Source of Space
Source of Space
net/publication/279707605
CITATIONS READS
13 4,064
1 author:
Aleksander Szwedek
Adam Mickiewicz University
44 PUBLICATIONS 233 CITATIONS
SEE PROFILE
All content following this page was uploaded by Aleksander Szwedek on 04 July 2015.
Aleksander Szwedek
That description is illustrated with examples the first of which comes from 1390:
Gower Conf. III. 107 Astronomie .. makth a man have knowlechinge Of Sterres .. And what betwen
hem is of space.
It seems, however, that from the point of view of the degree of metaphoricity the OED order
should be reversed, as the temporal sense of space seems to be more metaphorical than, let’s call it the
material senses, as the material sense involves implicit reference to material objects existing in that
space.
Regardless of the order in OED, space has two major senses:
1) the material sense,
2) the temporal sense.
and a number of minor, but related senses, for example, personal space, space between letters, etc.
The two senses II.5. and II.6. in the OED description are related in that they both refer to
boundaries and containment. The difference is that distance is the extent between two reference
points, and area within more reference points than two.
To all intents and purposes, space has no material existence, and in the ‘material’ sense is defined
relative to objects – it is a relation between objects existing in it. As we read in Encyclopedia
Britannica, space is “a boundless, three-dimensional extent in which objects and events occur and
have relative position and direction.” and further on: “It appears that there is no quality contained in
our individual primitive sense-experiences that may be designated as spatial. Rather, what is spatial
appears to be a sort of order of the material objects of experience. The concept “material object”
must therefore be available if concepts concerning space are to be possible. It is the logically
primary concept.”
In other words, absurdly as it may sound, if there were no objects, there would be no space, no
extent and distance. Needless to add, the temporal space is not ‘material’ either and would not exist
without changing and moving objects.
The OED placement of the temporal sense of space as the first one indicates that time may be
conceptualized in terms of space. If that is the case, the concept of space is the source domain for the
domain of time as the following examples show.
1382 Wyclif Gen. xxx. 36 He .. putte a space of thre daies weye bitwix hem and his dowtir
husboond.
1300 Cursor M. 6980 Þair faith lasted littel space.
1782 Cowper Gilpin 242 The turnpike gates again Flew open in short space.
1812 Cary Dante, Parad. xxiii. 16 Short space ensued; I was not held .. Long in expectance.
The spatial representation of time is also seen in the use of spatial prepositions with expressions of
time, such as, for example, in or within five minutes, after an hour, to space out somebody’s visits more
and more, etc.
The claim that time is conceptualized in terms of space is also corroborated by Langacker’s (1990)
discussion of the verb ‘go’: “How does this future sense of ‘go’ derive from the original spatial sense?
One might suggest that it constitutes a metaphorical extension from the spatial to the temporal domain:
rather than moving through space in order to initiate the infinitival process, the subject moves through
time. It does seem evident that the notion of path receives a temporal interpretation.” (1990: 330).
All that means that the concept of space is the source domain for time. It seems reasonable then, to
focus first on the conceptualization of space, and see what consequences that analysis might have for
the conceptualization of time
space is an object which one can make, have, give, possess, share; spaces may be spread about:
1606 Shakes. Ant. & Cl. ii. iii. 23 Therefore Make space enough betweene you.
1610 Shakes. Temp. i. ii. 492 Might I but through my prison once a day Behold this Mayd: .. space
enough Haue I in such a prison.
1706 Phillips (ed. Kersey) Vacuum Disseminatum, or Interspersum, i.e. small void Spaces spread
about between the Particles of Bodies.
The room should only hold ten people, but somehow a space is found for Michael.(BNC)
From inside the room it must have looked like he was just hopping off into empty space,… (BNC)
We had very large rooms, a wonderful space, and we were quite successful.(BNC)
The above examples illustrate the material sense of space in that they refer to space among material
objects. The concept of space as an object extends to less material relations such as personal, social,
etc. as in the following examples:
1950 Times 7 Feb. 5/5 In the last election, one company gave space to the Communist Party and the
Commonwealth Party, but the main newsreels adhered to the general agreement that space should
be given only to the main parties.
1980 G. B. Trudeau Tad Overweight, Seriously, I think I know where you’re coming from, and I’d like
to share that space.
1981 Gossip (Holiday Special) 31/3 The reason why I can say that so boldly is because they give me
my space. They let me be me.
1818 Shelley Rosalind 952 And then I sunk in his embrace, Enclosing there a mighty space Of love.
1854 H. Reed Lect. Brit. Poets xv. (1857) 355 The vast spaces of our English poetry.
1977 C. McFadden Serial (1978) iii. 13/2 Leonard had a lot going for him otherwise, and Kate liked
the space he was in.
1850 H. Reed Lect. Eng. Lit. iv. (1855) 140 His human heart had large spaces to hold his fellow-
beings in.
Lots of bustle but just enough space to breathe.(BNC)
…neo-disco tracks and trackers of the Nineties elegantly negotiate a space between nostalgia
and machine futurism. (BNC)
…space for individualist explanation (BNC)
…I'm not left with much empty space in my life.';(BNC
…to create an enlarged European economic space.(BNC).
space is an animate object which can make noise, produce, breed, challenge and permit:
1565 Cooper Thesaurus, Raucus tractus, a long space of the sea makynge an hoarse noyse.
1667 Milton P.L. i. 650 Space may produce new Worlds.
1940 R. S. Lambert Ariel & All his Quality vii. 168 Selling ‘space’ .. breeds a very different
outlook from providing programmes.
1878 Browning La Saisiaz 6 No blue space in its outspread .. challenged my emerging head.
1866 Chambers's Encycl. VIII. 7/2 Various expressive adjectives, .. into the consideration of
which our space will not permit us to enter.
space is a container (which first of all is an object) into which other things can be put, or in which
other things are, it can be deep, and open or closed.
1451 J. Capgrave Life St. Aug. 3 Asia .. conteyneth as mech in space as do þe othir too parties.
1671 Milton P.R. ii. 339 Our Saviour .. beheld In ample space under the broadest shade A Table richly
spred.
1697 Dryden Virg. Georg. iv. 218 But streighten'd in my Space, I must forsake This Task.
1816 Shelley Daemon i. 251 Each [orb] with undeviating aim .. through the depths of space Pursued
its wondrous way.
1873 Helps Anim. & Mast. i. (1875) 6 The pamphlet has vanished into space.
1854 Tomlinson Arago's Astron. 95 Suppose the body A is projected .. into free space.
1885 C. Leudesdorf Cremona's Proj. Geom. 33 In the above the geometric forms are supposed to lie in
space.
1827 Faraday Chem. Manip. vi. (1842) 179 Even the space left open round the neck may be closed
when desirable.
space has object–like properties. It can be small and large, and there may be more or less of it:
1815 J. Smith Panorama Sci. & Art II. 42 The more it is heated, the more space it takes up.
1774 Goldsm. Nat. Hist. (1776) II. 298 With a studied brevity, his system comprehends the greatest
variety, in the smallest space.
1565 Cooper Thesaurus s.v. Spatium, Great and large spaces in wide roomes.
Synonyms of space, such as place, room, and even Prepositional Phrases denoting place display
similar collocation potential.
place
OED explains ‘place’ as “Space; extension (in two or three directions).”. That sense is illustrated
with the following examples of various metaphorical domains.
1628 Hobbes Thucyd. (1822) 85 When they were come in the city had not place for them all. [place as
an object one can have].
She had a special place in his heart.
600 J. Pory tr. Leo's Africa vi. 278 It is an extreme hot and drie place, bringing foorth no corne at all,
but great plenty of dates. [hot and dry are properties of material objects, not of places].
a 1631 Donne Nativitie 10 Seest thou, my Soule, ..how he Which fils all place, yet none holds him,
doth lye? [place is a container].
1655 Stanley Hist. Philos. i. (1701) 7/2 That the World is contained in place. This agrees with the
definition of place by space. [place is a container].
?_1366 Chaucer Rom. Rose 657 In many places were nightingales, Alpes, finches, and wodewales.
[place is a container].
1613 Purchas Pilgrimage vi. xiii. 534 Not staying aboue three or foure dayes in a place, as long as the
grasse will serue their Camels. [place is a container].
1897 Westm. Gaz. 13 Mar. 5/1 The Act expressly declared such betting in any place, [place is a
container].
room
Room is defined in OED as “Space; dimensional extent.” and illustrated by the following examples:
1757 Gray Bard 51 Give ample room, and verge enough The characters of hell to trace. [room as an
object that one can give]
1833 H. Martineau Loom & Lugger ii. i. 18 We must teach him .. that there is room in the wide world
for all. [room as an object that exists in the world].
1840 Penny Cycl. XVII. 345/1 The plants .. would then have room to grow out. [room as an object that
one can have].
1830 Wordsw. Let. to Dyce, In the edition of 1827 it was diligently revised, and the sense in several
instances got into less room. [room is a container].
prepositional phrases
Rather unexpectedly, prepositional phrases denoting space have received a similar, cognitive
interpretation consistent with the analysis of examples presented above. In his 1993 paper, Langacker
discusses the phrase “under the bed (is all dusty)” in the following words:
“The search domain is defined as the region to which a locative expression confines its
trajector [...]. Observe that a phrase like ‘under the bed (is all dusty)’ is construed as naming
a spatial region - a type of ‘thing’ [emphasis A.S.] - rather than a relationship (a
relationship per se can hardly be dusty). Our ability to conceptually reify and refer to the
search domain argues strongly for the psychological validity of this notion.” (Langacker
1993:16).
Langacker’s words leave no doubt that spatial region (space) is conceptualized as „a type of
thing”. Describing that example in terms of reification, Langacker narrowed his interpretation to
inanimate things. My earlier examples show that space can also be conceptualized in terms of
animate beings, and that is why I prefer to use a more general space is an object conceptual
metaphor, where object is understood as containing inanimate and animate entities. The theory
behind that claim is explained in section 5 below.
The analysis of the material sense of space presented above indisputably shows that the ultimate
source domain for space is material object.
For time, if we accept the “time is space” metaphor, we could postulate that if time is space and
space is an object, then time is an object. However, we need not take that complex, roundabout route. It
is much easier to postulate that the underlying metaphor for time is simply time is an object as above
examples evidently demonstrate.
4. Objectification
All those examples clearly show that we conceptualize space, in all its senses, in terms of material
objects, the only entities accessible to our senses on which all cognition is founded. The theory in
which the ultimate source of metaphorization are physical objects has been called objectification and
has been developed by the present author in a number of papers (Szwedek 2000, 2002a, 2002b, 2004a,
2004b, 2007, 2008). The term objectification is used in its common OED sense: “The action of
objectifying, or condition of being objectified; an instance of this, an external thing in which an idea,
principle, etc. is expressed concretely”.
That fundamental claim, that the ultimate source of metaphorization is the level of material objects,
the only entities accessible to our senses. is based on four arguments: the cultural model of the Great
Chain of Being (as a model of people’s conceptualization of the world), Kotarbiński’s (1929) reism,
neuroembryological evidence, and linguistic expressions reflecting conceptualization.
4.1.The Great Chain of Being, introduced to linguistics in Lakoff and Turner (1989), is adopted here
in its reduced form of four levels proposed by Krzeszowski (1997: 67).
If, as is generally claimed, that cultural model represents our experience of the world, it is necessary to
emphasize three points:
i) material substance is the only property shared by all levels;
ii) there is no place for non-physical phenomena, abstract entities and relations such as, for
example, states, activities, events, etc.;
iii) i) and ii) lead to an obvious and clear conclusion that our fundamental, ordinary, everyday
cognition is the cognition of physical objects.
We overlook the importance of those obvious facts because, as Lakoff and Turner (1989) wrote,
this model “is largely unconscious and so fundamental to our thinking that we barely notice it” (1989:
167) (see also the neuroembryological evidence discussed below).
4.2. In 1929 Tadeusz Kotarbiński, a Polish philosopher, introduced reism on the basis of his criticism of
Aristotelian categories. He suggested
…at least tentatively, adopting a stance in which all categories are reduced to the category of
things. […] … every “name” which is not a name of a thing, we take to be an illusory name. Let
us take states, first. However, it will be better in this case not to use the word “state”, but the
word “event”, equivalent to the word “state” in a more general sense which we have in mind
here. (1929:71). (tr. A.S.)
And he concluded:
In consequence of that reduction it turns out that there are no other objects except things, in
other words – every object is a thing, whatever is, is a thing. […] However, it needs to be
emphasised clearly here that by a thing we do not understand only an inanimate block. To the
contrary – there are things inanimate, as well as animate, soulless, as well as “endowed with
psychic life”, thus both things in the narrower sense of the word, as well as people.” So much
about the reduction of the category of objects to the category of things. The position of such a
reduction can be called r e i s m” (1929: 75).
Comparing the Great Chain of Being and Kotarbiński’s reism one cannot help noticing a striking
similarity in their final conclusion that the basis of all our understanding and experience is the world of
physical objects and that physical experience is the basis and point of reference for all other possible
kinds of experience and conceptualisation.
In that situation it is quite remarkable that in our everyday communication the level of objects is
absent. We never say: „Oh, it’s an object, and it is a pen”, „It’s an object and it’s a cow”, etc.
It simply means that we take that level for granted to the extent that we are unaware of its
existence. This is also observed in linguistic discussions of image schemata such as container, path,
link, balance, etc. which have been analysed quite frequently and in detail. The object schema is only
listed as one of many, but, with one exception (Krzeszowski 1991), no attempt has been made to
describe it in any detail.
Why we are not aware of that level, and why that level is absent from thought and language, was
simply and brilliantly elucidated by Wittgenstein (1953):
„The aspects of things that are most important for us are hidden because of their simplicity and
familiarity. (One is unable to notice something – because it is always before one’s eyes.)” (1953:30)
4.3. There is also strong neurological evidence supporting Wittgenstein’s lucid observation. It explains
the absence of the object–level in thought and language in terms of the depth of embedding of object-
schema in our cognition.
In the physical world, the most fundamental property of objects is density of matter – density
which is the basis for the identification of surface, size, weight, shape, etc. The only sense that allows
us to experience density, and consequently surface, weight, etc. is touch (for an extensive discussion of
the sense of touch see Hatwell, Streri and Gentaz 2003; see also Szwedek 2000 for knowing is touching
metaphor in a number of languages).
Touch is also unique among the senses in that it is the only whole-body sense, it is the only
physical-contact sense, and in that the touching-organs, hands and mouth have the biggest neuronal
representation in the brain (cf. sensory and motor homunculus models).
However, more importantly, it is the most fundamental and primeval of all senses. It develops as
early as the 8th week of pregnancy and thus simultaneously with the formation of the neural system
(also in the 8th week). It is a clear evidence that the sense of touch is programmed earliest and at the
deepest level of the neural system.
Evidence from the phylogenetic development of mankind, from physical objects to ideas, and
ontogenetic development of neural system of individuals clearly show the neural depth of embedding
of the physical object schema, its primeval character, and in consequence explain its absence from our
consciousness, from thought and language.
In their development, our ancestors first limited their communication to physical objects. With
evolution they developed mental and emotional worlds which with time became equally, if not more
important than the physical world. While developing abstract concepts in metaphysical worlds, they
naturally based on what had been known to them, i.e. the physical objects and their properties.
A parallel development is also seen in the development of writing – from very concrete –
pictographic to abstract – ideographic system.
Those abstract worlds are not accessible to our senses; we can only perceive physical symptoms
accompanying mental processes and emotional states.
Despite that inaccessibility, people are rarely short of words to talk about thoughts and emotions
without restraint.
4.4. And finally, there is linguistic evidence, as the example below clearly show, that supports my
claim about objectification. The concept of thought that I have chosen as an illustration has all the
conceptual complexities - it is not only definitely non-physical, inaccessible to our senses, but, what is
more, it is processual in nature. We first have to somehow break up the process of thinking, identify a
segment of it, form a concept of that segment as an object with all adequate properties and then assign
some language expressions which we will use to refer to the concept and its properties. Thus it is a
good example to adequately illustrate the issue of linguistic representation of the non-physical worlds,
as well as the relation between the physical and non-physical worlds.
– thought is an object:
We have thoughts, take thoughts, give thoughts, abandon thoughts, thoughts can be scattered,
gathered or collected, suspended, etc., exactly like any physical objects.
– thought is a container:
We can be deep or lost in thoughts. Thoughts can be deep, etc.
– thought is a moving object:
Thoughts can be passing, moving or fleeting.
– thoughts have properties like physical objects:
Thoughts can have weight, can be weighty or hard, dark, brilliant, clear and gloomy.
thoughts can be counted: We can have many thoughts, first thought, second thought and
last thought.
– thoughts are animate objects:
Thoughts can be dangerous, happy, sober; Thoughts are born, cross one’s mind, and
strike. Thoughts are born (the birth of thought).
– thoughts are a reading matter: We read thought.
– thoughts, like all physical objects, have spatial orientation: current of thoughts, train of
thoughts, next, last thought.
– thoughts, like objects, can be evaluated: They can be good or bad, evil, wicked and sinful.
5. Conclusions
Up to now all studies on metaphors have focused on the source domain of many concepts such as
time, thought, love, fear, etc. pointing at space as the ultimate source domain. But nobody so far has
attempted to investigate the concept of space as a target domain and ask a question what might be the
source domain of space. This is quite odd as space, which in itself is non-physical, should be the prime
candidate for such an analysis. The reason of that situation probably is that space has commonly been
confused with the totality of objects (also spatial, i.e. three-dimensional, in themselves). The present
paper argues that if all our cognition has a bodily basis, then it is not space that is accessible to our
senses and that constitutes the ultimate source domain. It is the physical objects (both animate and
inanimate) that are the only entities accessible to our senses and it is the physical object that is the
ultimate source domain of space, time and other concepts.
The position that the physical object is the ultimate source domain is called objectification, the first
step in all metaphorical processes. The term objectification is used in its common OED sense as “The
action of objectifying, or condition of being objectified; an instance of this, an external thing in which
an idea, principle, etc. is expressed concretely”.
One consequence is that if we accept objectification, Lakoff and Johnson’s (1980) typology into
structural, orientational and ontological metaphors will lose sense, as structure and orientation are
aspects of objects (ontology), and therefore structural and orientational metaphors derive naturally from
objectification. What, however, will remain a problem is the issue of which aspects of objects are
inherited along with objectification and which are not or even cannot.
References
fabiszak, m. (ed.) 2007. Language and Meaning. Peter Lang Verlag.
fauconnier, g., e. sweetser (eds.). 1996. Spaces, Worlds, and Grammar. Chicago: Chicago
University Press.
fauconnier, g. 1985. Mental spaces: Aspects of meaning construction in natural language.
Cambridge: MIT Press.
górska, e., g. radden (eds). 2005. Metonymy – Metaphor Collage. Warszawa: Warsaw
University Press.
kotarbiński, t.1990 [1929]. Elementy teorii poznania, logiki formalnej i metodologii nauk. Wrocław:
Zakład Narodowy im. Ossolińskich.
krzeszowski, t.p. 1997. Angels and Devils in Hell. Warszawa: Wydawnictwo Energeia.
krzeszowski, t.P. 1991. “Metaphor - metaphorization - cognition”, Biuletyn Polskiego Towarzystwa
Językowego XLIII-XLV, 83-95.
lakoff g., m. johnson. 1980 [2003]. Metaphors We Live By. Chicago: Chicago University Press.
lakoff g., m. turner. 1989. More than Cool Reason: A Field Guide to Poetic Metaphor. Chicago
and London: The University of Chicago Press.
langacker, r. 1993. “Reference-point constructions.” Cognitive Linguistics, 4, 1-38.
langacker, r. 1990. Concept, Image, and Symbol. Berlin – New York: Mouton de Gruyter.
langacker, r. 1982. “Space Grammar, Analysability, and the English Passive”. Language 50, 22-80.
lyons, j. 1977. Semantics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
hatwell, y., a. streri, e. gentaz (eds). 2003. Touching for Knowing. Cognitive psychology of haptic
manual perception. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins (tr. from y. hatwell, a. streri, e.
gentaz. 2000. Toucher pour connaître. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France).
lewandowska–tomaszczyk, b., k. turewicz (eds) 2002. Cognitive Linguistics To-day. Frankfurt
am Main; Peter Lang.
oleksy, w. (ed.) 2002. Language, Function, Structure, and Change. Peter Lang Verlag: 61-65.
puppel, s., k. dziubalska-kołaczyk, (eds). 2000. Multibus vocibus de lingua. Wydział Filologiczny
UAM: Poznań.
radden, g. 2005. “The metaphor time as space across languages”. In: górska , radden 2005: 99 –
120
szwedek, a. 2007. “An Alternative Theory of Metaphorization”. In: fabiszak 2007: 313-327.
szwedek, a. 2004. „Reizm Kotarbińskiego a współczesna teoria metafory” (Kotarbiński’s reism and
the contemporary theory of metaphor. Rozprawy Komisji Językowej Naukowe Łódzkiego
Towarzystwa Naukowego. 347-354.
szwedek, a. 2004. “Objectification in metaphorical processes – some philosophical issues”. Poznań:
Lingua Posnaniensis XLVI:121-130.
szwedek, a. 2002. “Shared or inherited entailments among metaphors” In: oleksy 2002: 61-65.
szwedek, a.. 2002. “Objectification: From Object Perception To Metaphor Creation”. In:
lewandowska-tomaszczyk, turewicz 2002: 159-175.
szwedek, a. 2000. “Senses, perception and metaphors (of Object and Objectification)”. In: puppel,
dziubalska-kołaczyk 2000: 143-153.
wittgenstein, l. 1953. Philosophical Investigations (Translated by G.E.M. Anscombe). Oxford: Basil
Blackwell.