Cantor's First Set Theory Article
Cantor's First Set Theory Article
Cantor's first set theory article contains Georg Cantor's first theorems of transfinite
set theory, which studies infinite sets and their properties. One of these theorems is his
"revolutionary discovery" that the set of all real numbers is uncountably, rather than
countably, infinite.[1] This theorem is proved using Cantor's first uncountability
proof, which differs from the more familiar proof using his diagonal argument. The
title of the article, "On a Property of the Collection of All Real Algebraic Numbers"
("Ueber eine Eigenschaft des Inbegriffes aller reellen algebraischen Zahlen"), refers to
its first theorem: the set of real algebraic numbers is countable. Cantor's article was
published in 1874. In 1879, he modified his uncountability proof by using the
topological notion of a set being dense in an interval.
Cantor's article also contains a proof of the existence of transcendental numbers. Both
constructive and non-constructive proofs have been presented as "Cantor's proof." The
popularity of presenting a non-constructive proof has led to a misconception that
Cantor's arguments are non-constructive. Since the proof that Cantor published either
constructs transcendental numbers or does not, an analysis of his article can determine
whether or not this proof is constructive.[2] Cantor's correspondence with Richard
Dedekind shows the development of his ideas and reveals that he had a choice between Georg Cantor, c. 1870
two proofs: a non-constructive proof that uses the uncountability of the real numbers
and a constructive proof that does not use uncountability.
Historians of mathematics have examined Cantor's article and the circumstances in which it was written. For example, they
have discovered that Cantor was advised to leave out his uncountability theorem in the article he submitted — he added it
during proofreading. They have traced this and other facts about the article to the influence of Karl Weierstrass and Leopold
Kronecker. Historians have also studied Dedekind's contributions to the article, including his contributions to the theorem on
the countability of the real algebraic numbers. In addition, they have recognized the role played by the uncountability theorem
and the concept of countability in the development of set theory, measure theory, and the Lebesgue integral.
The article
Cantor's article is short, less than four and a half pages.[A] It begins with a discussion of the real algebraic numbers and a
statement of his first theorem: The set of real algebraic numbers can be put into one-to-one correspondence with the set of
positive integers.[3] Cantor restates this theorem in terms more familiar to mathematicians of his time: "The set of real
algebraic numbers can be written as an infinite sequence in which each number appears only once."[4]
Cantor's second theorem works with a closed interval [a, b], which is the set of real numbers ≥ a and ≤ b. The theorem states:
Given any sequence of real numbers x1, x2, x3, ... and any interval [a, b], there is a number in [a, b] that is not contained in the
given sequence. Hence, there are infinitely many such numbers.[5]
Cantor observes that combining his two theorems yields a new proof of Liouville's theorem that every interval [a, b] contains
infinitely many transcendental numbers.[5]
the reason why collections of real numbers forming a so-called continuum (such as, all real numbers which are ≥ 0
and ≤ 1) cannot correspond one-to-one with the collection (ν) [the collection of all positive integers]; thus I have
found the clear difference between a so-called continuum and a collection like the totality of real algebraic
numbers.[6]
This remark contains Cantor's uncountability theorem, which only states that an interval [a, b] cannot be put into one-to-one
correspondence with the set of positive integers. It does not state that this interval is an infinite set of larger cardinality than
the set of positive integers. Cardinality is defined in Cantor's next article, which was published in 1878.[7]
Cantor only states his uncountability theorem. He does not use it in any proofs.[3]
The proofs
First theorem
To prove that the set of real algebraic numbers is countable, define the height of a
polynomial of degree n with integer coefficients as: n − 1 + |a0| + |a1| + ... + |an|, where
a0, a1, ..., an are the coefficients of the polynomial. Order the polynomials by their
height, and order the real roots of polynomials of the same height by numeric order.
Since there are only a finite number of roots of polynomials of a given height, these
orderings put the real algebraic numbers into a sequence. Cantor went a step further
and produced a sequence in which each real algebraic number appears just once. He Algebraic numbers on the complex
did this by only using polynomials that are irreducible over the integers. The following plane colored by polynomial degree.
table contains the beginning of Cantor's enumeration.[9] (red = 1, green = 2, blue = 3,
yellow = 4). Points become smaller
as the integer polynomial
coefficients become larger.
Cantor's enumeration of the real algebraic numbers
x1 = 0 x 1
x2 = −1 x+1 2
x3 = 1 x−1 2
x4 = −2 x+2 3
1
x5 = −2 2x + 1 3
1
x6 = 2 2x − 1 3
x7 = 2 x−2 3
x8 = −3 x+3 4
−1 − √5
x9 = 2
x2 + x − 1 4
x10 = −√ 2 x2 − 2 4
1
x11 = −√2 2x2 − 1 4
1 − √5
x12 = 2 x2 − x − 1 4
1
x13 = −3 3x + 1 4
1
x14 = 3 3x − 1 4
−1 + √5
x15 = 2
x2 + x − 1 4
1
x16 = √2 2x2 − 1 4
x17 = √ 2 x2 − 2 4
1 + √5
x18 = 2 x2 − x − 1 4
x19 = 3 x−3 4
Second theorem
Only the first part of Cantor's second theorem needs to be proved. It states: Given any sequence of real numbers x1, x2, x3, ...
and any interval [a, b], there is a number in [a, b] that is not contained in the given sequence.[B]
To find a number in [a, b] that is not contained in the given sequence, construct two sequences of real numbers as follows:
Find the first two numbers of the given sequence that are in the open interval (a, b). Denote the smaller of these two numbers
by a1 and the larger by b1. Similarly, find the first two numbers of the given sequence that are in (a1, b1). Denote the smaller
by a2 and the larger by b2. Continuing this procedure generates a sequence of intervals (a1, b1), (a2, b2), (a3, b3), ... such that
each interval in the sequence contains all succeeding intervals — that is, it generates a sequence of nested intervals. This
implies that the sequence a1, a2, a3, ... is increasing and the sequence b1, b2, b3, ... is decreasing.[10]
Either the number of intervals generated is finite or infinite. If finite, let (aL, bL) be the last interval. If infinite, take the limits
a∞ = limn → ∞ an and b∞ = limn → ∞ bn. Since an < bn for all n, either a∞ = b∞ or a∞ < b∞. Thus, there are three cases to
consider:
Case 1: There is a last interval (aL, bL). Since at most one xn can be in this interval, every y in this interval
except xn (if it exists) is not in the given sequence.
Case 2: a∞ = b∞. Then a∞ is not in the sequence since for all n : a∞ is in the interval (an, bn) but xn does not
belong to (an, bn). In symbols: a∞ ∈ (an, bn) but xn ∉ (an, bn).
Proof that for all n : xn ∉ (an, bn)
The proof is complete since, in all cases, at least one real number Case 3: a∞ < b∞
in [a, b] has been found that is not contained in the given
sequence.[D]
Cantor's proofs are constructive and have been used to write a computer program that generates the digits of a transcendental
number. This program applies Cantor's construction to a sequence containing all the real algebraic numbers between 0 and 1.
The article that discusses this program gives some of its output, which shows how the construction generates a
transcendental.[12]
Since the sequence contains all the rational numbers in (0, 1), the construction generates an irrational number, which turns out
to be √2 − 1.[14]
Proof that the number generated is √ 2 − 1
The proof uses Farey sequences and simple continued fractions. The Farey sequence is the increasing sequence of completely
reduced fractions whose denominators are If and are adjacent in a Farey sequence, the lowest denominator fraction
[15]
between them is their mediant This mediant is adjacent to both and in the Farey sequence
Cantor's construction produces mediants because the rational numbers were sequenced by increasing
denominator. The first interval in the table is Since and are adjacent in their mediant is the
first fraction in the sequence between and Hence, In this inequality, has the smallest
denominator, so the second fraction is the mediant of and which equals This implies:
We will prove that the endpoints of the intervals converge to the continued fraction This continued
fraction is the limit of its convergents:
First, we prove by induction that for odd n, the n-th interval in the table is:
Assume that the inductive hypothesis is true for the k-th interval. If k is odd, this interval is:
The mediant of its endpoints is the first fraction in the sequence between these
endpoints.
Hence,
In this inequality, has the smallest denominator, so the second fraction is the mediant of and
which equals
This implies:
true for the (k + 1)-st interval. For even k, the proof is similar. This completes the inductive proof.
Since the right endpoints of the intervals are decreasing and every other endpoint is their limit equals
The left endpoints have the same limit because they are increasing and every other endpoint is
As mentioned above, this limit is the continued fraction which equals [17]
Everywhere dense
In 1879, Cantor published a new uncountability proof that modifies his 1874 proof. He first defines the topological notion of a
point set P being "everywhere dense in an interval":[E]
If P lies partially or completely in the interval [α, β], then the remarkable case can happen that every interval
[γ, δ] contained in [α, β], no matter how small, contains points of P. In such a case, we will say that P is
everywhere dense in the interval [α, β].[F]
In this discussion of Cantor's proof: a, b, c, d are used instead of α, β, γ, δ. Also, Cantor only uses his interval notation if the
first endpoint is less than the second. For this discussion, this means that (a, b) implies a < b.
Since the discussion of Cantor's 1874 proof was simplified by using open intervals rather than closed intervals, the same
simplification is used here. This requires an equivalent definition of everywhere dense: A set P is everywhere dense in the
interval [a, b] if and only if every open subinterval (c, d) of [a, b] contains at least one point of P.[18]
Cantor did not specify how many points of P an open subinterval (c, d) must contain. He did not need to specify this because
the assumption that every open subinterval contains at least one point of P implies that every open subinterval contains
infinitely many points of P.[G]
In the first case, P is not dense in [a, b]. By definition, P is dense in [a, b] if and only if for all subintervals (c, d) of [a, b],
there is an x ∈ P such that x ∈ (c, d). Taking the negation of each side of the "if and only if" produces: P is not dense in [a, b]
if and only if there exists a subinterval (c, d) of [a, b] such that for all x ∈ P : x ∉ (c, d). Therefore, every number in (c, d) is
not contained in the sequence P.[proof 1] This case handles case 1 and case 3 of Cantor's 1874 proof.
In the second case, which handles case 2 of Cantor's 1874 proof, P is dense in [a, b]. The denseness of sequence P is used to
recursively define a sequence of nested intervals that excludes all the numbers in P and whose intersection contains a single
real number in [a, b]. The sequence of intervals starts with (a, b). Given an interval in the sequence, the next interval is
obtained by finding the two numbers with the least indices that belong to P and to the current interval. These two numbers are
the endpoints of the next open interval. Since an open interval excludes its endpoints, every nested interval eliminates two
numbers from the front of sequence P, which implies that the intersection of the nested intervals excludes all the numbers in
P.[proof 1] Details of this proof and a proof that this intersection contains a single real number in [a, b] are given below.
Definition and proofs for the nested intervals
The denseness of sequence P is used to recursively define a nested sequence of intervals that excludes all of the numbers in P. The
base case starts with the interval (a, b). Since P is dense in [a, b], there are infinitely many numbers of P in (a, b). Let xk be the
1
number with the least index and xk be the number with the next larger index, and let a1 be the smaller and b1 be the larger of these
2
two numbers. Then, k1 < k2, a < a1 < b1 < b, and (a1, b1) is a proper subinterval of (a, b). Also, xm ∉ (a1, b1) for m ≤ k2 since these
xm are the endpoints of (a1, b1). Repeating the above proof with the interval (a1, b1) produces k3, k4, a2, b2 such that
k1 < k2 < k3 < k4 and a < a1 < a2 < b2 < b1 < b and xm ∉ (a2, b2) for m ≤ k4.[proof 1]
The recursive step starts with the interval (an–1, bn–1), the inequalities k1 < k2 < . . . < k2n–2 < k2n–1 and
a < a1 < . . . < an–1 < bn–1 . . . < b1 < b, and the fact that the interval (an–1, bn–1) excludes the first 2n –2
members of the sequence P — that is, xm ∉ (an–1, bn–1) for m ≤ k2n–2. Since P is dense in [a, b], there are
infinitely many numbers of P in (an–1, bn–1). Let xk2n –1 be the number with the least index and xk2n be the
number with the next larger index, and let an be the smaller and bn be the larger of these two numbers. Then,
k2n –1 < k2n, an–1 < an < bn < bn–1, and (an, bn) is a proper subinterval of (an–1, bn–1). Combining these
inequalities with the ones for step n –1 of the recursion produces k1 < k2 < . . . < k2n–1 < k2n and
a < a1 < . . . < an < bn . . . < b1 < b. Also, xm ∉ (an, bn) for m = k2n–1 and m = k2n since these xm are the
endpoints of (an, bn). This together with (an–1, bn–1) excluding the first 2n –2 members of sequence P implies
that the interval (an, bn) excludes the first 2n members of P — that is, xm ∉ (an, bn) for m ≤ k2n. Therefore, for
all n, xn ∉ (an, bn) since n ≤ k2n.[proof 1]
The sequence an is increasing and bounded above by b, so the limit A = limn → ∞ an exists. Similarly, the limit
B = limn → ∞ bn exists since the sequence bn is decreasing and bounded below by a. Also, an < bn implies
A ≤ B. If A < B, then for every n: xn ∉ (A, B) because xn is not in the larger interval (an, bn). This contradicts P
being dense in [a, b]. Hence, A = B. For all n, A ∈ (an, bn) but xn ∉ (an, bn). Therefore, A is a number in [a, b]
that is not contained in P.[proof 1]
Dedekind replied that he was unable to answer Cantor's question, and said that it "did not deserve too much effort because it
has no particular practical interest". Dedekind also sent Cantor a proof that the set of algebraic numbers is countable.[20]
On December 2, Cantor responded that his question does have interest: "It would be nice if it could be answered; for example,
provided that it could be answered no, one would have a new proof of Liouville's theorem that there are transcendental
numbers."[21]
On December 7, Cantor sent Dedekind a proof by contradiction that the set of real numbers is uncountable. Cantor starts by
assuming that the real numbers in can be written as a sequence. Then, he applies a construction to this sequence to
produce a number in that is not in the sequence, thus contradicting his assumption.[22] Together, the letters of December
2 and 7 provide a non-constructive proof of the existence of transcendental numbers.[23] Also, the proof in Cantor's December
7 letter shows some of the reasoning that led to his discovery that the real numbers form an uncountable set.[24]
Cantor's December 7, 1873 proof
The proof is by contradiction and starts by assuming that the real numbers in can be written as a
sequence:
An increasing sequence is extracted from this sequence by letting the first term the next largest
term following the next largest term following and so forth. The same procedure is applied to the
remaining members of the original sequence to extract another increasing sequence. By continuing this
process of extracting sequences, one sees that the sequence can be decomposed into the infinitely many
sequences:[22]
Let be an interval such that no term of sequence (1) lies in it. For example, let and satisfy
Then for so no term of sequence (1) lies in [22]
Now consider whether the terms of the other sequences lie outside All terms of some of these
sequences may lie outside of however, there must be some sequence such that not all its terms lie
outside Otherwise, the numbers in would not be contained in sequence contrary to the initial
hypothesis. Let sequence be the first sequence that contains a term in and let be the first term.
Since let and satisfy Then is a proper superset of (in
symbols, ). Also, the terms of sequences lie outside of [22]
Repeat the above argument starting with Let sequence be the first sequence containing a term in
and let be the first term. Since let and satisfy Then
and the terms of sequences lie outside of [22]
Since and are bounded monotonic sequences, the limits and exist. Also, for all
implies Hence, there is at least one number in that lies in all the intervals
and Namely, can be any number in This implies that lies outside all the
sequences contradicting the initial hypothesis that sequence contains all the real numbers
in Therefore, the set of all real numbers is uncountable.[22]
Dedekind received Cantor's proof on December 8. On that same day, Dedekind simplified the proof and mailed his proof to
Cantor. Cantor used Dedekind's proof in his article.[25] The letter containing Cantor's December 7 proof was not published
until 1937.[26]
On December 9, Cantor announced the theorem that allowed him to construct transcendental numbers as well as prove the
uncountability of the set of real numbers:
This is the second theorem in Cantor's article. It comes from realizing that his construction can be applied to any sequence, not
just to sequences that supposedly enumerate the real numbers. So Cantor had a choice between two proofs that demonstrate
the existence of transcendental numbers: one proof is constructive, but the other is not. These two proofs can be compared by
starting with a sequence consisting of all the real algebraic numbers.
The constructive proof applies Cantor's construction to this sequence and the interval [a, b] to produce a transcendental
number in this interval.[5]
1. The proof by contradiction used to prove the uncountability theorem (see Proof of Cantor's uncountability
theorem).
2. The proof by contradiction used to prove the existence of transcendental numbers from the countability of the
real algebraic numbers and the uncountability of real numbers. Cantor's December 2nd letter mentions this
existence proof but does not contain it. Here is a proof: Assume that there are no transcendental numbers in
[a, b]. Then all the numbers in [a, b] are algebraic. This implies that they form a subsequence of the sequence
of all real algebraic numbers, which contradicts Cantor's uncountability theorem. Thus, the assumption that
there are no transcendental numbers in [a, b] is false. Therefore, there is a transcendental number in [a, b].[H]
Cantor chose to publish the constructive proof, which not only produces a transcendental number but is also shorter and
avoids two proofs by contradiction. The non-constructive proof from Cantor's correspondence is simpler than the one above
because it works with all the real numbers rather than the interval [a, b]. This eliminates the subsequence step and all
occurrences of [a, b] in the second proof by contradiction.[5]
Cantor's published proof and the reverse-order proof both use the theorem: Given a sequence of reals, a real can be found that
is not in the sequence. By applying this theorem to the sequence of real algebraic numbers, Cantor produced a transcendental
number. He then proved that the reals are uncountable: Assume that there is a sequence containing all the reals. Applying the
theorem to this sequence produces a real not in the sequence, contradicting the assumption that the sequence contains all the
reals. Hence, the reals are uncountable.[5] The reverse-order proof starts by first proving the reals are uncountable. It then
proves that transcendental numbers exist: If there were no transcendental numbers, all the reals would be algebraic and hence
countable, which contradicts what was just proved. This contradiction proves that transcendental numbers exist without
constructing any.[29]
Cantor's diagonal argument has often replaced his 1874 construction in expositions of his
proof. The diagonal argument is constructive and produces a more efficient computer
program than his 1874 construction. Using it, a computer program has been written that
computes the digits of a transcendental number in polynomial time. The program that uses
Cantor's 1874 construction requires at least sub-exponential time.[35][K]
Asserting that Cantor gave a non-constructive argument without mentioning the constructive proof he published can lead to
erroneous statements about the history of mathematics. In A Survey of Modern Algebra, Birkhoff and Mac Lane state:
"Cantor's argument for this result [Not every real number is algebraic] was at first rejected by many mathematicians, since it
did not exhibit any specific transcendental number."[39] The proof that Cantor published produces transcendental numbers, and
there appears to be no evidence that his argument was rejected. Even Leopold Kronecker, who had strict views on what is
acceptable in mathematics and who could have delayed publication of Cantor's article, did not delay it.[4] In fact, applying
Cantor's construction to the sequence of real algebraic numbers produces a limiting process that Kronecker accepted—namely,
it determines a number to any required degree of accuracy.[M]
From his correspondence, it appears that Cantor only discussed his article with Weierstrass. However, Cantor told Dedekind:
"The restriction which I have imposed on the published version of my investigations is caused in part by local circumstances
..."[46] Cantor biographer Joseph Dauben believes that "local circumstances" refers to Kronecker who, as a member of the
editorial board of Crelle's Journal, had delayed publication of an 1870 article by Eduard Heine, one of Cantor's colleagues.
Cantor would submit his article to Crelle's Journal.[48]
Weierstrass advised Cantor to leave his uncountability theorem out of the article he
submitted, but Weierstrass also told Cantor that he could add it as a marginal note during
proofreading, which he did.[43] It appears in a remark at the end of the article's
introduction. The opinions of Kronecker and Weierstrass both played a role here.
Kronecker did not accept infinite sets, and it seems that Weierstrass did not accept that two
infinite sets could be so different, with one being countable and the other not.[49]
Weierstrass changed his opinion later.[50] Without the uncountability theorem, the article
needed a title that did not refer to this theorem. Cantor chose "Ueber eine Eigenschaft des
Inbegriffes aller reellen algebraischen Zahlen" ("On a Property of the Collection of All
Real Algebraic Numbers"), which refers to the countability of the set of real algebraic
numbers, the result that Weierstrass found useful.[51]
Kronecker's influence appears in the proof of Cantor's second theorem. Cantor used
Dedekind's version of the proof except he left out why the limits a∞ = limn → ∞ an and Leopold Kronecker, 1865
b∞ = limn → ∞ bn exist. Dedekind had used his "principle of continuity" to prove they
exist. This principle (which is equivalent to the least upper bound property of the real
numbers) comes from Dedekind's construction of the real numbers, a construction Kronecker did not accept.[52]
Cantor restricted his first theorem to the set of real algebraic numbers even though Dedekind had sent him a proof that handled
all algebraic numbers.[20] Cantor did this for expository reasons and because of "local circumstances".[53] This restriction
simplifies the article because the second theorem works with real sequences. Hence, the construction in the second theorem
can be applied directly to the enumeration of the real algebraic numbers to produce "an effective procedure for the calculation
of transcendental numbers". This procedure would be acceptable to Weierstrass.[54]
Dedekind's first contribution concerns the theorem that the set of real algebraic numbers is
countable. Cantor is usually given credit for this theorem, but the mathematical historian
José Ferreirós calls it "Dedekind's theorem." Their correspondence reveals what each
mathematician contributed to the theorem.[56]
In his letter introducing the concept of countability, Cantor stated without proof that the
set of positive rational numbers is countable, as are sets of the form (an1, n2, ..., nν) where
n1, n2, ..., nν, and ν are positive integers.[57] Cantor's second result uses an indexed family
Richard Dedekind, c. 1870
of numbers: a set of the form (an1, n2, ..., nν) is the range of a function from the ν indices to
n1
the set of real numbers. His second result implies his first: let ν = 2 and an , n = n . The
1 2 2
n1 1 n4
function can be quite general—for example, an , n , n , n , n = (n )n3 + tan(n ).
1 2 3 4 5 2 5
Dedekind replied with a proof of the theorem that the set of all algebraic numbers is countable.[20] In his reply to Dedekind,
Cantor did not claim to have proved Dedekind's result. He did indicate how he proved his theorem about indexed families of
numbers: "Your proof that (n) [the set of positive integers] can be correlated one-to-one with the field of all algebraic numbers
is approximately the same as the way I prove my contention in the last letter. I take n12 + n22 + ··· + nν2 = and order the
elements accordingly." [58] However, Cantor's ordering is weaker than Dedekind's and cannot be extended to -tuples of
integers that include zeros.[59]
Dedekind's second contribution is his proof of Cantor's second theorem. Dedekind sent this proof in reply to Cantor's letter
that contained the uncountability theorem, which Cantor proved using infinitely many sequences. Cantor next wrote that he
had found a simpler proof that did not use infinitely many sequences.[60] So Cantor had a choice of proofs and chose to
publish Dedekind's.[61]
Cantor thanked Dedekind privately for his help: "... your comments (which I value highly) and your manner of putting some
of the points were of great assistance to me."[46] However, he did not mention Dedekind's help in his article. In previous
articles, he had acknowledged help received from Kronecker, Weierstrass, Heine, and Hermann Schwarz. Cantor's failure to
mention Dedekind's contributions damaged his relationship with Dedekind. Dedekind stopped replying to his letters and did
not resume the correspondence until October 1876.[62][N]
In 1883, Cantor extended the positive integers with his infinite ordinals. This extension was necessary for his work on the
Cantor–Bendixson theorem. Cantor discovered other uses for the ordinals—for example, he used sets of ordinals to produce
an infinity of sets having different infinite cardinalities.[65] His work on infinite sets together with Dedekind's set-theoretical
work created set theory.[66]
The concept of countability led to countable operations and objects that are used in various areas of mathematics. For
example, in 1878, Cantor introduced countable unions of sets.[67] In the 1890s, Émile Borel used countable unions in his
theory of measure, and René Baire used countable ordinals to define his classes of functions.[68] Building on the work of
Borel and Baire, Henri Lebesgue created his theories of measure and integration, which were published from 1899 to 1901.[69]
Countable models are used in set theory. In 1922, Thoralf Skolem proved that if conventional axioms of set theory are
consistent, then they have a countable model. Since this model is countable, its set of real numbers is countable. This
consequence is called Skolem's paradox, and Skolem explained why it does not contradict Cantor's uncountability theorem:
although there is a one-to-one correspondence between this set and the set of positive integers, no such one-to-one
correspondence is a member of the model. Thus the model considers its set of real numbers to be uncountable, or more
precisely, the first-order sentence that says the set of real numbers is uncountable is true within the model.[70] In 1963, Paul
Cohen used countable models to prove his independence theorems.[71]
See also
Cantor's theorem
Notes
A. In letter to Dedekind dated December 25, 1873, Cantor states that he has written and submitted "a short
paper" titled On a Property of the Set of All Real Algebraic Numbers. (Noether & Cavaillès 1937, p. 17; English
translation: Ewald 1996, p. 847.)
B. This implies the rest of the theorem — namely, there are infinitely many numbers in [a, b] that are not contained
in the given sequence. For example, let be the interval and consider its subintervals
Since these subintervals are pairwise disjoint, applying the first part of the theorem to each
subinterval produces infinitely many numbers in that are not contained in the given sequence. In general,
for the interval apply the first part of the theorem to the subintervals
C. Cantor does not prove this lemma. In a footnote for case 2, he states that xn does not lie in the interior of the
interval [an, bn].[11] This proof comes from his 1879 proof, which contains a more complex inductive proof that
demonstrates several properties of the intervals generated, including the property proved here.
D. The main difference between Cantor's proof and the above proof is that he generates the sequence of closed
intervals [an, bn]. To find an + 1 and bn + 1, he uses the interior of the interval [an, bn], which is the open interval
(an, bn). Generating open intervals combines Cantor's use of closed intervals and their interiors, which allows
the case diagrams to depict all the details of the proof.
E. Cantor was not the first to define "everywhere dense" but his terminology was adopted with or without the
"everywhere" (everywhere dense: Arkhangel'skii & Fedorchuk 1990, p. 15; dense: Kelley 1991, p. 49). In 1870,
Hermann Hankel had defined this concept using different terminology: "a multitude of points ... fill the segment
if no interval, however small, can be given within the segment in which one does not find at least one point of
that multitude" (Ferreirós 2007, p. 155). Hankel was building on Peter Gustav Lejeune Dirichlet's 1829 article
that contains the Dirichlet function, a non-(Riemann) integrable function whose value is 0 for rational numbers
and 1 for irrational numbers. (Ferreirós 2007, p. 149.)
F. Translated from Cantor 1879, p. 2: Liegt P theilweise oder ganz im Intervalle (α . . . β), so kann der
bemerkenswerthe Fall eintreten, dass jedes noch so kleine in (α . . . β) enthaltene Intervall (γ . . . δ) Punkte von
P enthält. In einem solchen Falle wollen wir sagen, dass P im Intervalle (α . . . β) überall-dicht sei.
G. This is proved by generating a sequence of points belonging to both P and (c, d). Since P is dense in [a, b], the
subinterval (c, d) contains at least one point x1 of P. By assumption, the subinterval (x1, d) contains at least
one point x2 of P and x2 > x1 since x2 belongs to this subinterval. In general, after generating xn, the
subinterval (xn, d) is used to generate a point xn + 1 satisfying xn + 1 > xn. The infinitely many points xn belong to
both P and (c, d).
H. The beginning of this proof is derived from the proof below by restricting its numbers to the interval [a, b] and
by using a subsequence since Cantor was using sequences in his 1873 work on countability.
German text: Satz 68. Es gibt transzendente Zahlen.
Gäbe es nämlich keine transzendenten Zahlen, so wären alle Zahlen algebraisch, das Kontinuum also
identisch mit der Menge aller algebraischen Zahlen. Das ist aber unmöglich, weil die Menge aller
algebraischen Zahlen abzählbar ist, das Kontinuum aber nicht.[28]
Translation: Theorem 68. There are transcendental numbers.
If there were no transcendental numbers, then all numbers would be algebraic. Hence, the continuum would be
identical to the set of all algebraic numbers. However, this is impossible because the set of all algebraic
numbers is countable, but the continuum is not.
I. By "Cantor's proof," Perron does not mean that it is a proof published by Cantor. Rather, he means that the
proof only uses arguments that Cantor published. For example, to obtain a real not in a given sequence,
Perron follows Cantor's 1874 proof except for one modification: he uses Cantor's 1891 diagonal argument
instead of his 1874 nested intervals argument to obtain a real. Cantor never used his diagonal argument to
reprove his theorem. In this case, both Cantor's proof and Perron's proof are constructive, so no misconception
can arise here. Then, Perron modifies Cantor's proof of the existence of a transcendental by giving the reverse-
order proof. This converts Cantor's 1874 constructive proof into a non-constructive proof which leads to the
misconception about Cantor's work.
J. This proof is the same as Cantor's 1874 proof except for one modification: it uses his 1891 diagonal argument
instead of his 1874 nested intervals argument to obtain a real.
K. The program using the diagonal method produces digits in steps, while the program
using the 1874 method requires at least steps to produce digits. (Gray 1994, pp. 822–823.)
L. Starting with Hardy and Wright's book, these books are linked to Perron's book via their bibliographies:
Perron's book is mentioned in the bibliography of Hardy and Wright's book, which in turn is mentioned in the
bibliography of Birkhoff and Mac Lane's book and in the bibliography of Spivak's book. (Hardy & Wright 1938,
p. 400; Birkhoff & Mac Lane 1941, p. 441; Spivak 1967, p. 515.)
M. Kronecker's opinion was: "Definitions must contain the means of reaching a decision in a finite number of
steps, and existence proofs must be conducted so that the quantity in question can be calculated with any
required degree of accuracy."[40] So Kronecker would accept Cantor's argument as a valid existence proof, but
he would not accept its conclusion that transcendental numbers exist. For Kronecker, they do not exist
because their definition contains no means for deciding in a finite number of steps whether or not a given
number is transcendental.[41] Cantor's 1874 construction calculates numbers to any required degree of
1
accuracy because: Given a k, an n can be computed such that bn – an ≤ k where (an, bn) is the n-th interval of
Cantor's construction. An example of how to prove this is given in Gray 1994, p. 822. Cantor's diagonal
argument provides an accuracy of 10−n after n real algebraic numbers have been calculated because each of
these numbers generates one digit of the transcendental number.[42]
N. Ferreirós has analyzed the relations between Cantor and Dedekind. He explains why "Relations between both
mathematicians were difficult after 1874, when they underwent an interruption..." (Ferreirós 1993, pp. 344,
348–352.)
O. Cantor's method of constructing a one-to-one correspondence between the set of irrational numbers and R can
be used to construct one between the set of transcendental numbers and R.[64] The construction begins with
e
the set of transcendental numbers T and removes a countable subset {tn} (for example, tn = n ). Let this set be
T0. Then T = T0 ∪ {tn} = T0 ∪ {t2n – 1} ∪ {t2n}, and R = T ∪ {an} = T0 ∪ {tn} ∪ {an} where an is the sequence of
real algebraic numbers. So both T and R are the union of three pairwise disjoint sets: T0 and two countable
sets. A one-to-one correspondence between T and R is given by the function: g(t) = t if t ∈ T0, g(t2n – 1) = tn,
and g(t2n) = an.
[Seite 5]
. . . Dem widerspricht aber ein sehr allgemeiner Satz,
welchen wir in Borchardt's Journal, Bd. 77, pag. 260,
[Page 5] mit aller Strenge bewiesen haben, nämlich der
. . . But this contradicts a very general theorem, folgende Satz:
which we have proved with full rigor in Borchardt's
"Hat man eine einfach unendliche Reihe
Journal, Vol. 77, page 260; namely, the following
ω1, ω2, . . . , ων, . . .
theorem:
von reellen, ungleichen Zahlen, die nach irgend
"If one has a simply [countably] infinite sequence
einem Gesetz fortschreiten, so lässt sich in jedem
ω1, ω2, . . . , ων, . . .
vorgegebenen, Intervalle (α . . . β) eine Zahl η (und
of real, unequal numbers that proceed according to
folglich lassen sich deren unendlich viele) angeben,
some rule, then in every given interval [α, β] a
welche nicht in jener Reihe (als Glied derselben)
number η (and thus infinitely many of them) can be
vorkommt."
specified that does not occur in this sequence (as a
member of it)." In Anbetracht des grossen Interesses, welches
sich an diesen Satz, nicht blos bei der gegenwärtigen
In view of the great interest in this theorem, not
Erörterung, sondern auch in vielen anderen sowohl
only in the present discussion, but also in many other
arithmetischen, wie analytischen Beziehungen,
arithmetical as well as analytical relations, it might not
knüpft, dürfte es nicht überflüssig sein, wenn wir die
be superfluous if we develop the argument followed
dort befolgte Beweisführung [Cantors 1874 Beweis],
there [Cantor's 1874 proof] more clearly here by
unter Anwendung vereinfachender Modificationen,
using simplifying modifications.
hier deutlicher entwickeln.
Starting with the sequence:
Unter Zugrundelegung der Reihe:
ω1, ω2, . . . , ων, . . .
ω1, ω2, . . . , ων, . . .
(which we give [denote by] the symbol (ω)) and an
(welcher wir das Zeichen (ω) beilegen) und eines
arbitrary interval [α, β], where α < β, we will now
beliebigen Intervalles (α . . . β), wo α < β ist, soll also
demonstrate that in this interval a real number η can
nun gezeigt werden, dass in diesem Intervalle eine
be found that does not occur in (ω).
reelle Zahl η gefunden werden kann, welche in (ω)
I. We first notice that if our set (ω) is not nicht vorkommt.
everywhere dense in the interval [α, β], then within
I. Wir bemerken zunächst, dass wenn unsre
this interval another interval [γ, δ] must be present, all
Mannichfaltigkeit (ω) in dem Intervall (α . . . β) nicht
of whose numbers do not belong to (ω). From the
überall-dicht ist, innerhalb dieses Intervalles ein
interval [γ, δ], one can then choose any number for η.
anderes (γ . . . δ) vorhanden sein muss, dessen
It lies in the interval [α, β] and definitely does not
Zahlen sämmtlich nicht zu (ω) gehören; man kann
occur in our sequence (ω). Thus, this case presents
alsdann für η irgend eine Zahl des Intervalls (γ . . . δ)
no special considerations and we can move on to the
wählen, sie liegt im Intervalle (α . . . β) und kommt
more difficult case.
sicher in unsrer Reihe (ω) nicht vor. Dieser Fall bietet
II. Let the set (ω) be everywhere dense in the daher keinerlei besondere Umstände; und wir können
interval [α, β]. In this case, every interval [γ,δ] located zu dem schwierigeren übergehen.
in [α,β], however small, contains numbers of our
II. Die Mannichfaltigkeit (ω) sei im Intervalle
sequence (ω). To show that, nevertheless, numbers η
(α . . . β) überall-dicht. In diesem Falle enthält jedes,
in the interval [α, β] exist that do not occur in (ω), we
noch so kleine in (α . . . β) gelegene Intervall (γ . . . δ)
employ the following observation.
Zahlen unserer Reihe (ω). Um zu zeigen, dass
Since some numbers in our sequence: nichtsdestoweniger Zahlen η im Intervalle (α . . . β)
ω1, ω2, . . . , ων, . . . existiren, welche in (ω) nicht vorkommen, stellen wir
die folgende Betrachtung an.
Da in unserer Reihe:
ω1, ω2, . . . , ων, . . .
[Page 6]
definitely occur within the interval [α, β], one of these [Seite 6]
numbers must have the least index, let it be ωκ , and sicher Zahlen innerhalb des Intervalls (α . . . β)
1
another: ωκ2 with the next larger index. vorkommen, so muss eine von diesen Zahlen den
kleinsten Index haben, sie sei ωκ1, und eine andere:
Let the smaller of the two numbers ωκ1, ωκ2 be ωκ2 mit dem nächst grösseren Index behaftet sein.
denoted by α', the larger by β'. (Their equality is
impossible because we assumed that our sequence Die kleinere der beiden Zahlen ωκ1, ωκ2 werde mit
consists of nothing but unequal numbers.) α', die grössere mit β' bezeichnet. (Ihre Gleichheit ist
ausgeschlossen, weil wir voraussetzten, dass unsere
Then according to the definition: Reihe aus lauter ungleichen Zahlen besteht.)
α < α' < β' < β ,
furthermore: Es ist alsdann der Definition nach:
κ1 < κ2 ; α < α' < β' < β ,
and all numbers ωμ of our sequence, for which μ ≤ ferner:
κ2, do not lie in the interior of the interval [α', β'], as is κ1 < κ2 ;
immediately clear from the definition of the numbers und ausserdem ist zu bemerken, dass alle Zahlen ωμ
κ1, κ2. Similarly, let ωκ and ωκ be the two numbers unserer Reihe, für welche μ ≤ κ2, nicht im Innern des
3 4
of our sequence with smallest indices that fall in the Intervalls (α' . . . β') liegen, wie aus der Bestimmung
interior of the interval [α', β'] and let the smaller of the der Zahlen κ1, κ2 sofort erhellt. Ganz ebenso mögen
numbers ωκ3, ωκ4 be denoted by α'', the larger by β''. ωκ3, ωκ4 die beiden mit den kleinsten Indices
versehenen Zahlen unserer Reihen [see note 1
Then one has: below] sein, welche in das Innere des Intervalls
α' < α'' < β'' < β' , (α' . . . β') fallen und die kleinere der Zahlen ωκ3, ωκ4
κ2 < κ3 < κ4 ; werde mit α'', die grössere mit β'' bezeichnet.
and one sees that all numbers ωμ of our sequence,
for which μ ≤ κ4, do not fall into the interior of the Man hat alsdann:
interval [α'', β'']. α' < α'' < β'' < β' ,
κ2 < κ3 < κ4 ;
After one has followed this rule to reach an und man erkennt, dass alle Zahlen ωμ unserer Reihe,
interval [α(ν - 1), β(ν - 1)], the next interval is produced für welche μ ≤ κ4 nicht in das Innere des Intervalls
by selecting the first two (i. e. with lowest indices) (α'' . . . β'') fallen.
numbers of our sequence (ω) (let them be ωκ and
2ν - 1
ωκ ) that fall into the interior of [α(ν - 1), β(ν - 1)]. Let Nachdem man unter Befolgung des gleichen
2ν
Gesetzes zu einem Intervall (α(ν - 1), . . . β(ν - 1))
the smaller of these two numbers be denoted by α(ν),
gelangt ist, ergiebt sich das folgende Intervall
the larger by β(ν).
dadurch aus demselben, dass man die beiden ersten
The interval [α(ν), β(ν)] then lies in the interior of all (d. h. mit niedrigsten Indices versehenen) Zahlen
preceding intervals and has the specific relation with unserer Reihe (ω) aufstellt (sie seien ωκ2ν – 1 und
our sequence (ω) that all numbers ωμ, for which μ ≤ ωκ2ν), welche in das Innere von (α(ν – 1) . . . β(ν – 1))
κ2ν, definitely do not lie in its interior. Since obviously: fallen; die kleinere dieser beiden Zahlen werde mit
κ1 < κ2 < κ3 < . . . , ωκ2ν – 2 < ωκ2ν – 1 < ωκ2ν , . . . α(ν), die grössere mit β(ν) bezeichnet.
and these numbers, as indices, are whole numbers,
so: Das Intervall (α(ν) . . . β(ν)) liegt alsdann im Innern
κ2ν ≥ 2ν , aller vorangegangenen Intervalle und hat zu unserer
and hence: Reihe (ω) die eigenthümliche Beziehung, dass alle
Zahlen ωμ, für welche μ ≤ κ2ν sicher nicht in seinem
ν < κ2ν ;
thus, we can certainly say (and this is sufficient for Innern liegen. Da offenbar:
the following): κ1 < κ2 < κ3 < . . . , ωκ2ν – 2 < ωκ2ν – 1 < ωκ2ν , . . .
That if ν is an arbitrary whole number, the [real] und diese Zahlen, als Indices, ganze Zahlen sind, so
quantity ων lies outside the interval [α(ν) . . . β(ν)]. ist:
κ2ν ≥ 2ν ,
und daher:
ν < κ2ν ;
wir können daher, und dies ist für das Folgende
ausreichend, gewiss sagen:
[Page 7] [Seite 7]
Da die Zahlen α', α'', α''', . . ., α(ν), . . . ihrer
Since the numbers α', α'', α''', . . ., α(ν), . . . are
Grösse nach fortwährend wachsen, dabei jedoch im
continually increasing by value while simultaneously
Intervalle (α . . . β) eingeschlossen sind, so haben
being enclosed in the interval [α, β], they have, by a
sie, nach einem bekannten Fundamentalsatze der
well-known fundamental theorem of the theory of
Grössenlehre, eine Grenze, die wir mit A bezeichnen,
magnitudes [see note 2 below], a limit that we denote
by A, so that: so dass:
A = Lim α(ν) für ν = ∞.
A = Lim α(ν) for ν = ∞.
The same applies to the numbers β', β'', β''', . . ., Ein Gleiches gilt für die Zahlen β', β'', β''', . . .,
β(ν),. . . welche fortwährend abnehmen und dabei
β(ν), . . ., which are continually decreasing and
ebenfalls im Intervalle (α . . . β) liegen; wir nennen
likewise lying in the interval [α, β]. We call their limit
ihre Grenze B, so dass:
B, so that:
B = Lim β(ν) für ν = ∞.
B = Lim β(ν) for ν = ∞.
Man hat offenbar:
Obviously, one has:
α(ν) < A ≤ B < β(ν).
α(ν) < A ≤ B < β(ν).
Es ist aber leicht zu sehen, dass der Fall A < B
But it is easy to see that the case A < B can not
hier nicht vorkommen kann; da sonst jede Zahl ων,
occur here since otherwise every number ων of our
sequence would lie outside of the interval [A, B] by unserer Reihe ausserhalb des Intervalles (A . . . B)
liegen würde, indem ων, ausserhalb des Intervalls
lying outside the interval [α(ν), β(ν)]. So our sequence
(ω) would not be everywhere dense in the interval (α(ν) . . . β(ν)) gelegen ist; unsere Reihe (ω) wäre im
[α, β], contrary to the assumption. Intervall (α . . . β) nicht überalldicht, gegen die
Voraussetzung.
Thus, there only remains the case A = B and now
it is demonstrated that the number: Es bleibt daher nur der Fall A = B übrig und es
η=A=B zeigt sich nun, dass die Zahl:
does not occur in our sequence (ω). η=A=B
in unserer Reihe (ω) nicht vorkommt.
If it were a member of our sequence, such as the
νth, then one would have: η = ων. Denn, würde sie ein Glied unserer Reihe sein,
etwa das νte, so hätte man: η = ων.
But the latter equation is not possible for any value
of ν because η is in the interior of the interval Die letztere Gleichung ist aber für keinen Werth
[α(ν), β(ν)], but ων lies outside of it. von v möglich, weil η im Innern des Intervalls
[α(ν), β(ν)], ων aber ausserhalb desselben liegt.
Note 1: This is the only occurrence of "unserer Reihen" ("our sequences") in the proof. There is only one sequence involved in
Cantor's proof and everywhere else "Reihe" ("sequence") is used, so it is most likely a typographical error and should be "unserer
Reihe" ("our sequence"), which is how it has been translated.
Note 2: Grössenlehre, which has been translated as "the theory of magnitudes", is a term used by 19th
century German mathematicians that refers to the theory of discrete and continuous magnitudes. (Ferreirós
2007, pp. 41–42, 202.)
References
1. Dauben 1993, p. 4.
2. Gray 1994, pp. 819–821.
3. Cantor 1874. English translation: Ewald 1996, pp. 840–843.
4. Gray 1994, p. 828.
5. Cantor 1874, p. 259. English translation: Ewald 1996, pp. 840–841.
6. Cantor 1874, p. 259. English translation: Gray 1994, p. 820.
7. Cantor 1878, p. 242.
8. Gray 1994, p. 820.
9. Cantor 1874, pp. 259–260. English translation: Ewald 1996, p. 841.
10. Cantor 1874, pp. 260–261. English translation: Ewald 1996, pp. 841–842.
11. Cantor 1874, p. 261. English translation: Ewald 1996, p. 842.
12. Gray 1994, p. 822.
13. Havil 2012, pp. 208–209.
14. Havil 2012, p. 209.
15. LeVeque 1956, pp. 154–155.
16. LeVeque 1956, p. 174.
17. Weisstein 2003, p. 541.
18. Arkhangel'skii & Fedorchuk 1990, p. 16.
19. Noether & Cavaillès 1937, pp. 12–13. English translation: Gray 1994, p. 827; Ewald 1996, p. 844.
20. Noether & Cavaillès 1937, p. 18. English translation: Ewald 1996, p. 848.
21. Noether & Cavaillès 1937, p. 13. English translation: Gray 1994, p. 827.
22. Noether & Cavaillès 1937, pp. 14–15. English translation: Ewald 1996, pp. 845–846.
23. Gray 1994, p. 827
24. Dauben 1979, p. 51.
25. Noether & Cavaillès 1937, p. 19. English translation: Ewald 1996, p. 849.
26. Ewald 1996, p. 843.
27. Noether & Cavaillès 1937, p. 16. English translation: Gray 1994, p. 827.
28. Perron 1921, p. 162.
29. Kanamori 2012, p. 4.
30. Gray 1994, pp. 827–828.
31. Perron 1921, p. 162
32. Fraenkel 1930, p. 237. English translation: Gray 1994, p. 823.
33. Kaplansky 1972, p. 25.
34. Gray 1994, pp. 829–830.
35. Gray 1994, pp. 821–824.
36. Bell 1937, pp. 568–569; Hardy & Wright 1938, p. 159 (6th ed., pp. 205–206); Birkhoff & Mac Lane 1941,
p. 392, (5th ed., pp. 436–437); Spivak 1967, pp. 369–370 (4th ed., pp. 448–449).
37. Dasgupta 2014, p. 107; Sheppard 2014, pp. 131–132.
38. Jarvis 2014, p. 18; Chowdhary 2015, p. 19; Stewart 2015, p. 285; Stewart & Tall 2015, p. 333.
39. Birkhoff & Mac Lane 1941, p. 392, (5th ed., pp. 436–437).
40. Burton 1995, p. 595.
41. Dauben 1979, p. 69.
42. Gray 1994, p. 824.
43. Ferreirós 2007, p. 184.
44. Noether & Cavaillès 1937, pp. 12–16. English translation: Ewald 1996, pp. 843–846.
45. Dauben 1979, p. 67.
46. Noether & Cavaillès 1937, pp. 16–17. English translation: Ewald 1996, p. 847.
47. Grattan-Guinness 1971, p. 124.
48. Dauben 1979, pp. 67, 308–309.
49. Ferreirós 2007, pp. 184–185, 245.
50. Ferreirós 2007, p. 185: It is unclear when his attitude changed, but there is evidence that by the mid-1880s he
was accepting the conclusion that infinite sets are of different powers [cardinalities].
51. Ferreirós 2007, p. 177.
52. Dauben 1979, pp. 67–68.
53. Ferreirós 2007, p. 183.
54. Ferreirós 2007, p. 185.
55. Ferreirós 2007, pp. 109–111, 172–174.
56. Ferreirós 1993, pp. 349–350.
57. Noether & Cavaillès 1937, pp. 12–13. English translation: Ewald 1996, pp. 844–845.
58. Noether & Cavaillès 1937, p. 13. English translation: Ewald 1996, p. 845.
59. Ferreirós 2007, p. 179.
60. Noether & Cavaillès 1937, pp. 14–16, 19. English translation: Ewald 1996, pp. 845–847, 849.
61. Ferreirós 1993, pp. 358–359.
62. Ferreirós 1993, p. 350.
63. Cantor 1878, pp. 245–254.
64. Cantor 1879, p. 4.
65. Ferreirós 2007, pp. 267–273.
66. Ferreirós 2007, pp. xvi, 320–321, 324.
67. Cantor 1878, p. 243.
68. Hawkins 1970, pp. 103–106, 127.
69. Hawkins 1970, pp. 118, 120–124, 127.
70. Ferreirós 2007, pp. 362–363.
71. Cohen 1963, pp. 1143–1144.
Bibliography
Arkhangel'skii, A. V.; Fedorchuk, V. V. (1990), "The basic concepts and constructions of general topology", in
Arkhangel'skii, A. V.; Pontryagin, L. S. (eds.), General Topology I, New York, Berlin: Springer-Verlag, pp. 1–90,
ISBN 978-0-387-18178-3.
Audin, Michèle (2011), Remembering Sofya Kovalevskaya, London: Springer, ISBN 978-0-85729-928-4.
Bell, Eric Temple (1937), Men of Mathematics, New York: Simon & Schuster, ISBN 978-0-671-62818-5.
Birkhoff, Garrett; Mac Lane, Saunders (1941), A Survey of Modern Algebra, New York: Macmillan, ISBN 978-1-
56881-068-3.
Burton, David M. (1995), Burton's History of Mathematics (3rd ed.), Dubuque, Iowa: William C. Brown,
ISBN 978-0-697-16089-8.
Cantor, Georg (1874), "Ueber eine Eigenschaft des Inbegriffes aller reellen algebraischen Zahlen" (http://www.
digizeitschriften.de/main/dms/img/?PPN=GDZPPN002155583), Journal für die Reine und Angewandte
Mathematik (in German), 1874 (77): 258–262, doi:10.1515/crll.1874.77.258 (https://doi.org/10.1515%2Fcrll.187
4.77.258), S2CID 199545885 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:199545885).
Cantor, Georg (1878), "Ein Beitrag zur Mannigfaltigkeitslehre" (http://www.digizeitschriften.de/dms/img/?PID=G
DZPPN002156806), Journal für die Reine und Angewandte Mathematik (in German), 1878 (84): 242–258,
doi:10.1515/crll.1878.84.242 (https://doi.org/10.1515%2Fcrll.1878.84.242) (inactive 1 November 2024).
Cantor, Georg (1879), "Ueber unendliche, lineare Punktmannichfaltigkeiten. 1." (http://www.digizeitschriften.de/
dms/img/?PID=GDZPPN002244853), Mathematische Annalen (in German), 15: 1–7, doi:10.1007/bf01444101
(https://doi.org/10.1007%2Fbf01444101), S2CID 179177510 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:179177
510).
Chowdhary, K. R. (2015), Fundamentals of Discrete Mathematical Structures (3rd ed.), Delhi, India: PHI
Learning, ISBN 978-81-203-5074-8.
Cohen, Paul J. (1963), "The Independence of the Continuum Hypothesis", Proceedings of the National
Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 50 (6): 1143–1148, Bibcode:1963PNAS...50.1143C (htt
ps://ui.adsabs.harvard.edu/abs/1963PNAS...50.1143C), doi:10.1073/pnas.50.6.1143 (https://doi.org/10.1073%
2Fpnas.50.6.1143), PMC 221287 (https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC221287), PMID 16578557 (ht
tps://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/16578557).
Dasgupta, Abhijit (2014), Set Theory: With an Introduction to Real Point Sets, New York: Springer, ISBN 978-1-
4614-8853-8.
Dauben, Joseph (1979), Georg Cantor: His Mathematics and Philosophy of the Infinite, Cambridge, Mass.:
Harvard University Press, ISBN 978-0-674-34871-4.
Dauben, Joseph (1993), "Georg Cantor and the Battle for Transfinite Set Theory" (http://acmsonline.org/home
2/wp-content/uploads/2016/05/Dauben-Cantor.pdf) (PDF), 9th ACMS Conference Proceedings.
Edwards, Harold M. (1989), "Kronecker's Views on the Foundations of Mathematics" (https://archive.org/detail
s/historyofmodernm0000symp/page/67), in Rowe, David E.; McCleary, John (eds.), The History of Modern
Mathematics, Volume 1, New York: Academic Press, pp. 67–77 (https://archive.org/details/historyofmodernm00
00symp/page/67), ISBN 978-0-12-599662-4.
Ewald, William B., ed. (1996), From Immanuel Kant to David Hilbert: A Source Book in the Foundations of
Mathematics, Volume 2, New York: Oxford University Press, ISBN 978-0-19-850536-5.
Ferreirós, José (1993), "On the relations between Georg Cantor and Richard Dedekind", Historia Mathematica,
20 (4): 343–363, doi:10.1006/hmat.1993.1030 (https://doi.org/10.1006%2Fhmat.1993.1030).
Ferreirós, José (2007), Labyrinth of Thought: A History of Set Theory and Its Role in Mathematical Thought
(2nd revised ed.), Basel: Birkhäuser, ISBN 978-3-7643-8349-7.
Fraenkel, Abraham (1930), "Georg Cantor" (http://www.digizeitschriften.de/main/dms/img/?PPN=PPN3772185
7X_0039&DMDID=dmdlog27), Jahresbericht der Deutschen Mathematiker-Vereinigung (in German), 39: 189–
266.
Grattan-Guinness, Ivor (1971), "The Correspondence between Georg Cantor and Philip Jourdain" (http://www.
digizeitschriften.de/main/dms/img/?PPN=GDZPPN002136651), Jahresbericht der Deutschen Mathematiker-
Vereinigung, 73: 111–130.
Gray, Robert (1994), "Georg Cantor and Transcendental Numbers" (https://web.archive.org/web/20220121155
859/https://www.maa.org/sites/default/files/pdf/upload_library/22/Ford/Gray819-832.pdf) (PDF), American
Mathematical Monthly, 101 (9): 819–832, doi:10.2307/2975129 (https://doi.org/10.2307%2F2975129),
JSTOR 2975129 (https://www.jstor.org/stable/2975129), MR 1300488 (https://mathscinet.ams.org/mathscinet-g
etitem?mr=1300488), Zbl 0827.01004 (https://zbmath.org/?format=complete&q=an:0827.01004), archived from
the original (http://www.maa.org/sites/default/files/pdf/upload_library/22/Ford/Gray819-832.pdf) (PDF) on 2022-
01-21, retrieved 2016-02-13.
Hardy, Godfrey; Wright, E. M. (1938), An Introduction to the Theory of Numbers, Oxford: Clarendon Press,
ISBN 978-0-19-921985-8.
Havil, Julian (2012), The Irrationals, Princeton, Oxford: Princeton University Press, ISBN 978-0-691-16353-6.
Hawkins, Thomas (1970), Lebesgue's Theory of Integration (https://archive.org/details/lebesguestheoryo0000h
awk_p7z9), Madison, Wisconsin: University of Wisconsin Press, ISBN 978-0-299-05550-9.
Jarvis, Frazer (2014), Algebraic Number Theory, New York: Springer, ISBN 978-3-319-07544-0.
Kanamori, Akihiro (2012), "Set Theory from Cantor to Cohen" (http://math.bu.edu/people/aki/16.pdf) (PDF), in
Gabbay, Dov M.; Kanamori, Akihiro; Woods, John H. (eds.), Sets and Extensions in the Twentieth Century,
Amsterdam, Boston: Cambridge University Press, pp. 1–71, ISBN 978-0-444-51621-3.
Kaplansky, Irving (1972), Set Theory and Metric Spaces, Boston: Allyn and Bacon, ISBN 978-0-8284-0298-9.
Kelley, John L. (1991), General Topology, New York: Springer, ISBN 978-3-540-90125-9.
LeVeque, William J. (1956), Topics in Number Theory (https://archive.org/details/topicsinnumberth0000leve),
vol. I, Reading, Mass.: Addison-Wesley, ISBN 978-0-486-42539-9. (Reprinted by Dover Publications, 2002.)
Noether, Emmy; Cavaillès, Jean, eds. (1937), Briefwechsel Cantor-Dedekind (in German), Paris: Hermann.
Perron, Oskar (1921), Irrationalzahlen (https://archive.org/stream/irrationalzahlen00perruoft#page/n5/mode/2u
p) (in German), Leipzig, Berlin: W. de Gruyter, OCLC 4636376 (https://search.worldcat.org/oclc/4636376).
Sheppard, Barnaby (2014), The Logic of Infinity, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, ISBN 978-1-107-
67866-8.
Spivak, Michael (1967), Calculus (https://archive.org/details/Calculus_643), London: W. A. Benjamin,
ISBN 978-0914098911.
Stewart, Ian (2015), Galois Theory (4th ed.), Boca Raton, Florida: CRC Press, ISBN 978-1-4822-4582-0.
Stewart, Ian; Tall, David (2015), The Foundations of Mathematics (2nd ed.), New York: Oxford University
Press, ISBN 978-0-19-870644-1.
Weisstein, Eric W., ed. (2003), "Continued Fraction", CRC Concise Encyclopedia of Mathematics, Boca Raton,
Florida: Chapman & Hall/CRC, ISBN 978-1-58488-347-0.