARIES: AN OVERVIEW
N
!1/2 N
X X
kxk = (xn )2 , kxk = |xn | , kxk = max |xn | .
n
n=1 n=1
The next result shows how to obtain a natural metric in a normed vector
space.
Claim 1 Let (S, k·k) be a normed vector space. Let ρk·k (x, y) = kx − yk for
all x, y ∈ S. Thus S, ρk·k defines a metric space
The following concept is very useful when the candidate limit point is not
immediately available.
αx + (1 − α) y ∈ A.
(i) Bounded:
(ii) Closed:
Suppose {xn , yn } ∈ Ŝ and {xn , yn } → (x, y) ∈ C × D.
Now, ||xn − yn || ≤ ||x̂ − ŷ|| → ||x − y|| ≤ ||x̂ − ŷ|| since weak inequalities
are preserved by limits.
So (x, y) ∈ Ŝ.
D̂ ŷ
x̂ Ĉ
Now define:
a=d−c
||d||2 − ||c||2
b=
2
a 6= 0 since δ > 0.
We argue that:
a · x < b ∀x ∈ C
a · y > b ∀y ∈ D
8 CHAPTER 1. MATHEMATICAL PRELIMINARIES: AN OVERVIEW
c
C
Note that
c+d (d + c)
a· = (d − c) ·
2 2
2 2
||d|| − ||c||
=
2
=b
Then,
∇g(y) = 2(y − c)
1.1. BASIC CONCEPTS FOR CONVEX ANALYSIS 9
We claim that (ŷ−d) is a descent direction for g at d (it lowers from ||d−c||).
Recall that for a given point z ∈ Rn and a function f , we say that a direction
t ∈ Rn is a descent direction if there exists ᾱ > 0 such that f (x + αt) <
f (x) ∀α ∈ (0, ᾱ), with α ∈ R.
In order to show that (ŷ − d) is a descent direction for y at d, we will show
that the directional derivative of g at d in the direction (ŷ − d) is negative:
||d||2 − ||c||2
2
≤2 − ||d|| + c · d
2
= − ||d||2 + ||c||2 − 2 c · d
But this implies that the point d + α(ŷ − d) is closer to c than d, which
contradicts that (c, d) were the minimizers.
p·y ≤p·x ∀y ∈ A.
Proof. x ∈ ∂(A), where ∂(A) is the boundary of set A. Hence, B1/n (x) ∩
AC 6= ∅.
Take any xn . It can be constructed such that xn → x, xn ∈ int(AC ).
Hence, by the Separating Hyperplane Theorem, there exist (pn , cn ) such that:
pn · xn > cn > pn · y ∀y ∈ A
pn
Moreover, p̂n = also satisfies this for all n (Check).
||pn ||
10 CHAPTER 1. MATHEMATICAL PRELIMINARIES: AN OVERVIEW
p·x≥c≥p·y ∀y ∈ A
3. Continuity.
∂F (x) F (x + 4) − F (x)
= lim ,
∂xn 4→0 4
is called the partial derivative of F with respect to xn at x.
∂F ∂F
Let ∇F (x) = ( ∂x1
(x), ..., ∂xN
(x)) be the vector of partial derivatives of
F. We say that F is continuously differentiable (denoted C 1 ) if ∇f (x) is a
continuous function. It is important to mention that differentiable functions
are continuous.
subject to,
L
X L
X
p·x= p l xl ≤ p · w = pl w l
l=1 l=1
subject to
G1 (x) ≥ 0, ..., GK (x) ≥ 0,
where F : RN N
+ → R, Gj : R+ → R for j = 1, ..., K are all concave functions.
We assume that K < L.
Thus, we can reinterpret our previous example where F = U , K = 1
L
P L
P
with: G1 (x) = p · w − p · x = pl wl − pl xl ≥ 0.
l=1 l=1
Let L(x, λ) = F (x) + λ · G(x) be the Lagrangian associated to the pro-
gramming problem (CPP) above. We say that (x∗ , λ∗ ) is a saddle point of L
if:
L(x, λ∗ ) ≤ L(x∗ , λ∗ ) ≤ L(x∗ , λ),
for all x ∈ RN and all λ ∈ RK
+.
Theorem 7 Let F : RN N
+ → R, Gj : R+ → R (j : 1, ..., K < L) be contin-
uously differentiable concave functions. Consider the optimization problem
(CP) above.
Then x∗ ∈ Rn+ is a global Maximizer for (CP) if and only if there exists
λ∗ = (λ∗1 , ..., λ∗K ) , given the Lagrangian
Proof. See Simon and Blume: for necessity (”only if”) see pg. 430-1; for
sufficiency (”if”) pg. 532-3.
It is important to mention that we do not need concavity for necessity.
Concavity is important for sufficiency.
Remark 5 We should mention that this result can be obtained with weaker
assumptions than those we have imposed on F and Gj . It is sufficient that
these functions are quasiconcave (remember that a concave function is qua-
siconcave, but the converse is not true in general).
1.2. FINITE DIMENSIONAL PROGRAMMING PROBLEMS 15
∂Ui (x̂i ) bi
i bi p̂
∇Ui (x̂ ) = λ ⇒ = λ p̂n for all n = 1, ..., N, (1.1)
∂xin
p̂wi − p̂x̂i = 0. (1.2)
i i
Note that since we assume that ∇Ui (x̂ ) >> 0 for all ∀x >> 0 and
i
lim ∂U∂x
i (x̂ )
i = ∞, we have that:
xl →0 l
I N
" I I
#
X X X X
Lp (x1 , ..., xL , λ1 , ..., λK ) = αi Ui (xi ) + qn wni − xin ,
i=1 n=1 i=1 i=1
I I
!
X X
q̃n wn − x̃in =0 , n : 1, ..., N, (1.4)
i=1 i=1
I
X
wni − x̃in ≥ 0,
q̃n ≥ 0, , , n : 1, ..., N. (1.5)
i=1
i
Since αi > 0and ∇ui (x̃ ) >> 0 for all i, we have q̃ >> 0 (q̃n > 0 for all
n : 1, ..., N ). Hence (P.2) can be written as:
I
X I
X
wn − x̃in = 0, for all n = 1, ..., N.
i=1 i=1
(i) ∅ ∈ F
(ii) If A ∈ F, then Ac ∈ F
(i) P (∅) = 0
(iv) P (Ω) = 1
3
A.N. Kolmogorov is considered the founding father of modern probability theory. In
1933, he provided an axiomatic basis that it is now universally accepted. Thus, he invented
so many things in this field and so his name will appear repeatedly. If you study probability
theory seriously, you will soon detect that this is the reason why, as usual if you invent
too many things, he will share some results with other names to avoid confusion.
18 CHAPTER 1. MATHEMATICAL PRELIMINARIES: AN OVERVIEW
π1 = P 0 π0
0
π1 (s̄1 ) P11 P12 . . . P1n π0 (s̄1 )
π1 (s̄2 ) P21 P22 . . . P2n π0 (s̄2 )
.. = ..
.. . . .. ..
. . . . . .
π1 (s̄n ) Pn1 Pn2 . . . Pnn π0 (s̄n )
π1 (s̄1 ) P11 P21 . . . Pn1 π0 (s̄1 )
π1 (s̄2 ) P12 P22 . . . Pn2 π0 (s̄2 )
.. = ..
.. .. .. ..
. . . . . .
π1 (s̄n ) P1n P2n . . . Pnn π0 (s̄n )
π1 (s̄1 ) P11 π0 (s̄1 ) + P21 π0 (s̄2 ) + ... + Pn1 π0 (s̄n )
π1 (s̄2 ) P12 π0 (s̄1 ) + P22 π0 (s̄2 ) + ... + Pn2 π0 (s̄n )
.. =
..
. .
π1 (s̄n ) P1n π0 (s̄1 ) + P2n π0 (s̄2 ) + ... + Pnn π0 (s̄n )
Similarly, for π2 :
π20 = π10 P
= (π00 P )P
= π00 P 2
And thus πk0 = π00 P k . We can summarize this by saying that the probability
distributions follow the following law of motion:
0
πt+1 = πt0 P
20 CHAPTER 1. MATHEMATICAL PRELIMINARIES: AN OVERVIEW
π0 = π0P
π = P 0π
(P 0 − I)π = 0
P
This means that π is an eigenvector (normalized to satisfy πi = 1)
a unit eigenvalue P 0 . Since none of the elements of P are
associated to P
negative and nj=1 Pij = 1, we know that P 0 has at least one unit eigenvalue
and then there is some π that satisfies the equation (P 0 − I)π = 0.
We want to know if given some initial distribution π0 , the distributions πt
approach a stationary distribution lim πt = π∞ , and wether the stationary
t→∞
distribution π∞ will depend on the initial distribution π0 .
Throughout this notes, we mostly assume that {st }∞ t=0 is a finite state first-
order stationary Markov chain. Recalling our definitions above, this means
that Pr{st+1 | st } = Pr{st+1 | st } for all (st+1 , st ). Transition
P probabilities
are denoted by Pr{st+1 = s | st = s} = π(s, s ) > 0 where s0 ∈S π(s, s0 ) = 1
0 0
for all s ∈ S. We write st+1 /st to denote that st+1 is an immediate successor
of st . A simple application of the so-called Chapman-Kolmogorov equations
implies that the probability of st is constructed from π as follows:
Definition 12 Let 2X the power set of X (i.e. the set of all the subsets of
X.). For each st ∈ S, we define Γ(st , ·) : X → 2X as a correspondence.
That is, given (s, x) ∈ S × X, Γ assigns a particular subset of X.
Let
Π (s0 , x0 ) = {{xt }∞ t t
t=0 : xt+1 : S → X such that xt+1 (s ) ∈ Γ(st , xt (s
t−1
))
for all st−1 , st , given (s0 , x0 )},
∞ X
X
∗
β t π st F st , xt (st−1 ), xt+1 (st ) . (SP)
V (s0 , x0 ) ≡ sup
x
e(s0 ,x0 )∈Π(s0 ,x0 ) t=0
st
22 CHAPTER 1. MATHEMATICAL PRELIMINARIES: AN OVERVIEW
subject to y ∈ Γ (st , x∗t (st−1 )) and x∗t+2 (st , s0 ) ∈ Γ (s0 , y) for all s0 .
To see this, note that otherwise there exists some set such that y ∗ 6=
x∗t+1 (e
st ). To get a contradiction, construct an alternative feasible plan as
follows:
xt+1 (st ) = x∗t+1 (st ) ∈ Γ st , x∗t (st−1 ) ∀st 6= set
st ) = y ∗ ∈ Γ st , x∗t (st−1 )
xt+1 (e
e∗ (s0 , x0 )
This alternative plan obtains a larger value, but this violates that x
was an optimum for (SP).
( )
X
βT T
Fxj sT , x∗T s T −1
, x∗T +1 s T
x∗jT s T −1
lim π s =0
T →∞
sT
∀j = 1, ..., L.
Proof. Suppose that x e∗ (s0 , x0 ) is an interior feasible plan that satisfies (EE)
and (TC). Let x e (s0 , x0 ) be any arbitrary alternative feasible plan. Define
T X
X
β t π st F st , x∗t (st−1 ), x∗t+1 (st ) − F st , xt (st−1 ), xt+1 (st ) .
DT ≡
t=0 st
T X
X
β t π st Fx st , x∗t (st−1 ), x∗t+1 (st ) · x∗t (st−1 ) − xt (st−1 )
=
t=1 st
T −1 X
X
β t π st Fy st , x∗t (st−1 ), x∗t+1 (st ) x∗t+1 (st ) − xt+1 (st )
+
t=0 st
X
β T π sT Fy sT , x∗T (sT −1 ), x∗T +1 (sT ) x∗T +1 (sT ) − xT +1 (sT )
+
ST
We use the EE’s in the second line to write the last expression as follows:
T X
X
β t π st Fx st , x∗t (st−1 ), x∗t+1 (st ) · x∗t (st−1 ) − xt (st−1 )
=
t=1 st
T
XX−1
X
β t π st β π (st , s0 ) Fx s0 , x∗t+1 (st ), x∗t+2 (st , s0 ) · x∗t+1 (st ) − xt+1 (st )
−
t=0 st s0
X
+β T T
Fy sT , x∗T (sT −1 ), x∗T +1 (sT ) · x∗T +1 (sT ) − xT +1 (sT )
π s
sT
T X
X
β t π st Fx st , x∗t (st−1 ), x∗t+1 (st ) · x∗t (st−1 ) − xt (st−1 )
=
t=1 st
T −1 X
X
β t+1 π st+1 Fx st+1 , x∗t+1 (st ), x∗t+2 (st , st+1 ) · x∗t+1 (st ) − xt+1 (st )
−
t=0 st+1
X X
−β T π sT β π (sT , s0 ) Fx s0 , x∗T +1 (sT ), x∗T +2 (sT , s0 ) · x∗T +1 (sT ) − xT +1 (sT ) .
sT s0
sT +1
We take the limit with T → ∞ and apply the TC on the RHS to get the
desired result since lim DT ≥ 0.
T →∞
1.4. INFINITE DIMENSIONAL PROGRAMMING PROBLEMS 25
e (s0 , x0 ) ∈ Π (s0 , x0 ) .
for all x
Note that this implies that
∞ X
X
β t π st π sT F xt (z t−1 ), xt+1 (z t ) = 0,
lim (LC)
T →∞
t=T +1 st
X
Fy st , x∗t st−1 , x∗t+1 st + β π (st , s0 ) Fx s0 , x∗t+1 (st ), x∗t+2 (st , s0 ) = 0
s0
(1.7)
t
for all s .
X
lim β T π sT Fx sT, x∗T (sT −1 ), x∗T +1 (sT ) x∗T (sT −1 ) = 0
(TC’)
T →∞
sT
Proof. Note first that if f : [0, 1] → R is concave, then ∀γ, λ such that
0 ≤ γ ≤ λ < 1 it follows that
f (1) − f (λ) f (1) − f (γ)
≤ .
1−λ 1−γ
Let xe∗ (s0 , x0 ) be an interior optimal path and T ∈ Z+ . Given that x e∗ is
interior and (0, 0) is feasible ∀st ( that is, 0 ∈ Γ (st , 0) , ∀st ), it follows that
there exists λ ∈ [0, 1), sufficiently close to 1, such that
∗ t−1
λ t−1 xt (s ) ∀t ≤ T, ∀st
xt (s ) =
λx∗t (st−1 ) ∀t ≥ T + 1, ∀st−1
e∗ , we have that
defines a feasible plan. By optimality of x
∞ X
X
β t π st F st , x∗t (st−1 ), x∗t+1 (st ) − F st , xλt (st−1 ), xλt+1 (st )
0 ≤
t=0 st
X
β T π sT F sT , x∗T (sT −1 ), x∗T +1 (sT ) − F sT , x∗T (sT −1 ), λx∗T +1 (sT )
=
sT
∞ X
X
β t π st F st , x∗t (st−1 ), x∗t+1 (st ) − F st , λx∗t (st−1 ), λx∗t+1 (st ) ,
+
t=T +1 st
that
F sT , x∗T (sT −1 ), λx∗T +1 (sT ) − F sT , x∗T (sT −1 ), x∗T +1 (sT )
Therefore, since
X
β T π sT F sT , x∗T (sT −1 ), x∗T +1 (sT ) − F sT , x∗T (sT −1 ), λx∗T +1 (sT )
−
sT
∞
X X
β t π st F st , x∗t (st−1 ), x∗t+1 (st ) − F st , λx∗t (st−1 ), λx∗t+1 (st ) ,
≤
t=T +1 st
The first inequality is due to the fact that −Fy (s, x, y) · y ≥ 0 for all
(s, x, y) by assumption. We claim that when T → ∞, then the (RHS) goes
to 0 by (LC). To see this, notice that
∞ X
X
β t π st F st , x∗t (st−1 ), x∗t+1 (st ) − F (st , 0, 0)
t=T +1 z t
X∞ X ∞ X
X
t t
st , x∗t (st−1 ), x∗t+1 (st ) β t π st |F (st , 0, 0)|
≤ βπ s F +
t=T +1 st t=T +1 z t
Exercises
Exercise 1 In text.
Exercise 2 Show that if a sequence converges, then it is Cauchy.
Exercise 3 Show that if a sequence is Cauchy, then it is bounded. That is,
supn,m d (xn , xm ) < ∞.
Exercise 4 Show that xn → x if and only if every subsequence of {xn }
converges to x.
Exercise 5 Show that if for every n, xn+1 ≥ xn , and the sequence {xn }∞
n=1
is bounded, then xn converges.
28 CHAPTER 1. MATHEMATICAL PRELIMINARIES: AN OVERVIEW
Chapter 2
29
30 CHAPTER 2. OPTIMALITY AND COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM
In period t, actions are taken after st has been observed and, in general,
x(s ) denotes the value of x at the node st . Agents value consumption at
t
each node st and, thus, the commodity space (i.e., the real vector space
containing all the relevant objects) is given by
C = X+ = {{ct }Tt=0 | ct : S t → RN
+ , sup c(st ) < ∞}.
(t,st )
Notice that this means that the household will continuously update the infor-
mation set, conditioning on all information available at the time the decision
is made.
Preferences are represented by expected, time-separable, discounted util-
ity. That is , if ci ∈ C then:
T X
X
Ui (ci ) = βit π(st )ui (ci (st )), (UF)
t=0 st ∈S t
Let yi (st ) ∈ RN
++ be the endowment process for agent i at s . That
t
is, if the history of events st has been observed at the beginning of period t,
agent i receives from heaven yin (st ) units of the nth − consumption good as
endowment. We assume that sup(t,st ) kyi (st )k = y < ∞ and denote y(st ) =
PI t N
i=1 yi (s ) ∈ R++ as the vector of aggregate endowment. Note the
individual endowment process is an element of the consumption set.
As you have already noticed, we assume here that these stochastic events
do not affect preferences (i.e. preferences are state independent) but only
endowments. This assumption was made only to simplify notation. State
dependent preferences can be incorporated without any inconvenient.
We say that (ci )Ii=1
PI is an tallocation if ci ∈ C for all i. An allocation
(ci )i=1 is feasible if i=1 ci (s ) ≤ y(s ) for all st .
I t
Let αi > 0 denote the welfare weight for agent i. Given the vector
(αi )Ii=1 , the corresponding Pareto problem is given by
I
( T )
X XX
sup αi βit π(st ) ui (ci (st )) , (PP)
(ci )Ii=1 i=1 t=0 st ∈S t
subject to
I
X
ci (st ) ≤ y(st ) for all st , (2.1)
i=1
ci ∈ C for all i.
Exercise 6 1 Suppose that T < ∞ and show that, under our assumptions,
there exists a unique (c∗i )Ii=1 solving (PP). Show also that any solution to (PP)
I
is
PIhomogeneous of degree zero in (αi )i=1 . Conclude that we can normalize
i=1 αi = 1.
Theorem 11 If a feasible allocation (c∗i )Ii=1 solves (PP) for some (αi )Ii=1 ,
then (c∗i )Ii=1 is a PO allocation. Furthermore, if (c∗i )Ii=1 is a PO allocation,
then there exists some vector (αi∗ )Ii=1 such that (c∗i )Ii=1 solves PP correspond-
ing to (αi∗ )Ii=1 .
You are asked to prove this theorem in Exercise 7.
XT X
P st · ci st − yi st ≤ 0.
(BC-AD)
t=0 st
The interpretation in this general stochastic context is that, given the
restrictions imposed by (BC-AD), agent i chooses ex-ante the best contingent
plan (i.e., a consumption bundle that is a sequence of random variables in
the consumption set).
2.2. ARROW-DEBREU ECONOMIES 33
If T < ∞ and P (st ) >> 0 for all st we can apply Weiestrass’ Theorem to
show that the sup is attained in (AP-AD) and it can be replaced by a max
since preferences are continuous and the budget set is compact. If T = ∞,
the same result can be obtained but some additional technical details must
be handled. Also, note that the budget constraint will hold with equality in
any solution since the utility function is strictly increasing.
The equilibrium concept for an economy with this market structure is the
following.
∂ui
βit π st ci st = λ
bi Pbn st for all n, all st and all i,
b (2.2)
∂cin
T X
X T X
X
Pb st · b
ci s t = Pb st · yi st ,
for all i, (2.3)
t=0 st t=0 st
X X
cin st = yin st for all n and all st .
b (2.4)
i i
On other hand, we define the Lagrangian for the Pareto problem (PP),
denoted LP P , as follows. Let µn (st ) > 0 be the Lagrange multiplier corre-
sponding to the nth −feasibility constraint (4.11) at st . Thus, for a given α
34 CHAPTER 2. OPTIMALITY AND COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM
we have
I
( T )
X X X
LP P (c, µ, α) = αi βit π(st ) ui (ci (st ))
i=1 t=0 st ∈S t+1
T X I
!
X X
t t t
+ µ s · y s − ci s .
t=0 st i=1
∂ui ∗ t
αi βit π st (ci s )(α) = µ∗n st (α) for all n, all st and all i,
∂cin
(2.5)
X X
c∗in (st )(α) = yin st for all n and all st .
(2.6)
i i
Now we are ready to use the power of necessary and sufficient conditions
characterizing solutions to show the two fundamental theorems in welfare
economics. Again, we assume that T < ∞ to avoid technical details.
ci )Ii=1 is
Theorem 12 (First Welfare Theorem) An ADCE allocation (b
Pareto optimal.
Proof. Suppose that (c∗i )Ii=1 is PO allocation. Since we assume that T < ∞,
it follows by Theorem 10 that there exists a vector of welfare weights α∗ such
that (c∗i )Ii=1 solves (PP) given α∗ . Necessary and sufficient conditions for an
interior solution imply that there exists a process of Lagrange multipliers
µ∗ ∈ X+ such that (c∗i (α∗ ), µ∗ (α∗ ))Ii=1 satisfy (4.12) and (4.13) given welfare
weights α∗ . It is necessary and sufficient to show that there exists a price
system P ∗ and a vector of Lagrange multipliers (λ∗i )Ii=1 such that (c∗i , λ∗i )Ii=1
satisfy (2.2)-(2.4) with transfers, given P ∗ . We proceed constructively again
and define
µ∗n (st )(α)
Pn∗ t ∗
for all n and all st ,
s ,α = ∗
µ1 (s0 )(α)
1
λ∗i = for all i.
αi∗
Finally, define transfers for agent i as follows
∞ X
X
∗
P ∗ (st )(α) · c∗i (st )(α) − yi st
Ai (α ) = .
t=0 st
Note that feasibility implies that i Ai (α∗ ) = 0 and then some transfers
P
are negative (i.e. those agents are ”taxed away”). Thus, if agents are entitled
to transfers (Ai (α∗ ))Ii=1 , the budget constraints are satisfied and (c∗i )Ii=1 , P ∗
constitutes an ADCE (with transfers) by construction.
Note that if any αi equals 0, we are not able to construct the Lagrange
multiplier λ∗i as before. In that case, we set c∗i (st ) = 0 for all st and the
equivalence still holds, since αi = 0 implies that the planner will not asign
consumption to houshold i (we need to assume that 0 ∗ ui (0) = 0).
According to our analysis, there is still an open question regarding time
consistency of agents’ choices. More precisely, in this framework agents are
36 CHAPTER 2. OPTIMALITY AND COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM
It can be shown that the functions (Ai (α))Ii=1 are continuous with respect
to α. We can then apply the Brouwer Fixed Point theorem to show that there
exists some α b such that Ai (b
α) = 0 for all i. This implies that there exists
an ADCE without initial transfers. This is the celebrated Negishi’s
approach to compute competitive equilibria. To illustrate this methodology,
consider the following example based on Kehoe (1989).
Suppose that N = 1, I = {1, 2}, T = +∞ and St = 1 for all t (i.e. there
is no uncertainty). Preferences are represented by (UF) where ui (c) = ln c
for all i ∈ I, 0 < β1 < β2 < 1 and yi (t) = 1 for all i ∈ I and all t = 0, 1....
In this case, (2.2)-(2.4) reduce to
1
βit =λ
bi Pb (t) for all t and all i, (2.7)
ci (t)
b
∞
X ∞
X
Pb (t) b
ci (t) = Pb (t) for all i, (2.8)
t=0 t=0
c1 (t) + b
b c2 (t) = 2 for all t. (2.9)
On the other hand, given α = (α1 , α2 ), we have that (4.12) and (4.13)
reduce to
1
αi βit = µ∗ (t) for all n, all t and all i, (2.10)
c∗i (t)(α)
2.2. ARROW-DEBREU ECONOMIES 37
Let q (st ) (s0 ) be the price of the s0 −security at st where ai (st , s0 ) denotes
holdings of this security chosen by agent i at st . We normalize p1 (st ) = 1 for
all st and therefore all prices are in units of consumption good 1. We denote
(q, p) = ((q (st ))st , (p (st ))st ) as the price system.
To rule out Ponzi schemes, we restrict agents to bounded trading
strategies. That is, there exists a large negative number A such that
ai (st , s0 ) ≥ A for all (st , s0 ).3 We assume that A is large enough such that
these constraints are not binding in equilibrium. These securities are all in
zero net supply and the initial endowment is ai (s0 ) = 0 for all i.
Given (q, p), agent i’s problem in an economy with this market structure
is given by
XT X
max βit π(st ) ui (ci (st )), (SM-AP)
(ci ,ai )
t=0 st
subject to
2
Yes, Arrow invented too many things in economics and, then, he also had to share
some names to avoid our confusion. Here, we build on his insight, Arrow (1964), that
sequential trading of one-period securities are sufficient to implement PO allocations and
consequently equivalent to the set of ADCE allocations.
3
Below we define a more intuitive bound, the so-called natural debt limit.
2.3. SEQUENTIAL MARKETS ECONOMIES 39
X
p s t · ci s t + q st (s0 ) ai st , s0 ≤ p st · yi st + ai st for all st ,
s0
(BC-SM)
ci ∈ C, and ai (s0 ) = 0,
T
ai s , sT +1 = 0 if T < +∞, for all sT +1 ∈ S,
ai st , s0 ≥ A, for all st , s0 if T = +∞.
I
X
ci (st ) = y(st )
b for all st ,
i=1
X
ai st , s0 for all st and all s0 .
b = 0
i
T X
X
βit π(st ) ui (ci (st ))
LSM (ci , ai , γi ) =
t=0 st
+γi st p st · yi st + ai st − ...
#)
t
t
X t
0 t 0
... − p s · ci s − q s (s ) ai s , s .
s0
∂ui
βit π st ci st = βit π st γbi st pbn st for all st and for all n,
b
∂cn
(2.12)
X
ci s t +
pb st ·b qb st (s0 ) b
ai st , s0 = pb st · yi st +b
ai s t for all st ,
s0
(2.14)
ai sT , snT +1 = 0
(
b o for all sT +1 ∈ S
if T < +∞,
0= (2.15)
lim E0 (βi )t ∂ui
∂c1
ci (st )) b
(b ai (st ) if T = +∞
t→∞
I
X
ci (st ) = y(st )
b for all st , (2.16)
i=1
I
X
ai st , s0 = 0 for all st and all s0 .
b (2.17)
i=1
bi = ∂ui (b
λ ci (s0 )) , for all i,
∂c1
Pbn st = pbn st qb st−1 (st )...b for all (st−1 , st ) and all n.
q (s0 ) (s1 )
....
= pbn st qb st−1 (st )...b
q (s0 ) (s1 ) γ
bi (s0 ) ,
= Pbn st γ
bi (s0 ) ,
= Pbn st λ
bi .
k X
X k X
X
t t t
Pb1 st bai s t
P s · b
b ci s − yi s =
t=0 st t=0 st
k
XX X
Pb1 st qb st (s0 ) b
ai (st , s0 ),
−
t=0 st s0
k
XX
Pb1 st bai s t
=
t=0 st
k XX
X
Pb1 st , s0 bai (st , s0 ),
−
t=0 st s0
= Pb1 (s0 ) b
ai (s0 )
X
Pb1 sk , sk+1 bai (sk , sk+1 ),
−
(sk ,sk+1 )
X
Pb1 sk+1 bai (sk , sk+1 ).
= 0−
(sk+1 )
Note first that if T < ∞, this holds for k = T and therefore b ai (sT , sT +1 ) =
T
0 for all (s , sT +1 ) and for all i. Thus, (2.3) is immediately satisfied.
On the other hand, if T = +∞ we have that
X 1 X k+1 ∂ui
Pb1 sk+1 bai (sk+1 ) = π sk+1 ci sk+1 b ai (sk+1 )
β b
λ
bi T +1 ∂ci1
sk+1 s
1 k+1 ∂ui
= E β (b
ci,k+1 ) b
ai,k+1 .
bi 0
λ ∂c1
Proof. If (b
c, Pb) constitute an ADCE, then there exists Lagrange multipliers
I
λ
bi such that (2.2)-(2.4) are satisfied. It is sufficient to find (b
a, qb, pb) and
i=1
γi )Ii=1 such that (2.12)-(2.16) are satisfied. We proceed by construction as
(b
follows:
∂ui
bi st = ci s t for all st and for all i,
γ b
∂c1
0 0 b1 (st , s0 )
γ
t
for all (st , s0 ),
qb s (s ) = βi π (st , s ) t
γ
b1 (s )
1 ∂u 1
pbn st = t
for all st and for all n.
c 1 s
b1 (st ) ∂cn
b
γ
Very importantly, note that (2.2) implies that the last two conditions hold
for all i > 1 and then agent 1 was chosen without loss of generality. Finally,
we need to construct portfolios supporting this allocation. To do that, define
for each agent and for all st
XT X P1 (st+j )
ai s t t+j t+j t+j
= p s · c i s − y i s
P1 (st )
b b b
j=0 t+j t
s |s
T X P1 (st+j )
t
t t
X
pb st+j · b
ci st+j − yi st+j
= pb s · bci s − yi s + t
j=1 t+j t
P1 (s )
s |s
Note that
XT X P1 (st+j )
pb st+j · b
ci st+j − yi st+j
t
P1 (s )
j=1 t+j t
s |s
T X
X X P1 (st+j )
q st (st+1 ) pb st+j · b
ci st+j − yi st+j
= ... t t
j=1 st+1 st+j
P1 (s ) q (s ) (st+1 )
T X
X X X P1 (st+j )
q st (st+1 ) t+j t+j t+j
= ... p s · c i s − y i s
P1 (st+1 )
b b
j=1 st+1 st+2 st+j
X
q st (st+1 ) b
ai st , st+1 ,
=
st+1
44 CHAPTER 2. OPTIMALITY AND COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM
XT X P1 (st+j )
Ai (st ) = − pb st+j · yi st+j .
t
(2.18)
j=0 j+t t
P (s )
s /s
This is the so-called natural debt limit. It is the value of the maximal amount
that agent i can repay starting from that period t, assuming that his future
consumption is 0 forever; i.e. it will not be feasible for any agent to repay
more than Ai (st ).
Finally, if T = +∞ we need to show that the transversality condition
holds. To do this, notice that t st kP (st )k < ∞ implies that lim P1 (st ) =
P P
t→∞
0 (more technically, st -almost surely). Thus, when this coupled with (2.2)
we have that
bi P1 (st ) = β t π st ∂ui b ci s t → 0
λ i
∂ci1
as t goes to infinity (again, st almost surely) and consequently (2.15) is
satisfied since the supporting asset holdings are uniformly bounded by (2.18).
subject to
X
ci s t + q st (s0 ) ai st , s0 ≤ yi st − τbi st + ai st for all st ,
s0
(BC-SMG)
ci ∈ C, and ai (s0 ) = 0,
T
ai s , sT +1 = 0 if T < +∞, for all sT +1 ∈ S,
b
ai st , s0 ≥ A, for all st , s0 if T = +∞.
st+1
(2.19)
bb (s0 ) = eb (s0 ) = 0,
X Yt
lim eb st qb(sj−1 )(sj ) = 0,
t→∞ j=0
st
2.5. APPLICATION: ECONOMIES WITH GOVERNMENT AND RICARDIAN EQUIVALENCE47
and XX
Pb st τbi st − τei st = 0, for all i.
(2.20)
t st
n o
a such that {b
Then, there exists e a, qb} constitutes a SMCE given gb, τe, b .
c, e e
Within this class of government policies, the way the government finances
its expenditures is irrelevant and, consequently, it does no have any equilib-
rium implications. Two assumptions are critical to obtain this result. First,
taxes are lump sum and, thus, they do not distort incentives at the margin.
Secondly, (2.20) restrict the set of policies to those with same net income
effect for each agent.
Proof. We use the one-to-one equivalence between ADCE and SMCE with
government provedQtin Exercise 9.
Let P (s ) = j=0 qb(s )(sj ) = Pb (st−1 ) qb(st−1 )(st ) be defined as before,
b t j
which are the same Arrow-Debreu prices with a single good, and Pb (s0 ) = 1.
Multiplying equation (2.19) at st by Pb (st ), we can write
X
gb st Pb st +eb st Pb st = τe st Pb st + Pb st , st+1 eb st , st+1 ∀t, st ,
st+1
P e t b t
Look that for 0 < t < T + 1, we can simplify st b (s ) P (s ) on both sides.
Hence
T X
X T X
t t
X X
τe st Pb st + Pb st , st+1 eb st , st+1 .
gb s P s =
b
t=0 st t=0 st sT +1
Exercises
Exercise 6 In text.
Prove also that if, on the other hand,{b c, b, qb} constitutes a SMCE given
a
gb, τb, bb , then there exists Pe such that b c, Pe constitutes an ADCE given
(b
g , τb).
Chapter 3
49
50CHAPTER 3. THE ONE-SECTOR NEOCLASSICAL GROWTH MODEL
C = {{ct , lt }∞ t t
t=0 : (ct , lt ) : S → R+ × [0, 1], sup c(s ) < ∞}.
(t,st )
Production Possibilities
Condition (a) above rules out corner solutions for capital accumulation.
Very importantly, condition (b) guaranties that there exists some (0, K) such
that 0 ≤ K(st ) ≤ K for all st for all feasible allocations since consumption
must be bounded from below and δ ∈ (0, 1). To see this, let s = max S and
define K such that δK = sF (K, I), where I is the upper bound of labor
supply. Note that δK > sF (K, I) for all K > K given strict concavity of
F and condition (b) above. Thus, without loss of generality, we can restrict
K(st ) ∈ X ≡ [0, K] for all st whenever the initial stock of capital satisfies
0 ≤ K0 ≤ K. On the other hand, if K0 > K it can be shown that in finite
time 0 ≤ K(st ) ≤ K with probability 1.
In any case, in general we can define X ≡ [0, max{K0 , K}] as the set of
sustainable levels of capital and thus guarantee that K(st ) ∈ X for all st . We
denote K = (K(st )st ) as a capital accumulation path.
Under our concavity assumptions on both utility and the production func-
tions, it can be shown that U(s0 , K0 ) is convex and closed for all (s0 , K0 ), the
supporting hyperplane theorem can be applied and, consequently, the set of
Pareto optimal allocations can be parametrized by welfare weights.
Suppose that αi is the welfare weight assigned by the planner to agent i.
Given a vector of welfare weights α = (αi )Ii=1 , the planner’s problem is given
by:
52CHAPTER 3. THE ONE-SECTOR NEOCLASSICAL GROWTH MODEL
I
(∞ )
X XX
t
β t π s ui ci s , 1 − li s
t t
max αi , (PP-NGM)
( (ci ,li )Ii=1 ,K ) i=1 t=0 st
subject to
I
X
ci (st ) + X(st ) = st F (K(st−1 ), L(st )) for all st ,
i=1
(ci , li ) ∈ C, K(st ) ∈ X for all st and all i,
K 0 ∈ X given.
PI
where X (st ) = K(st ) − (1 − δ)K(st−1 ) and L (st ) = i=1 li (st ) .
uin st = uin ci st , 1 − li st
for n = c, l,
Fj st = Fj K st−1 , L st
for j = K, L.
∞ X
I
!
X X
LN GM
β t π s ui ci s , 1 − li s
t t t
P P (c, l, K, µ, α) = αi
i=1 t=0 st
∞ X
X I
X
µ st (st F (K(st−1 ), li st )
+
t=0 st i=1
I
X
+(1 − δ)K(st−1 ) − ci st − K(st )).
i=1
ci s t : αi β t π st uc st = µ st ,
(3.1)
li st : αi β t π st u l st = µ st F L st ,
(3.2)
X
k st : µ st = µ st , s0 s0 Fk st , s0 + (1 − δ) ,
(3.3)
s0
( )
X
T T T −1
lim µ s sT F k s + (1 − δ) K s =0 (3.4)
T →∞
sT
where we denote K d (st ), Ld (st ) the solutions for this problem at st . Observe
that the representative firm does not face any intertemporal decision and,
54CHAPTER 3. THE ONE-SECTOR NEOCLASSICAL GROWTH MODEL
∞ X
X
β t π st ui ci st , 1 − li st ,
max (AP-NGM)
(ci ,li ,ki )
t=0 st
subject to
∞ X
X
P st ci st + ki st − (1 − δ)ki (st−1 )
t=0 st
X∞ X
P st (r(st )ki (st−1 ) + w st li st ).
≤
t=0 st
such that (ci , li ) ∈ C, ki (st ) ≥ 0 for all st and ki0 > 0 given.
I
d t
X
ki st−1 ,
K s =
b b
i=1
I
X d t
ci s t + b
ki st − (1 − δ) b
ki st−1 = st F Kb d st , L
b b s .
i=1
3.4. WELFARE THEOREMS 55
Characterizing an ADCE
First note that (FP-NGM) is a standard static concave problem and thus
it can characterized with necessary and sufficient first order conditions. For
an interior solution, those are given by
ci s t : β t π st uic st = λi P st ,
(3.6)
li st : β t π st uil st = λi P st w st ,
(3.7)
X
k st : P st = P st , st+1 r(st , st+1 ) + (1 − δ) ,
(3.8)
st+1
∞ X
X
P st [ci st + xi st − r(st )ki (st−1 ) − w st li st ] = 0
(3.9)
t=0 st
( )
X
T T
+ (1 − δ) k sT −1
lim λi P s sT Fk s =0 (3.10)
T →∞
sT
In the same way, the value of individual human wealth for agent i is
∞ X
X
VWi (s0 , K0 , α) = P (st )(α)w(st )(α)li (st )(α).
t=0 st
The planner owns the stock of capital in this setting. Agents’ Euler equa-
tions corresponding the capital accumulation (3.8) will hold by construction.
Thus, agents are indifferent about the level of capital they want to accu-
mulate. Remember that capital accumulation is redundant for insurance
purposes: markets are complete at date 0 and then they can trade any af-
fordable contingent consumption bundle they wish. Thus, we need to make
the corresponding allocation affordable for each agent and define a distribu-
tion of the aggregate stock of capital across agents.
Proposition 5 Let (b c, b
l), K
b be a PO allocation. Then, there exist a price
b and individual capital holdings (ki )Ii=1 such that constitute an
system (Pb, w)
ADCE with transfers given by 3.12.
and, then, agent i0 s budget constraint is satisfied. Agent i uses this transfer
to generate additional wealth through capital accumulation and thus make
this allocation affordable. With this purpose, the planner assigns capital as
follows:
ki (st )(α) = θi (α)K(st )(α) for all st .
obtains
XX
P (st )(α)[r(st )(α)ki (st−1 )(α) + (1 − δ)ki (st−1 )(α) − ki (st )(α)]
t st
XX
= P (st )(α)[r(st )(α)θi (α)K(st−1 )(α) + (1 − δ)θi (α)K(st−1 )(α) − θi (α)K(st )(α)]
t st
XX
= θi (α) P (st )(α)[r(st )(α)K(st−1 )(α) + (1 − δ)K(st−1 )(α) − K(st )(α)],
t st
= θi (α)VF (s0 , K0 , α) = Ai (s0 , K0 , α).
Thus, it makes the consumption allocation affordable while agents have in-
centives to keep these capital holdings.
Let (c(α), l(α), K(α)) be the solution to the planner’s problem (PP-NGM)
corresponding to α where µ (α) is the vector of Lagrange multipliers. We
take as given the initial distribution of shares of the representative firm (or,
equivalently, P
the date 0 distribution of the initial stock of capital), denoted
θi > 0 with Ii=1 θi0 = 1. Given (s0 , K0 , θ0 ), define the net transfers needed
0
and thus τi (s0 , K0 , θ0 )(α) < 0 for all α. Note also that
I
X I
X I
X I
X
0
τi (s0 , K0 , θ )(α) = VCi (s0 , K0 , α) − VWi (s, K, α) − θi0 VF (s0 , K0 , α)
i=1 i=1 i=1 i=1
I
!
X
= VC (s0 , K0 , α) − VWi (s, K, α) + VF (s0 , K0 , α) ,
i=1
PI 0
and thus i=1 τi (s0 , K0 , θ )(α) = 0 for all α.
60CHAPTER 3. THE ONE-SECTOR NEOCLASSICAL GROWTH MODEL
Therefore, αi0 = αi0 −τi (s0 , K0 , θ0 )(α0 ), which immediately shows that τi (s0 , K0 , θ0 )(α0 ) =
0 for each i.
3.5. ON THE DYNAMICS OF THE DETERMINISTIC VERSION 61
u0 (ct ) = µt , (3.14)
−1
µt+1 = µt [β (f 0 (f (kt ) + (1 − δ) kt − c (µt )) + (1 − δ))] .
Once we obtain (c0 , k0 ) , we can determine the solution through itera-
tion. But c0 (and µ0 ) is a choice variable and, indeed, the second necessary
condition to determine the solution will be given by (3.16).
Consider first the locus (A) such that k = f (k) + (1 − δ) k − c (µ) , and
thus c (µA (k)) = f (k) − δk. We can obtain
∂µA f 0 (k) − δ
= 0 .
∂k c (µA (k))
| {z }
<0
Let k be such that f k = δk. Note that when k → k, c goes to zero and
thus µ → ∞.
3.5. ON THE DYNAMICS OF THE DETERMINISTIC VERSION 63
Note that if µ > µA (k), then c (µ) < c (µA (k)) and thus kt+1 − kt > 0. If
µ < µA (k), then c (µ) > c (µA (k)) and thus kt+1 − kt = k < 0. The arrows in
the graph indicate these properties.
Consider now the other locus (B) where µt+1 = µt = µ. Hence,
β (f 0 (k ∗ ) + (1 − δ)) = 1,
where k ∗ is denoted the golden rule steady state capital level. Here, µ satisfies
k ∗ = f (k) + (1 − δ) k − c (µ) and then µB (k) is defined by
f (k) + (1 − δ) k ≥ k ∗
Thus, let k be defined by f (k) + (1 − δ) k = k ∗ and note that µB (k) = +∞.
To see the dynamics note that if µ > µB (k) , then c is relatively low, k t+1
is relatively high (f 0 (kt+1 ) is low) and thus µt+1 > µt .
We need to show that the only solution satisfying (3.14)-(3.17) will assign
µ0 such that (k0 , µ0 ) belongs to the stable arm given by the arrows.
We need to show that regions I and III are absorbent. That is, once the
system gets in there, it does stay there for all consecutive periods. Regions
II and IV are transient; i.e. possibly except for one path, the dynamics will
make the system to get into either I or III. Note that there is at least one
path in region II and IV converging to (k ∗ , µ∗ ).
64CHAPTER 3. THE ONE-SECTOR NEOCLASSICAL GROWTH MODEL
Proof. Note that any solution that enters in region I moves in a southwest
direction. This implies that µ(t) → 0 and then c (µ(t)) → +∞. Also, kt
decreases monotonically. But then there exists some Te such that c µ(Te) ≥
f kTe + (1 − δ) kTe . But this implies that the solution {c∗t } imposes c∗t = 0
∀t ≥ Te, and this leads to a contradiction since the Inada conditions hold.
The idea is that the aggregate state of capital is 0 in finite time and,
then, consumption is 0 from that point in time on. No solution can satisfy
that property since the Inada Conditions implies that the unique solution is
interior.
The two previous results imply that any solution path representing the
evolution of the PO allocation must be in region II and IV. Thus, it must
converge to (k ∗ , µ∗ ) because otherwise the optimal path gets into regions I
or III.
Proof. We only need to check that the system cannot jump from one side
of the converging stable arm to the other. To see this, suppose that (k, µ) is
in region II and thus µ < µB (k). Given that
k ∗ = f (k) + (1 − δ) k − c (µB (k)) ,
it follows that c (µ) > c (µB (k)) and consequently k 0 = f (k) + (1 − δ) k −
c (µ(k)) < k ∗ implying that the system stays in region II.
To conclude, the stable arm represents the unique solution to the planner’s
problem and the system convergence monotonically. To determine these
properties, we had to use both k0 and also the transversality condition (3.16)
as boundary conditions for this nonlinear system of 2 first order difference
equations.
subject to
C(st ) + K(st ) − (1 − δ)K(st−1 ) = st F (K(st−1 ), L(st )) for all st ,
C ∈ C, K(st ) ∈ X for all st ,
s0 and K0 ∈ X are given.
That is, v(s0 , K0 ) is the maximum utility attained for an economy with
(s0 , K0 ) as initial values. That is, the level of utility evaluated at the solution
of the Pareto problem given (s0 , K0 ). As you might properly remember, this
is object is the indirect utility function in the classical static setting studied
in micro. In a dynamic framework, in general it is denoted the value function.
Note that PPR-NGM can be rewritten as follows. Let
Γ(s, K) = {(K 0 , L) ∈ X × [0, 1] : 0 ≤ K 0 ≤ sF (K, L) + (1 − δ)K} ,
3.6. RECURSIVE FORMULATION: A HEURISTIC INTRODUCTION67
and define
Π(s0 , K0 ) = {(K, L) : K(st ), L(st ) ∈ Γ(st , K(st−1 )), ∀st , given (s0 , K0 )},
as the set of feasible allocations given (s0 , K0 ). Note that by definition (K, L) ∈
Π(s0 , K0 ) if and only if (K(s0 ), L(s0 )) ∈ Γ(s0 , K0 ) and (K(st ), L(st ))t≥1 ∈
Π(s1 , K(s0 )) for all s1 (where (K(st ), L(st ))t≥1 is called the continuation of
(K, L)).
Notice that
(∞ )
XX
β t π s u C(st ), 1 − L s
t t
v(s0 , K0 ) = max ,
(K,L)∈Π(s0 ,K0 )
t=0 st
= max {u (C(s0 ), 1 − L (s0 ))
K(s0 ), L(s0 ) ∈ Γ(s0 , K 0 ),
(K(st ), L(st ))t≥1 ∈ Π(s1 , K(s0 ))
∞ X
)
X
β t π st u C(st ), 1 − L st
+
t=1 st
While this operation will be in general valid in our setting but it will NOT
be necessarily valid in ANY setting. But now it is easy to observe that we
could write
where
X∞ X
β t π (s0 , s1 ) ...π (st−1 , st ) u C(st ), 1 − L st
t=2 (s1 ,...,st )
X ∞
X X
β t−1 π (s1 , s2 ) ...π (st−1 , st ) u C(st ), 1 − L st
= β π (s0 , s1 )
s1 t=2 (s2 ,...,st )
Therefore,
∞ X
X
β t π st u C(st ), 1 − L st }
t=1 st
X
= β π (s0 , s1 ) {u (C (s0 , s1 ) , 1 − L (s0 , s1 ))
s1
∞
X X
+ β t−1 π (s1 , s2 ) ...π (st−1 , st ) u C(st ), 1 − L st
t=2 (s2 ,...,st )
v(st , K(st−1 )) = t t
max {u C(s ), 1 − L s
(K,L)(st )∈Γ(st ,K(st−1 ))
X
+β π (st , s0 ) v(s0 , K(st ))}.
s0
3
See Stokey, Lucas and Prescott (1989, Chapter 4 and 9) for a superb discussion of this
issue.
4
A seminal contribution is Kydland, Finn E., and Edward C. Prescott. 1977. “Rules
Rather than Discretion: The Inconsistency of Optimal Plans.” Journal of Political Econ-
omy, Vol. 85(3), pp. 473–491.
70CHAPTER 3. THE ONE-SECTOR NEOCLASSICAL GROWTH MODEL
The solutions to the problem above will be denoted K 0 (s, K) and L(s, K)
and represent the optimal level of next period capital and labor, respectively.
At a glance, (3.19) looks much better: instead of dealing with a infinite di-
mensional programming problem where we need to find the optimal contin-
gent infinite sequence {K(st ), L(st )}st , we just look for the optimal level of
investment and labor, (K 0 , L), given the function v. But that is, indeed, the
problem: the function v is unknown and it needs, if possible, to be found and
characterized. Under some standard assumptions, it can be shown that it ex-
ists and it is unique. Furthermore, some properties about the function v can
be established under mild assumptions, in particular its partial derivative.
There is a solution method to find v that works only under very restrictive
assumptions: first, guess a particular function v; then, verify that it satisfies
the functional equation (3.19) given above. The next example illustrates this
alternative.
Once the value function itself v is known, this optimization problem would
be standard and it could be solved using well-known arguments. Then, the
strategy is the following. We guess a particular functional form for v, solve
the corresponding problem and then verify if effectively v satisfies the oper-
ator defined by (3.20).
To do so, we guess that v(s, K) = A1 + A2 ln s + A3 ln K. We then need
to find out for which set of parameters (A1 , A2 , A3 ) this function satisfies the
operator above. Hence, we first solve
X
0
α 1−α
π (ε0 ) (A1 +A2 ln (sρ ε0 )+A3 ln K 0 )}.
max
0
{ln sK L − K ) + γ ln(1 − L +β
K ,L
0
3.6. RECURSIVE FORMULATION: A HEURISTIC INTRODUCTION71
1 βA3
K0 : = ,
sK α L1−α − K0 K0
(1 − α)sK α L−α γ
L : α 1−α 0
= ,
sK L −K 1−L
and thus
βA3
K0 = sK α L1−α ,
1 + βA3
(1 − α) (1 + βA3 )
L = .
γ + (1 − α) (1 + βA3 )
Exercises
Exercise 10 In text.
C = {{ct }∞
t=0 : (ct ) : S
t+1
→ R+ , sup c(st ) < ∞}.
(t,st )
where the initial stock of human capital is given by H0 = H (s−1 ) > 0 and A
is a positive parameter.
There is a CRS aggregate technology to produce the consumption good
operated by a representative firm and subject to productivity shocks. Let
K(st ) ≥ 0 denote the aggregate stock of physical capital determined at the
node st and available in period t + 1 to produce with the aggregate technology.
Goods invested transform one-to-one in new physical capital next period and
the depreciation rate is given by δ ∈ (0, 1). Therefore, the stock of physical
capital evolves according to
α 1−α
c(st ) + I(st ) = st K(st−1 ) L(st ) , ∀st
L(st ) = u st H st−1 , ∀st
Pareto Optimality
(a) Carefully define the Planner’s Problem for this economy. Characterize
the solution justifying your answer.
Welfare Theorems
Hint: Use the FOC’s characterizing the Planner’s problem to answer this
question
75
76 CHAPTER 4. ASSET PRICING AND TRADING
Additionally, we assume that dj (st ) = dj (st−1 , st ) for all st−1 and for all
j. This means that both output of the J trees and the aggregate endowment
depend only on the current shock st .
Consider the Pareto problem (PP) defined in Chapter 2 given some vector
of welfare weights α. Under our assumptions, we can characterize the unique
solution with the necessary and sufficient FOC given by,
t
βi αi u0i (ci (st )(α))
=1 (4.1)
βh αh u0h (ch (st )(α))
I
X
ci (st )(α) = y(st ) (4.2)
i=1
where (u0i )−1 , the inverse function of u0i , is well defined since ui is strictly
concave.
Firm j pays dj (st ) as dividends at each date t with realization st . That is,
this is a fixed dividend policy. Below we allow for alternative firm’s financial
policies to show that real equilibrium allocations are immune to these changes
and remain unaltered. Let θij (s−1 ) denote agent i0 s endowment of tree j 0 s
shares at date 0.
Let pj (st ) be the one share of firm j at the node st after dividends have
been paid (i.e., the ex-dividend price of the firm, since there is only one fully
divisible outstanding share).
Agents can also trade a full set of Arrow securities in zero net supply.
The Arrow security s0 traded at st pays one unit of consumption next period
if st+1 = s0 and 0 otherwise. Let q(st )(s0 ) be the price of this security at st .
Denote ai (st , s0 ) the holdings of this security. As usual, we restrict agents
to bounded trading strategies to rule out Ponzi schemes. These (implicit)
bounds are assumed to be sufficiently large such that they do not bind in
equilibrium. All prices are in units of the st -consumption good.
From the consumer side, given a price system (p, q) agent i0 s problem is
given by:
XX
max β t π(st )u(ci (st )),
(ci ,ai ,θi )
t st
subject to
X X
ci (st ) + pj (st )θij (st ) + q(st )(s0 )ai (st , s0 )
j s0
X
= ai (st−1 , st ) + [pj (st ) + dj (st )]θij (st−1 ),
j
(STCE 1) Given (b
p, q
b), (b
ci , θbi , b
ai ) solves agent i’s problem for each i.
78 CHAPTER 4. ASSET PRICING AND TRADING
I
X J
X
t
ci (s ) =
b dj (st ) = y(st ),
i=1 j=1
X
ai (st , s0 ) = 0 for all s0 ,
b
i
X
θbij (st ) = 1 for all j.
i
∞ X
X
β t π(st ) u(ci (st )) + ...
LSM (ci , ai , γi ) =
t=0 st
"
X
t
ai (st−1 , st ) + [pj (st ) + dj (st )]θij (st−1 )
+γi s
j
#)
X X
−ci (st ) − pj (st )θij (st ) − q(st )(s0 )ai (st , s0 ) .
j s0
4.2. COMPETITIVE SEQUENTIAL TRADINGWITH DINAMICALLY COMPLETE MARKETS79
bi st = u0 b ci s t
γ
bi st , s0 β t+1 π(st , s0 ) = qb st (s0 ) β t π(st )b
γi st
γ
X X
ci (st ) +
b pbj (st )θbij (st ) + qb(st )(s0 )b
ai (st , s0 )
j s0
X
ai (st−1 , st ) +
= b pj (st ) + dj (st )]θbij (st−1 ),
[b
j
X
β t π(st )b
γi st pbj (st ) = bi st , st+1 β t+1 π(st , st+1 )[b
pj (st , st+1 )+dj (st , st+1 )]
γ
st+1
X u0 (b
ci (st , st+1 ))
pbj (st ) = βπ(st , st+1 ) pj (st , st+1 ) + dj (st , st+1 )]
[b
st+1
u0 (b
ci (st ))
X
qb st (st+1 ) [b
pj (st , st+1 ) + dj (st , st+1 )]
=
st+1
X
β T π(sT )b
γi sT bai s T
lim =
T →∞
sT
X
β T π(sT )u0 b
ci s T ai s T
lim b =
T →∞
sT
lim E0 β T u0 (b
ci,T ) b
ai,T = 0
T →∞
80 CHAPTER 4. ASSET PRICING AND TRADING
X
β T π(sT )b
γi sT dj (sT ) + pj (sT ) θbij (sT −1 )
lim
T →∞
sT
X
= lim β T −1 π(sT −1 )θbij (sT −1 ) × ...
T →∞
sT −1
!
X
γi (sT −1 , sT ) dj (sT ) + pj (sT −1 , sT )
βπ(sT −1 , sT )b
sT
X
= lim β T −1 π(sT −1 )b
γi (sT −1 )pj (sT −1 )θbij (sT −1 )
T →∞
sT −1
X
β T −1 π(sT −1 ) u0 b
ci sT −1 pj (sT −1 )θbij (sT −1 )
= lim
T →∞
sT −1
n o
T −1 0
= lim E0 β u (b
ci,T −1 ) pj,T −1 θij,T −1 = 0
b
T →∞
plus (STCE 2). The transversality conditions have the following heuristic
interpretation. If any of these expressions were strictly positive, the agent
would be overaccumulating assets so that a higher expected life-time utility
could be achieved by, for example, increasing consumption today. The coun-
terpart to such nonoptimality in a finite horizon model would be that the
agent dies with positive asset holdings.
Before proceeding to price different assets, let’s a close look at this ex-
pression
X u0 (b
ci (st , st+1 ))
pbj (st ) = βπ(st , st+1 ) pj (st , st+1 ) + dj (st , st+1 )]
[b
st+1
u0 (b
ci (st ))
X
qb st (st+1 ) [b
pj (st , st+1 ) + dj (st , st+1 )]
=
st+1
The first line makes clear that agents value units of the consumption
good at date t + 1, state st+1 , using their intertemporal marginal rate of
u0 (b
ci (st ,st+1 ))
substitution (IMRS), βπ(st , st+1 ) u0 (bci (st )) . The presence of a full set of
(fully enforceable) Arrow securities makes the IMRS of each agent in the
economy equal to the price of the corresponding Arrow security, qb (st ) (st+1 );
i.e., all the intertemporal individual valuations coincide. More about this
later.
This framework is particularly relevant because it allows to price any
security.
4.3. EQUILIBRIUM ASSET PRICES 81
1
Cochrane’s Happy-Meal Theorem: the price of a happy meal (in a frictionless market)
should be the same as the price of one hamburger, one small fries, one small drink and
the toy.
82 CHAPTER 4. ASSET PRICING AND TRADING
for all i, j and for all st due to the TC P (you t+kwill need to convince yourself
of one more step). And then, since i θij (s ) = 1 for all st+k , we can
conclude that X
lim P (st+k kst )pj (st+k ) = 0,
k→∞
st+k
for all j, as required. This kind of anomaly can be ruled out in general in
economies where the transversality condition is a necessary condition. When
markets are dynamically complete, this is always true. More about this later.
Therefore, the expression above reduces to
∞ X
X
pj (st ) = P (st+j kst )dj (st+j ),
j=1 st+j kst
and consequently the stock price is the present discounted value of the divi-
dends’ process.
4.3.3 Derivatives
Here we give examples of so-called derivative assets, that is of assets whose
returns are somehow derived from the return of another asset.
European Call Option
At st , consider a security that in T periods, after the realizations st+T
has been observed and dividends have been paid gives the right, but not
the obligation, to buy a share of the tree j at the strike price b > 0. Let
EOption t
qj,T (s ) be the price at st of an European call option with maturity T
and thus a specific expiration date t + T .2
2
An European option can only be exercised on the expiration date. If the option can
4.3. EQUILIBRIUM ASSET PRICES 83
where X
EOption t
qj,1 (s ) = q(st )(s0 ) max(pj (st , s0 ) − b, 0).
s0
That is, the option will be executed at T only its the price of the j tree is
higher that the strike price b (i.e. pj (st+T ) > b). Consequently,
EOption t
X
qj,T (s ) = P (st+T kst ) max(pj (st+T ) − b, 0).
st+T kst
where qn−1 (st , s0 ) is the price of the n − 1 risk free bond’s price at (st , s0 ).
The intuition is the standard. By non arbitrage, today’s price must equal the
right to have tomorrow in all the states a n − 1 risk free bond. For example,
if n = 1 the risk-free interest rate at st , Rrf (st ), is defined by
X
−1 t
Rrf (s ) = qrf (st ) = q(st )(s0 ).
s0
exercised any time as well as on the expiration date is named an American option. On
the other hand, a put option gives to the owner the right, but not the obligation, to sell.
More about this later.
3
Zero coupon means that it will pay nothing in between.
84 CHAPTER 4. ASSET PRICING AND TRADING
It is key to understand that even though safe bonds represent sure claims
to future consumption, these assets are subject to price risk prior to maturity.
To see this more precisely, let Rn−1 (st ) = qn (st ) and note that (4.6) for n = 2
implies that
X
R2−1 (st ) = −1 t 0
q(st )(s0 )Rrf (s , s ), (4.7)
s0
X u0 (ci (s0 )) −1 t 0
= π (st , s0 ) β R (s , s ),
0 (c (s )) rf
s 0
u i t
0
u (ci (s0 )) −1 t 0
= E β 0 Rrf (s , s ) k st ,
u (ci (st ))
−1 t −1 t 0
= Rrf (s )E Rrf (s , s ) k st +
0
u (ci (s0 )) −1 t 0
+Cov β 0 , Rrf (s , s ) k st
u (ci (st ))
This is the implicit yield per period. The term structure of the interest
rate (TSIR) is the collection of yields to maturity for bonds with different
maturities (also called the ”yield curve”).
It is already apparent that understanding what moves bond yields might
be important for forecasting. Indeed, yields on long-maturity bonds are
expected values of average future short yields, after an adjustment for risk.
This means that the current yields curve contains information about the
future path of the economy. Therefore, we could proceed as in (4.7) to
decompose (4.8) and obtain the corresponding risk premium represented by
covariance terms. But casual inspection of (4.8) suggests that this general
investigation might get quite complicated, as we have an implicit covariance
term involving nonlinear functions of consumption in at least three periods.
Since discretion is the better part of valor, it makes sense to examine some
simplified versions of the general problem.
Define the net risk-free interest rate at st , rRF (st ), is defined rRF (st ) =
−1
ln Rrf (st ) = ln (qrf (st )) where now
ρ −σ
st+1 (y(st ))
Z
t −1 t
qrf (s ) = Rrf (s ) = β F (dst+1 )
y(st )
−σ(ρ−1)
= β y(st ) E (st+1 )−σ .
where
−σ
y(st , st+1 , ..., st+n )
Z Z
t
qn (s ) = ... β F (dst+1 )...F (dst+n ).
st+1 st+n y(st )
Observe that the slope of the yield curve can be obtained from the fol-
lowing expression
1 (1 − ρn )
t RF t
rn (s ) − r (s ) = 1− σ (1 − ρ) ln y(st )
n (1 − ρ)
1 (1 − ρn ) 1 (1 − ρ2n ) 1 2 2
− 1− σµs + 1 − σ ξs
n (1 − ρ) n (1 − ρ2 ) 2
1 (1 − ρn ) y(st )
= 1− σ ln µs t ρ
n (1 − ρ) e y(s )
2n
1 (1 − ρ ) 1 2 2
+ 1− σ ξs .
n (1 − ρ2 ) 2
The first term is key to understand what is behind the yield curve in this
setting and it can interpreted as follows. If the economy is in an expansion
and current output is above its trend (i.e., y(st ) > eµs y(st )ρ ), the first term
is increasing in n. Since the second term is always increasing in n, the yield
curve is upward sloped.
Roughly speaking, a high level of output lowers short term rates rela-
tively more. Income today is relatively high, so people want to save the
extra income; consequently, they drive up the price of risk free bonds and
correspondingly drive down the interest rate. In addition, the term structure
steepens because short term rates fall more than long term rates. This is
because the effect of the positive shock dies off as long as ρ < 1 , so that
if income is high today, it is also expected to be higher than average next
period, but not quite so high. The size of the effect, and thus the incentive
to save, diminishes, leading to a smaller increase in long rates. Importantly,
observe that this description is also valid for the case of i.i.d. shocks if we
88 CHAPTER 4. ASSET PRICING AND TRADING
= (w + 1)st βE 1−σ ,
4.4. THE EQUITY PREMIUM PUZZLE 89
and thus
(w + 1) 1 βE {1−σ }
= ⇒ w= ,
w βE {1−σ } 1 − βE {1−σ }
and our conjecture is verified to be correct. Define the equity return in state
st+1
p(st , st+1 ) + st+1 (w + 1)
RE (st+1 ) = t
= t+1 ,
p(s ) w
E{}
and thus its expected value is given by E {RE (t + 1)} = βE{ 1−σ } .
Note that this implies that the average equity premium in the data is
0.0618 (approximately 6%).
Now we need to impose some restrictions to the choice of β and σ. Var-
ious studies suggest that σ is a small number, certainly less than 10. The
parameter β is calibrated such that it matches the risk-free interest rate in
a deterministic version of the economy in steady state. This implies that β
is approximately equal to 0.99(≈ (1.008)−1 ).
Thus using σ = 10 (the upper bound) and β = 0.99, we obtain the
predicted risk free interest rate
1
ln R
brf = − ln β + σµ − σ 2 ξ2 = 0.120
2
⇒ R
brf = 1.127,
that is, 12.7%! This inconsistency between the predicted and the observed
risk-free interest rate (which in the US averages less than 1%) has been
dubbed ”the risk-free rate puzzle”.
On the other hand, the predicted return on equity is 1.141 (that is, 14.1%)
and consequently the predicted equity premium amounts 1.4%, far lower than
the 6.18% historically observed in the data. This happens even imposing an
arbitrarily high number for σ, which most studies indicate to be close to 3.
This empirical fact has been known as ”the equity premium puzzle”.
It is important to mention that even though a higher σ might help to
explain the last puzzle, it would impose an even higher risk free interest rate,
leaving the first puzzle mentioned more unexplained.
∪ m(, τ ) ⊃ ∪ m(, τ ).
τ ∈E τ ∈P
−σ
t
X c (st , st+1 )
qn (s ) = βπ (st , st+1 ) hn (st+1 )
st+1
c (st )−σ
−σ
ct+1
= Et β −σ hn,t+1
c
−σt
c
= Et β t+1 Et (hn,t+1 )
c−σ
t
−σ
ct+1
+Covt β −σ , hn,t+1
ct
−σ
c
and hence, q RF (st ) = Et β ct+1
−σ , we have
t
c−σ
t+1
qn (st ) stdt β c−σ
t
RF t
≥ E t (hn,t+1 ) − RF t
sdt (hn,t+1 ) (4.10)
q (s ) q (s )
The LHS denotes the price of the security in terms of the price of the risk
free bond. The bound () holds with equality for those asset that are!
on the
c−σ
t+1
stdt β
c−σ
t
efficient mean-standard deviation frontier. The expresion is called
q RF (st )
the market price of risk. It provides an estimate of the rate at which the price
of a security falls with an increase in the conditional standard deviation of
its payoff.
Hansen and Jagannathan (1991) used data on asset prices and returns
alone to estimate the market price of risk
Equity premium puzzle: the market price of risk implied by the asset
market data alone is much higher than can be reconciled with the aggregate
consumption data.
c−σ
That is, aggregate consumption is not volatile enough to make stdt β ct+1
−σ
t
high enough for the reasonable values of σ.
4.5. AGGREGATION AND THE DISTRIBUTION OF WEALTH 93
subject to
I
X
ci (st ) = y(st ) for all st , (4.11)
i=1
ci ∈ C for all i.
X X
c∗i st )(α = yi (st ) for all st . (4.13)
i i
Under our assumption, we can characterize the unique solution with the
necessary and sufficient FOC given by
αi u0i (ci (st )(α))
= 1, (4.14)
αh u0h (ch (st )(α))
I
X
ci (st )(α) = y(st ). (4.15)
i=1
where (u0i )−1 , the inverse function of u0i , is well defined since ui is strictly
concave.
94 CHAPTER 4. ASSET PRICING AND TRADING
I
X X −1 αh 0
t
ci (s )(α) = (u0i ) u (ch (s )(α)) + ch (st )(α) = C(st ) = y(st ).
t
i=1 i6=h
αi h
(4.17)
where C(st ) stands for aggregate consumption at st .
Hence, given the distributional parameters α (which are fixed in this
artificial device called ”the Planner’s problem”), the only determinant of
individual consumption is the realization of the aggregate endowment. Very
importantly, this implies that at any competitive equilibrium, any kind of
individual risk will be perfectly traded away across agents. Additionally,
ch (st−1 , st )(α) = ch (st )(α) for all h; i.e., individual consumption depends
only on the current shock and thus the distribution of consumption is history
independent.
On the other hand, although the intertemporal margianl rates of sub-
stitutions are equalizaed acorss agents, these will in general depend on the
distribution parameter α. To see this consider a setting with a full set of
Arrow securities. Iin that economy, the competitive equibilibrium allocation
is PO for some α, (c∗i (α))Ii=1 . Notice that IMRS are equalized and thus, for
all agent i, we have that
But then, Arrow security prices and the corresponding state prices will
both depend on α in general.
Aggregation form in the sense of Gorman are possible. That is, under
specific assumptions, a fictitious representative aggregate consumer can be
constructed to deliver competitive equilibrium prices as IMRS at aggregate
quantities. Suppose that
(c−γi )1−σ
if σ 6= 1 and σ > 0
ui (c) = 1−σ ,
ln(c − γi ) if σ = 1
(αi )1/σ
[ci (α) − γi ] = PI 1/σ
[C − γ], (4.18)
h=1 (αh )
I
(∞ )
t 1−σ
X XX (c(s ) − γi )
αi β t π(st ) (4.19)
i=1 t=0 st ∈S t
1−σ
(∞ I
)
XX X (c(st ) − γi )1−σ
= β t π(st ) αi
t=0 st ∈S t i=1
1−σ
I
X (c(st ) − γi )1−σ
αi
i=1
1−σ
1−σ 1−σ
I
X αi σ (C(st ) − γ)
= αi 1−σ
PI 1/σ 1−σ
i=1
h=1 (αh )
I 1−σ
1 X (C(st ) − γ)
1
= 1−σ αi σ
PI 1/σ 1−σ
h=1 (αh ) i=1
I
!σ 1−σ
X 1/σ (C(st ) − γ)
= (αh )
h=1
1−σ
96 CHAPTER 4. ASSET PRICING AND TRADING
I
!σ ( ∞ 1−σ
)
X 1/σ
XX (C(st ) − γ)
(αh ) β t π(st )
h=1 t=0 st ∈S t
1−σ
where Dj (st ) is the dividend distributed among share owners holding Θj (st−1 )
shares issued at st−1 , Bj represents contingent debt and (Θj (st ) − Θj (st−1 ))
is the amount of new shares issued at st . At date t, the left-hand side in
(4.20) describes the firm’s obligations whereas the right-hand side describes
its sources of revenues. Conditions (4.21) and (4.22) rule out Ponzi schemes.
4.6. FIRM’S FINANCIAL POLICY AND THE MODIGLIANI-MILLER THEOREM97
A SMCE for this setting is defined as usual taking into account that the
market clearing condition for asset markets are now given by
X X
ai (st , s0 ) = Bj (st , s0 ) for all s0 ,
i j
X
θij (s ) = Θj (st ) for all j.
t
i.e., the total value of j stocks after dividends and debt obligations have been
paid at st whenever Θj (st ) is the total number of shares issued at st .
From (4.20), we have that (4.23) satisfies
X X
Θj (st )pj (st ) = q(st )(st+1 )dj (st+1 ) − q(st )(st+1 )Bj (st , st+1 )(4.24)
st+1 st+1
XX
+ q(s )(st+1 )q(s , st+1 )(st+2 )Bj (st , st+1 , st+2 )
t t
st+1 st+2
X
+ q(st )(st+1 )pj (st , st+1 )Θj (st , st+1 ).
st+1
Let P (st+h k st ) = q(st )(st+1 )q(st , st+1 )(st+2 )...q(st , st+1 , ..., st+h−1 )(st+h )
be the price of one unit of the consumption good delivered at st+h in st −units.
Thus, using (4.20)-(4.22) repeatedly in (4.24), we cancel the debt terms to
obtain
X X∞ X
t t t t
Θj (s )pj (s ) + q(s )(st+1 )Bj (s , st+1 ) = P (st+h k st )dj (st+h ).
st+1 h=1 st+h kst
(4.25)
98 CHAPTER 4. ASSET PRICING AND TRADING
Since the right-hand side of this last expression is independent of the firm’s
financial policy (i.e., the total value of the dividend process, purely techno-
logical), its total value itself is unaffected by any alternative (Bj , Θj , Dj ).
X∞ X
= P (st+h k st )y(st+h ),
h=1 st+h kst
i.e., the total wealth at the economy, unaffected by firms’ financial plans.
This theorem can be extended in several directions not discussed here.
However, we should mention two important properties that make the theorem
work in more general settings:
1. Consumers and firms face the same financial market opportunities.
Thus, consumers can repackage the financial component of dividends and,
in particular, if needed they can undo whatever firms do in the financial
markets.
2. In production economies, the total value of dividends depends only on
production plans, independently of financial plans.
has already been declared but not paid, so the market knows how much it is worth and
the corresponding price will reflect this. We will not consider this case below.
100 CHAPTER 4. ASSET PRICING AND TRADING
for each j ∈ {1, ..., J}. That is, the price of any security is the state-
price weighted sum (or expectation) of the security’s state-contingent payoffs.
Identifying the state prices is the major task at hand. To prove the next re-
sult we use the following version of the Separating Hyperplane Theorem for
cones.
Theorem 15 (Linear Separation of Cones) Suppose Q and K are closed
convex cones in RN such that Q ∩ K = {0}. If K does not contain a lin-
ear subspace other than {0}, then there is nonzero vector p ∈ RN such that
p · x < p · y for each x ∈ Q and each y ∈ K/{0}.
Now we show that the no-arbitrage condition is equivalent to the existence
of a state-price vector. To keep technical issues simple, we assume that
T < ∞.
Theorem 16 There is no arbitrage if and only if there exists a state-price
vector.
Proof. Let L+ be non-negative orthant of L and notice that the only linear
subspace of L+ is {0}. Observe that there is no arbitrage if and only if
M ∩ L+ = {0}.
Step 1. Suppose first that there is no arbitrage, i.e. M ∩ L+ = {0}.
Theorem 14 implies the existence of p ∈ L/{0} such that p · z < p · x for all
z ∈ M and for all x ∈ L+ /{0}. Suppose that there exists some zb ∈ M such
that p · zb 6= 0. Since M is a linear space, λz ∈ M for all λ ∈ R. Thus, if you
fix some x ∈ L+ /{0} (and then fix p · x), there exists some λ ∈ R such that
p · λb
z ≥ p · x, and we get a contradiction. Hence, p · z = 0 for all z ∈ M .
This implies that 0 < p · x for all x ∈ L+ /{0} and we claim that this implies
that p ∈ L++ . To see this, note that otherwise, if p(st ) ≤ 0 for some st , we
can choose x e such that it is equal to 0 for every node except at st and, then,
p·xe ≤ 0, a contradiction. Therefore, since p · z = 0 for any arbitrary z ∈ M ,
then
XT X
p(st )δ a (st ) = 0 (4.27)
t=0 st
The state-price process is constructed making m(st )(s0 ) = π(s1t ,s0 ) p(st ) for
each s0 .
Step 2. Suppose now that there exists a state-price. Denote
for all st (i.e., the shadow date 0 price implied by state prices). Consider any
trading strategy a ∈ A to compute
T X
X
m a
E (P ·δ ) = π(st )P m (st )δ a (st )
st
t=0
T
XX
π(st )P m (st ) h(st ) · a(st−1 ) − q(st ) · a(st ) .
=
t=0 st
T X
X
E (P m · δ a ) = π(st )P m (st ) h(st ) · a(st−1 ) − q(st ) · a(st ) .
t=0 st
T XX
X
π(st−1 )π(st−1 , st )P m (st−1 )m(st−1 )(st ) h(st ) · a(st−1 )
=
t=0 st−1 st
XT X
− π(st )P m (st )q(st ) · a(st )
t=0 st
T X
X X X
P m (st−1 ) aj (st−1 ) m(st−1 )π(st−1 , st )(st )hj (st )
=
t=0 st−1 j st
T X
X
− π(st )P m (st )q(st ) · a(st )
t=0 st
T
XX
P m (st−1 ) q(st−1 ) · aj (st−1 )
=
t=0 st−1
XT X
P m (st ) q(st ) · a(st )
−
t=0 st
102 CHAPTER 4. ASSET PRICING AND TRADING
Since aj (sT ) = aj (s−1 ) = 0 for all j, we can conclude that for any trading
strategy a ∈ A
T X
X
E (P m · δ a ) = P m (st−1 ) q(st−1 ) · aj (st−1 )
t=1 st−1
XT X
P m (st ) q(st ) · a(st )
−
t=0 st
= −P (s ) q(sT ) · a(sT ) = 0
m T
Exercises
Exercise 13 Exercise 13.3 [Ljungqvist, Sargent (2004)] Growth slowdowns
and stock market crashes, donated by Rodolfo Manuelli.6
Consider a simple one-tree pure exchange economy. The only source of
consumption is the fruit that grows on the tree. This fruit is called dividends
by the tribe inhabiting this island. The stochastic process for dividend dt is
described as follows: If dt is not equal to dt+1 , then dt+1 = γdt with probabil-
ity π, and dt+1 = dt with probability (1 − π). If in any pair of periods j and
j + 1, dj = dj+1 , then for all t > j , dt = dj .
c(1−σ)
where u(c) = (1−σ)
. Assume that σ > 0 , 0 < β < 1 , γ > 1, and
(1−σ)
βγ < 1.
6
See also Joseph Zeira (1999)
4.7. ARBITRAGE AND STATE PRICES 103
(a) Define a competitive equilibrium in which shares to this tree are traded.
(b) Display the equilibrium process for the price of shares in this tree pt as
a function of the history of dividends. Is the price process a Markov
process in the sense that it depends just on the last periodś dividends?
(c) Let T be the first time in which dT +1 = dT = γ (T −1) . Is pT −1 > pT
? Show conditions under which this is true. What is the economic
intuition for this result? What does it say about stock market declines
or crashes?
(d) If this model is correct, what does it say about the behavior of the ag-
gregate value of the stock market in economies that switched from high
to low growth (e.g., Japan)?
Exercise 14 (Exercise 13.4 [Ljungqvist, Sargent (2004)) The term struc-
ture and consumption, donated by Rodolfo Manuelli]
Consider an economy populated by a large number of identical households.
The (common) utility function is:
∞
X
U = E0 β t u(ct )
t=0
(1−θ)
where 0 < β < 1 , and u(x) = x(1−θ) , for some θ > 0. (If θ = 1, the
utility is logarithmic.) Each household owns one tree. Thus, the number of
households and trees coincide. The amount of consumption that grows in a
tree satisfies:
ct+1 = c∗ cϕt εt+1
where 0 < ϕ < 1, and εt is a sequence of i.i.d. log normal random
variables with mean one, and variance σ 2 . Assume that, in addition to
shares in trees, in this economy bonds of all maturities are traded.
(a) Define a competitive equilibrium.
(b) Go as far as you can calculating the term structure of interest rates,
R̃jt , for j = 1, 2, ....
(c) Economist A argues that economic theory predicts that the variance
of the log of short-term interest rates (say one-period) is always lower
than the variance of long-term interest rates, because short rates are
“riskier”. Do you agree? Justify your answer.
104 CHAPTER 4. ASSET PRICING AND TRADING
(e) Economist C claims that the Fed should lower interest rates because
whenever interest rates are low, consumption is high. Do you agree?
Justify your answer.
yt = λt λt−1 ...y0
where ζ > 0.
Assume that in period t = 0 we have:
s0 = 1
4.7. ARBITRAGE AND STATE PRICES 105
Suppose that there is a full set of Arrow securities and a risk-free bond
that can be traded. Let pbt be the time t of a risk-free claim to one unit of
consumption at time t + 1.
Asset Pricing
−1
(c) Let Rt = pbt be the one period risk-free gross interest rate. Give a
formula for Rt and tell how it depends on the history st .
P11 = 1
P12 = 0
P21 = 0.5
P22 = 0.5
i = 1, ..., τ and all st . Here q k (st ) denotes the zero coupon bond with
maturity k = 1, ..., τ at st .
Exercise 17 Suppose that there are N consumption goods every period. Agent
i’s preferences are represented by expected, discounted time-separable utility
for which the instantaneous utility function is
N
!
X (ci,n − γi,n )1−σ
u(ci,1 , ..., ci,n , ..., ci,N ) = φn
n=1
1−σ
where Cn = Ii=1 ci,n stands for aggregate consumption of the n−th commod-
P
Throughout this chapter we will use the standard notation for the case of
only 1 consumption good.
P Let yi (st ) be the agent i realization of his endow-
ment at date t, with i∈I yi (st ) = y(st ) denoting the aggregate endowment.
As a starting point, consider the most rudimentary asset market struc-
ture to analyze consumption dynamics: an endowment economy where at
any period t markets for state contingent securities are completely absent
(i.e. there is no way to trade contingent to future states st+1 ) and, addition-
ally, there is no storage technology to transfer resources across periods (i.e.,
the consumption good is perishable). In this economy, an individual i who
receives an income process {yit }∞t=0 has no other choice than consuming her
income every period, i.e.
ci (st ) = yi (st ), (5.1)
for each st . This is the most trivial setting where individual consumption ab-
sorbs all the idiosyncratic fluctuations in individual income. That is, agents
cannot trade away any kind of individual risk.
109
110 CHAPTER 5. CONSUMPTION AND SAVINGS
I
X
ci (st )(α) = y(st ). (5.3)
i=1
where (u0i )−1 , the inverse function of u0i , is well defined since ui is strictly
concave.
The limit distribution of consumption (and, consequently, equilibrium
wealth) will concentrate mass only on those agents with the highest discount
factors.
Proposition 8 Suppose that there two agents i and h such that βi < βh .
∞
Then, limt→∞ ci (st ) = 0 for all {st }t=0 .
Proof. Consumption is bounded from above by maxs y(s) and u0i (0) = +∞.
The result follows from inspecting condition (5.2) above.
In a market economy with complete markets, equilibrium asset prices will
adjust such that impatient agents borrow from patient agents to anticipate
consumption. Meanwhile, patient agents accumulate wealth such that they
end up consuming the aggregate endowment.
5.1. FULL RISK-SHARING WITH COMPLETE MARKETS 111
for all st . Sometimes this is the definition of full risk-sharing (or full insur-
ance).1
Furthermore, it follows from (5.4) and (4.2) that individual consumption
for agent h depends only upon y(st ) for all st given a vector of welfare weights
(αi )Ii=1 . To see this, notice that
t 0 −1 αh 0 t
ci (s )(α) = (ui ) u (ch (s )(α)) , (5.6)
αi h
and then it follows from feasibility that ch (st ) is the unique solution to
0 −1 αh 0
X
(ui ) uh (ch (s )(α)) + ch (st )(α) = y(st ).
t
(5.7)
i6=h
α i
for all stk . But this expression contradicts that ch (stk ) → 0 since in that case u0h (ch (stk )) →
∞.
112 CHAPTER 5. CONSUMPTION AND SAVINGS
For the particular case where ui (c) = c1−σ for all i with σ > 0, (5.2)
implies that
1/σ
ci (st )(α) αi
t
= ,
ch (s )(α) αh
and then (5.7) reduces to
1/σ 1/σ
α α
ci (s )(α) = P i 1/σ y(st ) = P i 1/σ C(st ),
t
(5.8)
h αh h αh
Empirical Implications
Expression (5.7) has strong empirical implications and, indeed, it has
been intensively tested empirically. Under CRRA preferences, for instance,
equation (5.8) implies that the log-change in individual consumption should
equal the log-change in aggregate consumption, for every individual, in every
period. If we estimate from micro-data the relationship
∆ log ci,t = β1 ∆ log Ct + β2 ∆ log yi,t + εi,t , (5.9)
where yi,t is current individual income. Then, the full risk-sharing hypothesis
implies to test β1 = 1, β2 = 0. On the other hand, autarky has predictions
that imply to test the alternative hypothesis: β1 = 0, β2 = 1; i.e., con-
sumption follows perfectly individual current income. In general, evidence
suggests that both hypothesis should be rejected, albeit the data seem to be
much closer to full risk-sharing in many contexts.2
Remark 8 From the empirical point of view, a reasonable model for con-
sumption must lie between autarky and full risk-sharing; i.e., agents should
have access to ”partial” consumption insurance.
2
Mace, Barbara (1991), ”Full Insurance in the Presence of Aggregate Uncertainty,”
Journal of Political Economy.
Cochrane, John (1991), ”A Simple Test of Consumption Insurance,” Journal of Political
Economy.
Parker, Jonathan and B. Preston (2005), ”Precautionary Saving and Consumption Fluc-
tuations,” American Economic Review, Vol 95 No 4 (September), 1119-43.
5.2. THE PERMANENT INCOME HYPOTHESIS (PIH) 113
1
q(st ) = q ≡ , (5.11)
1+r
for all st , where r is the (implicit) interest rate. Thus, we can impose a
No-Ponzi scheme condition as follows
" t+τ #
1
lim Et at+τ (5.12)
τ →∞ 1+r
t+τ !
X X 1
= lim ... π(st , st+1 , ..., st+τ ) at+τ ≥ 0.
τ →∞
s s
1+r
t+1 t+τ
1
t+τ
where 1+r is the implicit price of one unit of the consumption good
delivered at date t + τ .
3
It is important to mention that the coming results depend upon the particular asset
market structure under study.
114 CHAPTER 5. CONSUMPTION AND SAVINGS
Denoting xt+τ to any random variable with realization x(st , st+1 , ..., st+τ ),
proceed repeatedly as before, use (5.12) and take the limit to obtain
∞ τ
t−1
X 1
ai (s ) = Et (ci,t+τ − yi,t+τ ) , (5.13)
τ =0
1 + r
and thus
ci (st ) = Et (ci,t+1 ) (5.16)
i.e. individual consumption is a martingale.45
Dropping the index i, it is useful to note that from the law of iterated
expectations and the martingale property (5.16) imply that
where H(st ) denotes human wealth at st ; i.e. the expected discounted value
of future individual earnings. Since financial wealth is at = a(st−1 ), define
r
permanent income as the annuity value (i.e. 1+r ) of total (human and fi-
t t−1 t
nancial) wealth W (s ) = a(s ) + H(s ). Therefore, we can summarize this
important result for this setting.
4
We say that the stochastic process {xt } is a martingale if, E[|xt |] < ∞ for all t, and
if for any τ > 0, Et [xt+τ ] = x(st ).
5
Observe that without the assumption that β(1 + r) = 1, (5.15) generalizes to ci (st ) =
α0 + α1 Et (ci,t+1 ) (that is, β(1 + r) = 1 implies that α0 = 0 and α1 = 1).
116 CHAPTER 5. CONSUMPTION AND SAVINGS
Hence, under the assumption that utility is quadratic and that the real
interest rate is a constant and equal to the consumer’s rate of subjective
time preference, optimal consumption is proportional to permanent income
or wealth. One implication of this representation is that permanent changes
in income lead to permanent changes in consumption.
Certainty Equivalence
Notice that if one solves the non-stochastic version of the PIH problem
stated earlier, the Euler equation (5.15) implies immediately that ct+1 = ct .
Thus, proceeding as before in the budget constraint we can conclude that
" ∞ τ #
r X 1
ct = at + yt+τ . (5.19)
1+r τ =0
1 + r
If one compares equation (5.18) with (5.19), one can observe that individ-
ual consumption satisfies a certainty equivalence property. That is, one can
obtain the solution of the stochastic problem as follows. First, solve the de-
terminist problem and, then, instead of the individual income (yt+τ ) plug its
conditional expectations (Et (yt+τ )). This property is a direct consequence of
linear-quadratic preferences: the variance and higher moments of the income
process do not matter for consumption choices.
Consumption Dynamics
Since Et−1 ct = ct−1 for all t, it follows from (5.18), the change in con-
sumption at time t equals
r
∆ct = c(st ) − c(st−1 ) = c(st ) − Et−1 (ct ) = W (st ) − Et−1 (Wt ) .
1+r
(5.20)
t−1
Since agents decide asset holdings for period t at s , we have that
Et−1 (at ) = a(st−1 ). Thus, since W (st ) = a(st−1 ) + H(st ), we have that
Et−1 (Wt ) = a(st−1 ) + Et−1 (Ht ) and, then, an innovation to human wealth
5.2. THE PERMANENT INCOME HYPOTHESIS (PIH) 117
at t reduces to
W (st ) − Et−1 (Wt ) = H(st ) − Et−1 (Ht ) (5.21)
∞ τ
X 1
= [Et (yt+τ ) − Et−1 (Et (yt+τ ))]
τ =0
1+r
∞ τ
X 1
= (Et − Et−1 ) (yt+τ )
τ =0
1+r
since the law of iterated expectations implies that Et−1 (Et (yt+j )) = Et−1 (yt+j ).
Using (5.21) in (5.20) we obtain
∞ τ
r X 1
∆ct = (Et − Et−1 ) (yt+τ ) (5.22)
1 + r τ =0 1 + r
since both Et−1 (ut+τ ) = E(ut+τ ) = 0 and Et−1 (vt+τ ) = E(vt+τ ) = 0 for all
τ ≥ 0. Similarly, for any τ ≥ 0 we have that
i.e., the unexpected change in income yt is the sum of the permanent and
the transitory innovations at time t. For τ = 1 we have that
Now we complete our argument by induction. We argue that (Et − Et−1 ) (yt+τ +1 ) =
vt if (Et − Et−1 ) (yt+τ ) = vt for all τ ≥ 1. To see this, observe that
Then, our claim is true by induction since (Et − Et−1 ) (yt+1 ) = vt and,
thus, the forecast revision of individual income between t − 1 and t at any
period beyond t just equals the permanent innovation at time t, vt . Going
5.2. THE PERMANENT INCOME HYPOTHESIS (PIH) 119
2. For the general case (that is, without the assumption β(1 + r) = 1),
consumption should obey the regression
ct+1 = α0 + α1 ct + εt+1
3. The income realization in period yt+1 does affect ct+1 , but only that part
that is an unexpected change from income in period t. The component
of income yt+1 that is already predicable by yt or any other variable
that is in the period t information set should not affect consumption
in period t. Note that with complete markets not even unexpected
changes in individual income should affect consumption, since agents
can perfectly insure against these unexpected idiosyncratic changes.
1
a(st−1 ) = c(st ) − y(st ) + a(st ),
1+r
and thus rearranging, we obtain an expression for wealth changes
obtain
" ∞ τ #
X 1
∆at+1 = (1 + r)y(st ) + ra(st−1 ) − r a(st−1 ) + Et (yt+τ )
τ =0
1+r
∞ τ !
X 1
= (1 + r)y(st ) − ry(st ) − r Et (yt+τ ) .
τ =1
1+r
and thus
" ∞ #
X 1 1
∆at+1 = y(st ) − Et (yt+τ ) − Et (yt+τ ) (5.26)
τ =1
(1 + r)τ −1 (1 + r)τ
∞ τ −1 !
X 1
=− Et (∆yt+τ )
τ =1
1+r
This last expression has strong implications. For instance, suppose that
the individual income process follows a random walk, i.e. yt = yt−1 + εt ,
{εt } is an i.i.d. process with E(εt ) = 0. Then it is easy to see that ∆yt+τ =
εt+τ for all τ and, thus, (5.26) implies that ∆at+1 = 0 for all t. Therefore,
individual financial wealth is constant at the initial level (i.e. at = a0 for all
t) and, consequently, any properly chosen borrowing constraint will never be
binding. The reason for this result is that financial wealth changes only if
the individual is consuming just part of its income changes (and saving the
remaining part) in order to smooth consumption. With permanent shocks,
however, all income shock is consumed in every period since (5.18) reduces
to
r
c(st ) = a0 + y(st ).
1+r
However, this result depends on the assumption that the individual in-
come process follows a random walk. To see this, suppose instead that the
individual income process is i.i.d. and, thus, we have that ∆yt+1 = εt+1 − εt ,
122 CHAPTER 5. CONSUMPTION AND SAVINGS
This means that financial wealth follows a random walk, and since i.i.d shocks
compound with probability one, as a result we obtain that any constraint on
asset holding will be binding sooner or later.
To conclude, in this stylized setting whether ignoring borrowing con-
straint is troublesome or not depends on the specific individual income pro-
cess assumed. Thus, this result highlights the fact that borrowing constraint
cannot be simply ignored in general.
subject to
c0 + a1 = y0
c1 = Ra1 + ye1
c0 , c1 ≥ 0,
where y0 is initial income given at 0 and ye1 denotes next period random
income. Under the simplifying assumption βR = 1, the FOC implies that
The LHS in this expression is increasing in a1 since u00 < 0. On the other
hand, the RHS is decreasing for the same reason and, hence, a∗1 is uniquely
determined. Note that current consumption c0 is determined by
c0 = y0 − a∗1 .
and thus a1 (σε ) > a1 (0) to recover the equality at (5.30). Roughly speaking,
we can say that if u000 > 0, individual savings are increasing in the riskiness
of her individual income.
The convexity of the marginal utility (or u000 > 0) is called prudence and
refers to a property of preference, like risk aversion. Indeed, risk aversion
refers to the curvature of the utility function, whereas prudence refers to the
curvature of the marginal utility function. More precisely, Kimball (1990)
defines the index of absolute prudence as the ratio −u000 (.)/u00 (.), so in a
similar vein to the Arrow-Pratt index of absolute risk-aversion, −u00 (.)/u0 (.).
Conclusion 17 If the marginal utility is convex (or u000 > 0), then the risk
averse individual is prudent and, consequently, a rise in future income uncer-
tainty leads to a rise in current saving and a decline in current consumption.
It can be easily seen that any utility function with decreasing absolute
risk aversion (DARA class), which includes CRRA, displays positive third
5.3. PRECAUTIONARY SAVINGS: PRUDENCE AND BORROWING CONSTRAINTS125
derivative. To see this, let α(c) be the coefficient of absolute risk aversion.
Then,
u00 (c)
α(c) = − 0 , (5.31)
u (c)
and therefore
u000 (c)u0 (c) − [u00 (·)]2
α´(c) = −
[u0 (c)]2
With DARA α0 (c) < 0, then we have that
2
−u000 (c)u0 (c) + [u00 (·)] < 0,
and thus this implies that
[u00 (c)]2
u000 (c) > >0
u´(c)
Intuitively, a rise in uncertainty reduces the certainty equivalent for next
period income and, with DARA, this effectively increases the degree of risk-
aversion of the agent, which induces agents to save more (other things equal).
Prudence is a motive for additional saving in order to take precaution
against possible negative realizations of future income shocks. In this sense,
saving induced by prudence are called precautionary savings or self-insurance.
In this simple two-period partial equilibrium model, one can define precau-
tionary savings due to income uncertainty with variance σε , as the difference
between optimal asset holdings under uncertainty, a∗1 (σε ), and the optimal
asset holdings under certainty, a∗1 (0).7
Whenever Rβ > 1, there are other saving motives; i.e. intertemporal mo-
tives. In this case agents have incentives to postpone consumption and save
more since they are patient relative to the market. On the other hand, the
saving motive of the pure PIH with quadratic utility (i.e. uncertainty has ba-
sically no role) and Rβ = 1 (i.e. intertemporal motives are inactive) is called
smoothing motive. The agent wants to smooth consumption through income
shocks. That is why the saving motives just analyzed above are associated to
future income uncertainty and called precautionary or self-insurance motive.
Finally, in a life-cycle models individuals face a retirement period. Then, dur-
ing the working stage of their life-cycle, they would have a life-cycle motive
for savings associated to the desire of smoothing consumption.
7
It should be underscored that the term prudence characterizes preferences, whereas
precautionary saving characterizes agent’s optimal behavior: prudence leads to precau-
tionary saving, but both concepts should be kept separately.
126 CHAPTER 5. CONSUMPTION AND SAVINGS
subject to
c st
≥ 0, and a (s0 ) given,
T
a s = 0.
Note that since income process {yt } is i.i.d, we can define a sufficient
statistics for the agent’s choice problem, the so-called cash in hand, denoted
by w(st ) = y(st )+R a(st−1 ). This is so because (at , yt ) always enter additively
and, very importantly, the current levels of yt do not provide any information
about the future realization of income shocks since shocks are i.i.d. Hence
the agent’s problem can be reformulated as
T X
X
β t π(st ) u(c st ),
max
(c)
t=0 st
subject to
c st
≥ 0, and w (s0 ) given,
T
= c sT for all sT .
w s
5.3. PRECAUTIONARY SAVINGS: PRUDENCE AND BORROWING CONSTRAINTS127
= βR Et u0 yt+1 + R w st − c st
.
where
The first line is just the previous agent’s FOC’s when the constraint is not
binding. The second line descends directly from the reformulated budget
constraint
1
a(st ) = (y(st ) + a(st−1 ) − c(st )),
R
when the borrowing constraint is binding, i.e. a(st ) = 0. In this case, the
agent would like to borrow to finance current consumption further, but she
is not allowed to do so and so she must limit herself to consume as much as
she has at hand, all her resources.
Will this borrowing constraint be ever binding? For instance, suppose
that income is a random walk. Inspecting equation (5.27) we had concluded
above that financial wealth would follow a random walk, i.i.d shocks com-
pound with probability one and the non-negativity constraint on asset hold-
ing would be binding sooner or later.
Now notice that (5.32) can be reformulated as follows
c(st ) = Et (ct+τ +1 )
for all τ ≥ 0. Suppose that there exists some future period t + τ such that
for some realization of the income shock, st+τ , the borrowing constraint is
binding and thus y(st+τ ) + a(st+τ −1 ) < Et+τ (ct+τ +1 ). Since all probabilities
are positive, this implies that for any st+τ −1
Using this fact and the law of iterated expectations in equation (5.33), we can
conclude that c(st ) < Et (ct+τ +1 ). But this makes evident that even though
the liquidity constraint is not necessarily binding in period t, future potential
binding borrowing constraints affect current consumption.8
8
Thus, studies that provide support to the hypothesis that borrowing constraints are
not currently binding do not demonstrate that borrowing constraints are absent in general
or do not affect consumption decisions.
5.3. PRECAUTIONARY SAVINGS: PRUDENCE AND BORROWING CONSTRAINTS129
The previous analysis has shown how critical is to model debt limits. We
imposed an exogenous borrowing constraint like at+1 ≥ −A, where A > 0
is a parameter (in our previous case A = 0). Now we can move forward to
model a natural debt limit.
First suppose that the income process {yt }∞
t=0 is deterministic. Since
consumption is assumed bounded from below, in particular non-negative,
9
It is important to emphasize that even though we have showed these result for
quadratic utility, it is a general result that hold for concave utility functions.
130 CHAPTER 5. CONSUMPTION AND SAVINGS
This shows that the agent will have to consume zero with positive probability.
This cannot be an optimal choice since it is ruled out by the Inada condition
in that state. Thus, preferences by their own will insure that the natural
borrowing limit will never bind. Therefore, while you can safely assume
interior solutions if the natural debt limit is imposed, this is not true for
ad-hoc debt limits. Importantly, this makes evident that the peculiar case
studied above (see equation (5.27)) where financial wealth followed a random
walk (and, consequently, any finite borrowing limit would be violated with
probability one) draws heavily on the assumption of quadratic utility, where
the Inada condition is not satisfied.
Exercises
Exercise 18 (Wages and Consumption) A household solves
∞
X
max β t U (ct , lt )
{ct ,lt ,St }
t=0
lt + nt = 1
wt nt + (1 + r) St = ct + St+1
where nt is the labor supply, {wt } is a known sequence of wage rates, r is the
real and constant interest rate, St is savings, and S0 is given. The function
U is continuous, increasing, and strictly concave in both arguments. Con-
sumption and leisure are normal goods. Households maximize the discounted
present value of utility by choosing consumption and leisure.
(a) Set up the maximization problem and derive the first-order conditions
using the sequential approach. Demonstrate that optimal labor supply
can be expressed as a function:
nt = H(ct , wt ).
α1 ln ct + α2 ln lt .
Find the optimal consumption, savings, leisure, and labor supply ex-
pressed as a function of wages and past savings.
(d) Suppose that the wage rate follows a specific pattern: in even periods
let wt = wh and in odd periods wt = wl where wh > wl . Describe how
consumption, saving, and labor move over time.
Chapter 6
Overlapping Generation
Economies
133
134 CHAPTER 6. OVERLAPPING GENERATION ECONOMIES
for all t ∀t ≥ 1.
c = {b
A feasible allocation b c10 , (b
c1,1 , b
c2,1 ) , ..., (b
c1t , b
c2t+1 ) , ...} is PO if there
is no alternative feasible e
c such that
u (e c2t+1 ) ≥ u (b
c1t ) + βu (e c1t ) + βu (b
c2t+1 )
Suppose that each agent can buy and sell the consumption good in each
period at perfectly foreseen prices. Suppose that p1 = 1; i.e., the consumption
6.1. PURE EXCHANGE OLG ECONOMIES 135
subject to
pbt c1t + pbt+1 c2t+1 = pbt ω1t + pbt+1 ω2t+1
c10 = ω01 .
The initial old generation simply consumes b
OLG 2. Feasibility: for all t ≥ 1
Nt−1b
c2t + Ntbc1t = Nt−1 ω2t+1 + Nt ω1t
c2t ωt
⇐⇒ c1t = t−1 + ωtt
b
+b
1+n 1+n
Remark. Notice that an agent at date t is trading both ctt and ct+1 t (and
t t+1
also selling ωt and ωt ), given the price system. Also, we are not assuming
that agents in different generations are identical since both preferences and
endowments can be different. However, all agents in the same generation are
identical (ut and ωt are the same for all agents born at date t).
We analyze the agent t’s problem. Given p ∈ P, the constraint set is
compact, non-empty (i.e., it contains the endowment point) and the objective
function is continuous. Thus there exists a solution to the problem. Since
the utility function is strictly concave this solution is unique. Suppose for
simplicity that (ω1t , ω2t+1 ) = (ω1 , ω2 ) for all t and let c1t = c1 (pt , pt+1 ) and
c2t+1 = c2 (pt , pt+1 ) be the unique solution to the agent t’s problem. Since
demand functions are homogeneous of degree zero we can write them
pt+1
c1t = c1
p
t
pt+1
c2t+1 = c2
pt
136 CHAPTER 6. OVERLAPPING GENERATION ECONOMIES
where qt ≡ pt+1
pt
is the price of the consumption good t + 1 in terms of
1
consumption good t. So, qt ≡ 1+r t
where rt is the implicit interest rate.
c10 = ω01 ,
b
(b
c1t , b
c2t+1 ) = (ω1 , ω2 ) for all t
Proof. To see why, notice that since any agent in the initial old generation
only cares about goods dated at t = 1 and has only endowment at time t = 1,
then
c10 = ω01
b
Using market clearing for t = 1 gives
c10 + N1b
b c11 = ω01 + Nt ω1
and thus b c11 = ω1 . The budget constraint for agent t = 1 implies that
c22 = ω2 . The result follows by induction.
b
Equilibrium prices
We now describe the equilibrium price vector for this economy. Using the
previous proposition, and since the first order conditions are necessary and
sufficient for the agent maximization problem, it follows that
pt+1 u0 (ω2 )
qt = = 0
pt u (ω1 )
for all t (i.e., the budget set is tangent to the indifference curve evaluated at
the endowment point). Notice that these relative prices, qt , determine the
net interest rate, r, such that
pt+1 1
qt = = ,
pt 1+r
1
t
for all t. This implies that pt = 1+r for all t.
Offer Curves
6.1. PURE EXCHANGE OLG ECONOMIES 137
subject to
c1t + qt c2t+1 = ω1 + qt ω2 .
λt : Lagrange multiplier corresponding to agent t. Nec. and Suff. condi-
tions for an interior solution
u0 (c1t ) = λt , (6.1)
(ω1 − c1t )
qt = . (6.4)
(c2t+1 − ω2 )
Then, (6.2) and (6.1) coupled with (6.4) gives
Define excess demands for generation t when young (yt ) and old (zt )
yt = c1t − ω1 ,
zt = c2t+1 − ω2 .
subject to (1 + n) c1 + c2 = (1 + n) ω1 + ω2 .
µ: Lagrange multiplier for feasibility
u0 (c∗1 ) = µ (1 + n)
βu0 (c∗2 ) = µ
(1 + n) c1 + c2 = (1 + n) ω1 + ω2
And thus
βu0 (c∗2 ) 1
∗
=
u0 (c1 ) 1+n
Observe that we are NOT considering the IOG’s welfare. This will be
critical.
6.1. PURE EXCHANGE OLG ECONOMIES 139
such trades could be negotiated. Suppose that a young agent at time t could
sign a contract with a young agent at time t+1.Would there be an incentive
for the agents to enter into a contract? If the young agent would like to shift
some of his wealth forward to time t + 1, that would require that the young
agent at time t + 1 transfer some resources to the old generation at time t.
But what can the young agent at time t offer to a young agent at time t +
1? The young agent at time t is unable to transfer resources to period t + 2,
which is the time period that young agents born in period t+1 would like to
receive the resources.Hence, even if contingent claims among young agents at
time t and t +1 could be negotiated, no one would enter into these contracts.
Hence, the OLG model is not a model of incomplete markets, because these
markets exist, it is just that no one wishes to participate in them. Hence
for there to be any trading among different cohorts, there must be an outside
asset or some institution that clears the trades. A convenient outside asset
is nominal money.
6.2. OLG ECONOMIES WITH PRODUCTION 141
F (Kt ,Nt ) Kt
F is HOD 1, denote Nt
= F (Kt /Nt , 1) = f (kt ) where kt = Nt
and
subject to
c1t + st ≤ wt ,
c2t+1 ≤ (1 + rt+1 ) st ,
(c1t , c2t+1 ) ≥ 0.
The initial old generation owns k1 and then they consume c21 ≤ (1 + r1 ) k1 .
Also, note that generation t’s savings generate the stock of capital in t+1;
i.e., Nt st = Kt+1 . n o∞
Definition of a CE. A (Perfect Foresight) CE is an allocation b c21 , b
ct , b
kt ,
t=1
st }∞
savings{b t=1 and prices {w bt , rbt }∞
t=1 , such that
(1) Given {w bt , rbt+1 }, (b ct , sbt )solves
the agent t’s problem
and
bc21 = (1 + rb1 ) k1 .
0 b 0 b
(2) Given (w bt , rbt ) , rbt = f kt and w bt = f kt − kt f kt for all t.
b
(3) Market clearing conditions: For all t ≥ 1,
Nt f b kt = Nt−1b c2t + Ntb c1t + Kb t+1 − K
bt,
6.2. OLG ECONOMIES WITH PRODUCTION 143
K
b t+1 = Nt sbt .
Characterize the agent’s problem
Write the agent’s problem as
max u (wt − st ) + βu ((1 + rt+1 ) st ) .
0≤st ≤wt
Interior solution
st : u0 (wt − st ) = 1 + rt+1 βu0 ((1 + rt+1 ) st )
Apply the implicit function theorem (IFT) and write st = s(wt , rt+1 ).
Note that given (wt , rt+1 ), all generations have the same saving function
(i.e., it is time-invariant).
Let
1 + rt+1 0
G (st , wt , rt+1 ) = u0 (wt − st ) − u ((1 + rt+1 ) st )
1+θ
∂G
= −u00 (wt − st ) − (1 + rt+1 )2 βu00 ((1 + rt+1 ) st ) > 0,
∂st
∂G
= −β[u0 ((1 + rt+1 ) st )
∂rt+1
00
+ (1 + rt+1 ) st u ((1 + rt+1 )) R 0,
∂G
= u00 (wt − st ) < 0.
∂wt
IFT
∂s(wt , rt+1 )
sw =
∂wt
00
−u (wt − st )
= ∈ (0, 1)
−u (wt − st ) − (1 + rt+1 )2 βu00 ((1 + rt+1 ) st )
00
∂s(wt , rt+1 )
sr = =
∂rt+1
βu0 (·) [1 + (1 + rt+1 ) st u00 (·) /u0 (·)]
R0
−u00 (·) − (1 + rt+1 )2 βu00 (·)
sw ∈ (0, 1): both consumption goods are normal; i.e., any change in wt
has just an income effect.
A change in rt+1 has both income and substitution effect and then its
impact depends upon the IES.
144 CHAPTER 6. OVERLAPPING GENERATION ECONOMIES
Define
s (f (kt ) − kt f 0 (kt ) , f 0 (kt+1 ))
H (kt+1 , kt ) = kt+1 − ,
(1 + n)
dkt+1 sw f 00 (kt ) kt
=− R 0.
dkt (1 + n) − sr f 00 (kt )
dkt+1
dkt
> 0 if sr > 0.
General structure: we can say nothing about relation between kt+1 and
kt .
At steady state, kt+1 = kt = k ∗ for all t.
Some cases found interesting.
A steady state k ∗ is locally stable if
sw f 00 (k ∗ ) k ∗
− < 1.
(1 + n) − sr f 00 (k ∗ )
kt+1 ≈ g (k ∗ ) + g 0 (k ∗ ) (kt − k ∗ )
where
sw f 00 (k ∗ ) k ∗
g 0 (k ∗ ) = −
(1 + n) − sr f 00 (k ∗ )
Thus, g 0 (k ∗ ) will be the characteristic root of the 1st. order linear differ-
ence equation.
6.2. OLG ECONOMIES WITH PRODUCTION 145
[2] Arrow, Kenneth J., 1964. “The Role of Securities in the Optimal Alloca-
tion of Risk-Bearing,” Review of Economic Studies, Vol. 31, pp. 91–96.
[7] Brock, William A., and Leonard Mirman, 1972. “Optimal Economic
Growth and Uncertainty: The Discounted Case,” Journal of Economic
Theory, Vol. 4(3), pp. 479–513.
[10] Cooley, Thomas F., 1995. Frontiers of Business Cycle Research. Prince-
ton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
147
148 BIBLIOGRAPHY
[18] Kimball, Miles S. (1990). “Precautionary Saving in the Small and in the
Large,” Econometrica, 58, pp 53–73.
[19] Kydland, Finn E., and Edward C. Prescott (1977). “Rules Rather than
Discretion: The Inconsistency of Optimal Plans.” Journal of Political
Economy, Vol. 85(3), pp. 473–491.
[23]
BIBLIOGRAPHY 149
[31] Weil, P. (1989). “The Equity Premium Puzzle and the Riskfree Rate
Puzzle.” Journal of Monetary Economics 24, 401–421.