0% found this document useful (0 votes)
10 views8 pages

02 - Utilitarianism

Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
10 views8 pages

02 - Utilitarianism

Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 8

Lecture 2 - UTILITARIANISM

Transcript from the video with annotations

Dionisio E. Limos

One set of ethical theories that has become extremely popular stresses the importance of
focusing on the consequences of your actions. These theories are known as
consequentialist theories. The most famous consequentialist theory is called
utilitarianism.
Utilitarianism is easy to understand. In its most basic form, it argues that if you can
increase the overall happiness of the world in some way, then you should. By
concentrating on happiness, utilitarians are making claims about what they think makes
an outcome or consequence good. Not all consequentialists believe happiness is the only
good thing, but utilitarianism is the most popular form of consequentialism.
---

Should Batman kill the Joker?

If you were to ask the Dark Knight himself, with his hard-and-fast no-killing rule, he’d
say absolutely not.

Actually, in fact, he would say: [Batman voice] “Absolutely not.”

When you think about it, dude is pretty Kantian in his ethics.

Regardless of what Joker does, there are some lines that good people do not cross, and
for Batman, killing definitely falls on the wrong side of that line.

But, let’s be real here: Joker is never gonna stop killing.

Sure, Batman will have him thrown back in Arkham, but we all know that he’s gonna get
out – he always gets out – and once he’s free, he will kill again. And maim and terrorize.

And when he does won’t a little bit of that be Batman’s fault?

Batman has been in a position to kill Joker hundreds of times.

He has had the power to save anyone from ever being a victim of the Joker
again.

If you have the ability to stop a killer, and you don’t, are you morally pure
because you didn’t kill?
Or are you morally dirty because you refused to do what needs to be done?

So, why do I describe Batman as Kantian?

Well, the school of thought laid out by 18th century German philosopher Immanuel
Kant – now known as Kantianism – is pretty straightforward.

More precisely: It’s absolute.

Kantianism is all about sticking to the moral rulebook.

There are never any exceptions, or any excuses, for violating moral rules.

And our man Batman tries his hardest to stick to his code, no matter what.

But there are other ways of looking at ethics.

Like, instead of focusing on the intent behind our behavior, what if we paid more
attention to the consequences? (Consequentialism)

One moral theory that does this is utilitarianism.


It focuses on the results, or consequences, of our actions, and treats intentions as
irrelevant. Good consequences equal good actions, in this view.

So, what’s a good consequence?

Modern utilitarianism was founded in the 18th century by British philosophers Jeremy
Bentham and John Stuart Mill.

But the theory has philosophical ancestors in ancient Greek thinkers such as Epicurus.

All of these guys agreed that actions should be measured in terms of the
happiness, or pleasure, that they produce.

After all, they argued, happiness is our final end – it’s what we do everything else for.

Think about it like this: many things that you do, you do for the sake of something else.

You study to get a good grade.

You work to get money.


But why do you want good grades, or money?

There are different answers we could give – like maybe we’re seeking affirmation for our
intelligence, or the approval of our parents, or a degree that will give us a career we
want.

But why do we want that particular career?

Why do we want approval?

We can keep asking questions, but ultimately our answer will bottom out in,

“I want what I want because I think it will make me happy.”

That’s what we all want – it’s one of the few things everyone has in common.

And utilitarians believe that’s what should drive our morality.

Like Kant, utilitarians agree that a moral theory should apply equally to everyone.

But they thought the way to do that was to ground it in something that’s really intuitive.

And there’s really nothing more basic than the primal desire to seek pleasure and avoid
pain.

So, it’s often said that utilitarianism is a hedonistic moral theory – this means the good
is equal to the pleasant, and we ought, morally, to pursue pleasure and happiness, and
work to avoid pain.

[Hedonism is the ethical theory that pleasure (in the sense of the satisfaction of
desires) is the highest good and proper aim of human life.]

But, utilitarianism is not what you’d call an egoistic theory.

[Egoistic being centered in or preoccupied with oneself and the gratification of


one's own desires; self-centered (opposed to altruistic)]

Egoism says that everyone ought, morally, to pursue their own good.

In contrast to that, utilitarianism is other-regarding. (unselfish, thinks and regards the


other)
“It says we should pursue pleasure or happiness – not just for ourselves, but for as
many sentient beings as possible.”

To put it formally:
“we should act always so as to produce the greatest good for the greatest
number.”

This is known as the principle of utility.

Okay, no one’s gonna argue with a philosophy that tells them to seek pleasure.

But, sometimes doing what provides the most pleasure to the most people can mean
that you have to take one for the team.

It can mean sacrificing your pleasure, in order to produce more good overall.

Like when it’s your birthday and your family say you can choose any
restaurant you want.

The thing that would make you happiest is Thai food, but you know that that
would make the rest of your family miserable.

So, when you choose Chinese – which is nobody’s favorite, but everybody can
make do – then you’ve thought like a utilitarian.

You’ve chosen the action that would produce the most overall happiness for the
group, even though it produced less happiness for you than other alternatives
would have.

The problem is, for the most part, we’re all our own biggest fans.

We each come pre-loaded with a bias in favor of our own interests.

This isn’t necessarily a bad thing – caring about yourself is a good way to promote
survival.

But where morality is concerned, utilitarians argue, as special as you are, you’re no more
special than anybody else.

So, your interests count, but no more than anyone else’s.

Now, you might say that you agree with that.

I mean, we all like to think of ourselves as being generous and selfless.


But, even though I’m sure you are a totally nice person – you have to admit that things
seem way more important – weightier, higher-stakes – when they apply to you, rather
than to some stranger.

So, utilitarians suggest that we make our moral decisions from the position of a
benevolent, disinterested spectator.

Rather than thinking about what I should do, they suggest that I consider what I would
think if I were advising a group of strangers about what they should do.

That way, I have a disposition of good will, but I’m not emotionally invested.

And I’m a spectator, rather than a participant.

This approach is far more likely to yield a fair and unbiased judgment about what’s
really best for the group.

Now, to see utilitarianism put to the test, let’s pop over to the Thought Bubble for some
Flash Philosophy.

Thought Bubble

20th century British philosopher Bernard Williams offered this thought experiment.

Jim is on a botanical expedition in South America when he happens upon a group of 20


indigenous people, and a group of soldiers.

The whole group of indigenous people is about to be executed for protesting their
oppressive regime.

For some reason, the leader of the soldiers offers Jim the chance to shoot one of the
prisoners, since he’s a guest in their land.

He says that if Jim shoots one of the prisoners, he’ll let the other 19 go.

But if Jim refuses, then the soldiers will shoot all 20 protesters.

What should Jim do?

More importantly, what would you do?

Williams actually presents this case as a critique of utilitarianism.


The theory clearly demands that Jim shoot one man so that 19 will be saved.

But, Williams argues, “no moral theory ought to demand the taking of an innocent life.”

Thinking like a Kantian, Williams argues that it’s not Jim’s fault that the head soldier is
a total dirt bag, and Jim shouldn’t have to get literal blood on his hands to try and rectify
the situation.

So, although it sounds pretty simple, utilitarianism is a really demanding moral theory.

It says, we live in a world where sometimes people do terrible things.

And, if we’re the ones who happen to be there, and we can do something to make things
better, we must.

Even if that means getting our hands dirty.

And if I sit by and watch something bad happen when I could have prevented it, my
hands are dirty anyway.

So, Jim shouldn’t think about it as killing one man.

That man was dead already, because they were all about to be killed.

Instead, Jim should think of his decision as doing what it takes to save 19.

And Batman needs to kill the Joker already.

___

Now, if you decide you want to follow utilitarian moral theory, you have options.

Specifically, two of them.

When Bentham and Mill first posed their moral theory, it was in a form now known as
Act Utilitarianism, sometimes called classical utilitarianism.

And it says that, in any given situation, you should choose the action that
produces the greatest good for the greatest number.

But sometimes, the act that will produce the greatest good for the greatest number can
seem just wrong.

The Surgeon, the Neighbor, and the Organs Story


For instance, suppose a surgeon has five patients, all waiting for transplants.

One needs a heart, another a lung. Two are waiting for kidneys and the last needs a liver.

The doctor is pretty sure that these patients will all die before their names come up on
the transplant list.

And he just so happens to have a neighbor who has no family.

Total recluse. Not even a very nice guy.

The doctor knows that no one would miss this guy if he were to disappear.

And by some miracle, the neighbor is a match for all five of the transplant patients.

So, it seems like, even though this would be a bad day for the neighbor, an act-utilitarian
should kill the neighbor and give his organs to the five patients.

It’s the greatest good for the greatest number.

Yes, one innocent person dies, but five innocent people are saved.

This might seem harsh, but remember that pain is pain, regardless of who’s
experiencing it.

So, the death of the neighbor would be no worse than the death of any of those patients
dying on the transplant list.

In fact, it’s five times less bad than all five of their deaths.

So, thought experiments like this led some utilitarians to come up with another
framework for their theory.

This one is called Rule Utilitarianism. Philosophers Richard Brandt and Brad
Hooker are major proponents of such an approach.

This version of the theory says that we ought to live by rules that, in general, are likely
to lead to the greatest good for the greatest number.

So, yes, there are going to be situations where killing an innocent person will lead to the
greatest good for the greatest number.

But, rule utilitarians want us to think long-term, and on a larger scale.


And overall, a whole society where innocent people are taken off the streets to be
harvested for their organs is gonna have a lot less utility than one where you don’t have
to live in constant fear of that happening to you.

So, rule utilitarianism allows us to refrain from acts that might maximize utility in the
short run, and instead follow rules that will maximize utility for the majority of the time.

As an owner of human organs, this approach might make sense to you.

But I still gotta say: If Batman were a utilitarian of either kind, it wouldn’t look very
good for the Joker.

Today we learned about utilitarianism. We studied the principle of utility, and


learned about the difference between act and rule utilitarianism.

References:

1. Ethics 101 by Brian Boone


Chapter 3 – Consequentialist Ethics

2. Ethics for Dummies by Christopher Panza, PhD and Adam Potthast, PhD
Chapter 7 – Increasing the Good: Utilitarian Ethics

Video Reference:

1. https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=-a739VjqdSI – Utilitarianism - Crash


Course Philosophy
2. Utilitarianism | Ethics Defined – https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=-
FrZl22_79Q

You might also like