Interpretation of Statutes C Botha
Interpretation of Statutes C Botha
Preface
newest tablet computers, smart phones and other electronic gadgets, and well-
trained in social-media interaction—at South African law schools is not for the faint-
hearted. Since the preface to the fourth edition of this book was written in 2005
nothing has changed. If anything, students’ reading and writing skills are worse,
and they know (and care) less and less about time and space. For many students
Wikipedia, Blackberry, Twitter and Facebook represent the extreme limits of their
contextual world.
academics is whether or not we ‘over-teach’ law students (other buzz phrases are
the stage’, but rather a ‘guide on the side’; et cetera and so on and so forth.
However valuable these profound deliberations may turn out to be in the future, in
the meantime fewer law lecturers at understaffed faculties have to teach more and
lecturers just have to accept this situation as an unfortunate given. Get used to it,
get over it and get on with it, because (according to those in the know) if you are
not part of the solution, you are part of the problem. After all, to quote from one of
the many anonymous parodies of Rudyard Kipling’s If, lecturers are supposed to be
quite adaptable:
Yours are the Clouds and nothing else, you fool you
Page vi
Mind you, since beleaguered lecturers are struggling in the trenches, Alfred Lord
On the other hand the Y-generation law students will have to accept that, like
toll roads and rock ’n roll, interpretation of statutes is here to stay. During recent
discussions between the Council for Higher Education, members of the South
African Law Deans’ association, law teachers and members of the professions, one
of the required core skills of South African law graduates was identified as having
‘the ability to read and interpret statutes and legal documents’. So: as the
Americans are fond of saying, let’s cut to the chase. Law students may consider
legislation and Government Gazettes and Green Papers will still be waiting out
there, and the principles, rules and maxims needed to interpret legislation will
Because this book is aimed at the next generation of lawyers, allow me a number
suggested inclusive approach, it should be borne in mind that this book is,
work or complete compendium. After all, this year’s landmark case is next
Act . . .
Let us be frank about it: it is impossible to teach every rule, maxim, principle,
teach
Page vii
the golf swing should have the basic skills to deal with a plugged lie in the
bunker, to play a high fade into the wind or to take on a bump-and-run chip
from a tight lie. This also means that the golfer has to hone those skills on
the course, not only on the practice range. But then again, interpretation of
legislation and golf are not exact sciences: from time to time there will be
the same year of study), with suitable practical examples and references to
only enable the students to link the rules and principles of interpretation to
the ‘real’ world, but will also emphasise the interrelatedness of statutory
interpretation and the rest of the law. Needless to say, such an approach will
contact sessions.
This fifth edition is not only the product of more than three decades’ efforts
Pieter Carstens, Jakkie Wessels, Mike van Heerden, Koos Malan, Werner Krull and
all the other usual suspects. However, all the mistakes, shortcuts and wrong
mantra is ‘Why procrastinate if you can do it tomorrow’, Linda van de Vijver of Juta
Page viii
Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, 1996 and the Interpretation Act 33 of
1957
CHRISTO BOTHA
PRETORIA
2012
Page ix
Contents
Preface
General Introduction
1.1
1.2
1.3
2.1
What is legislation?
2.2
Categories of legislation
2.2.1
Chronological categories
(a)
(b)
(c)
2.2.2
Hierarchical categories
(a)
The Constitution
(b)
Original legislation
(c)
2.2.3
Old wine in new bags: Applying old order legislation in the new constitutional
order
2.2.4
2.3
2.4
3.1
3.2
Page x
3.3
3.3.1
Who promulgates?
3.3.2
When is it force?
(a)
(b)
(c)
(d)
Retroactive commencement
(e)
(f)
3.3.3
3.4
Back in the time warp: The presumption that legislation applies only to the
future
3.4.1
3.4.2
3.4.3
(a)
(b)
(c)
3.4.4
(b)
3.4.5
4.1
General
Page xi
4.2
Changes to legislation
4.2.1
4.2.2
(a)
(b)
4.3
(a)
Unconstitutional provisions
(b)
4.3.2
(a)
(b)
Repeal (deletion)
4.4
4.5
The presumption that legislation does not intend to change the existing law
4.5.1
Common law
4.5.2
Legislation
5
Theoretical foundations
5.1
Introduction
5.2
5.2.1
5.2.2
(a)
(b)
Deconstruction
(c)
5.3
5.3.1
Page xii
5.3.2
5.3.4
interpretation
6.1
6.1.1
Basic principles
(a)
(b)
(c)
No addition or subtraction
(d)
6.1.2
(a)
The preamble
(c)
(d)
(e)
(f)
(g)
Schedules
6.1.3
(a)
(b)
(c)
(d)
The holistic (contextual and structural) dimension: Don’t miss the wood for the
trees
6.2.1
Page xiii
6.2.2
6.2.3
Structure of legislation
6.2.4
Conflicting legislation
(a)
Legislation has a purpose: the presumption that legislation does not contain futile
or nugatory provisions
(b)
6.2.5
The King can do no wrong: The presumption that government bodies are not
6.3
6.3.2
Ubuntu
6.4
6.4.1
6.4.2
Prior legislation
6.4.3
Preceding discussions
(a)
(b)
Commission reports
6.4.4
6.4.5
Contemporanea expositio
6.4.6
Subsecuta observatio
6.5
6.5.1
Foreign law
6.5.2
International law
Part 3: Some practical issues and tricks of the trade: Judicial law-making during
7.1
What is concretisation?
Page xiv
7.2
7.2.1
7.2.2
7.2.3
interpretation
(a)
(b)
7.3
7.3.1
7.3.2
(a)
Restrictive interpretation
(b)
Extensive interpretation
7.3.3
8.1
General introduction
8.2
Some guidelines
8.2.1
Semantic guidelines
8.2.2
Jurisprudential guidelines
8.2.3
Constitutional interpretation
9.1
Introduction
9.1.1
9.1.2
9.2
9.2.1
Page xv
9.2.2
Substantive constitutionalism
9.2.3
Constitutional symbolism
9.3
9.3.1
Constitutional guidelines
9.3.2
A comprehensive methodology
(a)
Grammatical interpretation
(b)
(c)
(d)
Historical interpretation
(e)
Comparative interpretation
9.4
9.4.1
Reading-down
9.4.3
Reading-up
9.4.4
Reading-in
9.4.5
Severance
9.5
9.5.1
9.5.2
9.5.3
9.5.4
Bibliography
Table of Cases
Index
Supplementary material
Part 1
Statute law
1
General Introduction
2
The term ‘legislation’
3
Is it in force? The commencement of legislation
4
Is it still in force? Changes to and the demise
of legislation
Page 3
Chapter 1
General Introduction
•
The common law is composed of the rules of
law which were not originally written down, but
came to be accepted as the law of the land.
The common law is made up of the underlying
original or basic legal principles. South African
common law is known as Roman-Dutch law
and most of it originated during the
seventeenth century in the erstwhile province
of Holland.
•
Common law needs to be distinguished from
codifications, which are statutory compilations
of all the legal principles
Page 4
relating to a particular branch of the law (eg a
criminal code). The common law may be
changed by original legislation, but if there is
no statutory law on the subject, the common
law applies.
•
Indigenous law refers to the traditional law of
the indigenous black people of South Africa.
This may either be unwritten customary law, or
codified (statutory compilations).
•
Case law (also referred to as ‘judicial
precedent’) is the law as various courts in
specific cases before them have decided on it.
(For law students, the term ‘case law’ usually
refers to those cases they had to read, but did
not, and had to discuss in the examination, and
could not!) The precedent system (also known
as stare decisis) means that judgments of
higher courts bind lower courts and courts of
equal status.
Statute law (legislation) plays an ever-increasing
role in common-law legal systems. In the past,
legislation may have been viewed as exceptions to
the common law, but the rapid changes in modern
society have stretched the adaptability of common-
law rules to their limits. Since the common law
cannot deal with the regulation of new
technological and scientific developments such as
electronic funds transfers, stem cell research and
cross-border human trafficking (to name only a
few), more and more legislative intervention is
necessary and inevitable. As a result, legislation is
the most important source of new law in most
modern societies.
In South Africa there is, of course, a more
fundamental reason for a thorough understanding
of the technical aspects of legislation. In a strictly
legalistic sense apartheid was an ideologically
underpinned and public-law driven system, based
on a web of interlocking legislation. The
dismantling of this legal edifice not only requires
an excellent knowledge of statute law, but a great
deal of new legislation is needed to remedy the
situation in the new constitutional dispensation.
•
What is the impact of other legislation (eg the
Promotion of Access to Information Act 2 of
2000, the Promotion of Administrative Justice
Act 3 of 2000 and the Promotion of Equality
and Prevention of Unfair Discrimination Act 4 of
2000)?
•
Is the legislation that must be interpreted still
in force? If still in force, has it been amended
since?
•
If, for instance, a provision in an Act of
Parliament is to be interpreted, it must be read
with the rest of the Act, including its definition
section and possibly its schedules as well.
Regulations may have been issued in terms of
the particular provision, which have to read
with the enabling legislation. Are those
regulations valid?
•
What is the context (general background or
surrounding circumstances) of the legislative
text?
•
Other external aids (eg dictionaries or
commission reports) may be used to establish
the meaning of the legislation.
•
Sometimes the interpreter will be confronted
by the results of poor drafting, conflicting
provisions or a lack of resources to research
the current law.
Page 8
Make no mistake: interpretation of legislation is
not easy, quick or mechanical. It not only requires
excellent language skills, but the interpreter must
also have a very good knowledge of the law and
where to find it. This means research: reading
reported cases (lots of them!), finding and
analysing the latest Acts and regulations, and
keeping up to date with new developments in the
law.
Practical example:
As has been pointed out, interpretation of statutes
is not easy. Take a look at the definition of a
‘firearm’ in s 1 of the Firearms Control Act 60 of
2000:
In this Act, unless the context indicates
otherwise—
...
‘firearm’ means any—
(a)
device manufactured or designed to propel a
bullet or projectile through a barrel or cylinder
by means of burning propellant, at a muzzle
energy exceeding 8 joules (6 ft-lbs);
...
What is muzzle energy of 8 joules (6 ft-lbs)?
Muzzle energy is the kinetic energy of the bullet
when it exits the barrel. To know the muzzle
energy, you need to know the muzzle velocity (the
speed of the bullet when it exits the barrel), the
mass of the bullet, and a lot of mathematics!
Muzzle energy (in ft-lbs) is calculated as follows:
Muzzle velocity (in feet per second)2 d 450240 x
bullet weight in grains. One grain = .064789 gram,
and one ft-lb muzzle energy = 1.356 joule. Did the
legislative drafters know or understand this
definition? Do you think the prosecutors, legal
practitioners and the judiciary understand the
definition? To cut a long story short—there is more
to interpretation of legislation than merely glancing
through the words in the text!
Legalese
Bad drafting and legalese is another problem.
‘Legalese’ refers to the perplexing and specialised
language (or social dialect) used by lawyers in
legal documents, incomprehensible to the non-
lawyer. Somebody once defined it as ‘the language
of lawyers that they would not use in ordinary
communications but for the fact that they are
lawyers’. It is characterised by wordiness, Latin
expressions, passive verbs, lengthy sentences
Page 9
and legal doublets (stringing together two words to
convey a single legal concept such as null and
void, fit and proper, perform and discharge and
terms and conditions). Why do drafters use
verbose language? Maybe it is part of a
professional mystique, compelling lawyers to write
in a complicated and learned style in order to
maintain an aura of profound importance. Lord
Radcliffe (1950: 368) explained the use of legalese
as follows:
It seems to me that a sort of hieratic language
has developed by which the priests incant the
commandments. I seem to see the ordinary
citizen today standing before the law like the
laity in a medieval church: at the far end the
lights glow, the priestly figures move to and
fro, but it is in an unknown tongue that the
great mysteries of right and wrong are
proclaimed.
Yet despite the efforts of the advocates of more
understandable plain language in legal drafting,
interpreters still have to deal with convoluted
language in legislation. Just imagine you have to
interpret the following provisions:
Section 1 of the Orange Free State Civil
Protection Ordinance 10 of 1977 was a somewhat
ridiculous attempt to define a ‘disaster’:
In this Ordinance, unless the context otherwise
indicates—‘disaster’ means a disaster or a
state which is not a state of emergency or a
state of disaster and which, in the opinion of
the Administrator or of the local authority
concerned, is a disaster, as defined in section 1
of the Act, or is likely to develop into such a
disaster;
Or even worse, another potential tongue-twister
was s 1(4) of the previous Labour Relations Act 28
of 1956:
The definition of ‘unfair labour practice’
referred to in subsection (1), shall not be
interpreted either to include or exclude a
labour practice which in terms of the said
definition is an unfair labour practice, merely
because it was or was not an unfair labour
practice, as the case may be, in terms of the
definition of ‘unfair labour practice’, which
definition was substituted by section 1(a) of
the Labour Relations Amendment Act, 1991:
provided that a strike or lock-out shall not be
regarded as an unfair labour practice.
In an almost desperate attempt to make sense of s
22(1)(d) and 22(1)(bb) of the Compulsory Motor
Vehicle Insurance Act 56 of 1972 (as amended
several times), Botha JA in Santam
Page 10
Insurance Ltd v Taylor 1985 (1) SA 514 (A) 523B
and 526E expressed himself as follows on the
confusion:
In an attempt to escape from the prolixity
which disgraces this piece of legislation I shall
take a number of short cuts when referring to
its provisions . . . In my opinion the man in the
street would be at least as perplexed by the
language used by the legislature as is the man
on the Bench who is writing this judgment.
Clearly the judge was not impressed with the
standard of drafting and the legalese used in the
legislation which it had to interpret. As Botha &
Bekink (2007: 34) point out, it is not always easy
to use so-called ‘plain language drafting’ in
legislation and other legal documents. However,
even in South Africa legislative drafters,
legislatures and lawyers are becoming more aware
of the need to draft legal documents in more
understandable language.
Practical example:
Section 3(1)(b)(iv) of the Consumer Protection Act
68 of 2008 is a good example of an express
legislative acknowledgement of the link between
understandable language and access to justice:
3 Purpose and policy of Act
(1) The purposes of this Act are to promote
and advance the social and economic welfare
of consumers in South Africa by—
...
(b)
reducing and ameliorating any disadvantages
experienced in accessing any supply of goods
or services by consumers—
...
(iv)
whose ability to read and comprehend any
advertisement, agreement, mark, instruction,
label, warning, notice or other visual
representation is limited by reason of low
literacy, vision impairment or limited fluency in
the language in which the representation is
produced, published or presented;
•
The legislature is composed of a large number
of persons, all of whom take part in the
legislative process.
•
As part of the democratic legislative process
some members of the legislature may oppose
the legislation for various reasons, with the
result that the adopted legislation ultimately
reflects the ‘intention’ of only the majority of
the legislature.
•
Some members will support legislation for the
sake of party unity, though they may be
personally opposed to a Bill. This means that
the ‘intention’ of the legislature is subject to
what the individual members of the legislative
body, under pressure from their party caucus,
‘had to’ intend!
•
Parliamentarians are elected politicians, and
they do not necessarily understand the
complex and technical legislation which they
adopt.
•
A Bill introduced in the legislature is not drafted
by the public representatives, but by legislative
drafters and law advisers acting on the advice
of bureaucrats from various state departments.
•
Some members of the legislative body may
even be absent when voting on draft legislation
takes place.
To put it another way: the intention of the
legislature refers to the fictional collective intent of
the majority of the legislative body present at the
time when the vote took place, expressing their
will within the constraints of the voting guidelines
laid down by the caucus of the ruling party in the
legislature, and voting for draft legislation—
formulated by legal drafters on the advice of
bureaucrats from a government department—
which had been approved earlier by the state law
advisors!
In the final analysis the correct interpretation of
legislation does not depend on which term is used.
What is important,
Page 12
though, is how that purpose (or intention or
legislative scheme or aim of legislation) is
ascertained and construed. The correct way to
interpret legislation is discussed in greater detail in
Part 2 of this book.
Chapter 2
The term ‘legislation’
•
‘Enacted’ means it was
adopted/issued/promulgated in terms of the
prescribed legal requirements (for instance, the
Constitution and the Interpretation Act 33 of
1957 (‘the Interpretation Act’)).
•
‘Law’ means it has the force of law.
•
‘Text’ means it is written law.
The term ‘legislation’ (statute law or enacted law-
texts) comprises a number of sometimes confusing
names and concepts, for instance, Acts, statutes,
ordinances, regulations, proclamations, rules,
notices and by-laws. Apart from the fact that the
various types of legislation are categorised in
terms of both a chronological timeline and a
hierarchical power structure (discussed in 2.2
below), some of these names have different
meanings, depending on the context in which they
are used.
Page 16
Please note:
Generally a statute is an Act of Parliament, but
sometimes a statute may refer to the set of
subordinate legislation regulating the internal
organisation of a university. A notice may be a
specific type of subordinate legislation issued by a
competent functionary, but a notice in an official
Gazette could also be just that—an official
notification of facts or situations that must be
brought to the attention of the public.
In order to determine the legal meaning of
‘legislation’, let us start with the definitions in the
Interpretation Act. Section 1 of the Interpretation
Act provides:
1 Application of Act
The provisions of this Act shall apply to the
interpretation of every law (as in this Act
defined) in force, at or after the
commencement of this Act, in the Republic or
any portion thereof, and to the interpretation
of all by-laws, rules, regulations or orders
made under the authority of any such law,
unless there is something in the language or
context of the law, by-law, rule, regulation or
order repugnant to such provisions or unless
the contrary intention appears therein.
‘Law’ in this context does not include the common
law. In other words, the rules of statutory
interpretation apply only to legislation. But how
does legislation define itself? Section 2 of the
Interpretation Act defines ‘law’ as follows:
‘law’ means any law, proclamation,
ordinance, Act of Parliament or other
enactment having the force of the law.
According to the Interpretation Act (ss 1 and 2
read together) legislation consists of:
•
any law, proclamation, ordinance, Act of
Parliament, all by-laws, rules, regulations or
orders; and
•
any other enactment having the force of the
law.
So far, so good: if these different types of
legislation seem confusing, it gets worse! Section
239 of the Constitution also defines legislation:
In the Constitution, unless the context
indicates otherwise—
‘national legislation’ includes—
(a)
subordinate legislation made in terms of an Act
of Parliament; and
(b)
legislation that was in force when the
Constitution took effect and that is
administered by the national government;
Page 17
...
‘provincial legislation’ includes—
(a)
subordinate legislation made in terms of a
provincial Act; and
(b)
legislation that was in force when the
Constitution took effect and that is
administered by a provincial government.
Furthermore, ss 101(3) and 140(3) of the
Constitution refer to subordinate legislation as
proclamations, regulations and other instruments
of subordinate legislation, item 1 of Schedule 6 of
the Constitution distinguishes between old order
legislation and legislation since 1994, and ss 44,
104 and 156 of the Constitution mention assigned
legislation. Finally, s 156(2) of the Constitution
empowers local governments (municipalities) to
make by-laws as mentioned in the Interpretation
Act.
According to the Constitution the legislative
menu consists of the following:
•
national and provincial legislation;
•
proclamations, regulations and other
instruments of subordinate legislation;
•
assigned legislation;
•
old order legislation (defined in item 1 of
Schedule 6 of the Constitution as any
legislation enacted before the interim
Constitution took effect on 27 April 1994);
•
legislation in the new constitutional order since
1994; and
•
municipal by-laws.
All of these will be explained in the sections to
follow. It should now be clear that the
Interpretation Act and the Constitution refer not
only to legislation emanating from certain
geographical areas (national, provincial and local
authorities), but also to a time-line (old order and
post-1994 legislation) as well as to a hierarchical
distinction (for instance, ‘instruments of
subordinate legislation’). This means that the term
‘legislation’ needs to be understood, interpreted
and applied in terms of a horizontal timeline,
geographical space and vertical hierarchical
authority. Now things get interesting: fasten your
seatbelts, or as William Shakespeare (Julius
Caesar: Act 3 scene 1) put it: ‘Cry “Havoc!” and let
slip the dogs of war . . .’
2.2 Categories of legislation
In this part of the chapter the various categories
and types of legislation will be explained. These
categories relate to the historical origins of
legislation (chronological categories) as well as to
the status of the various types of legislation in the
Page 18
legal order (hierarchical categories). Students may
think that all types of legislation (statute law or
enacted law texts) are essentially the same.
Unfortunately this is not the case. The various
hierarchical categories of legislation differ
fundamentally from each other. These differences
have an impact on the commencement and demise
of legislation, and play an important role in all the
other branches of the law (more specifically
administrative law, human rights law and
constitutional law).
•
directly from the Constitution—Parliament (ss
43(a) and 44), provincial legislatures (ss 43(b)
and 104(1)) and municipalities (ss 43(c) and
156(1)(a)); and
•
indirectly from the Constitution (assigned by
another Act of Parliament or a provincial
legislature)—Provincial legislatures (additional
legislative powers assigned by Acts of
Parliament (ss 44(1)(a)(iii) and
104(1)(b)(iii))); and municipalities (additional
legislative powers assigned by Acts of
Parliament (ss 44(1)(a)(iii) and 156(1)(b)) and
additional legislative powers assigned by
provincial Acts (ss 104(1)(c) and 156(1)(b)).
Acts of Parliament
(a)
prohibits or restricts the disclosure of a record
of a public body or private body; and
(b)
is materially inconsistent with an object, or a
specific provision, of this Act.
Other examples of original legislation also contain
provisions stating that it will prevail over any other
law in a particular field of law (for example s 70 of
the Higher Education Act 101 of 1997):
Application of Act when in conflict with
other laws
This Act prevails over any other law dealing
with higher education other than the
Constitution.
Obviously provisions such as these have to be read
in conjunction with the supreme Constitution as
well as with the constitutional Acts (for instance,
the Promotion of Administrative Justice Act).
•
In terms of s 89 of the Defence Act 42 of 2002,
the President is authorised, subject to s 203 of
the Constitution, to declare a state of national
defence by proclamation.
•
A Minister is authorised to promulgate certain
regulations in accordance with the prescription
of the particular enabling Act (eg s 75 of the
National Road Traffic Act 93 of 1996, which
empowers the Minister of Transport to issue
regulations dealing with—amongst others—the
use of any vehicle on public roads; or s 69 of
the Higher Education Act 101 of 1997, which
empowers the Minister of Higher Education and
Training to issue regulations on a number of
higher education-related matters).
•
A statutory body or a person may be
empowered to make regulations (eg s 32 (read
with s 33) of the Higher Education Act 101 of
1997, which authorises the Council of a
university, subject to the approval of the
Minister of Higher Education and Training, to
issue an institutional statute for the university
dealing with the general management of such a
university; or s 6 of the Rules Board for Courts
of Law Act 107 of 1985, which empowers the
Rules Board for Courts of Law—subject to the
approval of the Minister of Justice—to make,
amend or repeal the rules for the Supreme
Court of Appeal, the High Courts and the lower
courts).
Page 28
•
Subordinate legislation may not be in conflict
with original legislation. The persons or bodies
authorised to issue delegated legislation may
do so only within the framework of the
authority specifically bestowed on them by the
enabling legislation. If not, they have acted
ultra vires (outside the scope of their powers)
and the subordinate legislation in question
could be invalidated by a court of law.
•
Delegated (subordinate) legislation owes both
its existence and its authority to its enabling
original legislation. If the enabling Act is
declared unconstitutional by a court, the
subordinate legislation issued in terms of such
an invalidated Act will also cease to exist
unless the court orders otherwise (Moseneke v
Master of the High Court 2001 (2) SA 18 (CC)).
If the enabling Act is repealed, all the
subordinate legislation issued in terms of the
repealed Act will also cease to exist (Hatch v
Koopoomal 1936 AD 197; Pharmaceutical
Manufacturers Association of SA; In re: Ex
parte Application of the President of the
Republic of South Africa 2000 (2) SA 674
(CC)), unless the repealing Act
Page 29
expressly provides otherwise. For example,
item 24(3) of Schedule 6 of the Constitution
expressly provides that although the interim
Constitution has been repealed, the regulations
made in terms of s 237(3) of the interim
Constitution remain in force.
•
Parliament cannot confer a power on a
delegated legislative body to amend or repeal
an Act of Parliament (Executive Council
Western Cape Legislature v President of the
RSA 1995 (4) SA 877 (CC)).
•
Although subordinate legislation must be read
and interpreted together with its enabling Act,
the enabling Act may not be interpreted on the
basis of the subordinate legislation made under
it (Freedom of Expression Institute v Chair,
Complaints and Compliance Committee
(unreported case 2009/51933) [2011]
ZAGPJHC 2 (24 January 2011)).
•
the Transvaal Removal of Graves and Dead
Bodies Ordinance 7 of 1925;
•
the Cape Province Exhumations Ordinance 12
of 1980; and
•
the Bophuthatswana Traditional Authorities Act
23 of 1978.
In terms of Proclamation 110 of 17 June, 1994, the
administration of the two provincial ordinances and
the Bophuthatswana Act have been assigned to the
North West province. In terms of the two
ordinances, permission to exhume a body has to
be obtained from the Administrator of the
province; and in terms of the Bophuthatswana Act,
permission for an exhumation has to be obtained
from the local tribal authority. So when a body is
to be exhumed, the permission necessary to do so
will depend on where the grave is located. But who
is the Administrator of the province (according to
the old order ordinance)? ‘Administrators’ of
provinces were abolished after the new
constitutional dispensation took effect. In general,
item 3 of Schedule 6 of the Constitution
(‘Interpretation of existing legislation’) deals with
old order terminology: a reference to ‘the
Administrator’ in existing legislation allocated to a
province should be construed as ‘the Premier’ of
that province. However, in terms of s 1 of the now-
repealed Local Government Transition Act 209 of
1993 ‘Administrator’ is substituted by ‘Member of
the Executive Council’ of the relevant province.
Page 32
Of course, the story does not end here. The
exhumed human remains have to be reburied
somewhere else, but by law permission for
reburials is required. ‘Cemeteries, funeral parlours
and crematoria’ fall within Schedule 5B of the
Constitution (read with s 13 of the Local
Government: Municipal Systems Act 32 of 2000),
which means that municipalities administer burials
and funerals. So: in this case, permission to
exhume is given by the relevant provincial
government (in terms of three possible sets of old
order legislation), and permission to rebury is
granted by the municipality in whose area of
jurisdiction the reburial will take place (for
instance, the Drakenstein Municipality Cemeteries
and Crematoria By-Law 2 of 2007). But there is
more! Let us assume the remains were exhumed in
the North West province, and the reburial will take
place in Limpopo. This means that the human
remains may have to be transported from North
West through Gauteng into Limpopo. Depending on
the location earmarked for the reburial there
might, in theory, be a number of different sets of
national and provincial legislation regulating the
transportation of human remains (eg regulations
made by the Minister of Health in terms of s 68 of
the National Health Act 61 of 2003; s 6(2)(dA) of
the Extension of Security of Tenure Act 62 of
1997; the Births and Deaths Registration Act 51 of
1992; the Transvaal Cemetery Ordinance 8 of
1932 for burials outside municipalities; the
Transvaal Local Government Ordinance 17 of 1939
(repealed for Gauteng by the Gauteng Local
Government Laws Amendment Act 1 of 2006)),
and so on and so forth. This is merely a
hypothetical example—apart from the cultural and
emotional issues involved in an exhumation and
subsequent reburial, this example tries to
emphasise that in the process there might be a
multitude of possible primary and subordinate legal
rules (both old and new) emanating from all three
spheres of government in a number of different
geographical areas.
Page 33
Another practical example
The Transkei Penal Code Act 9 of 1983 was
promulgated by the former Transkei for the
territory then known as the Republic of Transkei.
In 1994 the Transkei once again became part of
South Africa. In terms of s 229 of the interim
Constitution and item 2 of Schedule 6 of the
Constitution, the Transkei Penal Code remains in
force in the geographical area that used to be
Transkei. It has been amended a number of times
since: by the Justice Laws Rationalisation Act 18 of
1996 (which repealed Part 9 of the Transkei Penal
Code, which dealt with sexual offences), the
Criminal Law Amendment Act 105 of 1997 and the
Criminal Law (Sexual Offences and Related
Matters) Amendment Act 32 of 2007.
•
Common-law rules and rules of indigenous law
also constitute law (and can in most instances
be found in texts). However, these rules are
not enacted as legislation by an authorised
lawmaker.
Page 34
•
Case law is also binding law (dealing with
interpretation, development and application of
legal rules) and is found in texts, but since this
judge-made law is not issued by lawmakers it
does not constitute legislation.
•
Policy documents such as Green and White
Papers, interpretation notes, explanatory
memoranda and practice notes also constitute
law texts (practical applications of legal rules),
but as they were not enacted by lawmakers,
they do not constitute legislation. A wide range
of policy documents issued by government
departments in the process of formulating
public policy are published to elicit public
comment as part of a process of public
participation. In Akani Garden Route (Pty) Ltd
v Pinnacle Point Casino (Pty) Ltd 2001 (4) SA
501 (SCA) the court explained that laws,
regulations and rules are legislative
instruments, but policy determinations are not.
Policy determinations cannot override, amend
or be in conflict with legislation, otherwise the
separation between legislature and executive
will disappear.
Paradoxically, some of these legal texts
(explanatory memoranda, commission reports and
practice notes)—although not legislation—may be
used during the interpretation of legislation (as will
be explained in Chapter 6), or may even be part of
legislation in the future (Green and White Papers
and draft Bills).
Internal departmental memos and policy
guidelines on how government departments apply
legislation are circulated on a regular basis. These
and other official documents are not legislation.
Legislation (especially subordinate legislation)
should be distinguished from what Baxter (1984:
200) refers to as ‘administrative quasi-legislation’.
This consists of departmental memos and
directives, which, although enforceable in some
instances, do not constitute subordinate
legislation. Legal notices and even advertisements
are regularly published in the Gazette, but these
texts are not even close to being legislation.
List of amendments
If applicable, before the long title an Act will
include a list of Acts that have amended it since:
as amended by
Labour Relations Amendment Act 42 of 1996
Basic Conditions of Employment Act 75 of 1997
Labour Relations Amendment Act 127 of 1998
Labour Relations Amendment Act 12 of 2002
Intelligence Services Act 65 of 2002
Electronic Communications Security (Pty) Ltd Act
68 of 2002
General Intelligence Laws Amendment Act 52 of
2003
Prevention and Combating of Corrupt Activities Act
12 of 2004
Public Service Amendment Act 30 of 2007
List of regulations
If applicable, after the list of amendments an Act
will include a list of regulations issued in terms of
the Act:
Regulations under this Act
BARGAINING COUNCILS ACCREDITED BY THE
CCMA, 2009 (1) (GenN 195 in GG 31925 of 27
February 2009)
BARGAINING COUNCILS ACCREDITED BY THE
CCMA, 2009 (2) (GenN 863 in GG 32298 of 12
June 2009)
...
RULES FOR THE CONDUCT OF PROCEEDINGS IN
THE LABOUR COURT (GN 1665 in GG 17495 of 14
October 1996)
RULES REGULATING THE CONDUCT OF THE
PROCEEDINGS OF THE LABOUR APPEAL COURT
(GN 1666 of 14 October 1996)
Page 36
TARIFF OF FEES: COMMISSION FOR
CONCILIATION, MEDIATION AND ARBITRATION
(GN 231 in GG 34107 of 18 March 2011)
Preamble
The preamble (if there is one) states the
circumstances of, the background to and the
reasons for the legislation. Unlike private Acts,
where a preamble is always used, its use in
ordinary Acts is usually restricted to legislation of
constitutional or national importance. It is usually
placed after the long title and is an integral part of
the legislation. The following is the preamble to the
Prevention of Illegal Eviction from and Unlawful
Occupation of Land Act 19 of 1998:
Preamble
WHEREAS no one may be deprived of property
except in terms of law of general application,
and no law may permit arbitrary deprivation of
property;
AND WHEREAS no one may be evicted from
their home, or have their home demolished
without an order of court made after
considering all the relevant circumstances;
AND WHEREAS it is desirable that the law
should regulate the eviction of unlawful
occupiers from land in a fair manner, while
recognising the right of landowners to apply to
a court for an eviction order in appropriate
circumstances;
AND WHEREAS special consideration should
be given to the rights of the elderly, children,
disabled persons and particularly households
headed by women, and that it should be
recognised that the needs of those groups
should be considered; . . .
Long title
An Act always has a long title. It is not
really a title, but rather a short descriptive
summary of the subject matter of the Act.
The long title is a part of the statute
tabled for adoption by Parliament, and
always ends with an open-ended phrase
such as ‘. . . and matters incidental
thereto’.
ACT
To change the law governing labour
relations and, for that purpose—
to give effect to section 27 of the
Constitution; to regulate the
organisational rights of trade unions; to
promote and facilitate collective
bargaining at the workplace and at
sectoral level; to regulate the right to
strike and the recourse to lock-out in
conformity with the Constitution; to
promote employee participation in
decision-making through the
establishment of
Page 37
workplace forums; to provide simple
procedures for the resolution of labour
disputes through statutory conciliation,
mediation and arbitration (for which
purpose the Commission for Conciliation,
Mediation and Arbitration is established),
and through independent alternative
dispute resolution services accredited for
that purpose; to establish the Labour
Court and Labour Appeal Court as superior
courts, with exclusive jurisdiction to
decide matters arising from the Act; to
provide for a simplified procedure for the
registration of trade unions and
employers’ organisations, and to provide
for their regulation to ensure democratic
practices and proper financial control; to
give effect to the public international law
obligations of the Republic relating to
labour relations; to amend and repeal
certain laws relating to labour relations;
and to provide for incidental matters.
Enacting provision
This acknowledges the constitutional authority of
the body that is enacting the primary legislation
(the national legislative authority is vested in
Parliament; the provincial legislative authority is
vested in the provincial legislatures; and the
municipal legislative authority is vested in the
municipal councils):
BE IT ENACTED by the Parliament of the
Republic of South Africa as follows:—
Table of contents
The table of contents is the ‘road map’ of the Act.
It not only provides a quick reference to the reader
as to where to find particular provisions, but it also
gives an initial overview of the legislative scheme:
Contents of Act
Chapter I
Purpose, Application and Interpretation
1. Purpose of this Act
2. Exclusion from application of this
Act
3. Interpretation of this Act
...
As a ‘road map’ the table of contents of the
Income Tax Act 58 of 1962 (which is amended
very frequently) is a confusing reflection of the
continuous stream of amendments (including the
numbering of repealed provisions retained as
placeholders).
Page 38
Definitions
The definitions serve as an ‘internal dictionary’ for
the particular legislation. Definitions are usually
found at the beginning of an Act, but in the case of
the Labour Relations Act they are placed at the end
of the Act:
213 Definitions
In this Act, unless the context otherwise
indicates—
‘area’ includes any number of areas, whether
or not contiguous;
‘auditor’ means any person who is
registered to practise in the Republic as a
public accountant and auditor;
‘bargaining council’ means a bargaining
council referred to in section 27 and includes,
in relation to the public service, the bargaining
councils referred to in section 35;
...
But in the Labour Relations Act there are also
definitions in other parts of the Act, for example:
CHAPTER V
WORKPLACE FORUMS (ss 78-94)
78 Definitions in this Chapter
In this Chapter—
(a)
‘employee’ means any person who is
employed in a workplace, except a senior
managerial employee whose contract of
employment or status confers the authority to
do any of the following in the workplace—
(i)
...
[Sub-para. (i) deleted by s. 23 of Act 42 of
1996.]
(ii)
represent the employer in dealings with the
workplace forum; or
(iii)
determine policy and take decisions on behalf
of the employer that may be in conflict with the
representation of employees in the workplace;
...
(a)
any matter that in terms of this Act may or
must be prescribed; and
(b)
any matter that the Minister considers
necessary or expedient to prescribe or have
governed by regulation in order to achieve the
primary objects of this Act.
[Date of commencement of s. 208: 1
January 1996.]
Repeal/amendment of legislation
Repeals and amendments of an Act are made by
means of another Act. When a new Act is passed,
other existing Acts may need to be amended or
repealed. The new Act must contain a section that
provides for amendments and/or repeals. The
conventional way of dealing with repealed or
amended Acts is with a schedule at the end of the
Act.
211 Amendment of laws
Each of the laws referred to in items 1 and 2
of Schedule 5 is hereby amended to the extent
specified in those items.
212 Repeal of laws, and transitional
arrangements
(1) Each of the laws referred to in the first
two columns of Schedule 6 is hereby repealed
to the extent specified opposite that law in the
third column of that Schedule.
(2) The repeal of those laws does not affect
any transitional arrangements made in
Schedule 7.
(3) The transitional arrangements in Schedule
7 must be read and applied as substantive
provisions of this Act.
Schedules
These are used to deal with technical detail that
will otherwise clog up the main body of an Act (eg
Schedule 1 of the Constitution, which contains a
description of the national flag). Schedules are also
used when several Acts or parts of Acts are
repealed, or for a large number of amendments.
Numbering in legislation
The following is the traditional numbering system
used in primary legislation:
Section 1—Arabic figures
Subsection (1)—Arabic figures in brackets
Paragraph (a)—italicised lowercase letter in
italicised brackets
Subparagraph (i)—Roman figures in brackets
Item (aa)—italicised lowercase letters in
italicised brackets
Subitem (AA)—italicised uppercase letters in
italicised brackets
Where an additional section is inserted into an Act
through an amendment Act, the section to be
inserted takes the number of the section after
which it is to be inserted and gets a capital letter
after it. If, for example, you need to insert a new
section between the current ss 66 and 67, you will
insert s 66A. This system of numbering is
necessary, otherwise the whole Act would have to
be re-numbered, and such renumbering will have
to be done by means of an amendment Act.
However, in practical terms renumbering is
impossible: every cross-reference in other
legislation would have to be amended as well, but
references to the previous numbering in case law
and text books cannot be changed. In older
legislation the inserted sections were numbered
bis, ter, quat, and so on.
Page 41
For example:
200A Presumption as to who is employee
(1) Until the contrary is proved, a person
who works for, or renders services to, any
other person is presumed, regardless of the
form of the contract, to be an employee, if any
one or more of the following factors are
present:
(a)
the manner in which the person works is
subject to the control or direction of another
person;
...
[S. 200A inserted by s. 51 of Act 12 of
2002.]
When a part of legislation (be it a chapter, section,
paragraph, and so on) is repealed, the number of
the repealed provision remains as a placeholder to
avoid wholesale renumbering. For example, in the
Income Tax Act, where a number of provisions of
the Act were repealed, the original numbers
remain as placeholders:
49 . . .
[S. 49 repealed by s. 31(1) of Act 101 of
1990.]
50 . . .
[S. 50 repealed by s. 32(1) of Act 101 of
1990.]
51 . . .
[S. 51 repealed by s. 33(1) of Act 101 of
1990.]
52 . . .
[S. 52 repealed by s. 34(1) of Act 101 of
1990.]
53 . . .
[S. 53 repealed by s. 35(1) of Act 101 of
1990.]
Legislative ‘codes’
Amendments (including insertions and deletions)
are also indicated clearly in square brackets after
the relevant provisions in the amended version of
an Act. These indicators help the interpreter of the
Act in a number of ways, for example:
Page 42
•
It may indicate a particular date of
commencement for the provision.
•
It will serve as a historical paper trail should a
lawyer have to use the previous versions of the
legislation (for pending cases or as an aid to
interpreting the amended provisions). Please
bear in mind that although an amendment Act
is a separately enacted law-text in its own
right, the amendments in an amending Act will
later be incorporated into the initial Act. The
legislative ‘codes’ serve as a route map or
cross-reference to the amending Acts. In other
words, the ‘codes’, the list of amending Acts at
the beginning of the Act and the amending Acts
themselves should correlate.
•
Where a section was amended:
[S. 1 amended by s. 1 of Act 45 of 1961.]
•
Where a definition in the definition section was
first amended, then substituted and then finally
deleted:
‘dependant’ . . .
[Definition of ‘dependant’ substituted by s.4
(1)(b) of Act 88 of 1971 and by s. 4(1)(d) of
Act 85 of 1974, amended by s. 3(1)(a) of
Act 104 of 1979 and by s. 2(1)(c) of Act 104
of 1980 and deleted by s. 2(b) of Act 90 of
1988.]
•
Where a subsection was inserted without the
need for renumbering:
[Sub-s. (7) added by s. 4(b) of Act 16 of
2004.]
•
Where a paragraph was inserted without the
need for renumbering:
[Para. (c) added by s. 4(b) of Act 201 of
1993.]
•
Where a section was amended and later
repealed in full:
9 ...
[S. 9 substituted by s. 3 of Act 45 of 1961
and repealed by s. 344 (1) of Act 51 of
1977.]
•
Where a new section was inserted between ss
16 and 17:
[S. 16A inserted by s. 13 of Act 102 of
1967.]
•
Where a new section was inserted between ss
5 and 6, amended several times and later
repealed in full:
5A . . .
[S. 5A inserted by s. 6 of Act 88 of 1971,
amended by s. 5(1) of Act 85 of 1974, by s.
5 of Act 69 of 1975, by s. 6 of Act 103 of
1976, by s. 6 of Act 113 of 1977 and by s. 5
of Act 104 of 1979 and repealed by s. 4 of
Act 104 of 1980.]
Page 43
Chapter 3
Is it in force? The
commencement of legislation
•
If, for some reason beyond its control, the
Government Printer is unable to print the
Gazette, the President may by proclamation
prescribe alternative procedures for the
promulgation of legislation (s 16A of the
Interpretation Act).
•
When the President, a Minister, a Premier or a
member of the executive committee of a
province has the power to issue delegated
legislation, a list of proclamations and notices
under which such types of delegated legislation
were published must to be tabled in Parliament
(s 17 of the Interpretation Act). Certain new
legislation (eg the Promotion of Equality and
Prevention of Unfair Discrimination Act) also
requires regulations made in terms of the
particular Act to be furnished to Parliament
before publication.
•
Since a commencement date before the
enactment of the legislation is impossible in
real physical terms, the legislation creates a
legal fiction: the legislation does not change
the fact; it makes-believe that the facts
(reality) are otherwise.
Page 58
•
In other words, the deeming clause creates a
presumption, in this case by providing that
something is ‘deemed’ to have happened.
•
Such a necessary implication could be inferred
if the legislation would result in absurd or
unfair results should it not have retro-effect
(Lek v Estate Agents Board 1978 (3) SA 160
(C)).
Page 59
•
In Kruger v President Insurance Co Ltd 1994
(2) SA 495 (D) 503G the court held that it was
easier to decide (by necessary implication) that
legislation did not apply to the future only
when vested rights would not be affected by
the retro-effect of the legislation; or the
purpose of the legislation is to grant a benefit
or to effect even-handedness in the operation
of the law.
Case law example:
In R v Mazibuko 1958 (4) SA 353 (A) the court
heard an appeal against the death sentence
imposed for robbery. The Criminal Procedure Act
56 of 1955 was amended after the crime had been
committed but before sentence was passed. In
terms of the amended Act, the death sentence
could be imposed after a conviction for robbery
with aggravating circumstances. The court applied
the presumption that legislation only applies in
respect of the future, and found that the
legislature had not intended that the increased
penalty should apply retroactively. The earlier,
more lenient penalty was imposed. The increased
penalty could have been imposed only in respect of
crimes committed after the Amendment Act came
into effect. The court relied on the common-law
rule that if there is a difference in penalties
between the date of the crime and the date of the
trial, the date of the crime will be decisive.
•
As was explained earlier, all law in force when
the Constitution took effect remains in force
subject to amendment or repeal, and subject to
consistency with the Constitution (item 2
Schedule 6 of the Constitution).
•
All proceedings pending before a court when
the new Constitution took effect must be
finalised as if the new Constitution had not
been enacted, unless the interests of justice
require otherwise (item 17 Schedule 6 of the
Constitution).
•
However, any legislative process started in
terms of the interim Constitution, but not yet
finalised when the 1996 Constitution took
effect, must be finalised in terms of the 1996
Constitution (item 5 Schedule 6 of the
Constitution).
Page 63
Chapter 4
Is it still in force? Changes to
and the demise of legislation
4.1 General
In the previous chapter the commencement of
legislation was discussed, and the question was: Is
it in force yet? Now the question is: Is it still in
force, and if so, has it since been amended? In this
chapter the ways in which legislation may be
changed or come to end will be explained.
Common-law rules can be abrogated by disuse,
but this cannot happen to legislation (R v Detody
1926 AD 168). It cannot simply disappear; it needs
to be repealed by a competent body or declared
invalid by a court. Before 1994 Parliament was
sovereign, and the courts could only invalidate
delegated legislation which did not comply with the
rules of administrative law. After 1994 the courts
could test all legislation, including Acts of
Parliament, against the supreme Constitution.
Who may amend and repeal legislation?
It is important to understand that the Constitution
is not self-executing. Although s 2 of the
Constitution expressly states that legislation which
is in conflict with the Constitution is invalid, it
merely means that legislation is potentially
unconstitutional. Legislation that is inconsistent
with the Constitution will not automatically be
unconstitutional and invalid. All legislation in force
when the Constitution took effect remains in force
until it is amended or repealed, or is declared
Page 64
unconstitutional (item 2(1) Schedule 6 of the
Constitution). To remove potentially
unconstitutional legislation, a competent body
must either amend or repeal it, or a competent
court must declare it unconstitutional.
As was pointed out earlier, legislation cannot fall
away through disuse or simply disappear; it
remains in force until amended or repealed. But
amended or repealed by whom? Legislation—
enacted law-texts—is amended or repealed by the
relevant competent lawmakers, in other words,
those bodies or persons with the legislative
authority to do so.
For original legislation the legislative authority of
the relevant legislatures includes the power to pass
or amend any legislation before them, subject of
course to the hierarchical and territorial
competencies prescribed by the Constitution (ss 44
and 55 read with s 68, in the case of Parliament;
ss 104 and 114 in the case of provincial
legislatures; and s 156 in the case of
municipalities).
In the case of subordinate legislation the
enabling Act may in some cases expressly state
that the power to enact subordinate legislation
includes the power to amend or repeal it (eg the
Rules Board for Courts of Law Act, which
empowers the Rules Board for Courts of Law to
make, amend or repeal the rules for the Supreme
Court of Appeal, the High Courts and the lower
courts). In the absence of such an express
provision that the subordinate lawmaker may also
amend or repeal the subordinate legislation, the
common-law principle of implied powers will come
into play: if a delegated lawmaker gets the power
to enact subordinate legislation, it is assumed that
such a power to make laws also by implication
includes the power to amend or repeal (revoke,
rescind or retract) such subordinate legislation.
However, to avoid legal arguments about implied
delegated legislative powers, s 10 of the
Interpretation Act expressly deals with such a
situation:
10 Construction of provisions as to
exercise of powers and performance of
duties
(1) When a law confers a power or imposes a
duty then, unless the contrary intention
appears, the power may be exercised and the
duty shall be performed from time to time as
occasion requires.
...
(3) Where a law confers a power to make
rules, regulations or by-laws, the power shall,
unless the contrary intention appears, be
construed as including a power exercisable in
like manner and
Page 65
subject to the like consent and conditions (if
any) to rescind, revoke, amend or vary the
rules, regulations or by-laws.
...
(a)
determine a date on which this item ceases to
have effect, but no such notice may be given
until the Minister is satisfied that alternative
legislation has been brought into force
adequately providing for the winding-up and
liquidation of insolvent companies; and
(b)
prescribe ancillary rules as may be necessary
to provide for the efficient transition from the
provisions of the
Page 70
repealed Act, to the provisions of the
alternative legislation contemplated in
paragraph (a).
However, for those cases where the legislation in
question does not provide for express transitional
arrangements, s 11 of the Interpretation Act was
enacted to deal with those unfortunate gaps in the
law if the one enactment is repealed, but the
replacement enactment has not yet become
operational:
When a law repeals wholly or partially any
former law and substitutes provisions for the
law so repealed, the repealed law shall remain
in force until the substituted provisions come
into operation.
This means that if an enactment has been repealed
and is replaced by another, but the replacement is
not yet operational (for whatever reason), the
repealed provision will remain in force—although
repealed—until the replacement is in force.
Case law example:
In S v Koopman 1991 (1) SA 474 (NC) the accused
was found guilty in the magistrate’s court of a
contravention of the Road Traffic Act 29 of 1989
and sentenced to a fine, as well as to an
endorsement of his driver’s licence. On review his
lawyer argued that the endorsement was invalid,
because the Cape Province Road Traffic Ordinance
21 of 1966 had been repealed by the Road Traffic
Act 29 of 1989. The provisions in the Act which
authorised the suspension, endorsement or
rescission of driver’s licences had not yet come
into operation. However, the court held that in
terms of s 11 of the Interpretation Act the
provision in the repealed ordinance providing for
such endorsement was still in operation. The
endorsement of the licence by magistrate’s court
was then confirmed.
Practical examples:
The Child Care Act 74 of 1983 had been repealed
in total by the new Children’s Act 38 of 2005 (s
313 read with Schedule 4). The major part of the
Children’s Act commenced on 1 July 2007, and the
remainder took effect on 1 April 2010. This meant
that a number of provisions in the 1983
Page 71
Child Care Act (although repealed) remained in
force until the corresponding replacements in the
new 2005 Children’s Act finally entered into force
on 1 April 2010.
The Human Tissue Act 65 of 1983 was repealed
and replaced by the National Health Act 61 of
2003. The National Health Act commenced on 2
May 2005, unless otherwise indicated. One of the
parts of the National Health Act that did not
commence on 2 May 2005 was Chapter 8
(‘CONTROL OF USE OF BLOOD, BLOOD PRODUCTS,
TISSUE AND GAMETES IN HUMANS’), which meant
that the corresponding Chapter 2 of the repealed
Human Tissue Act (‘TISSUE, BLOOD AND GAMETES
OF LIVING PERSONS, AND BLOOD PRODUCTS’)
remained in operation until Chapter 8 of the
National Health Act was finally put into operation.
The remainder of the National Health Act took
effect on 1 March 2012, with the exception of s 53
(which had commenced on 30 June 2008), and ss
55, 56 and 68 (which had commenced on 17 May
2010). Consequently Chapter 2 of the Human
Tissue Act (which in some form or another
remained operational through the intervention of s
11 of the Interpretation Act) was finally put to rest
on 1 March 2012, nearly seven years after the rest
of the National Health Act had commenced.
(a)
revive anything not in force or existing at the
time at which the repeal takes effect; or
(b)
affect the previous operation of any law so
repealed or anything duly done or suffered
under the law so repealed; or
(c)
affect any right, privilege, obligation, or liability
acquired, accrued, or incurred under any law
so repealed; or
(d)
affect any penalty, forfeiture, or punishment
incurred in respect of any offence committed
against any law so repealed; or
(e)
affect any investigation, legal proceeding, or
remedy in respect of any such right, privilege,
obligation, liability, forfeiture, or punishment as
is in this sub-section mentioned;
and any such investigation, legal proceeding,
or remedy may be instituted, continued, or
enforced, any such penalty, forfeiture, or
punishment may be imposed, as if the
repealing law has not been passed.
Section 12(2) is a typical transitional provision.
Section 12(2)(a) means that a repealed Act does
not regain the force of law if the repealing Act itself
is repealed. If an Act, which declared a particular
action illegal, is repealed, the repeal does not have
retroactive effect, declaring legal that which was
illegal before the repeal; and if an amendment Act
is subsequently repealed, the amendment does not
lapse with the repeal (R v Maluma 1949 (3) SA
856 (T)).
Paragraphs (b) to (e) of s 12(2) are similar in
principle: all actions, transactions, processes,
prosecutions, enforcement of rights and remedies,
et cetera, which have been started, but not yet
completed, in terms of legislation which has
meanwhile been repealed, must be completed as if
the legislation has not been repealed. This also
means the following:
•
It forms a bridge between pending actions and
the repealed legislation; the current position is
preserved until the pending case is finished
(Transnet Ltd v Ngcezula (above)).
•
Actions executed legally and properly in
accordance with legislation, before that
legislation is repealed, remain valid and in
force after the repeal.
•
This provision deals with rights derived from
legislation only, and not with those stemming
from common law (Garydale Estate and
Investment Co (Pty) Ltd v Johannesburg
Western Rent Board 1957 (2) SA 466 (T)).
Page 73
•
The right or privilege in question needs to have
been acquired or accrued in terms of the
repealed legislation before the repeal
(Mahomed v Union Government 1911 AD 1).
Case law examples:
An excellent example is found in Estate Crosby v
Wynberg Municipality 1912 CPD 1026. A valuation
list was drawn up and an appraiser sworn in for the
intended session of a valuation court. All this was
properly done, but before the session of the court
could take place, the authorising Act was repealed
and replaced by an ordinance. The court decided
that the valuation process had to be completed in
terms of the repealed legislation as if it was not
repealed.
Another case which dealt with s 12(2)(c) and (d)
was Keagile v Attorney-General, Transvaal 1984
(2) SA 816 (T). The accused appeared in court in
June 1982 on a charge of contravening the
Internal Security Act 44 of 1950. He was refused
bail on 29 July 1982 on the grounds of a statement
by the Attorney-General of the Transvaal. Act 44 of
1950 was repealed on 2 July 1982, however, and
replaced by the Internal Security Act 74 of 1982.
The defence argued that the Attorney-General
could not issue his declaration for the refusal of
bail in terms of Act 44 of 1950, as this Act had
been repealed before the declaration was made.
Furthermore, the declaration could not be issued
by virtue of the new Act 74 of 1982, as the
accused had not committed the offence in terms of
the new Act. The court held that, in terms of s
12(2)(d) of the Interpretation Act, the accused
should still be tried under Act 44 of 1950.
Moreover, s 12(2)(c) of the Interpretation Act had
the effect that the Attorney-General’s power
(under Act 44 of 1950) to issue a statement with
regard to the refusal of bail remained effective, in
spite of the fact that Act 44 of 1950 had been
repealed in the interim. The court therefore
refused the application for review of the refusal of
bail.
Page 74
Another case law example:
Nourse v Van Heerden 1999 (2) SACR 198 (W) is a
very good example of the application of the demise
of legislation, s 12(2) of the Interpretation Act, as
well as of retroactivity. During 1992 a
gynaecologist and obstetrician from Durban was
charged in terms of the Abortion and Sterilization
Act 2 of 1975 with the performance of illegal
abortions. His trial commenced on 27 November
1992, but was not yet finished by 1997. On 1 July
1997 his legal representative brought an
application to have the charges against his client
dropped, since at that stage abortions were not
illegal anymore and as a result his client’s actions
no longer constituted crimes. The legal
representative of the physician based his
application on the following arguments:
•
The provisions of the Abortion and Sterilization
Act governing illegal abortions have not been
applied since the mid-1990s and as a result
those provisions were abrogated by disuse.
•
The Abortion and Sterilization Act was repealed
by the Choice on Termination of Pregnancy Act
92 of 1996 in so far as it relates to abortion
(the Choice on Termination of Pregnancy Act
entered into force on 1 February 1997).
•
In terms of the fundamental values referred to
in s 1 of the Constitution, as well as the Bill of
Rights (especially s 9 (the right to equality), s
12(2)(a) and (b) (the right to make decisions
concerning reproduction and security in and
control over one’s body), s 14 (right to privacy)
and s 27(1)(a) (the right to reproductive health
care)), the prohibition of abortions is in any
event retroactively unconstitutional.
The court found that legislation could not be
abrogated by disuse, and had to be repealed by a
competent legislature. Existing legislation
remained in force until repealed or declared
unconstitutional. The trial started before the repeal
of the Abortion Act, and in terms of s 12(2) of the
Interpretation Act the trial had to be completed as
if the Abortion Act had not been repealed.
Furthermore, the trial started before either the
interim Constitution or the 1996 Constitution
Page 75
commenced. Since none of the Constitutions was
retroactive, the trial had to be completed in terms
of the law existing at the start of the trial. Finally,
legislation is not automatically unconstitutional,
and the Abortion Act was never declared
unconstitutional by any court of law.
Repeal of legislation incorporated by reference
Sunset clauses
Implied repeal
4.5.2 Legislation
With regard to legislation, the presumption means
that in interpreting a subsequent Act it is assumed
that the legislature did not intend to repeal or
modify the earlier Act (Kent v SA Railways and
Harbours 1946 AD 405). Any repeal or amendment
has to be indicated expressly or by necessary
implication. An attempt should be made to read
the earlier and subsequent legislation together in
an effort to reconcile them (Wendywood
Development (Pty) Ltd v Rieger 1971 (3) SA 28
(A)). In Shozi v Minister of Justice, Kwazulu 1992
(2) SA 338 (NPD) 343B the court stated that-
if two apparently contradictory provisions are
capable of a sensible interpretation which
would reconcile the apparent contradiction,
that interpretation should be preferred.
If such reconciliation is impossible, it has to be
presumed by necessary implication that the later
of the two provisions prevails, resulting in the
amendment or repeal of the earlier one (Entabeni
Hospital Ltd v Van der Linde; First National Bank of
SA v Puckriah 1994 (2) SA 422 (N)).
Case law example:
An interesting example of the repeal of an earlier
Act by necessary implication concerned the
Ingwavuma/KwaZulu land issue during the
apartheid era. The State President proclaimed that
the Ingwavuma territory, which had belonged to
the KwaZulu homeland, would no longer be part of
that territory. The question arose whether the
State President should have consulted the KwaZulu
government or not. In Government of the Republic
of South Africa v Government of KwaZulu 1983 (1)
SA 164 (A) the Appellate Division heard the appeal
against a decision of the Supreme Court which
invalidated the proclamation, because the South
African government had not consulted the KwaZulu
homeland authorities. The appellants argued that
the proclamation had been promulgated correctly
in terms of the Black Administration Act 38 of
1927, which did not require consultation prior to
the alteration of the territories of the national
states. However, the court found that s 25(1)
Page 80
of Act 38 of 1927 conflicted with s 1(2) of the Self-
Governing Territories Constitution Act 21 of 1971,
which provided that the territory of a homeland
could only be altered after consultation with that
particular homeland. As the two provisions could
not be reconciled, it was presumed that the earlier
provisions in the 1927 Act had, by necessary
implication, been repealed by the later provisions
of the 1971 Act.
Obviously this rule only applies if the objects of the
two conflicting provisions are in pari materia
(essentially the same). Legislative repeal, by
implication, will only be accepted by the court if
the subsequent legislation manifestly contradicts
the earlier legislation (Minister of Police v Haunawa
1991 (2) SA 542 (Nm)). Furthermore, according to
the rule generalia specialibus non derogant, it is
presumed that a provision in a subsequent general
Act does not repeal an earlier specific provision
(Sappi Fine Papers (Pty) Ltd v ICI Canada Inc 1992
(3) SA 306 (A)).
Page 81
Part 2
How legislation is
interpreted
5
Theoretical foundations
6
A practical, inclusive methodology: The five
interrelated dimensions of interpretation
Page 83
Chapter 5
Theoretical foundations
5.1 Introduction
Most law students dislike profound philosophical
discourses about the theoretical foundations of any
legal subject. Unfortunately, the theoretical
background of statutory interpretation cannot
simply be ignored or wished away. A basic
understanding of theory is essential for a
perspective on and understanding of the subject.
The aim of this chapter is to provide a very brief
introduction to the theoretical basis of statutory
interpretation in general, and in South Africa in
particular. This chapter deals with what Eskridge
(2001: 200) refers to as ‘legisprudence’: the
jurisprudence of interpreting legislation.
5.2 Jurisprudential perspectives on
statutory interpretation
5.2.1 The general principles of hermeneutics
Lategan (1980: 107) defines hermeneutics as the
science of understanding, or more specifically, as
the theory of the interpretation of texts. Baxter
(1984: 315) describes it as the understanding and
explanation of texts to reveal their inherent
meaning. It is the art of understanding the
techniques, methods or approaches used to
interpret texts. In its broader sense, hermeneutics
applies to all forms of written or spoken
communication. Every day, each one of us has to
interpret symbols; not only texts, but also facial
expressions, films, traffic signs, et cetera. In fact,
interpretation is one of the most basic human
activities. We are constantly trying to ‘read
between the lines’.
The word ‘hermeneutics’ is derived from the
Greek word hermeneuein which means ‘to
interpret’. Hermeneuein is in
Page 84
turn derived from the name Hermes, the
messenger god of ancient Greece, who had to
explain the messages of the gods to the mortals on
earth. This means that hermeneutics is a very old
discipline, used by the Greeks of antiquity—
Aristotle addressed the science of interpretation in
his discourses. Throughout history it became an
important and useful tool in both Christian
theology and jurisprudence. Biblical hermeneutics
(scriptural exegesis) and legal hermeneutics
(interpretation of statutes) developed as separate
fields, although they had a great deal in common,
since both had very strong normative
characteristics. In the case of Biblical hermeneutics
(especially after the Reformation), the message of
the Scriptures has to be constantly reinterpreted to
adapt to changing circumstances and to retain its
relevance for the modern believer. Likewise, the
legislature cannot provide a set of exhaustive
descriptions and regulations for all possible
concrete situations. Therefore, it is the task of the
courts to concretise the general precepts of the
legislature through interpretation of legislation.
Lategan (1980: 108-110) points out a number of
similarities and differences between Christian
theological and legal hermeneutics. Some of the
similarities are the following:
•
Both disciplines aim to interpret established
authoritative texts with regard to current
concrete situations.
•
Both have an existential urgency: it is the
purpose of interpretation of the Scriptures to
offer a liberating message of salvation to
sinners, while statutory interpretation is aimed
at legal certainty and order.
•
In both disciplines the interpreter has to deal
with the demands of changing situations and
circumstances.
•
The interpretation of both the Scriptures and
legislation are influenced by history.
However, there are also a number of distinct
differences:
•
Legislation is a distinct style, with its own rules,
which is aimed at the legal regulation of
society.
•
The biblical text is closed (ie the text is
complete); legislation, on the other hand, is
characterised by continuous development and
change.
Labuschagne (1986: 370) distinguishes between
exegesis (that which the author originally wanted
to say to the readers), and hermeneutics (that
which the author wants to say to present-day
readers).
Page 85
It was only during the second half of the
nineteenth century that hermeneutics as a general
method of understanding for the human sciences
gained prominence. In this regard the work of the
German philosopher Dilthey was of decisive
importance. In contemporary hermeneutics the
German philosophers Hans-Georg Gadamer,
Ricoeur and Schleiermacher and the Italian Betti
are the leading figures. Gadamer’s hermeneutics
emphasised the importance of the socio-historical
situation or context of the interpreter, and is closer
to a contextual approach to texts than to a literal
one. Scholars of hermeneutics emphasised that
words and phrases do not have inherent meaning,
but that meaning is derived from the total
structure of language, including the context in
which it is used. Perhaps the greatest contribution
made by the hermeneutical theory is its emphasis
of the role of the interpreter during the
interpretation process, and that the science of
understanding is not a mechanical exercise, but
also involves value judgements. Baxter (1984:
319) argues that this supports the argument that
interpreters of legislation inevitably have to
exercise a judicial discretion.
But what is the practical relevance of
hermeneutics for the interpretation of legislation?
Du Plessis (1980: 29) explains it with the so-called
‘hermeneutical circle’—every part of a text must be
understood in terms of the whole, and in turn, the
whole in terms of its parts. This is a continuous
process during which both the whole and the parts
are progressively explained. This part-whole
approach underlines the importance of the context
of a specific phrase or sentence.
Context and interpretation
According to the well-known saying, every picture
tells a story, and that is true. Famous photographs
and paintings have been telling stories for
centuries. Assume that a painting is a unique type
of text, with the brush strokes on the canvas like
words on paper. However, to make sense of the
picture and what it wants to say, its context
(background) needs to be considered as well.
Page 86
Practical example:
Picasso’s famous painting Guernica (now in the
Museum of Modern Art, New York) consists of a
disturbing mix of violent images. Amongst other
things we see a screaming woman; a horse,
pierced by a spear, collapsing to its knees; a dead
fighter; a woman with a senseless child in her
arms; a burning house; and so on. To understand
the images, some research about the painting’s
context is necessary. On a time line the painting is
situated in 1937, during the Spanish civil war. It is
named after the Basque town Guernica which,
while under Republican control, was totally
destroyed by Franco’s Nationalist fascist forces
(supported by the German and Italian air forces)
during the indiscriminate aerial bombing of the
town. With other more conventional anti-war texts
(for instance, the poetry of Siegfried Sassoon and
Wilfred Owen, or the protest music of Bob Dylan) it
has since become a universal symbol of the horrors
and atrocities of war. To cut a long story short:
text (painting) plus context (background) equals
understanding (or at least the beginning of a
process of understanding).
•
Postmodernism argues that the utopian
promises of the modern world-view came to
nothing. The modernists tried to explain and
order the world with macro-arguments such as
liberalism, Marxism and fascism. These macro-
arguments (the so-called ‘big picture’) could
not solve global problems, because the
problems (questions) were too big, too wide,
and too abstract. These macro-arguments were
based on a naive humanism, a mistaken belief
in science and technology, and a false
optimism about the ability of language to
compile, disseminate and interpret information.
•
Postmodernism rejects the idea that
classifications and categories can be correct
and final, and the notions of both objectivity
and subjectivity are questioned; ultimately
everything (including knowledge) is relative,
temporary and incomplete. Therefore any
argument, no matter how logical it may seem,
is only as good as its preconceptions and
presuppositions.
Two postmodern theories will be discussed very
briefly. However, these are not the only modern
critical schools of thought. Theories such as critical
race theory, feminism, law and literature, and law
and economics are not even touched upon.
•
Within the liberal legal tradition the
determination of legal rules is based on hidden
political and ideological considerations. Rules
and principles only change as a result of
changes in the political arena.
•
The liberal legal tradition is based on individual
autonomy, which does not take
communitarianism and community involvement
into account. Existing rights favour the
individual. The liberal jurisprudence entrenches
the position of the individual and reinforces the
unequal distribution of power in society.
Ultimately the entire world-view is ‘encoded’
and interpreted in terms of the liberal legal
tradition.
•
With regard to interpretation of statutes in
particular, CLS argues that legal theories and
legal reasoning are supported by political
considerations, and the existing political and
social balance of power is consolidated.
(b) Deconstruction
•
It is impossible to obtain knowledge of the real
objective world. All meaning takes place within
the framework of language (symbols). The
meaning of each symbol (word) depends on
the differences from, as well as the similarities
between, other symbols in the system:
meaning depends not only on the differences
between symbols, but also on the continuous
reference to other symbols in the system. No
symbol is ever complete but it acquires
meaning from this never-ending circle of
mutual difference and dependence. Meaning is
indefinitely deferred, because inherently each
symbol refers to other symbols as well. A text
is never closed or finished, but consists of a
network of interlinked symbols which infinitely
refer to each other.
•
The meaning of a text is not determined by its
author, but by the relationship between texts,
and between text and reader. The fact that the
text is liberated from the author (the so-called
‘death of the author’), enables the reader to
read the symbols in the text (as well as other
texts) in an unbiased and impartial manner.
•
A text can never acquire one fixed and final
meaning, because each text refers to another
text. Meaning depends on a set of codes (eg
social, cultural and political) inherent in each
text and each reader. Each reader will have
different texts interacting with one another.
Consequently, any valid meaning depends on
the social, cultural and political circumstances
of each reader. Meaning is not inherently
embedded in the text, and consequently a text
may lead to any number of subjective
interpretations and meanings. In other words,
what we did not say is just as important as that
which we did say. By definition the
interpretation of a text is subjective. According
to deconstruction theory, meaning is always
disputable. The reading of a text does not end
with the fixing of a final meaning, but it ends
merely with a temporary undecidability, which
in turn is open to reinterpretations.
•
During the interpretation of statutes, different
texts are simultaneously in interaction with
each other: other legislative texts, the common
law, case law, and so on. The
Page 90
interpreter is informed not only by the
interacting texts, but also by other extra-legal
factors (codes) such as cultural and ideological
background. Thus interpretation of statutes has
to do with the relationship between the
interpreter and the text. The legislature cannot
control the manner in which the interpreter will
interpret the legislative text. The text-based
methods of statutory interpretation (literal
interpretation and the intention theory) cannot
explain the nature of the interpretation
process. Statutory interpretation requires an
ongoing reinterpretation of the past, as well as
a continuous open-mindedness about future
reinterpretations of the legislative text.
•
Contextual interpretation is also criticised. A
text can only acquire a fixed meaning through
its context if the context has a fixed content.
Context does not have boundaries, and there is
no limit to what is necessarily relevant for the
context.
•
Deconstruction shifts the focus to judicial
choices and accountability; interpretation is not
neutral and value-free. The interpreter is in a
sense controlled by personal, cultural and
ideological value systems. During statutory
interpretation the interpreter makes certain
‘choices’ which are explicit and conscious. Each
interpreter has to accept personal responsibility
for the choices that are made. Even if the
choice is in favour of the status quo (the
existing order), it is still a conscious choice,
one that should not be disguised by references
to clear texts and the intention of the
legislature. The interpreter cannot hide behind
value-free and mechanical methods of
interpretation, and is responsible for the
ideological values underlying each
interpretation.
•
It is the primary rule of interpretation that, if
the meaning of the text is clear (the plain
meaning), it should be applied, and, indeed,
equated with the legislature’s intention
(Principal Immigration Officer v Hawabu 1936
AD 26).
•
If the ‘plain meaning’ of the words is
ambiguous, vague or misleading, or if a strict
literal interpretation would result in absurd
results, then the court may deviate from the
literal meaning to avoid such an absurdity
(Venter v R 1907 TS 910 914). This is also
known as the ‘golden rule’ of interpretation.
Then the court will turn to the so-called
‘secondary aids’ to interpretation to find the
intention of the legislature (eg the long title of
the statute, headings of chapters and sections,
the text in the other official language, etc).
•
Only when these ‘secondary aids’ to
interpretation prove insufficient to ascertain the
intention, will the courts have recourse to the
so-called ‘tertiary aids’ to construction (ie the
common-law presumptions).
This approach was popular in legal systems
influenced by
Page 92
English law. Generally speaking, four factors
led to the adoption of the textual approach in
England:
•
Misconceptions about the doctrines of the
separation of powers (the trias politica
doctrine) and sovereignty of Parliament
resulted in acceptance of the idea that the
court’s function should be limited to the
interpretation and application of the will of the
legislature, as recorded in the text of the
particular legislation. In other words, the will of
the legislature is to be found in the words of
the legislation.
•
The doctrine of legal positivism influenced the
literal approach in England. The positivist idea
is based on the validity of the decree
(command): that which is decreed by the state
is law, and consequently the essence of the law
is to be found in the command or decree. The
role of the court is limited to the analysis of the
law as it is and to find the intention of the
legislature, and should not be a speculation
about what the law ought to be. A strict
distinction is made between ‘black-letter law’
and morality, because value judgements by the
courts would lead to the justiciability of policy
issues.
•
England has a common-law tradition, in which
the courts have traditionally played a very
creative role in regard to common-law
principles. Legislation was viewed as the
exception to the rule, altering the traditional
common law as little as possible.
•
English legislation was drafted to be as precise
and as detailed as possible, for the sake of
legal certainty and to cover any number of
possible future cases. The well-known maxim
that the legislature has prescribed everything it
wishes to prescribe is derived from this
approach.
This text-based approach was introduced into the
South African legal system in a roundabout way
from English law. In De Villiers v Cape Divisional
Council 1875 Buch 50, Chief Justice De Villiers
decided that legislation that had been adopted
after the British had taken over the Cape should be
interpreted in accordance with the English rules of
statutory interpretation. This was a strange
decision: in terms of English law, a conquered
territory continued to apply its own legal system
(in this case, Roman-Dutch law). Traditionally, the
Roman-Dutch rules of statutory interpretation were
based on a functional or purpose-oriented
approach, but after the British occupation of the
Cape, the English law rules of interpretation
started to play an increasingly important role.
Page 93
The text-based methodology is based on the
‘predominance of the word’, and the intention of
the legislature is demoted to the status of the
literal meaning of the text. Over the years the
courts came to regard the clear, literal meaning as
identical to what the legislature intended. In cases
such as Union Government v Mack 1917 AD 731
and Farrar’s Estate v CIR 1926 TPD 501 it was held
that the intention of the legislature should be
deduced from the words used in the legislation; in
other words, the plain meaning of the text in an
intentional disguise. As a result, only lip-service
was paid to the principle of legislative intent,
because the courts automatically elevated the so-
called ‘clear and unambiguous meaning of the
words’ to the status of the will and intention of the
legislature: if the legislature had a specific
intention, it would be reflected in the clear and
unambiguous words of the text (eg Ensor v Rensco
Motors (Pty) Ltd 1981 (1) SA 815 (A)).
Case law examples:
The following dictum of Stratford JA in Bhyat v
Commissioner for Immigration 1932 AD 125 129 is
probably the classic formulation of the orthodox
text-based method of interpretation employed by
South African courts:
The cardinal rule of construction of a statute is
to endeavour to arrive at the intention of the
lawgiver from the language employed in the
enactment . . . in construing a provision of an
Act of Parliament the plain meaning of its
language must be adopted unless it leads to
some absurdity, inconsistency, hardship or
anomaly which from a consideration of the
enactment as a whole a court of law is
satisfied the Legislature could not have
intended.
The Appellate Division in Swanepoel v
Johannesburg City Council 1994 (3) SA 789 (A)
794B again referred with approval to the orthodox
‘plain meaning’ approach to statutory
interpretation:
[T]he rules of statutory [exegesis] are
intended as aids in resolving any doubts as to
the Legislature’s true intention. Where this
intention is proclaimed in clear terms either
expressly or by necessary implication the
assistance of these rules need not be sought.
Page 94
More recently in Commissioner, SARS v Executor,
Frith’s Estate 2001 (2) SA 261 (SCA) 273 the
Supreme Court of Appeal reiterated the well-
known traditional rule of interpretation:
The primary rule in construction of a statutory
provision is (as is well established) to
ascertain the intention of the legislator and (as
is equally well established) one seeks to
achieve this, in the first instance, by giving the
words under consideration their ordinary
grammatical meaning, unless to do so would
lead to an absurdity so glaring that the
Legislature could not have contemplated it.
These three judgments have two things in
common: all three emanate from the Appellate
Division/Supreme Court of Appeal, and all three
were based on a formalistic and text-based view of
statutory interpretation. The foundations of a text-
based (literal) method of interpretation are many:
legal positivism (the essence of law is in the
decree, and law and morality should be
separated), sovereignty of Parliament (the will of
Parliament is expressed in the legislation), as well
as certain formalistic ideas about law, language
and understanding. Bhyat is understandable: it
was decided during the era of sovereignty of
Parliament, sixty-odd years before the
commencement of a new constitutional order
under a supreme and justiciable constitution.
Perhaps we can condone Swanepoel as well, since
judgment was given on 27 May 1994, exactly one
month after the interim Constitution took effect.
However, Frith’s Estate was decided four years
after the 1996 Constitution took effect, or roughly
seven years into the new constitutional era: after
Qozeleni v Minister of Law and Order 1994 (3) SA
625 (E) and Matiso v Commanding Officer, Port
Elizabeth Prison 1994 (4) SA 592 (SE) and S v
Makwanyane (above) and a host of other
influential decisions by the High Courts and the
Constitutional Court.
Criticism of the text-based (literal) approach to
statutory interpretation may be summarised as
follows:
•
In the first instance, the normative role of the
common-law presumptions during the
interpretation process is reduced to a mere
‘last resort’, to be applied only if the legislative
text is ambiguous.
•
Another point of criticism of this narrow
approach is that words (their literal meaning)
are regarded as the primary
Page 95
index to legislative meaning. According to the
court in R v Hildick-Smith 1924 TPD 68 81—
there is only one kind of interpretation with
one definite object, and that is to ascertain
the true intention of the legislature as
expressed in the Act.
•
Other important internal and external aids to
interpretation, which could be applied to
establish the meaning of text-in-context, are
ignored. The context of the legislation is only
used if the text is not clear. Unless the textual
meaning is ambiguous or unclear, the
interpreter will not have recourse to the wide
range of aids to interpretation at his disposal.
•
As a result, the ‘intention of the legislature’ is
ultimately dependent on how clear the
language used in the legislation may be to the
particular court!
•
Very few texts are so clear that only one final
interpretation is possible. The mere fact that a
discipline such as interpretation of statutes
exists would, by implication, suggest that
legislation is seldom clear and unambiguous.
•
The text-based approach leaves very little
room for judicial law-making, and the courts
are seen as mere mechanical interpreters of
the law (the so-called ‘his master’s voice’ role).
This view creates the impression that once the
legislature has spoken, the courts cease to
have any law-making function. According to
the text-based approach, the legislature has
enacted everything it wanted to, and is aware
of the existing law. As a result of a slavish and
rigid adherence to the doctrine of the
separation of powers, the courts may only
interpret the law, not make it. The legislature
creates the legislation, and the courts have no
law-making capacity with regard to legislation,
except in very exceptional cases, where the
courts deviate from ‘the literal meaning’ of the
legislation to apply some sort of corrective
interpretation. Generally speaking, it is the
function of the legislature to correct omissions
and bad drafting in legislation. The well-known
maxims (iudicis est ius dicere sed non dare and
the casus omissus rule) form the basis of the
general principle that no addition to or
subtraction from the legislative text is possible.
According to the maxim iudicis est ius dicere
sed non dare it is the function of the court to
interpret and not to make the law (Harris v Law
Society of the Cape of Good Hope 1917 CPD
449). A rigid obsession with this rule is the
result of a misunderstanding of the separation
of powers doctrine, with
Page 96
the result that this principle was conveniently
used to justify the text-based approach to
statutory interpretation. The casus omissus
rule (courts may not supply omissions in
legislation) is also derived from the principle
that the function of the courts is to interpret
law and not to make it (Ex Parte Slater, Walker
Securities (SA) Ltd 1974 (4) SA 657 (W)).
Case law examples:
Within the confines of sovereignty of Parliament
prior to 1994, which resulted in a blinkered ‘his
master’s voice’ role of the judiciary, the application
of an orthodox text-based approach had another,
darker side. In the absence of a justiciable bill of
rights under apartheid rule, the clear, plain
meaning of obnoxious legislation not only became
the justification for executive-minded decisions by
the courts, but was also used as a convenient
excuse for avoiding inconvenient moral dilemmas,
as two (in)famous cases dealing with the Group
Areas Act 36 of 1966 illustrate.
The following remark of King J in S v Adams
1979 (4) SA 793 (T) 801 illustrates the moral
dilemma of a judge trapped in the ‘black-letter’
confines of parliamentary sovereignty, and
confronted by the harsh effects of the letter of the
law:
An Act of Parliament creates law but not
necessarily equity. As a Judge in a Court of
law I am obliged to give effect to the
provisions of an Act of Parliament. Speaking
for myself and if I were sitting as a court of
equity, I would have come to the assistance of
the appellant. Unfortunately, and on an
intellectually honest approach, I am compelled
to conclude that the appeal must fail.
On the other hand, Holmes JA in Minister of the
Interior v Lockhat 1961 (2) SA 587 (A) 602 clearly
did not experience the same ethical soul-searching
in deciding whether to follow the ‘plain meaning’ of
the legislation (emphasis added):
Page 97
The Group Areas Act represents a colossal social
experiment and a long term policy. It necessarily
involves the movement out of Group Areas of
numbers of people throughout the country.
Parliament must have envisaged that compulsory
population shifts of persons occupying certain
areas would inevitably cause disruption and, within
the foreseeable future, substantial inequalities.
Whether all this will ultimately prove to be for the
common weal of all the inhabitants, is not for the
Court to decide . . . the question before this Court
is the purely legal one whether this piece of
legislation impliedly authorises, towards the
attainment of its goal, the more immediate and
foreseeable discriminatory results complained of in
this case. In my view . . . it manifestly does.
This text-based approach was the predominant
approach to interpretation in South Africa prior to
1994, and regrettably many of the courts still
follow the traditional plain meaning approach. In
Public Carriers Association v Toll Road
Concessionaries (Pty) Ltd 1990 (1) SA 925 (A)
934J Smalberger JA came to the conclusion that
although the intention of the legislature is the
primary rule of interpretation,
it must be accepted that the literal
interpretation principle is firmly entrenched in
our law and I do not seek to challenge it.
5.3.2 The text-in-context approach
The legislative function is a purposive activity. In
terms of the text-in-context approach, the purpose
or object of the legislation (the legislative scheme)
is the prevailing factor in interpretation. The
context of the legislation, including social and
political policy directions, is also taken into account
to establish the purpose of the legislation.
In contrast to the exaggerated emphasis on the
legislative text, the mischief rule (see 6.4.4 below)
is regarded as the forerunner of a text-in-context
approach to interpretation (Du Plessis 2002: 96).
The mischief rule acknowledges the application of
external aids: the common law prior to the
enactment of the legislation, defects in the law not
provided for by the common law, whatever new
remedies (solutions) the legislature provides, and
the true reason for the remedies. The search for
the purpose of legislation requires a purpose-
orientated approach which recognises the
contextual framework of the legislation right from
the outset, and not only
Page 98
in cases where a literal, text-based approach has
failed. The text-in-context approach provides a
balance between grammatical and overall
contextual meaning. The interpretation process
cannot be complete until the object and scope of
the legislation (ie its contextual environment) are
taken into account. In this way the flexibilities and
peculiarities of language, and all the intra-textual
and extra-textual factors, are accommodated in
the continuing time-frame within which legislation
operates.
Case law example:
In his famous minority decision in Jaga v Dönges
1950 (4) SA 653 (A), Schreiner JA identified the
following guidelines for interpretation of statutes:
•
Right from the outset the interpreter may take
the wider context of provision (eg its ambit and
purpose) into consideration with the legislative
text in question.
•
Irrespective of how clear or unambiguous the
grammatical meaning of the legislative text
may seem to be, the relevant contextual
factors (eg the practical effects of different
interpretations, as well as the background of
the provision) must be taken into account.
•
Sometimes this wider context may even be
more important than the legislative text.
•
Once the meaning of the text and context
(language in context) is determined, it must be
applied, irrespective of whether the interpreter
is of the opinion that the legislature intended
something else.
This was one of the first concrete efforts in South
African law to utilise the wider context to move
beyond the plain grammatical meaning to ascertain
the legislative purpose. After that, a few courts
were more prepared to interpret the text of
legislation in the light of the wider contextual
framework.
During the 1970s Cowen (1976 and 1980)
started to question the theoretical foundations of
literalism and the ‘intention of the legislature’.
Unfortunately, this process of change proved slow,
with progression alternating with regression. In
University of Cape Town v Cape Bar Council 1986
(4) SA 903 (A) Rabie CJ held that the court had to
examine all the contextual factors in ascertaining
the intention of the
Page 99
legislature, irrespective of whether or not the
words of the legislation were clear and
unambiguous.
According to the text-in-context approach, the
judiciary has inherent law-making discretion during
statutory interpretation; although an exception to
the rule, the courts may modify or adapt the initial
meaning of the text to harmonise it with the
purpose of the legislation. The role of the courts is
therefore far more flexible, and is not limited to
mere textual analysis and mechanical application
of the legislation. However, this discretion is
qualified by the prerequisite that modification of
the meaning of the text is possible (and
admissible) only if and when the scope and
purpose of the legislation is clear and supports
such a modification. Such a law-making function of
the judiciary is not an infringement of the
legislature’s legislative function, but merely a
logical extension of the powers of the court during
the interpretation and application of the relevant
legislation in each practical instance. For the text-
in-context approach the use of the common-law
presumptions, as well as all the various aids to
interpretation, are very important tools in the
quest for the scope and purpose of legislation.
Constitutional supremacy
(b)
Non-racialism and non-sexism.
(c)
Supremacy of the constitution and the rule of
law.
(d)
Universal adult suffrage, a national common
voters roll, regular elections and a multi-party
system of democratic government, to ensure
accountability, responsiveness and openness.
Section 2 is the constitutional supremacy clause.
According to Du Plessis (1997: 812) s 1(c)
(referring to the supremacy of the Constitution and
the rule of law) merely anticipates the supremacy
of the Constitution; s 2 unambiguously confirms it:
This Constitution is the supreme law of the
Republic; law or conduct inconsistent with it is
invalid, and the obligations imposed by it must
be fulfilled.
Section 2 must be read with s 7 of the
Constitution, which states that the Bill of Rights is
the cornerstone of the South African democracy,
and that the state must respect, protect, promote
and fulfil the rights in the Bill of Rights, s 8(1),
which states that the Bill of Rights applies to all
law, and binds the legislature, the executive, the
judiciary and all organs of state, as well as s 8(2),
which provides that the Bill of Rights applies to
both natural and juristic persons; and s 237, which
states that all constitutional obligations must be
performed diligently and without delay. If all these
provisions are read together, one principle is
indisputable: the Constitution is supreme, and
everything and everybody are subject to it. This
means that the Constitution cannot be interpreted
in the light of the Interpretation Act or the Roman-
Dutch common law or traditional customary law.
Everything and everybody, all law and conduct, all
cultural traditions and legal dogmas and religious
perceptions, all rules and procedures, and all
theories, canons and maxims of interpretation are
influenced and ultimately qualified by the
Constitution. In Holomisa v Argus Newspapers Ltd
1996 (2) SA 588 (W) 618 Cameron J summarised
this principle very well:
The Constitution has changed the ‘context’ of
all legal thought and decision-making in South
Africa.
Constitutional values
•
the golden rule (the plain meaning of the text
must be followed unless it leads to an absurdity
or a result not intended by the legislature);
•
the purposive approach (the words must be
read in context); and
•
reading-in in an attempt to make sense of the
legislation (the creative role of the court).
There are two problems with this reasoning: first,
it is also based on a mutually exclusive way of
thinking: if method A does not work the court will
try method B, and so on; and second, to argue
that a court will use ‘reading in’ (a form of
corrective interpretation) as a method to make
sense of the legislation is to put the cart before the
horse. After all (as will be discussed in Chapter 7
below), the legislative purpose must be clear
before a court may apply corrective interpretation;
it is ludicrous to suggest that a court may read
words into the legislation in order to understand it
(make sense of it)!
In Govender v Minister of Safety and Security 2001
(4) SA 273 (SCA) the court acknowledged that
interpretation of legislation under the Constitution
requires a new mind-set: the court has to sail
between the dangers of the Scylla of the old-style
literalism and the Charybdis of judicial law-making.
It would seem that the court was trying to suggest
that interpretation involves a journey between an
orthodox text-based approach and free-floating
judicial law-making, and that the correct course is
to be plotted somewhere between the two.
However, it is not entirely clear whether the court
was in actual fact trying to propagate a particular
approach to interpretation—the phrase ‘between
Scylla and Charybdis’ does not refer to avoiding
both possible dangers by trying to find some safe
middle ground, but rather to having to choose the
lesser of two evils.
Page 107
Please note:
In Greek mythology, Scylla and Charybdis were
two monsters who lurked on opposite sides of the
Strait of Messina (between Italy and Sicily). Scylla
was a six-headed monster and Charybdis was a
dangerous whirlpool, and a ship sailing the strait
was bound to be destroyed by one of the
monsters. The legend of the monsters gave rise to
a number of phrases: ‘between Scylla and
Charybdis’; ‘between the devil and the deep blue
sea’; and ‘between a rock and a hard place’—
meaning a situation where one has to choose
between two equally unattractive options.
Fortunately there is a practical, sensible and
theoretically correct alternative. Du Plessis &
Corder (1994: 73-74) originally suggested five
practical interrelated techniques for constitutional
interpretation. However, Du Plessis (2002: 197-
274) has applied this practical and inclusive
method for statutory interpretation as well. These
suggested techniques form the basis of a practical,
inclusive method of interpretation which is used in
the following chapter of this book. These
components of a practical methodology are
complementary and interrelated, and should be
applied in conjunction with one another.
Eskridge (2001: 207) also describes a pragmatic
approach to interpretation which is based on a—
grab bag of different techniques, including not
just textual analysis, but also sophisticated
appreciation of the goals underlying the legal
text and the consequences of adopting
different interpretations. Law involves a
balance between form and substance, tradition
and innovation, text and context.
However, the Du Plessis model is much more than
that. As a result of the influence of the Constitution
and the constitutional values, this suggested
practical, inclusive method of interpretation also
includes a strong normative component. This
practical and inclusive method consists of the
following components:
Comparative aspect
(i)
in general terms, ascertain the meaning of the
provision to be interpreted by an analysis of its
purpose and, in doing so;
(ii)
have regard to the context of the provision in
the sense of its historical origins;
(iii)
have regard to its context in the sense of the
statute as a whole, the subject matter and
broad objects of the statute and the values
which underlie it;
Page 110
(iv)
have regard to its immediate context in the
sense of the particular part of the statute in
which the provision appears or those provisions
with which it is interrelated;
(v)
have regard to the precise wording of the
provision . . .
Page 111
Chapter 6
A practical, inclusive
methodology: The five
interrelated dimensions of
interpretation
Original legislation
•
The signed version is conclusive only when
there is an irreconcilable conflict between the
versions (Handel v R 1933 SWA 37). In other
words, the signed version is used as a last
resort to avoid a stalemate.
•
If the one version of the text is wider than the
other (eg one version prescribes a penalty of
imprisonment and a fine, and the other only a
fine), then the common-denominator rule is
followed, and only a fine will be imposed. The
texts are read together to establish the
common denominator (Jaffer v Parow Village
Management Board 1920 CPD 267).
•
If the versions differ but there is no conflict,
the versions complement one another and they
have to be read together. An attempt should
be made to reconcile the texts with reference
to the context and the purpose of the
legislation (Zulu v Van Rensburg 1996 (4) SA
1236 (LC)).
•
Even the unsigned version of the legislative
text may be used to determine the intention of
the legislature (Commissioner of Inland
Revenue v Witwatersrand Association of Racing
Clubs 1960 (3) SA 291 (A) 302A–B).
•
Because statutes are signed using alternate
languages, amendment Acts may create a
problem. Suppose the Afrikaans version of a
statute was signed but the English version of
the amendment Act was signed. Which one of
the signed versions of the amendment Act will
prevail in case of an irreconcilable conflict?
There are conflicting answers to this question,
but the most acceptable solution was put
forward in R v Silinga 1957 (3) SA 354 (A). The
court suggested that the amendment Act be
regarded as part of the original statute. The
version of the statute signed originally will
prevail in the case of an irreconcilable conflict.
Subordinate legislation
(a)
to give effect to and regulate the fundamental
rights conferred by section 27 of the
Constitution;
(b)
to give effect to obligations incurred by the
Republic as a member state of the
International Labour Organisation;
(c)
to provide a framework within which
employees and their trade unions, employers
and employers’ organisations can—
(i)
collectively bargain to determine wages, terms
and conditions of employment and other
matters of mutual interest; and
(ii)
formulate industrial policy; and
(d)
to promote—
(i)
orderly collective bargaining;
(ii)
collective bargaining at sectoral level;
(iii)
employee participation in decision-making in
the workplace; and
(iv)
the effective resolution of labour disputes.
Page 121
3 Interpretation of this Act
Any person applying this Act must interpret
its provisions—
(a)
to give effect to its primary objects;
(b)
in compliance with the Constitution; and
(c)
in compliance with the public international law
obligations of the Republic.
(g) Schedules
Year:
A year consists of a cycle of 365 days (366 days
every fourth or leap year), and is based on the
Gregorian calendar. Every year commences on 1
January and ends on 31 December.
Month:
The term ‘month’ could have three possible
meanings:
•
according to s 2 of the Interpretation Act
‘month’ means a calendar month (not a lunar
month); in other words, the twelve unequal
named periods which make up a year on the
calendar (s 1 of the Value-Added Tax Act 89 of
1991 defines a month as ‘any of the twelve
portions into which a calendar year is divided’);
or
•
a lunar month of 28 days; or
•
a period of time stretching between two
corresponding dates in succeeding months of
the year (eg 9 June to 9 July).
The last meaning is the one used the most
frequently in law. However, it would be more
appropriate to use the term ‘calendar month’ for
the first alternative and ‘month’ for the last one.
Day:
Normally a day will be one of the 24-hour units of
a week stretching from midnight to midnight, or it
could be the hours of daylight (s 1 of the Criminal
Procedure Act 51 of 1977 defines a day as the
space of time between sunrise and sunset).
Week:
Traditionally a week as a part of a calendar runs
from midnight on a Saturday to midnight on the
next Saturday. For the purpose of computation of
time the courts regard a week as any period of
seven successive days.
Page 126
Computation of time
Common-law methods
Three common-law methods of computation of
time will be discussed briefly. Although part of
common law, these methods complement s 4 of
the Interpretation Act (the statutory method):
•
Ordinary civil method (computatio civilis):
Unless clearly indicated otherwise, this method
is the default method for the calculation of
months and years and is the opposite of the
statutory method (used for days). The first day
of the prescribed period is included and the last
day excluded. The last day is regarded as
ending at the very moment it begins, as it were
(at midnight of the previous day).
Case law examples:
A very interesting example of the ordinary civil
method is Minister van Polisie v De Beer 1970 (2)
SA 712 (T). The case dealt with a claim for
damages after a police vehicle had collided with a
private motor-car. In terms of s 32 of the Police
Act 7 of 1958, a claim for damages against the
police as a result of an action executed in terms of
the Police Act had to be instituted within six
months. The collision took place on 5 August 1967.
The summons was served on 5 February 1968. On
appeal the Supreme Court found that the ordinary
civil method should be used to calculate the time.
The last day was therefore excluded and the
summons was therefore served one day too late.
As a result the action was refused.
Page 128
However, in Pivot Point SA (Pty) Ltd v Registrar of
Companies 1980 (4) SA 74 (T) the issue was the
time period prescribed in s 45 of the Companies
Act 61 of 1973, which provided that the Registrar
may ‘within one month after the date of such
decision or order, apply to the Court for relief’. The
court held that the language of the Act clearly
indicated that the ordinary civil method of
calculating time was not to be used, because the
provision stated ‘after the date of such decision’. If
time is to run ‘after’ a day or date, then clearly
that day or date must be excluded from the
reckoning of time.
•
Natural method (computatio naturalis): Where
this method is used, the prescribed period is
calculated from the hour (or even minute) of
an occurrence to the corresponding hour or
minute on the last day of the period in
question.
•
Extraordinary civil method (computatio
extraordinaria): Both the first and the last day
of the period concerned are included. This
method of time calculation is obsolete and is no
longer used by the courts.
An important note:
The issue of time limits and computation of time is
far more complicated than it may seem from the
brief introduction above. The large number of
cases, legislation and exceptions to rules cannot be
dealt with fully in this book. Remember: whichever
method of computation of time is used, the
purpose of the legislation will remain the decisive
factor.
•
The common-law presumption against futile
and nugatory legislation was never raised.
•
It is a good example of reading different sets of
legislation together in order to solve an
interpretation problem.
This decision has since been confirmed by the
legislature. Parliament has passed the Criminal
Law (Sexual Offences and Related Matters)
Amendment Act 6 of 2012, which expressly
provides that the powers of courts with regard to
sentences for the offences in Chapters 2, 3 and 4
of the Act are the same as those specified in s 276
of the Criminal Procedure Act.
In Sekretaris van Binnelandse Inkomste v Lourens
Erasmus (Edms) Bpk 1966 (4) SA 434 (A) the
court held that if possible the interpretation that
avoids uncertainty, confusion and conflict must be
adopted. Furthermore, the presumption enables
courts to try to interpret legislation in such a
manner that evasion of its provisions is prevented
(Dadoo Ltd v Krugersdorp Municipal Council 1920
AD 530). In Dhanabakium v Subramanian 1943 AD
160, the court found that as far as possible,
legislation should be interpreted in such a way that
a
Page 136
casus omissus (omission) is avoided. As will be
discussed later (Chapter 7 below), the courts may
indeed modify (adapt) the initial meaning of the
legislation (in the light of the presumption against
futile provisions and within the framework of the
purpose of the legislation). However, this
presumption applies only if there is more than one
possible interpretation, and cannot be used by a
court to reinterpret legislation at will. In other
words, this presumption cannot be used to
hammer a square peg into a round hole.
The presumption also applies to subordinate
legislation. Here, the maxim ut res magis valeat
quam pereat applies. This means that an
interpretation which will not leave the subordinate
legislation ultra vires (and invalid), but rather intra
vires and valid must be preferred (R v Vayi 1946
NPD 792). The ut res magis valeat quam pereat
rule applies only where two interpretations of a
provision are possible. The presumption cannot be
used to rescue an administrative act (conduct)
which is defective and invalid from the outset
(Mamogalie v Minister van Naturellesake 1961 (1)
SA 467 (A)). Consequently, any subordinate
legislation in conflict with the enabling Act (or any
other original legislation, for that matter) will also
be invalidated.
(b) Conflicts with other legislation
•
if the state would be rendered subject to the
authority of or interference by its own officials;
and
Page 140
•
if the state would be affected by penal
provisions (as in S v Huyser 1968 (3) SA 490
(GW) (see below)).
The question whether the state is bound depends
on the particular legislation and specific
circumstances, and each case has to be judged on
its own merits. The following are examples of the
practical application of the presumption:
•
Government bodies and state-controlled
agencies are bound by town planning schemes
(Drakensberg Administration Board v Town
Planning Appeals Board 1983 (4) SA 42 (N)
and Boiler Efficiency Services CC v Coalcor
(Cape)(Pty) Ltd 1989 (3) SA 460 (C)).
•
A security official who contravenes a statutory
provision when acting outside the scope of his
duties cannot rely on the presumption against
the state being bound (S v Reed 1972 (2) SA
34 (RA)).
•
The driver of a fire engine may disregard a red
traffic light while fire-fighting (S v Labuschagne
1979 (3) SA 1320 (T)).
•
An agricultural official who combats stock
diseases and from time to time has to cull
animals is not bound by statutory requirements
regarding hunting permits (S v Huyser
(above)).
Case law example:
S v De Bruin (above) is a rather interesting case,
to put it mildly. The accused was charged with and
convicted of exceeding the statutory speed limit.
On appeal, De Bruin (a state prosecutor) claimed
that he was a public servant who, on the day in
question, had been running late for an on-site
inspection on the state’s behalf. If he had arrived
late at the inspection premises, this could have
been detrimental to the state’s case. The court
found that being bound by the provisions in
question could have obstructed essential state
services and jeopardised state security. The court
found that De Bruin’s decision to exceed the speed
limit was reasonable, and set aside the conviction.
Steyn (1981: 77) correctly points out that this
presumption applies to both original and
subordinate legislation. Furthermore Labuschagne
(1978: 54) indicates, with reference to R v Thomas
1954 (1) SA 185 (SWA), that strictly speaking
Page 141
this presumption deals with the state being bound
by particular provisions; the state might be bound
by one provision of the legislation, but not by
another.
Another distinction is necessary. Not being bound
by legislation (as a result of the presumption) does
not mean that state liability is also automatically
excluded. If police officers in hot pursuit of
criminals ignore a red traffic light (on the face of it
quite lawfully), but they do so at break-neck
speeds, not slowing down at intersections and
without taking pedestrians and other motorists into
consideration during the chase, they cannot rely on
this presumption to escape any possible delictual
liability resulting from their actions.
Criticism:
Since s 39(2) of the Constitution clearly stipulates
that rules of common law have to be developed in
the light of the fundamental rights in the
Constitution, it is submitted that this particular
presumption should in future no longer apply
under the new constitutional order:
•
Section 8(1) of the Constitution expressly
provides that government organs at all levels
are bound by the Bill of Rights. The
Constitution is the supreme law of the
Republic, and all law and government conduct
must be tested against the spirit, purport and
objects of the fundamental rights entrenched in
the Bill of Rights. In a system based on
constitutionalism it would not make sense that
government bodies are bound by the
Constitution (as the supreme law), but at the
same time are presumed not to be bound by
their own legislation, which legislation is also
subject to the supreme Constitution.
•
The Constitution abounds with references to
principles such as accountability and openness
(the preamble and s 1(d)); supremacy of the
Constitution (ss 1(a) and 2); the values
underlying an open and democratic society
based on freedom, equality and human dignity
(ss 7(1) and 39(2)); the state being bound by
the Constitution
Page 142
(ss 2 and 8(1)); the requirement that the state
must respect, protect, promote and fulfil the
Constitution and the Bill of Rights (s 7(2); and
the official oath of judicial officers (item 6 of
Schedule 2)). All of these support the
argument that this presumption should no
longer be applied.
As Du Plessis (2002: 177) points out, the view of
Wiechers that this presumption should be applied
the other way round has now been vindicated after
all these years:
In short, a state defined by its own constitution
as a ‘democratic state founded on the . . .
values’ of ‘[s]upremacy of the Constitution and
the rule of law’ most certainly is a
constitutional state (Rechtsstaat) heedful of the
principle of legality. This observation is
confirmed by the constitutional demand for the
accountability of the public administration. The
moment for what Wiechers foresaw more than
a decade and a half ago, has probably come.
In Fedsure Life Assurance Ltd v Greater
Johannesburg Transitional Metropolitan Council
(above) para 58 the Constitutional Court explained
the principle of legality in the new constitutional
order as follows:
It seems central to the conception of our
constitutional order that the Legislature and
Executive in every sphere are constrained by
the principle that they may exercise no power
and perform no function beyond that conferred
upon them by law. At least in this sense, then,
the principle of legality is implied within the
terms of the interim Constitution. Whether the
principle of the rule of law has greater content
than the principle of legality is not necessary
for us to decide here. We need merely hold
that fundamental to the interim Constitution is
a principle of legality.
Since the constitutionality of this common-law
presumption has not yet been tested in court, it
still applies in South Africa. However, the correct
legal position in future should rather be as follows:
government agencies and organs of state should
always be bound by their own legislation, unless
they can prove that they would be hampered in the
execution of their duties and functions if bound by
the legislation. Admittedly such a new principle will
have to be prospective only, since retroactively
undoing the vested rights and interests obtained
by the state as a result of the application of this
presumption in the past could prove to be
impossible.
Page 143
6.3 The value-laden (teleological)
dimension: The ghost in the machine
6.3.1 The new constitutional approach to
statutory interpretation, or, moving from
bumper stickers to substantive interpretation
In Sidumo v Rustenburg Platinum Mines Ltd 2008
(2) SA 24 (CC) para 149 Sachs J described the
constitutional values as follows (emphasis added):
The values of the Constitution are strong,
explicit and clearly intended to be considered
part of the very texture of the constitutional
project. They are implicit in the very structure
and design of the new democratic order. The
letter and the spirit of the Constitution cannot
be separated; just as the values are not free-
floating, ready to alight as mere adornments
on this or that provision, so is the text not self-
supporting, awaiting occasional evocative
enhancement. The role of constitutional values
is certainly not simply to provide a patina of
virtue to otherwise bald, neutral and discrete
legal propositions. Text and values work
together in integral fashion to provide the
protections promised by the Constitution.
However, the value-based dimension of statutory
interpretation is not easy to implement. Since
1994 the South African legal fraternity has had to
face the dreaded V-word: values. These lawyers,
judges and law teachers were schooled in and
indoctrinated by a positivist idea of the law: iudicis
est ius dicere sed non dare; Parliament knows best
and has spoken; lawyers are not philosophers;
plain meanings, clear texts and black letter law;
formalism and his master’s voice; and so on.
Indeed, we now have a supreme Constitution,
brimming with references to fundamental values:
freedom (including religious freedom, freedom of
speech, and so on), equality (both formal and
substantive), human dignity, all the trimmings of a
multi-party democracy, good governance (s 195 of
the Constitution), openness, transparency, non-
racism, non-sexism, tolerance, and so on and so
forth. These values form the basis of a more
mature society (S v Makwanyane (above)) trying
to be the better society alluded to by former Chief
Justice Mahomed in S v Acheson 1991 (2) SA 805
(Nm) 813, when he said that a supreme
Constitution is the mirror reflecting the national
soul. But what are we doing in practical terms to
animate those values through, amongst other
things, the interpretation of legislation? Is s 39(2)
of the Constitution nothing more than an empty
gesture, mere hollow rhetoric?
Page 144
The value-based dimension of interpretation is
more than simply paying lip-service, but involves
making those values real; animating them through
the making, interpretation, and application of the
law, as well as ensuring that the law is respected
and adhered to. It involves a willingness to keep
those values in mind, right from the outset; a mind
shift that law comprises more than ideologies,
power structures, politics, policies and the meaning
of the words on paper.
As was pointed out earlier, s 39(2) of the
Constitution ensures that interpretation of statutes
also occurs within the value-laden (teleological and
normative) constitutional framework. But s 39(2)
cannot be merely window-dressing or hollow
rhetoric. In Holomisa v Argus Newspaper Ltd
(above) 844 the court referred to s 35(3) of the
interim Constitution (the forerunner of s 39(2) of
the 1996 Constitution), stating that the
interpretation clause in the Constitution is
[not] merely an interpretive directive, but a
force that informs all legal institutions and
decisions with the new power of constitutional
values.
In Coetzee v Government of the Republic of South
Africa; Matiso v Commanding Officer, Port
Elizabeth Prison 1995 (4) SA 631 (CC) para 46
Sachs J explained the teleological dimension of
interpretation even better (emphasis added):
The values that must suffuse the whole process
are derived from the concept of an open and
democratic society based on freedom and
equality, several times referred to in the
Constitution. The notion of an open and
democratic society is thus not merely
aspirational or decorative, it is normative,
furnishing the matrix of ideals within which we
work, the source from which we derive the
principles and rules we apply, and the final
measure we use for testing the legitimacy of
impugned norms and conduct . . . [W]e should
not engage in purely formal or academic
analysis, nor simply restrict ourselves to ad hoc
technicism, but rather focus on what has been
called the synergetic relation between the
values underlying the guarantees of
fundamental rights and the circumstances of
the particular case.
This means that the constitutional values are not
there to be used as fridge magnets or bumper
stickers, or to be quoted and insisted on when it
suits you, but instantly forgotten when it does not.
In Harksen v President of The RSA 2000 (5) SA
478 (CC) para 18 the court emphasised that since
the Constitution is the supreme law of the land and
that all legislation must be
Page 145
read subject to it, it is unnecessary for legislation
expressly to incorporate terms of the Constitution,
and as a result constitutional provisions or values
or principles are part of the implied contents of
statutes. But by the same token these values
should not be used as a show of smoke and
mirrors as a cover-up for bad governance, like
hiding a badly baked cake under layers of nice-
looking icing.
Maybe it should be said: if we choose to ignore
the V-word; if these values are not taken seriously
and borne in mind constantly during (amongst
other things) interpretation of legislation; and if we
are not prepared to succumb to constitutionalism,
we might as well get rid of the supreme
Constitution, the justiciable Bill of Rights and rights
rhetoric, and return to the former bad old days of
sovereignty of Parliament and executive-minded
interpretation of legislation. Otherwise we need to
become serious about the rights and values in the
Constitution—including a new ‘constitutional’
approach to statutory interpretation—in other
words, moving from bumper stickers to
substantive justice.
But how do we animate and concretise those
values? How does freedom influence no-parking
signs? What is the link between having to pay your
income tax before the due date and human
dignity? How can values influence the black letter
of the law? A starting point for that is always using
the Constitution as a point of departure for legal
analysis, interpretation and application, something
which was not done by the court in the following
example:
Case law example:
In S v F 1999 (1) SACR 571 (C) the court had to
decide whether the 17-year-old rape victim could
testify from a room adjoining the court. This
required an interpretation of s 158(3) of the
Criminal Procedure Act 51 of 1977:
158 Criminal proceedings to take place in
presence of accused
...
(3) A court may make an order
contemplated in subsection (2) only if facilities
therefor are readily available or obtainable and
if it appears to the court that to do so
would. . .
(a)
prevent unreasonable delay;
(b)
save costs;
Page 146
(c)
be convenient;
(d)
be in the interest of the security of the State or
of public safety or in the interests of justice or
the public; or
(e)
prevent the likelihood that prejudice or harm
might result to any person if he or she testifies
or is present at such proceedings.
The court held that s 158(3) cannot be read
disjunctively (paras (a), (b), (c), (d) or (e)), but it
should rather be read conjunctively, in other
words, in order to testify via CCTV, the applicant
had to comply with the requirements set forth in
paragraphs (a), (b) and (c), as well as any of the
requirements set forth in either paragraph (d) or
(e) of s 158(3). This was a poor decision based on
an incorrect interpretation of the law, which meant
that all the lower courts in the Western Cape had
to apply the ridiculously strict requirements. In
practical terms the decision meant that it was
virtually impossible for a witness to be allowed not
to testify in the presence of the alleged rapist
(even six-year-old rape victims).
But why was this a bad interpretation? It was a
purely text-based analysis of s 158(3), dealing
with semi-colons and other rules of punctuation.
The judge referred to the common-law
presumption that legislature does not intend harsh
or unreasonable results; since the victim would not
be in court (if allowed to testify via CCTV) the
accused’s right to cross-examination would be
infringed; the court relied on a 1920 case (Dadoo
Ltd v Krugersdorp Municipal Council 1920 AD 530),
as well as English-law textbooks on interpretation
and procedure (R K Soonavala Advocacy: Its
Principles and Practice, and Maxwell Interpretation
of Statutes).
This was a 1999 decision—at least two years
after the 1996 Constitution took effect. However,
there is no reference to the Constitution, which
means there is no reference to human dignity (s
10); no reference to s 39(2); since the victim was
17 years old, no reference to s 28 (rights of the
child); no critical discussion about the struggle
between competing rights (in this case the s 28
children’s rights versus the s 35 rights of the
accused); no fundamental
Page 147
values—just a text-based analysis based on a
conjunctive grammatical reading of the provision
(plain meaning approach). This is a striking
example of what may happen if the value-based
dimension of statutory interpretation is ignored.
This decision was eventually held to be incorrect (S
v Staggie 2003 (1) SACR 232 (C)).
In fact, S v F was not the last case in the Western
Cape that failed to get to grips with the new
‘constitutional approach’ to interpretation. In
Winckler v Minister of Correctional Services 2001
(2) SA 747 (C) the court still followed the
discredited text-based approach:
The golden rule governing the interpretation of
a statute is to determine the intention of the
Legislature. Such intention is established, in
the first place, by the plain language of the
statute before resorting to other canons of
construction. The primary supposition is that
the Legislature intends what it says.
Fortunately there are examples of substantive
interpretation of statutes. In Ngxuza v Permanent
Secretary, Department of Welfare, Eastern Cape
2001 (2) SA 609 (E) Froneman J was aware of the
changes brought about by the new constitutional
order. The case dealt with a flexible and generous
approach to the issue of locus standi (including a
class action under s 38 of the Constitution) to
make it easier for disadvantaged and poor people
to approach courts on public issues to ensure that
public administration adheres to fundamental
principle of legality in exercising public power. His
substantive approach to statutory interpretation
and legal reasoning is clear from the following
excerpts from the judgment (at 619):
There is a broader social context in which law
is applied to particular facts in any given case.
Where that terrain is familiar and the law to be
applied is not new that context is often
assumed and not articulated. Here the position
is different. The law is new and the social
setting has changed. [T]he starting place to
determine our assumptions is the Constitution
. . . it is necessary in this case, because of the
relatively new legal position and the changed
social context in which it is to be applied, to be
open about one’s own views of that context.
The reality is that the outcome of this case is
not dictated by precedent or deductive legal
reasoning alone: my interpretation of s 38 of
the Constitution is inevitably also influenced by
my own views of the context in which it is to be
Page 148
interpreted and applied. This is a truth that, I
think, is now generally accepted by legal
theorists.
6.3.2 Ubuntu
The postamble of the English text of the 1993
Constitution referred to ubuntu:
There is a need for understanding but not for
vengeance, a need for reparation but not for
retaliation, a need for ubuntu but not for
victimisation . . .
Ubuntu is an indigenous African concept and refers
to a practical humanist disposition towards the
world, including compassion, tolerance and
fairness. (It is interesting to note that the African
Charter on Human and Peoples’ Rights also
includes a positive duty to tolerate.) The concept
was applied and explained by the Constitutional
Court in S v Makwanyane (above) 501D-E:
Generally, ubuntu translates as ‘humaneness’.
In its most fundamental sense, it translates as
‘personhood’ and ‘morality’ . . . While it
envelops the key values of group solidarity,
compassion, respect, human dignity,
conformity to basic norms and collective unity,
in its fundamental sense it denotes humanity
and morality. Its spirit emphasises respect for
human dignity, marking a shift from
confrontation to conciliation.
The concept of ubuntu is not expressly mentioned
in the Constitution of 1996. That does not mean
that ubuntu will disappear from the South African
legal stage. Since ubuntu was used in the
Makwanyane case (above), it forms part of the
new South African constitutional jurisprudence. It
may also be argued that ubuntu lives on in the
numerous references to human dignity in the
Constitution. It forms an important bridge between
the communal African traditions and Western
traditions, which focus on the individual, and could
be a very useful extra-textual aid to statutory and
constitutional interpretation.
•
What was the existing law (the legal position)
before the legislation in question was adopted?
•
Which problem (mischief or defect) was not
adequately addressed by the existing law
before the new legislation was adopted?
•
What remedy (solution) is proposed by the new
legislation to solve this problem?
•
What is the true reason for the proposed
remedy?
The aim of the rule is to examine the
circumstances that lead to the adoption of the
legislation in question. The mischief rule has been
applied on numerous occasions by the courts. For
example, as a result of the incomprehensible
language used in the Compulsory Motor Vehicle
Insurance Act 56 of 1972, the court in Santam
Insurance Ltd v Taylor (above) examined the
historical background of the Act in order to
ascertain its purpose.
Chapter 6
A practical, inclusive
methodology: The five
interrelated dimensions of
interpretation
Original legislation
•
The signed version is conclusive only when
there is an irreconcilable conflict between the
versions (Handel v R 1933 SWA 37). In other
words, the signed version is used as a last
resort to avoid a stalemate.
•
If the one version of the text is wider than the
other (eg one version prescribes a penalty of
imprisonment and a fine, and the other only a
fine), then the common-denominator rule is
followed, and only a fine will be imposed. The
texts are read together to establish the
common denominator (Jaffer v Parow Village
Management Board 1920 CPD 267).
•
If the versions differ but there is no conflict,
the versions complement one another and they
have to be read together. An attempt should
be made to reconcile the texts with reference
to the context and the purpose of the
legislation (Zulu v Van Rensburg 1996 (4) SA
1236 (LC)).
•
Even the unsigned version of the legislative
text may be used to determine the intention of
the legislature (Commissioner of Inland
Revenue v Witwatersrand Association of Racing
Clubs 1960 (3) SA 291 (A) 302A–B).
•
Because statutes are signed using alternate
languages, amendment Acts may create a
problem. Suppose the Afrikaans version of a
statute was signed but the English version of
the amendment Act was signed. Which one of
the signed versions of the amendment Act will
prevail in case of an irreconcilable conflict?
There are conflicting answers to this question,
but the most acceptable solution was put
forward in R v Silinga 1957 (3) SA 354 (A). The
court suggested that the amendment Act be
regarded as part of the original statute. The
version of the statute signed originally will
prevail in the case of an irreconcilable conflict.
Subordinate legislation
(a)
to give effect to and regulate the fundamental
rights conferred by section 27 of the
Constitution;
(b)
to give effect to obligations incurred by the
Republic as a member state of the
International Labour Organisation;
(c)
to provide a framework within which
employees and their trade unions, employers
and employers’ organisations can—
(i)
collectively bargain to determine wages, terms
and conditions of employment and other
matters of mutual interest; and
(ii)
formulate industrial policy; and
(d)
to promote—
(i)
orderly collective bargaining;
(ii)
collective bargaining at sectoral level;
(iii)
employee participation in decision-making in
the workplace; and
(iv)
the effective resolution of labour disputes.
Page 121
3 Interpretation of this Act
Any person applying this Act must interpret
its provisions—
(a)
to give effect to its primary objects;
(b)
in compliance with the Constitution; and
(c)
in compliance with the public international law
obligations of the Republic.
(g) Schedules
Year:
A year consists of a cycle of 365 days (366 days
every fourth or leap year), and is based on the
Gregorian calendar. Every year commences on 1
January and ends on 31 December.
Month:
The term ‘month’ could have three possible
meanings:
•
according to s 2 of the Interpretation Act
‘month’ means a calendar month (not a lunar
month); in other words, the twelve unequal
named periods which make up a year on the
calendar (s 1 of the Value-Added Tax Act 89 of
1991 defines a month as ‘any of the twelve
portions into which a calendar year is divided’);
or
•
a lunar month of 28 days; or
•
a period of time stretching between two
corresponding dates in succeeding months of
the year (eg 9 June to 9 July).
The last meaning is the one used the most
frequently in law. However, it would be more
appropriate to use the term ‘calendar month’ for
the first alternative and ‘month’ for the last one.
Day:
Normally a day will be one of the 24-hour units of
a week stretching from midnight to midnight, or it
could be the hours of daylight (s 1 of the Criminal
Procedure Act 51 of 1977 defines a day as the
space of time between sunrise and sunset).
Week:
Traditionally a week as a part of a calendar runs
from midnight on a Saturday to midnight on the
next Saturday. For the purpose of computation of
time the courts regard a week as any period of
seven successive days.
Page 126
Computation of time
Common-law methods
Three common-law methods of computation of
time will be discussed briefly. Although part of
common law, these methods complement s 4 of
the Interpretation Act (the statutory method):
•
Ordinary civil method (computatio civilis):
Unless clearly indicated otherwise, this method
is the default method for the calculation of
months and years and is the opposite of the
statutory method (used for days). The first day
of the prescribed period is included and the last
day excluded. The last day is regarded as
ending at the very moment it begins, as it were
(at midnight of the previous day).
Case law examples:
A very interesting example of the ordinary civil
method is Minister van Polisie v De Beer 1970 (2)
SA 712 (T). The case dealt with a claim for
damages after a police vehicle had collided with a
private motor-car. In terms of s 32 of the Police
Act 7 of 1958, a claim for damages against the
police as a result of an action executed in terms of
the Police Act had to be instituted within six
months. The collision took place on 5 August 1967.
The summons was served on 5 February 1968. On
appeal the Supreme Court found that the ordinary
civil method should be used to calculate the time.
The last day was therefore excluded and the
summons was therefore served one day too late.
As a result the action was refused.
Page 128
However, in Pivot Point SA (Pty) Ltd v Registrar of
Companies 1980 (4) SA 74 (T) the issue was the
time period prescribed in s 45 of the Companies
Act 61 of 1973, which provided that the Registrar
may ‘within one month after the date of such
decision or order, apply to the Court for relief’. The
court held that the language of the Act clearly
indicated that the ordinary civil method of
calculating time was not to be used, because the
provision stated ‘after the date of such decision’. If
time is to run ‘after’ a day or date, then clearly
that day or date must be excluded from the
reckoning of time.
•
Natural method (computatio naturalis): Where
this method is used, the prescribed period is
calculated from the hour (or even minute) of
an occurrence to the corresponding hour or
minute on the last day of the period in
question.
•
Extraordinary civil method (computatio
extraordinaria): Both the first and the last day
of the period concerned are included. This
method of time calculation is obsolete and is no
longer used by the courts.
An important note:
The issue of time limits and computation of time is
far more complicated than it may seem from the
brief introduction above. The large number of
cases, legislation and exceptions to rules cannot be
dealt with fully in this book. Remember: whichever
method of computation of time is used, the
purpose of the legislation will remain the decisive
factor.
•
The common-law presumption against futile
and nugatory legislation was never raised.
•
It is a good example of reading different sets of
legislation together in order to solve an
interpretation problem.
This decision has since been confirmed by the
legislature. Parliament has passed the Criminal
Law (Sexual Offences and Related Matters)
Amendment Act 6 of 2012, which expressly
provides that the powers of courts with regard to
sentences for the offences in Chapters 2, 3 and 4
of the Act are the same as those specified in s 276
of the Criminal Procedure Act.
In Sekretaris van Binnelandse Inkomste v Lourens
Erasmus (Edms) Bpk 1966 (4) SA 434 (A) the
court held that if possible the interpretation that
avoids uncertainty, confusion and conflict must be
adopted. Furthermore, the presumption enables
courts to try to interpret legislation in such a
manner that evasion of its provisions is prevented
(Dadoo Ltd v Krugersdorp Municipal Council 1920
AD 530). In Dhanabakium v Subramanian 1943 AD
160, the court found that as far as possible,
legislation should be interpreted in such a way that
a
Page 136
casus omissus (omission) is avoided. As will be
discussed later (Chapter 7 below), the courts may
indeed modify (adapt) the initial meaning of the
legislation (in the light of the presumption against
futile provisions and within the framework of the
purpose of the legislation). However, this
presumption applies only if there is more than one
possible interpretation, and cannot be used by a
court to reinterpret legislation at will. In other
words, this presumption cannot be used to
hammer a square peg into a round hole.
The presumption also applies to subordinate
legislation. Here, the maxim ut res magis valeat
quam pereat applies. This means that an
interpretation which will not leave the subordinate
legislation ultra vires (and invalid), but rather intra
vires and valid must be preferred (R v Vayi 1946
NPD 792). The ut res magis valeat quam pereat
rule applies only where two interpretations of a
provision are possible. The presumption cannot be
used to rescue an administrative act (conduct)
which is defective and invalid from the outset
(Mamogalie v Minister van Naturellesake 1961 (1)
SA 467 (A)). Consequently, any subordinate
legislation in conflict with the enabling Act (or any
other original legislation, for that matter) will also
be invalidated.
(b) Conflicts with other legislation
•
if the state would be rendered subject to the
authority of or interference by its own officials;
and
Page 140
•
if the state would be affected by penal
provisions (as in S v Huyser 1968 (3) SA 490
(GW) (see below)).
The question whether the state is bound depends
on the particular legislation and specific
circumstances, and each case has to be judged on
its own merits. The following are examples of the
practical application of the presumption:
•
Government bodies and state-controlled
agencies are bound by town planning schemes
(Drakensberg Administration Board v Town
Planning Appeals Board 1983 (4) SA 42 (N)
and Boiler Efficiency Services CC v Coalcor
(Cape)(Pty) Ltd 1989 (3) SA 460 (C)).
•
A security official who contravenes a statutory
provision when acting outside the scope of his
duties cannot rely on the presumption against
the state being bound (S v Reed 1972 (2) SA
34 (RA)).
•
The driver of a fire engine may disregard a red
traffic light while fire-fighting (S v Labuschagne
1979 (3) SA 1320 (T)).
•
An agricultural official who combats stock
diseases and from time to time has to cull
animals is not bound by statutory requirements
regarding hunting permits (S v Huyser
(above)).
Case law example:
S v De Bruin (above) is a rather interesting case,
to put it mildly. The accused was charged with and
convicted of exceeding the statutory speed limit.
On appeal, De Bruin (a state prosecutor) claimed
that he was a public servant who, on the day in
question, had been running late for an on-site
inspection on the state’s behalf. If he had arrived
late at the inspection premises, this could have
been detrimental to the state’s case. The court
found that being bound by the provisions in
question could have obstructed essential state
services and jeopardised state security. The court
found that De Bruin’s decision to exceed the speed
limit was reasonable, and set aside the conviction.
Steyn (1981: 77) correctly points out that this
presumption applies to both original and
subordinate legislation. Furthermore Labuschagne
(1978: 54) indicates, with reference to R v Thomas
1954 (1) SA 185 (SWA), that strictly speaking
Page 141
this presumption deals with the state being bound
by particular provisions; the state might be bound
by one provision of the legislation, but not by
another.
Another distinction is necessary. Not being bound
by legislation (as a result of the presumption) does
not mean that state liability is also automatically
excluded. If police officers in hot pursuit of
criminals ignore a red traffic light (on the face of it
quite lawfully), but they do so at break-neck
speeds, not slowing down at intersections and
without taking pedestrians and other motorists into
consideration during the chase, they cannot rely on
this presumption to escape any possible delictual
liability resulting from their actions.
Criticism:
Since s 39(2) of the Constitution clearly stipulates
that rules of common law have to be developed in
the light of the fundamental rights in the
Constitution, it is submitted that this particular
presumption should in future no longer apply
under the new constitutional order:
•
Section 8(1) of the Constitution expressly
provides that government organs at all levels
are bound by the Bill of Rights. The
Constitution is the supreme law of the
Republic, and all law and government conduct
must be tested against the spirit, purport and
objects of the fundamental rights entrenched in
the Bill of Rights. In a system based on
constitutionalism it would not make sense that
government bodies are bound by the
Constitution (as the supreme law), but at the
same time are presumed not to be bound by
their own legislation, which legislation is also
subject to the supreme Constitution.
•
The Constitution abounds with references to
principles such as accountability and openness
(the preamble and s 1(d)); supremacy of the
Constitution (ss 1(a) and 2); the values
underlying an open and democratic society
based on freedom, equality and human dignity
(ss 7(1) and 39(2)); the state being bound by
the Constitution
Page 142
(ss 2 and 8(1)); the requirement that the state
must respect, protect, promote and fulfil the
Constitution and the Bill of Rights (s 7(2); and
the official oath of judicial officers (item 6 of
Schedule 2)). All of these support the
argument that this presumption should no
longer be applied.
As Du Plessis (2002: 177) points out, the view of
Wiechers that this presumption should be applied
the other way round has now been vindicated after
all these years:
In short, a state defined by its own constitution
as a ‘democratic state founded on the . . .
values’ of ‘[s]upremacy of the Constitution and
the rule of law’ most certainly is a
constitutional state (Rechtsstaat) heedful of the
principle of legality. This observation is
confirmed by the constitutional demand for the
accountability of the public administration. The
moment for what Wiechers foresaw more than
a decade and a half ago, has probably come.
In Fedsure Life Assurance Ltd v Greater
Johannesburg Transitional Metropolitan Council
(above) para 58 the Constitutional Court explained
the principle of legality in the new constitutional
order as follows:
It seems central to the conception of our
constitutional order that the Legislature and
Executive in every sphere are constrained by
the principle that they may exercise no power
and perform no function beyond that conferred
upon them by law. At least in this sense, then,
the principle of legality is implied within the
terms of the interim Constitution. Whether the
principle of the rule of law has greater content
than the principle of legality is not necessary
for us to decide here. We need merely hold
that fundamental to the interim Constitution is
a principle of legality.
Since the constitutionality of this common-law
presumption has not yet been tested in court, it
still applies in South Africa. However, the correct
legal position in future should rather be as follows:
government agencies and organs of state should
always be bound by their own legislation, unless
they can prove that they would be hampered in the
execution of their duties and functions if bound by
the legislation. Admittedly such a new principle will
have to be prospective only, since retroactively
undoing the vested rights and interests obtained
by the state as a result of the application of this
presumption in the past could prove to be
impossible.
Page 143
6.3 The value-laden (teleological)
dimension: The ghost in the machine
6.3.1 The new constitutional approach to
statutory interpretation, or, moving from
bumper stickers to substantive interpretation
In Sidumo v Rustenburg Platinum Mines Ltd 2008
(2) SA 24 (CC) para 149 Sachs J described the
constitutional values as follows (emphasis added):
The values of the Constitution are strong,
explicit and clearly intended to be considered
part of the very texture of the constitutional
project. They are implicit in the very structure
and design of the new democratic order. The
letter and the spirit of the Constitution cannot
be separated; just as the values are not free-
floating, ready to alight as mere adornments
on this or that provision, so is the text not self-
supporting, awaiting occasional evocative
enhancement. The role of constitutional values
is certainly not simply to provide a patina of
virtue to otherwise bald, neutral and discrete
legal propositions. Text and values work
together in integral fashion to provide the
protections promised by the Constitution.
However, the value-based dimension of statutory
interpretation is not easy to implement. Since
1994 the South African legal fraternity has had to
face the dreaded V-word: values. These lawyers,
judges and law teachers were schooled in and
indoctrinated by a positivist idea of the law: iudicis
est ius dicere sed non dare; Parliament knows best
and has spoken; lawyers are not philosophers;
plain meanings, clear texts and black letter law;
formalism and his master’s voice; and so on.
Indeed, we now have a supreme Constitution,
brimming with references to fundamental values:
freedom (including religious freedom, freedom of
speech, and so on), equality (both formal and
substantive), human dignity, all the trimmings of a
multi-party democracy, good governance (s 195 of
the Constitution), openness, transparency, non-
racism, non-sexism, tolerance, and so on and so
forth. These values form the basis of a more
mature society (S v Makwanyane (above)) trying
to be the better society alluded to by former Chief
Justice Mahomed in S v Acheson 1991 (2) SA 805
(Nm) 813, when he said that a supreme
Constitution is the mirror reflecting the national
soul. But what are we doing in practical terms to
animate those values through, amongst other
things, the interpretation of legislation? Is s 39(2)
of the Constitution nothing more than an empty
gesture, mere hollow rhetoric?
Page 144
The value-based dimension of interpretation is
more than simply paying lip-service, but involves
making those values real; animating them through
the making, interpretation, and application of the
law, as well as ensuring that the law is respected
and adhered to. It involves a willingness to keep
those values in mind, right from the outset; a mind
shift that law comprises more than ideologies,
power structures, politics, policies and the meaning
of the words on paper.
As was pointed out earlier, s 39(2) of the
Constitution ensures that interpretation of statutes
also occurs within the value-laden (teleological and
normative) constitutional framework. But s 39(2)
cannot be merely window-dressing or hollow
rhetoric. In Holomisa v Argus Newspaper Ltd
(above) 844 the court referred to s 35(3) of the
interim Constitution (the forerunner of s 39(2) of
the 1996 Constitution), stating that the
interpretation clause in the Constitution is
[not] merely an interpretive directive, but a
force that informs all legal institutions and
decisions with the new power of constitutional
values.
In Coetzee v Government of the Republic of South
Africa; Matiso v Commanding Officer, Port
Elizabeth Prison 1995 (4) SA 631 (CC) para 46
Sachs J explained the teleological dimension of
interpretation even better (emphasis added):
The values that must suffuse the whole process
are derived from the concept of an open and
democratic society based on freedom and
equality, several times referred to in the
Constitution. The notion of an open and
democratic society is thus not merely
aspirational or decorative, it is normative,
furnishing the matrix of ideals within which we
work, the source from which we derive the
principles and rules we apply, and the final
measure we use for testing the legitimacy of
impugned norms and conduct . . . [W]e should
not engage in purely formal or academic
analysis, nor simply restrict ourselves to ad hoc
technicism, but rather focus on what has been
called the synergetic relation between the
values underlying the guarantees of
fundamental rights and the circumstances of
the particular case.
This means that the constitutional values are not
there to be used as fridge magnets or bumper
stickers, or to be quoted and insisted on when it
suits you, but instantly forgotten when it does not.
In Harksen v President of The RSA 2000 (5) SA
478 (CC) para 18 the court emphasised that since
the Constitution is the supreme law of the land and
that all legislation must be
Page 145
read subject to it, it is unnecessary for legislation
expressly to incorporate terms of the Constitution,
and as a result constitutional provisions or values
or principles are part of the implied contents of
statutes. But by the same token these values
should not be used as a show of smoke and
mirrors as a cover-up for bad governance, like
hiding a badly baked cake under layers of nice-
looking icing.
Maybe it should be said: if we choose to ignore
the V-word; if these values are not taken seriously
and borne in mind constantly during (amongst
other things) interpretation of legislation; and if we
are not prepared to succumb to constitutionalism,
we might as well get rid of the supreme
Constitution, the justiciable Bill of Rights and rights
rhetoric, and return to the former bad old days of
sovereignty of Parliament and executive-minded
interpretation of legislation. Otherwise we need to
become serious about the rights and values in the
Constitution—including a new ‘constitutional’
approach to statutory interpretation—in other
words, moving from bumper stickers to
substantive justice.
But how do we animate and concretise those
values? How does freedom influence no-parking
signs? What is the link between having to pay your
income tax before the due date and human
dignity? How can values influence the black letter
of the law? A starting point for that is always using
the Constitution as a point of departure for legal
analysis, interpretation and application, something
which was not done by the court in the following
example:
Case law example:
In S v F 1999 (1) SACR 571 (C) the court had to
decide whether the 17-year-old rape victim could
testify from a room adjoining the court. This
required an interpretation of s 158(3) of the
Criminal Procedure Act 51 of 1977:
158 Criminal proceedings to take place in
presence of accused
...
(3) A court may make an order
contemplated in subsection (2) only if facilities
therefor are readily available or obtainable and
if it appears to the court that to do so
would. . .
(a)
prevent unreasonable delay;
(b)
save costs;
Page 146
(c)
be convenient;
(d)
be in the interest of the security of the State or
of public safety or in the interests of justice or
the public; or
(e)
prevent the likelihood that prejudice or harm
might result to any person if he or she testifies
or is present at such proceedings.
The court held that s 158(3) cannot be read
disjunctively (paras (a), (b), (c), (d) or (e)), but it
should rather be read conjunctively, in other
words, in order to testify via CCTV, the applicant
had to comply with the requirements set forth in
paragraphs (a), (b) and (c), as well as any of the
requirements set forth in either paragraph (d) or
(e) of s 158(3). This was a poor decision based on
an incorrect interpretation of the law, which meant
that all the lower courts in the Western Cape had
to apply the ridiculously strict requirements. In
practical terms the decision meant that it was
virtually impossible for a witness to be allowed not
to testify in the presence of the alleged rapist
(even six-year-old rape victims).
But why was this a bad interpretation? It was a
purely text-based analysis of s 158(3), dealing
with semi-colons and other rules of punctuation.
The judge referred to the common-law
presumption that legislature does not intend harsh
or unreasonable results; since the victim would not
be in court (if allowed to testify via CCTV) the
accused’s right to cross-examination would be
infringed; the court relied on a 1920 case (Dadoo
Ltd v Krugersdorp Municipal Council 1920 AD 530),
as well as English-law textbooks on interpretation
and procedure (R K Soonavala Advocacy: Its
Principles and Practice, and Maxwell Interpretation
of Statutes).
This was a 1999 decision—at least two years
after the 1996 Constitution took effect. However,
there is no reference to the Constitution, which
means there is no reference to human dignity (s
10); no reference to s 39(2); since the victim was
17 years old, no reference to s 28 (rights of the
child); no critical discussion about the struggle
between competing rights (in this case the s 28
children’s rights versus the s 35 rights of the
accused); no fundamental
Page 147
values—just a text-based analysis based on a
conjunctive grammatical reading of the provision
(plain meaning approach). This is a striking
example of what may happen if the value-based
dimension of statutory interpretation is ignored.
This decision was eventually held to be incorrect (S
v Staggie 2003 (1) SACR 232 (C)).
In fact, S v F was not the last case in the Western
Cape that failed to get to grips with the new
‘constitutional approach’ to interpretation. In
Winckler v Minister of Correctional Services 2001
(2) SA 747 (C) the court still followed the
discredited text-based approach:
The golden rule governing the interpretation of
a statute is to determine the intention of the
Legislature. Such intention is established, in
the first place, by the plain language of the
statute before resorting to other canons of
construction. The primary supposition is that
the Legislature intends what it says.
Fortunately there are examples of substantive
interpretation of statutes. In Ngxuza v Permanent
Secretary, Department of Welfare, Eastern Cape
2001 (2) SA 609 (E) Froneman J was aware of the
changes brought about by the new constitutional
order. The case dealt with a flexible and generous
approach to the issue of locus standi (including a
class action under s 38 of the Constitution) to
make it easier for disadvantaged and poor people
to approach courts on public issues to ensure that
public administration adheres to fundamental
principle of legality in exercising public power. His
substantive approach to statutory interpretation
and legal reasoning is clear from the following
excerpts from the judgment (at 619):
There is a broader social context in which law
is applied to particular facts in any given case.
Where that terrain is familiar and the law to be
applied is not new that context is often
assumed and not articulated. Here the position
is different. The law is new and the social
setting has changed. [T]he starting place to
determine our assumptions is the Constitution
. . . it is necessary in this case, because of the
relatively new legal position and the changed
social context in which it is to be applied, to be
open about one’s own views of that context.
The reality is that the outcome of this case is
not dictated by precedent or deductive legal
reasoning alone: my interpretation of s 38 of
the Constitution is inevitably also influenced by
my own views of the context in which it is to be
Page 148
interpreted and applied. This is a truth that, I
think, is now generally accepted by legal
theorists.
6.3.2 Ubuntu
The postamble of the English text of the 1993
Constitution referred to ubuntu:
There is a need for understanding but not for
vengeance, a need for reparation but not for
retaliation, a need for ubuntu but not for
victimisation . . .
Ubuntu is an indigenous African concept and refers
to a practical humanist disposition towards the
world, including compassion, tolerance and
fairness. (It is interesting to note that the African
Charter on Human and Peoples’ Rights also
includes a positive duty to tolerate.) The concept
was applied and explained by the Constitutional
Court in S v Makwanyane (above) 501D-E:
Generally, ubuntu translates as ‘humaneness’.
In its most fundamental sense, it translates as
‘personhood’ and ‘morality’ . . . While it
envelops the key values of group solidarity,
compassion, respect, human dignity,
conformity to basic norms and collective unity,
in its fundamental sense it denotes humanity
and morality. Its spirit emphasises respect for
human dignity, marking a shift from
confrontation to conciliation.
The concept of ubuntu is not expressly mentioned
in the Constitution of 1996. That does not mean
that ubuntu will disappear from the South African
legal stage. Since ubuntu was used in the
Makwanyane case (above), it forms part of the
new South African constitutional jurisprudence. It
may also be argued that ubuntu lives on in the
numerous references to human dignity in the
Constitution. It forms an important bridge between
the communal African traditions and Western
traditions, which focus on the individual, and could
be a very useful extra-textual aid to statutory and
constitutional interpretation.
•
What was the existing law (the legal position)
before the legislation in question was adopted?
•
Which problem (mischief or defect) was not
adequately addressed by the existing law
before the new legislation was adopted?
•
What remedy (solution) is proposed by the new
legislation to solve this problem?
•
What is the true reason for the proposed
remedy?
The aim of the rule is to examine the
circumstances that lead to the adoption of the
legislation in question. The mischief rule has been
applied on numerous occasions by the courts. For
example, as a result of the incomprehensible
language used in the Compulsory Motor Vehicle
Insurance Act 56 of 1972, the court in Santam
Insurance Ltd v Taylor (above) examined the
historical background of the Act in order to
ascertain its purpose.
Part 3
Some practical issues
and tricks of the trade:
Judicial law-making
during interpretation,
and peremptory and
directory provisions
7
Judicial law-making during concretisation
8
Peremptory and directory provisions
Page 159
Chapter 7
Judicial law-making during
concretisation
•
Du Toit (1977: 11) points out that the essence
of successful interpretation lies in the current
realisation of the possible meanings of the
original legislation. The meaning of the text is
tantamount to its application in a given
concrete situation.
Page 160
•
Lategan (1980: 107) defines interpretation as
the concretisation of the meaning of a text in a
concrete, present situation during the last
stage of the interpretation process. Such a
process is not simply the application of the
provisions of the legislation, but rather the
process of transition from interpretation to
application.
•
During concretisation the abstract text of the
legislation and the purpose of the legislation
(which was determined earlier in the process)
are correlated with the concrete facts of the
case within the framework of the prescribed
constitutional principles and guidelines.
•
He points out (1978: 62) that the court has a
peripheral and subordinate law-making
function and inevitably forms part of the
legislative process in concrete cases, aimed at
the fulfilment of needs in society (the reason
for the legislation).
•
Later he states (1985: 60) that the court is the
final link in the legislative chain and that it
should be its task to ensure that the legislative
process has a meaningful and just end.
•
Furthermore, he also explains (1983: 422) and
(1982: 402) that the legislation contained in
the document is incomplete and only
represents the initial structure of the statute.
Only when the court applies the legislation
does it become real and completely functional.
The legislation is situation-bound and the
process passes through stages—from the
generality of the structural statute to the
particularity of the functional statute. It is an
ongoing case-to-case process. So, in reality
legislation is not interpreted, but shaped or
moulded. The legislative process invariably
begins with a need for legal order and ends
every time with the fulfilment of that need by
the court. The purpose of the legislation is the
directing principle throughout the process.
•
The principle of democracy (the preamble and
s 1 of the Constitution) reminds us that
democracy is one of the fundamental
constitutional values. As a matter of fact, the
preamble of the Constitution refers to a
democratic and open society in which
government is based on the will of the people.
Although the courts are the guardians of the
constitutional values, they are not allowed to
take over the constitutional role of the
legislature. Sachs J explained this complex
constitutional balance between court and
legislature in Du Plessis v De Klerk (above)
para 18:
The function of the courts, I believe, is, in
the first place, to ensure that legislation
does not violate fundamental rights,
secondly, to interpret legislation in a
manner that furthers the values expressed
in the Constitution, and thirdly, to ensure
that common law and custom outside of the
legislative sphere is developed in such a
manner as to harmonise with the
Constitution.
•
The important principle of separation of powers
ensures that state power is shared between the
three branches of government, resulting in
formal built-in checks and balances to curb
abuse of power by the government (eg s 43 of
the Constitution deals with the legislative
authority in the RSA).
•
A common-law presumption holds that the
legislature does not intend to change the
existing law more than is necessary.
•
The rule of law principle, including the principle
of legality, should apply throughout.
•
Froneman (1996: 15–22) points out that
judicial law-making is not unbridled. Judicial
officers are accountable and responsible for
their actions on three levels: firstly, personal
responsibility, because they have to take
personal moral responsibility for their
decisions; secondly, formal responsibility,
consisting of the formal constitutional and
other legislative controls over the judiciary;
and thirdly, substantive accountability, in that
judicial decisions are open to public debate and
academic criticism (with reference to the
constitutional values of accountability,
responsiveness and openness expressed in s
1(d) of the Constitution);
•
Penal provisions or restrictive provisions in the
legislation,
Page 165
as well as the presumption against
infringement of existing rights, are also factors
which limit the discretion of the courts to
modify the initial meaning of the text.
•
The reading-down principle: ss 35(3) and
232(3) of the interim Constitution (the so-
called ‘reading down’ clauses) provided that if
legislation is on the face of it unconstitutional
(because it conflicts with the fundamental
rights and the rest of the Constitution
respectively) but is reasonably capable of a
more restricted interpretation which would be
constitutional and valid, such restricted
interpretation should be followed. These
provisions have not been repeated in the
Constitution of 1996. However, the principle
that courts should, as far as possible, try to
keep legislation constitutional (and therefore
valid) is a well-known principle of constitutional
interpretation.
•
Section 39(2) of the Constitution states that
during interpretation the courts must try to
reconcile the aim and purpose of the legislation
with the spirit and purport of the Bill of Rights
in particular.
•
The Bill of Rights is the cornerstone of the
South African democracy and the state must
respect, protect, promote and fulfil the rights in
the Bill of Rights (s 7 of the Constitution), and
it applies to all law and binds the judiciary as
well (s 8(1) of the Constitution).
•
The Constitution is the supreme law of the land
(s 2 of the Constitution), which means the end
of sovereignty of Parliament and the slavish
‘his master’s voice’ role of the courts.
•
The common-law presumption is that the
legislature does not intend futile, meaningless
and nugatory legislation.
•
The independence of the judiciary (s 165(2) of
the Constitution) also strengthens the
argument in favour of judicial law-making
during interpretation.
Eiusdem generis
•
The eiusdem generis rule can only be applied if
the specific words refer to a definite genus or
category. In Colonial Treasurer v Rand Water
Board 1907 TS 479 the court referred to such a
genus as a ‘common quality’ or ‘common
denominator’.
Case law example:
In Skotnes v South African Library 1997 (2) SA
770 (SCA) the court had to interpret s 2(1)(b) of
the Legal Deposit of Publications Act 17 of 1982
which required that a copy of every publication
published in the Republic be supplied free of
charge to every legal deposit library if copies of
such a publication are intended to be sold to
members of the public. The definition of
‘publication’ in the Act included ‘a printed book,
newspaper, magazine, periodical, journal,
pamphlet, brochure, sheet, card or portion thereof
or any other similar printed matter’.
Page 171
The appellant refused to supply a free copy of a
publication to the respondent, a legal deposit
library, arguing that it was not a ‘printed book’ as
defined in the Act. Counsel for the appellant
argued that the words following ‘printed book’ in
the definition restrict its meaning. Since these
items were all mass produced, inexpensive,
machinery-produced publications involving
essentially commercial printing, it created a
distinct category (genus). As a result of the distinct
category, the eiusdem generis rule applies, the
Skotnes book falls outside that category and the
Act does not apply to it.
However, the court took the other view. It
pointed out that unless there is a distinct category
formed by the specific words the eiusdem generis
rule cannot be applied. The court held that the
words following ‘printed book’ in the definition
section did not clearly indicate a genus of printed
material which would—through the application of
the eiusdem generis rule—restrict the meaning of
‘printed book’ to some species of that genus. The
intention of the legislature with the Act was to
build up a national collection of books providing a
record of cultural and scientific activities. The
scope and purpose of the Act did not support such
a restrictive interpretation, and the eiusdem
generis rule did not apply.
•
The specific words must not have exhausted
the genus (Carlis v Oldfield 4 HCG 379). In
such a case, it is assumed that the general
words refer to a broader genus and therefore
cannot be interpreted restrictively.
•
The rule can be applied even when a single
specific word precedes the general words. In
Director of Education, Transvaal v McCagie
1918 AD 616, the court found that the general
words ‘other evidence’ in the provision ‘a
university degree or other evidence of the
necessary qualifications’ had to be interpreted
eiusdem generis. ‘Other evidence’ refers to
something else in the same category as a
university degree.
•
In Bugler’s Post (Pty) Ltd v Secretary for Inland
Revenue 1974 (3) SA 28 (A) it was held that
the order in which the words occur is not
important: the general words may precede,
appear amongst or follow the specific words.
•
In PMB Armature Winders v Pietermaritzburg
City Council 1981 (2) SA 129 (A), the Appellate
Division stressed the
Page 172
requirement that the eiusdem generis rule
should be applied only if the ‘legislature’s
intention’ supports such a restrictive
interpretation. As a result the courts apply this
rule with circumspection.
Case law example:
In S v Kohler 1979 (1) SA 861 (T), the court heard
an appeal against the decision of a magistrate’s
court. Kohler was found guilty of contravening a
municipal by-law because he kept a peacock within
the municipal boundaries without the required
licence. The by-law required a licence for keeping
any fowl, duck, goose, turkey, guinea fowl,
partridge, pheasant, pigeon or the chickens
thereof, or any other bird on municipal premises.
Read in its literal sense the words ‘any other bird’
in the by-law would have meant that even a
budgie or parakeet required a licence. The defence
argued that the specific words in the by-law
created the category of poultry. Therefore eiusdem
generis had to apply, and since a peacock was not
a species of poultry, the municipal by-law did not
apply to peacocks.
The court agreed that the specific words did
indeed form the category of poultry, but the
dictionaries consulted by the court referred to
peacocks as ‘chicken-like decorative birds’. Since
there was a definite genus (ie poultry), the general
words ‘any other bird’ were restricted to that
genus. A peacock is a species of that genus, and
Kohler’s appeal against his conviction was
dismissed by the court.
Interpretation by implication
•
Ex contrariis: Here the implications arise from
opposites. If the legislation provides for a
particular circumstance, by implication it
provides the contrary provision for the opposite
circumstance. This overlaps with the principle
‘expression of the one thing by implication
means the exclusion of the other’ (expressio
unius est exclusio alterius), which is not a hard
and fast rule but merely a prima facie indicator
of meaning.
•
Ex consequentibus: If legislation demands or
allows a certain result or consequence,
everything which is reasonably necessary to
bring about that result or consequence may be
implied (in other words, instances where
additional powers or authority are implied as a
result of the initial express power or authority).
The test is not usefulness or convenience, but
necessity.
Case law example:
In Bloemfontein Town Council v Richter 1938 AD
195 the court found that where a municipality has
a statutory right to contain a river for the purposes
of water supply, it also, by implication, has a right
to remove washed-up silt from the dam. In each
instance the underlying principle is whether the
conferred power can be exercised effectively.
•
Ex accessorio eius de quo verba loquuntur: If a
principal thing is forbidden or permitted, the
accessory thing is also forbidden or permitted.
•
Anatura ipsius rei: This refers to implied
inherent relationships—for example, the power
to issue a regulation implies the power to
withdraw it.
Page 174
•
Ex correlativis: This arises from mutual or
reciprocal relationships (eg prohibiting the
purchase of certain things includes the
prohibition of the sale of such goods).
Interpretation by analogy
Page 175
Chapter 8
Peremptory and directory
provisions
•
A word or words with an imperative or
affirmative character indicate a peremptory
provision (eg the words ‘shall’ or ‘must’)
(Messenger of the Magistrate’s Court, Durban v
Pillay 1952 (3) SA 678 (A)). In Bezuidenhout v
AA Mutual Insurance Association Ltd 1978 (1)
SA 703 (A), for example, the court found that
‘shall’ is a strong indication that the provision is
peremptory. In S v Takaendesa 1972 (4) SA 72
(RAD) 78C–D this principle was explained as
follows:
Where a statute prohibits the doing of
something unless something else is done as
a precedent to doing the thing prescribed,
it is a general rule of interpretation that the
provisions of the Act are obligatory and not
directory.
On the other hand, in
Motorvoertuigassuransiefonds v Gcwabe 1979
(4) SA 986 (A) the court held that ‘shall’ does
not necessarily indicate a peremptory meaning.
•
Permissive words (such as ‘may’) indicate a
discretion and will be interpreted as being
directory, unless the purpose of the provision
indicates otherwise (Amalgamated Packaging
Industries v Hutt 1975 (4) SA 943 (A)).
•
Words in negative form indicate a peremptory
connotation (Samuel Thomas Meyers v
Pretorius & Etc 1944 OPD 144).
•
Positive language suggests that the provision is
merely directory (R v Sopete 1950 (3) SA 796
(E)).
•
If the provision is formulated in flexible or
vague terms, it is an indication that it is
directory (Leibrandt v SA Railways 1941 AD 9).
•
If the wording of the provision is in positive
terms, and no penal sanction (punishment) is
included for non-compliance with the
requirements, it is an indication that the
provision in question should be regarded as
being merely directory (ie in favour of validity
of the ensuing act). Steyn (1981: 197)
questions this ‘test’, because without a penalty,
the only sanction to prevent the defeat of the
legislative scheme is to declare the act null and
void.
Page 179
•
If strict compliance with the provisions would
lead to injustice and even fraud (and the
legislation contains neither an express
provision as to whether the action would be
null and void nor a penalty), it is presumed
that the provision is directory (Johannesburg
City Council v Arumugan 1961 (3) SA 748
(W)).
•
In some instances, the historical context of the
legislation (in other words, the mischief rule)
will provide a reliable indication as to whether
the provision is peremptory or merely
directory.
•
Adding a penalty to a prescription or
prohibition is a strong indication that the
provision is peremptory (Rooiberg Minerals and
Development Co Ltd v Du Toit 1953 (2) SA 505
(T)). Nevertheless, this prima facie
presumption was rebutted by the purpose of
the legislation in Standard Bank v Estate van
Rhyn 1925 AD 266. On the other hand, the
addition of a penal clause may be an indication
that the legislature intended the penalty to be
sufficient and that the act should not be
declared null and void as well (Eland Boerdery
(Edms) Bpk v Anderson 1966 (4) SA 400 (T)).
•
If the validity of the act would defeat the
purpose of the legislation, this is an indication
that the act (conduct) should be null and void
(R v Lewinsohn 1922 TPD 336).
•
Where legislation protects the public revenue
(ie rates, taxes and levies due to the state), a
presumption against nullity exists, even if a
penal clause has been added (McLoughlin v
Turner 1921 AD 537).
•
Where legislation confers a right, privilege or
immunity, the requirements are peremptory
and the right, privilege or immunity cannot be
validly obtained unless the prescribed
formalities are fully complied with (Orpen v
Cilliers 20 SC 264). Where the freedom of an
individual is at stake, the court will stress the
peremptory nature of a requirement.
•
If other provisions in the legislation could
become superfluous (meaningless) when non-
compliance with prescribed requirements
results in the nullity of the act, there is a
presumption that the requirements are merely
Page 180
directory. In Hurwitz v SA Mining and General
Insurance Co Ltd 1958 (4) SA 136 (W) the
court found that s 3(2) of the Motor Vehicle
Insurance Act 29 of 1942 was merely directory,
since ss 24 and 31 would otherwise be
superfluous.
•
If a provision requires that a certain act must
be performed within a prescribed time, and the
court has not been empowered to grant an
extension of the time limit, the requirement is
presumed to be peremptory (Le Roux v Grigg-
Spall 1946 AD 244).
The courts have developed a large number of
guidelines to assist them to determine whether
exact compliance or merely substantive compliance
with prescribed statutory requirements is
necessary. However, the supreme Constitution as
well as specific requirements in important
legislation (such as the Promotion of Access to
Information and the Promotion of Administrative
Justice Act) must always be borne in mind when
the issue of exact compliance or substantive
compliance is considered during statutory
interpretation. The Constitution itself also contains
a number of peremptory provisions. Some of the
most important of these are s 2 (‘This Constitution
is the supreme law of the Republic . . . and the
obligations imposed by it must be fulfilled’), s 7(2)
(‘The state must respect, protect, promote and
fulfil the rights in the Bill of Rights’) and s 39(2)
(‘every court, tribunal or forum must promote the
spirit, purport and objects of the Bill of Rights’).
Page 181
Part 4
Constitutional
interpretation
9
Constitutional interpretation
Page 183
Chapter 9
Constitutional interpretation
9.1 Introduction
Why is constitutional interpretation an issue?
Interpretation is interpretation is interpretation, is
it not? You just read the text, follow the well-
known rules of statutory interpretation and apply
the maxims. However, it is not that simple: by now
it should be clear that interpretation of legislation
(including a constitution), is not mechanical and
formalistic, but a comprehensive analysis of the
text-in-context.
(a)
Must promote the values which underlie an
open and democratic society based on human
dignity, equality and freedom;
(b)
Must consider international law; and
(c)
May consider foreign law.
The first part of the provision is peremptory: when
interpreting the Bill of Rights, a court, tribunal or
forum must make value judgements (ie promote
the values which underlie an open and democratic
society based on human dignity, equality and
freedom) and must have regard to international
law (international human rights law in particular).
This is a set of universal rules and norms dealing
with the protection of fundamental human rights
and consists of a number of international
documents and rules of customary international
law.
Furthermore, a court, tribunal or forum may also
refer to foreign law when interpreting the Bill of
Rights. The rules of foreign law applicable here are
those legal principles (in particular case law) which
do not conflict with the South African legal order (s
35(1) of the interim Constitution referred to
‘comparable foreign case law’); in other words,
those legal principles applied in a democratic legal
order based on constitutionalism.
The interpretation clause of the Bill of Rights
must be read with the supremacy clause, as well
as with s 1. Section 1 is arguably one of the most
important provisions in the supreme Constitution:
The Republic of South Africa is one, sovereign,
democratic state founded on the following
values:
(a)
Human dignity, the achievement of equality
and the advancement of human rights and
freedoms.
(b)
Non-racialism and non-sexism.
(c)
Universal adult suffrage, a national common
voters roll,
Page 190
regular elections and a multi-party system
of democratic government, to ensure
accountability, responsiveness and
openness.
An in-depth discussion of all the rules and
principles of constitutional interpretation is a
subject on its own. The following are some of the
general principles formulated by Southern African
courts:
•
A supreme constitution must be given a
generous and purposive interpretation
(Shabalala v The Attorney-General of Transvaal
1996 (1) SA 725 (CC) 740 para 26). In
Nyamakazi v President of Bophuthatswana
(above) 567H it was held that a purposive
interpretation of the Constitution is necessary,
since it enables the court to take into account
more than legal rules:
These are the objectives of the rights
contained therein, the circumstances
operating at the time when the
interpretation has to be determined, the
future implications of the construction, the
impact of the said construction on future
generations, the taking into account of new
developments and changes in society.
•
Case law also refers to a liberal interpretation
of the Constitution. A liberal interpretation does
not have a political connotation, but refers to
flexibility and generosity. The Constitution
must be liberally construed, taking into account
its terms and spirit, the intention of the
framers and the objectives of and reasons for
the legislation. In the process, the ordinary
rules of statutory interpretation must give way
to this more adaptable and flexible method.
•
During the interpretation of the Constitution,
its spirit and tenor must be adhered to (S v
Acheson (above)). This means that the values
and moral standards underpinning the
Constitution must be taken into account
throughout the entire interpretation process.
•
A provision in the Constitution cannot be
interpreted in isolation, but must be read in the
context as a whole. The context includes the
historical factors that led to the adoption of the
Constitution in general, and the fundamental
rights in particular (S v Makwanyane (above)).
•
Respect must be paid to the language
employed in the Constitution. Although the text
is balanced and qualified by various contextual
factors, the context is anchored to the
particular constitutional text. In other words,
historical context and comparative
interpretation can never reflect a
Page 191
purpose that is not supported by the
constitutional text as a legal instrument.
However, this does not imply a mechanical
adherence to the strict austerity of literal
legalism (Shabalala v The Attorney-General of
Transvaal (above) 740 para 27). In Nyamakazi
v President of Bophuthatswana (above) 566G
this method was referred to as an open-ended
process of elucidation and commentary which
explores, reads into, derives and attaches
significance to every word, section or clause in
relation to the whole context.
•
In S v A Juvenile 1990 (4) SA 151 (ZSC) 176B,
the court stressed the fact that the
Constitution, as the supreme law of the land,
has bestowed on the court the sacred trust of
protecting human rights.
•
The Constitution was drafted with a view to the
future, providing a continuing framework for
the legitimate exercise of government power
and the protection of individual rights and
freedoms (Khala v The Minister of Safety and
Security (above) 122D–E). The Constitution
has to be interpreted in the context and setting
existing at the time when the case is heard,
and not when it was passed, otherwise the
growth of society will not be taken into
account. The Constitution must be interpreted
so that it gives clear expression to the values
the Constitution intends to nurture for the
future (Qozoleni v Minister of Law and Order
(above)).
•
Some die-hard supporters of the orthodox text-
based approach who do not understand a
system of constitutional supremacy refer to
constitutional interpretation as a free-floating
exercise. This is simply not correct. Ultimately,
constitutional interpretation is a question of
law: if the particular legislation is consistent
with the Constitution, it is valid and in force; if
not, the court which exercises a judicial check
in terms of the Constitution will declare it
unconstitutional and strike it down.
Constitutional interpretation is an exercise in
the balancing of various societal interests and
values.
•
These methods and principles of constitutional
interpretation do not constitute a closed set of
hard and fast rules. Constitutional
interpretation is an inherently flexible process.
It is not a dogmatic and mechanical application
of predefined approaches and rules. Allowance
must be made for changing circumstances
(Nortje v Attorney-General of the Cape (above)
472F–473C).
Page 192
•
The principles of international human rights law
and foreign law must be applied with due
regard for the South African context (S v Zuma
1995 (2) SA 642 (CC) 651H–I). In other words,
constitutional interpretation must start and end
with the South African Constitution (S v
Makwanyane (above) 406E–407C, Du Plessis v
De Klerk (above) para 123).
•
All judges and judicial officers are obliged to
interpret and apply legislation so as to give
effect to the fundamental values and rights in
the supreme Constitution. This role is not a
mechanical reiteration of the mythical intent of
the lawgiver, but is rather an ongoing, value-
based struggle between competing rights and
values. This struggle (engagement) with the
constitutional text, context, law and society in
transformation is eloquently described (with
reference to the limitation of rights) by Sachs J
in Prince v Cape Law Society 2002 (2) SA 794
(CC) para 155:
What it requires is the maximum
harmonisation of all the competing
considerations, on a principled yet nuanced
and flexible case-by-case basis, located in
South African reality yet guided by
international experience, articulated with
appropriate candour and accomplished
without losing sight of the ultimate values
highlighted by our Constitution. In
achieving this balance, this Court may
frequently find itself faced with complex
problems as to what properly belongs to
the discretionary sphere which the
Constitution allocates to the Legislature and
the Executive, and what falls squarely to be
determined by the Judiciary.
9.3.2 A comprehensive methodology
But how do we concretise these principles and
guidelines? How do we make it practical in the real
world of racism and politics and poverty and crime
and aspirations and so on? As was pointed out
earlier (Chapter 5), Du Plessis & Corder (1994: 73-
74) discuss five techniques of interpretation. These
complementary techniques apply to constitutional
interpretation as well.
•
The results of reading-in/severance/reading-up
must be consistent with the Constitution and
its values.
•
The result achieved should interfere with the
existing law as little as possible.
Page 196
•
The courts must be able to define with
sufficient precision how the legislative meaning
ought to be modified to comply with the
Constitution.
•
The court should endeavour to be as faithful as
possible to the legislative scheme (ie
aim/purpose) within the constraints of the
Constitution.
•
The remedy of reading-in ought not to be
granted where this would result in an
unsupportable budgetary intrusion.
9.4.2 Reading-down
Sections 35(2) and 232(2) of the interim
Constitution provided that if legislation is on the
face of it unconstitutional (because it conflicts with
the fundamental rights and the rest of the
Constitution respectively), but is reasonably
capable of a more restricted interpretation which
would be constitutional and valid, such restricted
interpretation should be followed (ie ‘reading-
down’). These provisions have not been repeated
in the Constitution of 1996, but the principle that
courts should as far as possible try to keep
legislation constitutional—and therefore valid—is a
well-known principle of constitutional interpretation
(in Germany it is called Verfassungskonforme
Auslegung). This principle is similar to the common
law presumption that the legislation does not
contain futile or meaningless provisions (see
Chapter 6 above).
9.4.3 Reading-up
Reading-up takes place when there is more than
one possible reading of the legislative text, and a
more extensive reading is adopted in order to keep
the legislation in question constitutional.
Case law example:
In Daniels v Campbell 2004 (5) SA 331 (CC) the
court held that a person who is party to a
monogamous Muslim marriage is not included
under the terms ‘spouse’ and ‘spouses’ in the
Intestate Succession Act 81 of 1987 and the
Maintenance of Surviving Spouses Act 27 of 1990.
In order to avoid unconstitutionality of the
legislation, the court interpreted the words in a
broad and inclusive way to include persons married
according to Muslim rites.
Page 197
9.4.4 Reading-in
Reading-in is a more drastic remedy used by the
courts in order to change legislation in order to
keep it constitutional. In exceptional circumstances
the court will ‘read’ something into the meaning of
a provision in order to rescue a provision, or a part
of it. Reading-in should be applied with caution,
since the court will change the meaning of the
legislation, and after all, the legislative function is
entrusted to bodies and persons authorised to
enact legislation.
Case law example:
In Gory v Kolver (Starke and Others Intervening)
2007 (4) SA 97 (CC) the court found that the
provisions of s 1(1) of the Intestate Succession Act
81 of 1987 were unconstitutional, and it was
reasonably possible to interpret the provision as if
the words ‘or partner in a permanent same-sex life
partnership in which the partners have undertaken
reciprocal duties of support’ appeared after the
word ‘spouse’ in the section.
9.4.5 Severance
In practical terms ‘severance’ is the opposite of
‘reading-in’. Here the court will try to rescue a
provision from the fate of unconstitutionality by
‘cutting out’ a part of the provision from the rest of
the text to keep the remainder constitutional and
valid. Before severance can be applied, the two
requirements must be met: First, it must be
possible to separate (sever or cut out) the
unconstitutional (bad) part of the provision from
the rest (the good). Secondly, what remains of the
provision must still be able to give effect to the
purpose of the legislation (Coetzee v Government
of the Republic of South Africa (above)).
9.5 Contemporary challenges, or,
whose Constitution is it anyway?
So: after nearly two decades of rainbow democracy
and constitutionalism, the question of
constitutional interpretation and application has
been sorted out, right? The Constitution and the
Bill of Rights require a purposive interpretation,
with due regard to the values and aspirations
expressed in the constitutional text, right? Now
that the philosophical issues
Page 198
have been addressed, we can concentrate on real
issues, right?
It is not that simple and final. Constitutional
interpretation is a dynamic process which can
never be finished, since circumstances and
perceptions and values will change. There can
never be one final interpretation which is cast in
stone. No understanding of the Constitution is holy
writ, and there are many unanswered questions
and unsolved problems that need to be addressed.
After all, the Constitution is supposed to be a living
document, and unless we understand and accept
the indeterminacy and evolving nature of
constitutional interpretation and constitutional
jurisprudence, there is a danger of falling back into
other new rigid orthodoxies: not sovereignty of
Parliament (‘Parliament has spoken’), but maybe
this time series of executive-minded
pronouncements by the Constitutional Court (the
Oracle of Braamfontein), or government’s
oligarchical obstinacy in Pretoria. In S v Mhlungu
1995 (3) SA 867 (CC) para 129, Sachs J explained
this ever-changing process of interpretation as
follows:
I regard the question of interpretation to be
one to which there can never be an absolute
and definitive answer and that, in particular
. . . how to balance out competing provisions,
will always take the form of a principled judicial
dialogue, in the first place between members of
this Court, then between our Court and other
Courts, the legal profession, law schools,
parliament, and indirectly, with the public at
large.
9.5.1 The counter-majoritarian difficulty
There is still a lingering tension between the
testing right of the judiciary and the will of the
people: Is it acceptable and legitimate for an
unelected court to thwart the democratic wishes of
the majority (as expressed in the measures taken
by the elected government)? On the one hand the
Constitution is also the product of a negotiated
settlement involving the people. This Constitution
(including a Bill of Rights) must serve, amongst
other things, as a shield to protect the
fundamental rights of the people and to promote
the values expressed in the Constitution. According
to Michelman (1988: 1537) the judiciary has a
‘situational advantage over the people at large in
listening to the voices from the margins’. On the
other hand, however, the principles of democracy
and the separation of powers are also some of the
fundamental values underlying a constitutional
state. Any court involved in constitutional review
(the so-called testing right of the judiciary) has to
walk
Page 199
a very fine and sometimes precarious line.
Suddenly, policy issues seem to be justiciable. Du
Plessis & De Ville (1993: 81) explain:
[A] bill of rights judicialises politics because it
requires the judiciary to act as an independent
referee who keeps (party) political actors to the
basic ‘rules of the (political) game’ enshrined in
the bill of rights. This in turn calls for political
skills on the part of the ‘referee itself’—a
politicisation of the judiciary in other words.
But what are the boundaries of constitutional
review? The courts may have a ‘sacred duty’ to
protect the rights in the Constitution, but is the
Constitution what the judges say it is? What about
the inputs of civil society and the other participants
in the democratic process? The court is the
guardian of constitutional rights and values, but it
is not a super legislature. Where to draw the line,
and who draws that line during interpretation and
application, are some of the vexing questions still
facing the courts in a constitutional state.
9.5.2 The constitutional values
With the establishment of the new constitutional
order on 27 April 1994, South Africa underwent a
number of fundamental changes. In the process,
South Africans made the choice in favour of a
constitutional state, underpinned by express
fundamental values (including human dignity,
freedom and equality). The Constitution enjoins
the judiciary to consider, respect, protect, promote
and fulfil these constitutional values (ss 2, 7(2)
and 39(2)). In short, these fundamental values are
in the Constitution and have to be applied.
However, the question is: What is to be done
with these values? Are these constitutional values
merely high-sounding and impressive references to
human dignity, justice, and so on, which are only
used from time to time as moral embroidery for
case law? It has already been mentioned that the
Critical Legal Studies movement criticises these
hollow promises and empty rhetoric about rights. If
supporters of the constitutional state do not wish
to be guilty of the accusations by CLS that only lip
service is paid to fundamental rights, the judiciary
must adopt a more ‘activist’ role with regard to the
fundamental values during constitutional
interpretation.
What is activist constitutional interpretation? It
deals primarily with the active and positive
promotion and strengthening of the fundamental
constitutional values. The
Page 200
substantive (value-laden) component of the
constitutional state must be activated and
concretised by the courts. Not only the rights and
values of the individual must be emphasised, but
those of the community (including the
marginalised and disadvantaged) as well.
The Constitution is a value-laden document, and
these values (or the spirit of the Bill of Rights)
must be promoted and nurtured and applied. But
whose values are we talking about? From whose
point of view are these values identified and
interpreted? What about cultural relativism? For
example: different cultures and ethnic groups have
very different ideas about non-sexism and the
place of women in society. Put another way, there
is a diverse community of constitutional
interpreters involved in the constitutional discourse
in South Africa. Linked to this challenge is the role
of dominant cultures and groups in the
interpretation process. How open-ended concepts
such as open and democratic society or non-
sexism or human dignity are concretised in
practice, would to some degree depend on who the
interpreters are. For example, if the interpreters in
a given situation are only men, the concretised
meaning of non-sexism will inevitably be biased,
influenced by culture, pre-understanding and
preconceived ideas about sex and gender.
Hypothetical example:
As was pointed out in Chapter 5 above, the
consideration of fundamental values during
interpretation is not easy, but by the same token it
cannot be ignored. However, as the Critical Legal
Studies scholars point out, we all have
preconceived ideas and perceptions based on our
culture, history, religion and other factors. We all
have our personal baggage; a monkey on our
backs. We should not deny it but be aware of it
during the interpretation process. But that begs
the question: When will whose personal
perceptions about race and gender and rights and
values prevail? For instance, take the following
hypothetical scenario. An illiterate black woman
lives in a poverty-stricken rural area. She cannot
read, does not know a thing about a supreme
constitution and equality and all the wonderful
rights guaranteed in the Bill of Rights. She lives
the typical life of a
Page 201
black woman in a traditional patriarchal and male-
dominated society, governed by the age-old tribal
customs, culture and rules of an indigenous
people. She is also constantly abused by her often-
drunk husband—both sexually and physically.
During one vicious attack, she kills her husband
(probably in self-defence). Nonetheless, she is
accused of murder, and on a particular day she
appears in court. She cannot read, and does not
understand the strange and frightening
surroundings. And guess who the presiding officer
is? None other than a middle-aged white man.
Whose values and which values will be considered?
Yes, of course, the fundamental values in the
supreme Constitution must be applied. But in the
process the clash of languages, traditions, cultures,
and all the other baggage of all the role-players
will have to be dealt with. The values must be
used, but how that is to be accomplished during
interpretation and application of the law is not as
easy as it may seem.
The question during interpretation is not only who
the ‘others’ are, but also who speaks for the
‘others’. In other words, will weak and
marginalised groups be given the opportunity to
take part in the interpretive discourse? Will they be
heard? Will they be taken seriously? In a diverse
society (such as South Africa), with a history of
oppression, racism, sexism and discrimination, this
issue cannot be ignored. Tully (1995: 34) explains
the problems as follows:
To respond to the strange multiplicity of
culturally diverse voices that have come
forward . . . to demand a hearing . . . it is
necessary to call into question and amend a
number of unexamined conventions . . . that
continue to inform the language of
constitutionalism in which the demands are
taken up and adjudicated.
Bibliography
Abbreviations
LJ Law Journal
LR Law Review
CILSA The Comparative and International
Law Journal of South Africa
SAJHR South African Journal on Human
Rights
SALJ South African Law Journal
SAPR/PL SA Publiekreg/Public Law
SAYIL South African Yearbook of
International Law
Stell LR Stellenbosch Law Review
THRHR Tydskrif vir Hedendaagse Romeins-
Hollandse Reg
TRW Tydskrif vir Regswetenskap
TSAR Tydskrif vir die Suid-Afrikaanse
Reg
Baxter, L Administrative law (Juta 1984)
Botha, CJ Waarde-aktiverende grondwetuitleg:
Vergestalting van die materiële regstaat LLD
thesis UNISA (1996)
Botha, CJ ‘Maatskaplike geregtigheid, die
“animering” van fundamentele grondwetlike
waardes en regterlike aktivisme: ’n nuwe
paradigma vir grondwetuitleg’ in Carpenter (ed)
Suprema lex: essays in honour of Marinus
Wiechers (Butterworths 1998)
Botha, CJ ‘Failed states, fading dreams and a
failing democracy: The critical role of public law
academics’ Inaugural lecture, University of
Pretoria (2007)
Botha, CJ & Bekink, B ‘Aspects of legislative
drafting: Some South African realities (or, plain
language is not always plain sailing)’ (2007)
Statute Law Review 34
Cowen, DV ‘Prolegomenon to a restatement of the
principles of statutory interpretation’ (1976)
TSAR 131
Cowen, DV ‘The interpretation of statutes and the
concept of the intention of the legislature’ (1980)
THRHR 374
Devenish, GE Interpretation of statutes (Juta
1992)
De Ville, JR Constitutional and statutory
interpretation (Interdoc 2000)
Page 206
Table of Cases
A
Administrator, Cape v Raats Rontgen & Vermeulen
(Pty) Ltd 1992 (1) SA 245 (A)
— 139
African and European Investment Co v Warren
1924 AD 360
— 122
Akani Garden Route (Pty) Ltd v Pinnacle Point
Casino (Pty) Ltd 2001 (4) SA 501 (SCA)
— 34
Amalgamated Packaging lndustries v Hutt 1975 (4)
SA 943 (A)
— 178
Association of Amusement & Novelty Machine
Operators v Minister of Justice 1980 (2) SA 636
(A)
— 112
B
Baloro v University of Bophuthatswana 1995 (4)
SA 197 (B)
— 114
Bato Star Fishing (Pty) Ltd v Minister of
Environmental Affairs 2004 (4) SA 490 (CC)
— 101
Bezuidenhout v AA Mutual Insurance Association
Ltd 1978 (1) SA 703 (A)
— 178
Bhyat v Commissioner for Immigration 1932 AD
125
— 93, 118
Bloemfontein Town Council v Richter 1938 AD 195
— 173
Boiler Efficiency Services CC v Coalcor (Cape) (Pty)
Ltd 1989 (3) SA 460 (C)
— 140
Bok v Allen 1884 SAR 137
— 150
Bolnik v Chairman of the Board appointed by the
SA Council of Architects 1982 (2) SA 397 (C)
— 116
Brown v Cape Divisional Council 1979 (1) SA 589
(A)
— 119
Bugler’s Post (Pty) Ltd v Secretary for Inland
Revenue 1974 (3) SA 28 (A)
— 171
Bulawayo Municipality v Bulawayo Waterworks Ltd
1915 CPD 435
— 160
C
Carlis v Oldfield 4 HCG 379
— 170
Carmichele v Minister of Safety and Security 2001
(4) SA 938 (CC)
— 6, 43
Case v Minister of Safety and Security; Curtis v
Minister of Safety and Security 1996 (3) SA 617
(CC)
— 150
Page 210
D
Dadoo Ltd v Krugersdorp Municipal Council 1920
AD 530
— 135, 146
Daniels v Campbell 2004 (5) SA 331 (CC)
— 196
De Beers Industrial Diamond Division (Pty) Ltd v
Ishizuka 1980 (2) SA 191 (T)
— 123
De Reuck v Director of Public Prosecutions,
Witwatersrand Local Division 2003 (3) SA 389
(W)
— 150
De Villiers v Cape Divisional Council 1875 Buch 50
— 92
Dhanabakium v Subramanian 1943 AD 160
— 135
Diepsloot Residents’ and Landowners’ Association v
Administrator, Transvaal 1994 (3) SA 336 (A)
— 132
Dilokong Chrome Mines (Edms) Bpk v Direkteur-
Generaal, Departement van Handel en Nywerheid
1992 (4) SA 1 (A)
— 151
Director of Education, Transvaal v McCagie 1913
AD 616
— 171
Director of Public Prosecutions, Western Cape v
Prins 2012 (2) SACR 183 (SCA)
— 135
Directory Advertising v Minister for Posts and
Telecoms 1996 (3) SA 800 (TPD)
— 131
Drakensberg Administration Board v Town Planning
Appeals Board 1983 (4) SA 42 (N)
— 140
Page 211
Du Plessis v De Klerk 1996 (3) SA 850 (CC)
— 33, 115, 164, 192
Du Plessis v Southern Zululand Rural Licensing
Board 1964 (4) SA 168 (D)
— 116
E
Eland Boerdery (Edms) Bpk v Anderson 1966 (4)
SA 400 (T)
— 179
Engelbrecht v Road Accident Fund 2007 (6) SA 96
(CC)
— 67
Engels v Allied Chemical Manufacturers (Pty) Ltd
1993 (4) SA 45 (Nm)
— 160
Ensor v Rensco Motors (Pty) Ltd 1981 (1) SA 815
(A)
— 93
Entabeni Hospital Ltd v Van der Linde; First
National Bank of SA v Puckriah 1994 (2) SA 422
(N)
— 79
Esselman v Administrateur SWA 1974 (2) SA 597
(SWA)
— 133
Estate Crosby v Wynberg Municipality 1921 CPD
1026
— 73
Euromarine International of Mauren v The Ship
Berg 1986 (2) SA 700 (A)
— 61
Evans v Schoeman 1949 (1) SA 571 (A)
— 139
Ex Parte Attorney-General, Namibia: In re The
Constitutional Relationship between the Attorney-
General and the Prosecutor-General 1995 (8)
BCLR 1070 (NmSC)
— 186
Ex Parte Slater, Walker Securities (SA) Ltd 1974
(4) SA 657 (W)
— 96
Ex Parte the Minister of Justice: In re R v Jacobson
and Levy 1931 AD 466133 Ex parte Minister of
Safety and Security: in re S v Walters 2002 (4)
SA 613 (CC)
— 6, 48
Executive Council Western Cape Legislature v
President of the RSA 1995 (4) SA 877 (CC)
— 29
F
Farrar’s Estate v CIR 1926 TPD 501
— 93
Fedsure Life Assurance Ltd v Greater Johannesburg
Transitional Metropolitan Council 1999 (1) SA
374 (CC)
— 25, 142
Ferreira v Levin 1996 (2) SA 984 (CC)
— 193
Finbro Furnishers (Pty) Ltd v Registrar of Deeds,
Bloemfontein 1985 (4) SA 773 (A)
— 113
Fourie v Minister of Home Affairs 2005 (3) SA 429
(SCA)
— 114
Freedom of Expression Institute v Chair,
Complaints and Compliance Committee
(unreported case 2009/51933) [2011] ZAGPJHC
2 (24 January 2011)
— 29
Fundstrust (Pty) Ltd (in liquidation) v Van
Deventer 1997 (1) SA 710 (A)
— 123
G
Gardner v Lucas (1878) 3 App Cas 582
— 55
Page 212
Garydale Estate and Investment Co (Pty) Ltd v
Johannesburg Western Rent Board 1957 (2) SA
466 (T)
— 72
Geyser v Msunduzi Municipality 2003 (5) SA 19 (N)
— 105
Golden China TV Game Centre v Nintendo Co Ltd
1997 (1) SA 405 (A)
— 114
Goodman Bros (Pty) Ltd v Transnet Ltd 1998 (4)
SA 989 (W)
— 131
Gordon v Standard Merchant Bank 1983 (3) SA 68
(A)
— 78
Gory v Kolver (Starke and Others Intervening)
2007 (4) SA 97 (CC)
— 197
Govender v Minister of Safety and Security 2001
(4) SA 273 (SCA)
— 106
Government of the Republic of South Africa v
Government of Kwazulu 1983 (1) SA 164 (A)
— 79
Green v Fitzgerald 1914 AD 88
— 168
H
Handel v R 1933 SWA 37
— 116
Harksen v President of The RSA 2000 (5) SA 478
(CC)
— 144
Harris v Law Society of the Cape of Good Hope
1917 CPD 449
— 95
Hatch v Koopoomal 1936 AD 197
— 28
Heydon’s Case (1584) 3 Co Rep 7a (76 ER 637)
— 152
Hoffmann v South African Airways 2001 (1) SA 1
(CC)
— 131
Holomisa v Argus Newspapers Ltd 1996 (2) SA 588
(W)
— 100, 144
Hopkinson v Bloemfontein District Creamery 1966
(1) SA 159 (O)
— 151
Hurwitz v SA Mining and General Assurance Co Ltd
1958 (4) SA 136 (W)
— 180
I
Independent Electoral Commission v Langeberg
Municipality 2001 (3) SA 925 (CC)
— 131
Investigating Directorate: Serious Economic
Offences v Hyundai Motor Distributors (Pty) Ltd:
In re Hyundai Motor Distributors (Pty) Ltd v Smit
2001 (1) SA 545 (CC)
— 101, 184
J
Jaffer v Parow Village Management Board 1920
CPD 267
— 116
Jaga v Dönges 1950 (4) SA 653 (A)
— 98, 118, 131
Johannesburg City Council v Arumugan 1961 (3)
SA 748 (W)
— 179
Johannesburg Municipality v Cohen’s Trustees
1909 TS 811
— 78
Page 213
K
Kalla v The Master 1995 (1) SA 261 (T)
— 104
Kanhym Bpk v Oudtshoorn Munisipaliteit 1990 (3)
SA 252 (C)
— 119
Keagile v Attorney-General, Transvaal 1984 (2) SA
916 (T)
— 73
Kent v SA Railways and Harbours 1946 AD 405
— 79
Keyter v Minister of Agriculture 1908 NLR 522
— 112
Khala v Minister of Safety and Security 1994 (4)
SA 218 (W)
— 118, 191
Kleynhans v Yorkshire Insurance Co Ltd 1957 (3)
SA 544 (A)
— 126
Klipriviersoog Properties (Edms) Bpk v
Gemeenskapsontwikkelingsraad 1984 (3) SA 768
(T)
— 167
Kock v Scottburgh Town Council 1957 (1) SA 213
(D)
— 117
Kommissaris van Doeane en Aksyns v Mincer
Motors 1959 (1) SA 114 (A)
— 112
Kruger v President Insurance Co Ltd 1994 (2) SA
495 (D)
— 59
L
Le Roux v Grigg-Spall 1946 AD 244
— 180
Leibrandt v SA Railways 1941 AD 9
— 178
Lek v Estate Agents Board 1978 (3) SA 160 (C)
— 58
M
Maccsand (Pty) Ltd v City of Cape Town, Minister
for Water Affairs and Environment, MEC for Local
Government, Environmental Affairs and
Development Planning, Western Cape Province,
Minister for Rural Development and Land Reform,
and Minister for Mineral Resources 2012 (4) SA
181 (CC)
— 137
Mahomed v Union Government 1911 AD 1
— 73
Makwanyane and Ex parte Minister of Safety and
Security: In re S v Walters 2002 (4) SA 613 (CC)
— 6
Mamogalie v Minister van Naturellesake 1961 (1)
SA 467 (A)
— 136
Matatiele Municipality v President of the RSA 2006
(5) SA 47 (CC)
— 68
Mateis v Ngwathe Plaaslike Munisipaliteit 2003 (4)
SA 361 (SCA)
— 105
Mathiba v Moschke 1920 AD 354
— 150
Matiso v Commanding Officer, Port Elizabeth Prison
1994 (4) SA 592 (SE)
— 94, 163, 183
Page 214
McLoughlin v Turner 1921 RD 537
— 179
MEC for Public Works, Roads and Transport, Free
State v Morning Star Minibus Hiring Services
2003 (4) SA 429 (O)
— 69
Messenger of the Magistrate’s Court, Durban v
Pillay 1952 (3) SA 678 (A)
— 178
Metro Transport (Pty) Ltd v National Transport
Commission 1981 (3) SA 114 (W)
— 124
Middelburg Municipality v Gertzen 1914 AD 544
— 22
Minister of the Interior v Lockhat 1961 (2) SA 587
(A)
— 96
Minister v Land Affairs v Slamdien 1999 (4) BCLR
413 (LCC)
— 109
Minister of Police v Haunawa 1991 (2) SA 542
(Nm)
— 80
Minister van Polisie v De Beer 1970 (2) SA 712 (T)
— 127
Minister of Public Works v Haffejee 1996 (3) SA
745 (A)
— 61
Minister of Water Affairs and Forestry v
Swissborough Diamond Mines (Pty) Ltd 1999 (2)
SA 345 (T)
— 114
Mkontwana v Nelson Mandela Metropolitan
Municipality; Bissett v Buffalo City Municipality;
Transfer Rights Action Campaign v MEC, Local
Government and Housing, Gauteng 2005 (1) SA
530 (CC)
— 149
Morake v Dubedube 1928 TPD 625
— 149
Moseneke v The Master 2001 (2) SA 18 (CC)
— 28
Motorvoertuigassuransiefonds v Gcwabe 1979 (4)
SA 986 (A)
— 178
N
Nasionale Vervoerkommissie van Suid-Afrika v Salz
Gossow Transport (Edms) Bpk 1983 (4) SA 344
(A)
— 129
National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality v
Minister of Home Affairs 2000 (2) SA 1 (CC)
— 195
National Director of Public Prosecutions v Carolus
1999 (2) SACR 607 (SCA)
— 55
National Director of Public Prosecutions v
Seevnarayan 2003 (2) SA 178 (C)
— 118
National Union of Mineworkers of SA v Driveline
Technologies 2002 (4) SA 645 (LAC)
— 152
Ngcobo v Van Rensburg 1999 (2) SA 525 (LCC)
— 150
Ngxuza v Permanent Secretary, Department of
Welfare, Eastern Cape 2001 (2) SA 609 (E)
— 147
Nissan SA (Pty) Ltd v Commissioner for Inland
Revenue 1998 (4) SA 860 (SCA)
— 153
Nkisimane v Santam Insurance Co Ltd 1978 (2) SA
430 (A)
— 177
Page 215
Nortje v Attorney-General, Cape 1995 (2) SA 460
(C)
— 188, 191
Nourse v Van Heerden 1999 (2) SACR 198 (W)
— 74
Nyamakazi v President of Bophuthatswana 1992
(4) SA 540 (BGD)
— 114, 190, 191
O
Orpen v Cilliers 20 SC 264
— 179
P
Pharmaceutical Manufacturers Association of SA;
In re: Ex parte Application of the President of the
Republic of South Africa 2000 (2) SA 674 (CC)
— 28, 43, 49
Pio v Franklin 1949 (3) SA 442 (C)
— 178
Pivot Point SA (Pty) Ltd v Registrar of Companies
1980 (4) SA 74 (T)
— 128
PMB Armature Winders v Pietermaritzburg City
Council 1981 (2) SA 129 (A)
— 171
Premier, Limpopo Province v Speaker of the
Limpopo Provincial Government 2011 (6) SA 396
(CC)
— 24
President of the Republic of South Africa v Hugo
1997 (4) SA 1 (CC)
— 47
Prince v Cape Law Society 2002 (2) SA 794 (CC)
— 192
Principal Immigration Officer v Hawabu 1936 AD
26
— 91
Principal Immigration Officer v Purshotam 1928 AD
435
— 55
Prokureur-Generaal v Van Zyl 1961 (1) SA 729 (C)
— 133
Public Carriers Association v Toll Road
Concessionaries (Pty) Ltd 1990 (1) SA 925 (A)
— 97
Q
Qozeleni v Minister of Law and Order 1994 (3) SA
625 (E)
— 118
Queen v Jizwa 11 SC 337
— 47
R
R v Detody 1926 AD 168
— 63, 168
R v Forlee 1917 TPD 52
— 134
R v Herman 1937 AD 168
— 112
R v Hildick-Smith 1924 TPD 68
— 94
R v Lewinsohn 1922 TPD 336
— 179
R v Magana 1961 (2) SA 654 (T)
— 54
R v Maleka 1929 OPD 171
— 169
R v Maluma 1949 (3) SA 856 (T)
— 72
R v Mazibuko 1958 (4) SA 353 (A)
— 59
R v Njiwa 1957 (2) SA 5 (N)
— 132
Page 216
S
S v A Juvenile 1990 (4) SA 151 (ZSC)
— 191
S v Acheson 1991 (2) SA 805 (NmHc)
— 143
S v Adams 1979 (4) SA 793 (T)
— 96
S v De Bruin 1975 (3) SA 56 (T)
— 139, 140
S v Dodo 2001 (3) SA 382 (CC)
— 134
S v Dzukuda; S v Tilly; S v Tshilo 2000 (3) SA 229
(W)
— 151
S v F 1999 (1) SACR 571 (C)
— 145
S v Huyser 1968 (3) SA 490 (GW)
— 140
S v Kohler 1979 (1) SA 861 (T)
— 172
S v Koopman 1991 (1) SA 474 (NC)
— 70
S v Labuschagne 1979 (3) SA 1320 (T)
— 140
S v Makhubela 1981 (4) SA 210 (B)
— 123
S v Makwanyane 1995 (3) SA 391 (CC)
— 3, 6, 67, 94, 102, 143, 148, 186, 190, 192,
194-195
S v Mhlungu 1995 (3) SA 867 (CC)
— 55, 148, 198
S v Mujee 1981 (3) SA 800 (Z)
— 169
S v Ndiki 2008 (2) SACR 252 (Ck)
— 60
S v Reed 1972 (2) SA 34 (RA)
— 140
S v Staggie 2003 (1) SACR 232 (C)
— 147
S v Taekendesa 1972 (4) SA 72 (RAD)
— 178
S v Yolelo 1981 (1) SA 1002 (A)
— 133
S v Zuma 1995 (2) SA 642 (CC)
— 154, 192
SA Medical Council v Maytham 1931 TPD 45
— 133
Samuel Thomas Myers v Pretorius & Etc 1944 OPD
144
— 178
Santam Insurance Ltd v Taylor 1985 (1) SA 514
(A)
— 9, 152
Sappi Fine Papers (Pty) Ltd v ICI Canada Inc 1992
(3) SA 306 (A)
— 80
Secretary for Inland Revenue v Somers Vine 1968
(2) SA 138 (A)
— 113
Page 217
Sekretaris van Binnelandse Inkomste v Lourens
Erasmus (Edms) Bpk 1966 (4) SA 434 (A)
— 135
Sentrale Kunsmis Korporasie (Edms) Bpk v NKP
Kunsmisverspreiders (Edms) Bpk 1970 (3) SA
367 (A)
— 177
Shabalala v Attorney-General, Transvaal 1996 (1)
SA 725 (CC)
— 190
Shackleton Credit Management (Pty) Ltd v Scholtz
(unreported case 12611/2010, Western Cape
High Court)
— 106
Shoprite Checkers (Pty) Ltd v Ramdaw 2001 (3)
SA 68 (LC)
— 152
Shozi v Minister of Justice, Kwazulu 1992 (2) SA
338 (N)
— 79
Sidumo v Rustenburg Platinum Mines Ltd 2008 (2)
SA 24 (CC)
— 143
Sigcau v Sigcau 1941 CPD 334
— 112
Skinner v Palmer 1919 WLD 39
— 167
Skipper International v SA Textile and Allied
Workers’ Union 1989 (2) SA 612 (W)
— 133
Skotnes v South African Library 1997 (2) SA 770
(SCA)
— 170
Solicitor-General v Malgas 1918 AD 489
— 75
Soobramoney v Minister of Health, Kwazulu-Natal
1998 (1) SA 765 (CC)
— 6
South African Transport Services v Olgar 1986 (2)
SA 684 (A)
— 133
Standard Bank v Estate van Rhyn 1925 AD 266
— 179
Stellenbosch Farmers’ Wineries v Distillers
Corporation (SA) Ltd 1962 (1) SA 458 (A)
— 132
Sutter v Scheepers 1932 AD 165
— 178
Swanepoel v Johannesburg City Council 1994 (3)
SA 789 (A)
— 93
T
Transnet Ltd v Chairman National Transport
Commission 1999 (4) SA 1 (SCA)
— 55
Transnet Ltd v Ngcezulu 1995 (3) SA 538 (A)
— 55, 72
Transvaal Consolidated Land and Exploration Co
Ltd v Johanneshurg City Council 1972 (1) SA 88
(W)
— 123
Trivett & Co (Pty) Ltd v W M Brandt’s Sons & Co
1975 (3) SA 423 (A)
— 167
Turffontein Estates v Mining Commissioner
Johannesburg 1917 AD 419
— 121
U
Union Government v Mack 1917 AD 731
— 93, 111
Union Government v Tonkin 1918 AD 533
— 139
Page 218
V
Van Rooyen v The State 2001 (4) SA 396 (T)
— 131
Veldman v Director of Public Prosecutions,
Witwatersrand Local Division 2007 (3) SA 210
(CC)
— 55
Venter v R 1907 TS 910
— 91
Volschenk v Volschenk 1946 TPD 486
— 112
W
Weenen Transitional Council v Van Dyk 2002 (4)
SA 653 (SCA)
— 176
Wendywood Development (Pty) Ltd v Rieger 1971
(3) SA 28 (A)
— 79
Western Cape Provincial Government: In re DVB
Behuising (Pty) Ltd 2001 (1) SA 500 (CC)
— 150
Westinghouse Brake and Equipment (Pty) Ltd v
Bilger Engineering (Pty) Ltd 1986 (2) SA 555 (A)
— 151
Winckler v Minister of Correctional Services 2001
(2) SA 747 (C)
— 147
Y
Ynuico Ltd v Minister of Trade and Industry 1996
(3) SA 989 (CC)
— 30
Z
Zantsi v Council of State, Ciskei 1995 (4) SA 615
(CC)
— 25
Zimnat Insurance Co Ltd v Chawanda 1991 (2) SA
825 (ZSC)
— 162
Zulu v Van Rensburg 1996 (4) SA 1236 (LC)
— 116
Page 219
Index
A
abuse of power — 139, 164
accessibility of law — 46-47
act — 3
Acts of Parliament — 3, 22-23
administrative quasi-legislation — 34
adoption of legislation — 45
amendments to legislation
clause in legislation about — 39
formal by competent legislature — 65
list of and structure of legislation — 35
non-textual (indirect) — 65
number of Acts at same time — 65
original legislation — 64
specific Act — 65
subordinate legislation — 64-65
textual (direct) — 65
to suspend legislation — 77
who may make — 63-65
analogy, interpretation by — 174
apartheid — 4, 13, 203
approaches to interpretation
influence of Constitution (see also ‘constitutional
interpretation’) — 99-105
practical and inclusive method — 105-110
text-based approach — 91-97
text-in-context approach — 97-99, 132, 160-
161
C
case law — 4, 34
casus omissus rule — 95, 134, 136
cessante ratione legis, cessat et ipsa lex (see
‘restrictive interpretation’)
changes to legislation
formal amendments by legislature — 39, 65
modification of meaning by courts — 65-66,
161-162
circulars — 153-154
codifications — 3
Page 220
commencement of legislation (see also
‘promulgation of legislation’)
application of Act and — 54
combination of options — 51-52
delayed on specified future date — 49-50
delayed on unspecified future date — 49-50
general — 39-40, 45-62
on date of publication — 49
retroactive — 50-51, 57
subordinate legislation — 53-54
commission reports — 151
common law
computation of time — 127-128
Constitution and — 43-44
legislation and — 3-4, 33, 43-44
presumptions of interpretation (see
‘presumptions’)
comparative dimension of interpretation (see also
‘practical and inclusive method of interpretation’)
constitutional interpretation and — 194-195
foreign law — 154
general — 108-109
public international law — 155-156
computatio civilis (see ‘computation of time’)
computatio extraordinaria (see ‘computation of
time’)
computatio naturalis (see ‘computation of time’)
computation of time
common-law method — 127-128
computatio civilis — 127-128
computatio extraordinaria — 128
computatio naturalis — 128
day — 52, 125, 126-127
month — 125
statutory method — 126-127
week — 125
year — 125
concretisation
law making function of courts — 160-165
modification of meaning — 166-174
no problems with — 166
possibilities during — 165-174
text-based approach — 160
text-in-context approach — 160-161
conflicting legislation — 136-138
Page 221
Constitution
application clause — 14
Bill of Rights — 6-7, 13, 23, 33, 43-44, 59, 67-
68, 74, 96, 101-104, 114, 117, 130-131, 137,
141-142, 145, 154-155, 165, 180, 186, 188-
189, 197-200, 203-204
category of legislation — 21
citation — 21
common law development and — 43-44
founding provision — 14, 99-100
framework of and interpretation — 6-7
guidelines — 189-192
how to interpret — 188-195
influence of — 99-105
interpretation clause — 14, 100-102
law making powers derived from — 22
limitation clause — 14, 33
obligation clause — 14
old order legislation, definition — 18, 29
retro-effect of legislation and rights — 59-60
retroactivity and — 61-62
supremacy clause (see also ‘supreme
Constitution’) — 14, 99-100
symbolism — 187-188
teleological interpretation — 143-148
constitutional interpretation
challenges — 197-204
comparative interpretation — 194-195
comprehensive and inclusive methodology —
192-195
constitutional symbolism — 187-188
constitutional values — 199-201
counter-majoritarian difficulty — 198-199
grammatical interpretation — 192-193
historical interpretation — 194
how to interpret — 188-195
limitations of corrective interpretation — 195-
196
ordinary statutory interpretation and — 183-
184
rights culture — 201-203
social justice — 203-204
substantive constitutionalism — 186-187
supreme Constitution and ordinary legislation —
184
systematic interpretation — 193
teleological interpretation — 193-194
constitutional order — 12-14
Page 222
constitutional review
amendments to legislation — 66
conflicting legislation — 136
limits of corrective interpretation — 195-196
reading-down — 165, 196
reading-in — 197
reading-up — 196
severance — 197
unconstitutionality — 67-69, 195-197
constitutional state — 52, 103-104, 142, 186-
187, 198-204
constitutional values — 102-103, 143-148, 199-
201
constitutionalism — 19
formal — 185-186
impact of — 103-105
substantive — 186-187
contemporanea expositio — 152
context (see also ‘contextual interpretation’;
‘holistic dimension of interpretation’; ‘text-in-
context approach’)
balance between text and — 131-132
of legislation — 7
contextual and structural dimension (see ‘holistic
dimension of interpretation’)
contextual interpretation
Constitution and — 193
deconstruction — 86-87
co-operative government
conflicting legislation — 136
suspension of legislation — 77
corrective interpretation — 95, 106, 162-163,
167, 195-196
counter-majoritarian difficulty — 198-199
courts
corrective interpretation — 162-163
invalidation of legislation by — 67-69
law making function (see ‘judicial law-making’;
‘modification of the meaning’)
role of in text-in-context approach — 98-99
to determine purpose of legislation — 133-136
Critical Legal Studies Movement (CLS) — 88-89
D
day (see ‘computation of time’)
debates during legislative process — 150-151
deconstruction — 89-90
deeming clause — 57
Page 223
definitions
as external language aids — 124
disaster — 9
intra-textual aids — 119-120
law — 16
national legislation — 16-17
old order legislation — 18, 29
provincial legislation — 17
structure of legislation and — 38, 119-120
delegated legislation (see ‘subordinate legislation’)
democratic values — 102, 164
dictionaries — 123-124
directory provisions
general — 175-177
guidelines — 177-180
jurisprudential guidelines — 178-179
presumptions — 179-180
semantic guidelines — 177-178
E
eiusdem generis (see ‘restrictive interpretation’)
enacted law-text, meaning — 15, 33
enacting provision — 37
examples and footnotes (see ‘extra-textual aids’)
explanatory memoranda — 152
explanatory notes — 41, 153-154
extensive interpretation
by analogy — 174
by implication — 173-174
general — 172
extra-textual aids
circulars — 153-154
commission reports — 7, 151
contemporanea expositio — 152
debates during legislative process — 150-151
definitions in Constitution — 124
definitions in other legislation — 124
dictionaries and linguistic evidence — 7, 123-
124
examples and footnotes — 124
explanatory memoranda and notes — 152, 153-
154
foreign law — 154
international law — 155-156
interpretation notes — 153-154
mischief rule — 152
preamble to the Constitution — 148-149
preceding discussions — 150-151
Page 224
prior legislation — 149-150
subsecuta observatio — 153-154
extra-textual context — 128-129
F
footnotes, as external language aids — 124
foreign law — 154
formalism — 86-87
G
gazettes — 46-47
generalia specialibus non derogant — 80
geographical areas
application of old order legislation in new — 29-
33
government bodies, presumption that not bound
by own legislation — 138-142
government gazettes (see ‘gazettes’)
grammatical interpretation — 192-193
Green Papers — 34
H
headings to chapters and sections — 121-122
hermeneutics — 83-86
hierarchical categories of legislation
Constitution — 21
original — 21-25
subordinate legislation — 25-29
historical dimension of interpretation (see also
‘practical and inclusive method of interpretation’)
— 108, 148-154, 194
holistic dimension of interpretation (see also
‘practical and inclusive method of interpretation’)
balance between text and context — 131-132
conflicting legislation — 133-138
constitutional interpretation — 193
extra-textual context — 128-129
intra-textual context — 128
legislation to be studied as a whole — 128-131
organ of state — 130-131
presumption that government bodies not bound
by own legislation — 138-142
presumption that legislation not containing futile
or nugatory provisions — 133-136
structure of legislation — 132-133
homelands (see ‘self-governing territories’)
Page 225
I
implication, interpretation by — 174
independent homelands — 20, 24-25
indigenous law — 3-4, 33
institutional statutes — 27
intention of legislature — 11-12, 90-95, 97-98,
105, 114, 116, 133, 147, 150, 160, 162, 170-
171, 177-178, 190
intention theory (see ‘intention of legislature’)
interim Constitution — 12-13, 17-20, 29-30, 33,
62, 74, 94, 99, 105, 165, 186, 189, 193, 196
internal department memos — 34
internal language aids (see ‘intra-textual aids’)
international law — 108-109, 155-156, 189, 194
Interpretation Act 33 of 1957 — 15-17, 46-47,
49, 50-54, 64, 70-74, 100, 124-127, 139
interpretation clauses
Constitution — 100-102
legislation — 38
interpretation guidelines, as language aid — 120-
121
interpretation notes — 153-154
interrelated dimensions of interpretation
comparative dimension — 154-156
historical dimension — 148-154
holistic dimension — 128-142
language dimension — 111-128
value-laden (teleological) dimension — 142-148
intra-textual aids
definition clause — 119-120
express purpose clause — 120-121
headings to chapters and sections — 121-122
interpretation guidelines — 120-121
legislative text in other official languages —
115-118
long title — 118
paragraphs and punctuation — 132-133
preamble — 118
schedules — 122
intra-textual context — 128
intra vires — 136
invalidation of legislation
by courts — 67-69
meaning — 67
subordinate legislation — 68-69
unconstitutional provisions — 67-68, 195-197
Page 226
iudicis est ius dicere sed non dare — 95, 143, 160
J
judicial discretion of courts — 66, 85, 161-162,
188
judicial law-making
factors supporting and limiting — 163-165
judicial discretion — 161-162
modification of meaning — 65-66, 162-163
modification of the language — 162
text-based approach — 160
text-in-context approach — 160-161
judiciary, independence of — 165
L
language aids (see ‘extra-textual aids’; ‘intra-
textual aids’)
language dimension of interpretation (see also
‘practical and inclusive method of interpretation’)
basic principles — 111-115
constitutional dynamic — 114-115
continuing time-frame of legislation — 113-115
every word is important — 112-113
initial meaning of text — 111-112
internal language aids — 115-122
no addition or subtraction — 113
ordinary meaning of text — 111-112
overlapping and repetition — 112-113
law
definition — 16
forms of — 3
meaning — 3
law of general application (see ‘Constitution:
limitation clause’)
law-making powers (see also ‘judicial law-
making’) — 22
legal hermeneutics — 85
legal positivism — 88, 92, 94
legalese — 8-10
legality principle — 103, 134-135, 142, 147, 164,
185
legislation
Acts — 22-23
adoption — 45
amendments — 35, 39, 63-66, 77
assent — 45
categories — 3, 15, 17-33
changes to (see ‘amendments to legislation’)
commencement — 7, 39-40, 45-62
Page 227
M
ministerial powers — 39
mischief rule — 97, 152
modern critical theories — 86-91
modification of the meaning
changes to legislation — 65-66
constitutional review — 66
law making function of courts — 161-162
restrictive interpretation — 167-172
when necessary — 166-174
when not possible — 174
modificative interpretation by courts (see
‘modification of the meaning’)
month (see ‘computation of time’)
municipal by-laws — 17, 25
N
national legislation
definition — 16-17
subordinate legislation in terms of — 27
noscitur a sociis — 170
notice, meaning — 15
nulla poena sine lege rule — 134
numbering in legislation — 40-41
O
offences, new and retro-effect of legislation — 59
official languages
subordinate legislation — 116-118
text in other — 115-118
old order legislation
application in new order — 29-33
before 1806 — 18
between 1910-1994 — 20
Constitution and — 18, 29 —
new provincial boundaries — 29-33
Page 229
R
reading-down — 165, 196
reading-in — 197
reading-up — 196
reburial of bodies — 31-32
Rechtsstaat (see ‘constitutional state’)
regulations
list of and structure of legislation — 35, 39
subordinate legislation — 27
when furnished to Parliament — 47
repeal of legislation
clause in legislation — 39
effect on pending cases — 71-75
implied — 76
implied powers — 64-65
legislation incorporated by reference — 75
meaning — 67
numbering of repealed provisions — 41
Page 231
original legislation — 64
re-enacted provisions — 71
repeal (deletion) — 71-76
subordinate legislation — 64-65
substitution (repeal and replace) — 69-71
sunset clauses — 76
transitional arrangements — 72
who may — 63-65
restrictive interpretation
cessante ratione legis, cessat et ipsa lex — 77,
168-170
eiusdem generis — 170-172
general — 167-168
retroactivity (see ‘retro-effect’)
retro-effect
common law presumption of future
application — 58-59
Constitution and — 61-62
constitutional rights and — 59-60
deeming clause — 57
higher penalties — 59
new offences — 59
retroactivity — 55-57
retrospectivity — 55-57
state of emergency — 60
what prevents legislation from applying with —
58-61
when enactment deals with procedure — 61
when favouring individual — 61-62
retrospectivity (see ‘retro-effect’)
rights culture — 201-203
rule of law — 164
rules of courts — 27
S
schedules — 40, 122
secondary legislation (see ‘subordinate legislation’)
self-governing territories — 20, 24
separation of powers — 25, 66, 92, 95, 103, 113,
164, 185, 198
severance — 197
short title — 39-40
signed version of legislation — 115-118
signing of legislation — 45, 115
social justice — 203-204
sovereignty of parliament — 11-13, 92, 94, 102,
145, 163, 165, 187, 189
statute law (see ‘legislation’)
structuralism — 88
Page 232
subordinate legislation — 17, 25-29
amendments — 64-65
commencement of legislation — 53-54
conflict with original legislation — 28
conflicting language versions — 116-118
constitutionality of original legislation and — 28-
29
declaration of state of national defence — 27
in terms of national legislation — 27
institutional statutes — 27
interpretation of enabling Act and — 29
invalidation of legislation — 68-69
legislative administrative acts — 27
powers of delegated legislative body — 29
presumption that legislation not containing futile
or nugatory provisions — 136
provincial proclamations and regulations — 28-
29
purpose of — 25-27
regulations — 27
repeal — 64-65
rules of courts — 27
scope — 27
separation of powers — 25
tabling in parliament — 47
subsecuta observatio — 153-154
substantive constitutionalism — 186-187
substantive interpretation — 143-148
substitution of legislation — 69-70
sunset clause — 76
supreme Constitution — 12-14, 19, 21, 22-23,
99-100, 103-105, 163, 165, 184-188
surrounding circumstances (see also ‘contextual
interpretation’; ‘mischief rule’) — 7, 58, 109,
132, 139
suspension of legislation — 77-78
by amendment — 77
cessante ratione legis, cessat et ipsa lex — 77
co-operative government and — 77
systematic interpretation (see ‘holistic dimension
of interpretation’)
T
TBVC states (see ‘independent homelands’)
teleological dimension of interpretation — 143-
148
teleological interpretation — 108, 193-194
text, balance between context and — 131-132
Page 233
text-based approach — 91-97
criticism of existing legal order — 94-96
examples — 92, 96-97
holistic dimension — 132
intention of legislature — 92-94
introduction into South African system — 92
judicial law-making — 94
law making function of courts — 160
legal positivism — 92, 94
pre-dominance of the word — 92
secondary aids — 91
separation of powers — 92
sovereignty of parliament — 92, 94
tertiary aids — 91
text in another official language — 115-118
text-in-context approach — 132
approaches to interpretation — 97-99
law making function of courts — 160-161
mischief rule — 97
role of the court — 98-99
theories of interpretation (see ‘approaches to
interpretation’)
time (see ‘computation of time’)
transitional arrangements
repeal of legislation and — 72
substitution of legislation — 69-70
trias politica doctrine (see ‘separation of powers’)
U
ubuntu — 148
ultra vires — 28, 68, 136
V
validity of legislation — 7
value-coherent theory — 13, 108, 193
value-laden dimension of interpretation (see
‘teleological dimension of interpretation’)
value-laden interpretation (see ‘teleological
interpretation’)
W
week (see ‘computation of time’)
White Papers — 34
words
colloquial speech — 112
definitions — 114, 119-120
dictionaries — 123-124
initial meaning of text — 111-112
Page 234
Y
year (see ‘computation of time’)
Page a33y1957
as amended by
Interpretation Amendment Act 7 of 1959
Interpretation Amendment Act 45 of 1961
General Law Amendment Act 102 of 1967
General Law Amendment Act 62 of 1973
Interpretation Amendment Act 42 of 1977
Criminal Procedure Act 51 of 1977
Republic of South Africa Constitution Second
Amendment Act 101 of 1981
Republic of South Africa Constitution Act 110 of
1983
Provincial Government Act 69 of 1986
General Law Third Amendment Act 129 of 1993
Constitution Consequential Amendments Act 201 of
1993
also amended by
Magistrates' Courts Amendment Act 120 of 1993
[with effect from a date to be proclaimed -
see PENDLEX]
ACT
To consolidate the laws relating to the
interpretation and the shortening of the
language of statutes.
Part I
General (ss 1-17)
1 Application of Act
The provisions of this Act shall apply to the
interpretation of every law (as in this Act defined)
in force, at or after the commencement of this Act
in the Republic or in any portion thereof, and to
the interpretation of all by-laws, rules, regulations
or orders made under the authority of any such
law, unless there is something in the language or
context of the law, by-law, rule, regulation or order
repugnant to such provisions or unless the
contrary intention appears therein.
[S. 1 amended by s. 1 of Act 45 of 1961.]
2 Definitions
The following words and expressions shall, unless
the context otherwise requires or unless in the
case of any law it is otherwise provided therein,
have the meanings hereby assigned to them
respectively, namely-
'administrator' . . . . . .
[Definition of 'administrator', previously
definition of 'Administrator', amended by s.
2 (a) of Act 45 of 1961, substituted by s. 22
(a) of Act 69 of 1986 and deleted by s. 4 (a)
of Act 201 of 1993.]
'Christian name' means any name prefixed to
the surname, whether received at Christian
baptism or not;
'district' means the area subject to the
jurisdiction of the court of any magistrate;
[NB: The definition of 'district' has been
substituted by s. 74 of the Magistrates'
Courts Amendment Act 120 of 1993, a
provision which will be put into operation by
proclamation. See PENDLEX.]
'Gazette'-
(a)
in the case of laws, proclamations, regulations,
notices or other documents published prior to
the thirty-first day of May, 1910, and required
under a law in force prior to that day to be
published in the Gazette, means the
Government Gazette of the Colony wherein
that law was in force; and
(b)
in the case of laws, proclamations, regulations,
notices or other documents published after the
thirty-first day of May, 1010, and required
under any law to be published in the Gazette,
means the Government Gazette of the Republic
or, if the matter is one entrusted to a provincial
council under the Republic of South Africa
Constitution Act 1961, means the Official
Gazette of the province concerned;
(c)
in the case of laws, proclamations, regulations,
notices or other documents published after the
date of commencement of the Constitution and
required under any law to be published in the
Gazette or the Provincial Gazette or any other
official Gazette, means the Government
Gazette of the Republic or the relevant
Provincial Gazette, according to whether the
administration of the law concerned or, as the
case may be, the law conferring the power to
make or issue such a proclamation, regulation,
notice or other document, vests in, or in a
functionary of, the national government or a
provincial government;
[Para. (c) added by s. 4 (b) of Act 201 of
1993.]
[Definition of 'Gazette' amended by s. 2 (b)
of Act 45 of 1961.]
'Governor-General' means the State
President as defined in this section;
[Definition of 'Governor-General' amended
by s. 2 (c) of Act 45 of 1961 and substituted
by s. 4 (c) of Act 201 of 1993.]
'law' means any law, proclamation, ordinance,
Act of Parliament or other enactment having the
force of law;
'month' means a calendar month;
'oath' and 'affidavit', in the case of persons
allowed by law to affirm or declare instead of
swearing, include affirmation and declaration,
and 'swear'; in such case, includes 'affirm' and
'declare';
'Parliament' means the Parliament of the
Republic;
[Definition of 'Parliament' amended by s. 2
(d) of Act 45 of 1961.]
'person' includes-
(a)
any divisional council, municipal council, village
management board, or like authority;
(b)
any company incorporated or registered as
such under any law;
(c)
any body of persons corporate or
unincorporate;
'Premier', with reference to a province, means
the Premier of that province, including any acting
Premier, acting in terms of the Constitution;
[Definition of 'Premier' inserted by s. 4 (d)
of Act 201 of 1993.]
'President' means the President of the
Republic, including any acting President, acting in
terms of the Constitution;
[Definition of 'President' inserted by s. 4 (d)
of Act 201 of 1993.]
'province'-
(a)
in the case of a law referred to in section 229
of the Constitution, means a province of the
Republic as it existed immediately before the
commencement of the Constitution;
(b)
in the case of a law passed or made after the
commencement of the Constitution, or passed
or made before such commencement, but with
reference to the Constitution, means a province
of the Republic referred to in section 124 (1) of
the Constitution;
[Definition of 'province' amended by s. 2 (e)
of Act 45 of 1961 and substituted by s. 4 (e)
of Act 201 of 1993.]
'provincial council' . . . . . .
[Definition of 'provincial council' amended by
s. 2 (f) of Act 45 of 1961 and deleted by s. 4
(f) of Act 201 of 1993.]
'State President' means, subject to section
232 (1) (c) of the Constitution, the President or
the Premier of a province;
[Definition of 'State President' inserted by s.
2 (g) of Act 45 of 1961 and substituted by s.
4 (g) of Act 201 of 1993.]
'the Constitution' means the Constitution of
the Republic of South Africa, 1993;
[Definition of 'the Constitution' inserted by
s. 4 (h) of Act 201 of 1993.]
'the Republic' means, subject to section 232
(1) (a) of the Constitution, the territorial limits of
the Republic of South Africa referred to in
section 1 of the Constitution;
[Definition of 'the Republic' inserted by s. 2
(h) of Act 45 of 1961 and substituted by s. 4
(i) of Act 201 of 1993.]
'the Union' means the Republic.
[Definition of 'the Union' amended by s. 2 (i)
of Act 45 of 1961.]
3 Interpretation of expressions relating to
writing
In every law expressions relating to writing shall,
unless the contrary intention appears, be
construed as including also references to
typewriting, lithography, photography and all other
modes of representing or reproducing words in
visible form.
4 Reckoning of number of days
When any particular number of days is prescribed
for the doing of any act, or for any other purpose,
the same shall be reckoned exclusively of the first
and inclusively of the last day, unless the last day
happens to fall on a Sunday or on any public
holiday, in which case the time shall be reckoned
exclusively of the first day and exclusively also of
every such Sunday or public holiday.
5 Measurement of distance
In the measurement of any distance for the
purpose of any law, that distance shall, unless the
contrary intention appears, be measured in a
straight line on a horizontal plane.
6 Gender and number
In every law, unless the contrary intention
appears-
(a)
words importing the masculine gender include
females; and
(b)
words in the singular number include the
plural, and words in the plural number include
the singular.
7 Meaning of service by post
Where any law authorizes or requires any
document to be served by post, whether the
expression 'serve', or 'give', or 'send', or any other
expression is used, then, unless the contrary
intention appears, the service shall be deemed to
be effected by properly addressing, prepaying, and
posting a registered letter containing the
document, and, unless the contrary is proved, to
have been effected at the time at which the letter
would be delivered in the ordinary course of post.
(a)
any reference in that law or provision to a
department, including any division of any
department or administration, administered by
such firstmentioned Minister, member of the
Executive Council or authority shall be
construed as a reference to the department
administered by such lastmentioned Minister,
member of the Executive Council or authority;
[Para. (a) substituted by s. 5 (b) of Act 201
of 1993.]
(b)
any reference in that law or provision to an
officer in the public service attached to such
firstmentioned department or to any such
officer holding a specified office in that
department, shall be construed as a reference
to an officer in the public service attached to
such lastmentioned department or, as the case
may be, as a reference to such an officer
holding a corresponding office in that
department;
(c)
any power, duty or function vested in or
imposed upon or entrusted to-
(i)
an officer of such firstmentioned department
who is then an officer of such lastmentioned
department; or
(ii)
the holder of a specified office in that
department,
by or under that law or provision, shall be
deemed to have been duly vested in or
imposed upon or entrusted to the officer
concerned in his capacity as an officer of
such lastmentioned department or, as the
case may be, to the holder of a
corresponding office in that department;
(d)
any regulation made or any notice, direction or
order issued or any appointment made or any
action taken under that law or provision prior
to the date on which the administration thereof
was so assigned, shall remain in full force and
effect as if it had been made, issued or taken
by the person who on that date was, by virtue
of the assignment of the administration of that
law or provision or the provisions of this
subsection, competent to make such regulation
or to issue such notice, direction or order or to
make such appointment or to take such action.
[Sub-s. (5) added by s. 1 of Act 7 of 1959
and amended by s. 4 of Act 45 of 1961, by
s. 8 (b) of Act 101 of 1981, by s. 101 (1) of
Act 110 of 1983 and by s. 5 (a) of Act 201
of 1993.]
(5A) The provisions of subsection (5) shall apply
in so far as the President or the Premier of a
province does not determine otherwise in the
assignment concerned and, if the administration of
any law or a provision of any law has been
assigned to any other Minister, member of the
Executive Council of a province or authority as
contemplated in that subsection, but in relation to
a matter specified in the assignment, the
provisions of that subsection shall apply
accordingly.
[Sub-s. (5A) inserted by s. 8 (c) of Act 101
of 1981 and substituted by s. 101 (1) of Act
110 of 1983 and by s. 5 (c) of Act 201 of
1993.]
(5B) . . . . . .
[Sub-s. (5B) inserted by s. 101 (1) of Act
110 of 1983 and deleted by s. 5 (d) of Act
201 of 1993.]
(6) Where any provision in any law confers a
power or imposes a duty or entrusts a function to
any Minister of State or other authority and
authorizes such Minister of State or authority to
delegate the exercise or performance of such
power, duty or function to the holder of an office
as such or to any particular person, and if the
exercise or performance of such power, duty or
function is delegated to the holder of any office,
that power, duty or function may or shall, unless
the contrary intention appears, be exercised or
performed by the holder for the time being of the
office or by the person lawfully acting in the
capacity of such holder.
[Sub-s. (6) added by s. 1 of Act 42 of
1977.]
11 Repeal and substitution
When a law repeals wholly or partially any former
law and substitutes provisions for the law so
repealed, the repealed law shall remain in force
until the substituted provisions come into
operation.
(a)
revive anything not in force or existing at the
time at which the repeal takes effect; or
(b)
affect the previous operation of any law so
repealed or anything duly done or suffered
under the law so repealed; or
(c)
affect any right, privilege, obligation or liability
acquired, accrued or incurred under any law so
repealed; or
(d)
affect any penalty, forfeiture or punishment
incurred in respect of any offence committed
against any law so repealed; or
(e)
affect any investigation, legal proceeding or
remedy in respect of any such right, privilege,
obligation, liability, forfeiture or punishment as
is in this subsection mentioned,
and any such investigation, legal proceeding or
remedy may be instituted, continued or enforced,
and any such penalty, forfeiture or punishment
may be imposed, as if the repealing law had not
been passed.
13 Commencement of laws
(1) The expression 'commencement' when used
in any law and with reference thereto, means the
day on which that law comes or came into
operation, and that day shall, subject to the
provisions of subsection (2) and unless some other
day is fixed by or under the law for the coming into
operation thereof, be the day when the law was
first published in the Gazette as a law.
(2) Where any law, or any order, warrant,
scheme, letters patent, rules, regulations or by-
laws made, granted or issued under the authority
of a law, is expressed to come into operation on a
particular day, it shall be construed as coming into
operation immediately on the expiration of the
previous day.
(3) If any Act provides that that Act shall come
into operation on a date fixed by the President or
the Premier of a province by proclamation in the
Gazette, it shall be deemed that different dates
may be so fixed in respect of different provisions of
that Act.
[Sub-s. (3) added by s. 10 of Act 129 of
1993 and amended by s. 6 of Act 201 of
1993.]
(a)
to make any appointment; or
(b)
to make, grant or issue any instrument, order,
warrant, scheme, letters patent, rules,
regulations or by-laws; or
(c)
to give notices; or
(d)
to prescribe forms; or
(e)
to do any other act or thing for the purpose of
the law,
that power may, unless the contrary intention
appears, be exercised at any time after the passing
of the law so far as may be necessary for the
purpose of bringing the law into operation at the
commencement thereof: Provided that any
instrument, order, warrant, scheme, letters patent,
rules, regulations or by-laws made, granted or
issued under such power shall not, unless the
contrary intention appears in the law or the
contrary is necessary for bringing the law into
operation, come into operation until the law comes
into operation.
15 Notification in Gazette of official acts
under authority of law
When any act, matter or thing is by any law
directed or authorized to be done by the President
or the Premier of a province, or by any Minister, or
by any public officer, the notification that such act,
matter or thing has been done may, unless a
specified instrument or method is by that law
prescribed for the notification, be by notice in the
Gazette.
[S. 15 amended by s. 5 of Act 45 of 1961
and by s. 7 of Act 201 of 1993.]
16 Certain enactments to be published in
Gazette
When any by-law, regulation, rule or order is
authorized by any law to be made by the President
or a Minister or by the Premier of a province or a
member of the Executive Council of a province or
by any local authority, public body or person, with
the approval of the President or a Minister, or of
the Premier of a province or a member of the
Executive Council of a province, such by-law,
regulation, rule or order shall, subject to the
provisions relative to the force and effect thereof in
any law, be published in the Gazette.
[S. 16 amended by s. 5 of Act 45 of 1961
and substituted by s. 8 of Act 201 of 1993.]
16A Promulgation and commencement of
laws and publication of certain notices when
publication of the Gazette impracticable
(1) If the President is satisfied that the
publication of the Gazette cannot be effected or is
likely to be seriously delayed as a result of
circumstances beyond the control of the
Government Printer, he may by proclamation
published in the manner directed by him, make
such rules as he may deem fit for the publication,
during any period specified in the proclamation, of
laws or notices required or authorized by law to be
published in the Gazette.
[Sub-s. (1) amended by s. 9 (a) of Act 201
of 1993.]
(2) Any law or notice published in accordance
with any rules so made, shall be deemed to have
been published in the Gazette, and any law so
published shall be deemed to have come into
operation on the day on which it was first so
published as a law, unless some other day is fixed
by or under that law for the commencement
thereof.
(3) The President of a province may at any time
vary or withdraw any proclamation referred to in
subsection (1) by like proclamation.
[Sub-s. (3) amended by s. 9 (a) of Act 201
of 1993.]
(4) Any law or notice published in accordance
with any rule made under subsection (1) shall, if it
is then still in force, be published in the Gazette for
general information as soon as publication of the
Gazette can be effected.
(5) The provisions of subsection (4) shall not
affect the validity of anything done under any rules
made under subsection (1).
(6) The Premier of a province may exercise the
President's powers in terms of this section with
reference to such province.
[Sub-s. (6) added by s. 9 (b) of Act 201 of
1993.]
[S. 16A inserted by s. 13 of Act 102 of
1967.]
Section 2 - definition
'district' means the area subject to the
jurisdiction of a magistrate's court;