02 - Utilitarianism
02 - Utilitarianism
Dionisio E. Limos
One set of ethical theories that has become extremely popular stresses the importance of
focusing on the consequences of your actions. These theories are known as
consequentialist theories. The most famous consequentialist theory is called
utilitarianism.
Utilitarianism is easy to understand. In its most basic form, it argues that if you can
increase the overall happiness of the world in some way, then you should. By
concentrating on happiness, utilitarians are making claims about what they think makes
an outcome or consequence good. Not all consequentialists believe happiness is the only
good thing, but utilitarianism is the most popular form of consequentialism.
---
If you were to ask the Dark Knight himself, with his hard-and-fast no-killing rule, he’d
say absolutely not.
When you think about it, dude is pretty Kantian in his ethics.
Regardless of what Joker does, there are some lines that good people do not cross, and
for Batman, killing definitely falls on the wrong side of that line.
Sure, Batman will have him thrown back in Arkham, but we all know that he’s gonna get
out – he always gets out – and once he’s free, he will kill again. And maim and terrorize.
He has had the power to save anyone from ever being a victim of the Joker
again.
If you have the ability to stop a killer, and you don’t, are you morally pure
because you didn’t kill?
Or are you morally dirty because you refused to do what needs to be done?
Well, the school of thought laid out by 18th century German philosopher Immanuel
Kant – now known as Kantianism – is pretty straightforward.
There are never any exceptions, or any excuses, for violating moral rules.
And our man Batman tries his hardest to stick to his code, no matter what.
Like, instead of focusing on the intent behind our behavior, what if we paid more
attention to the consequences? (Consequentialism)
Modern utilitarianism was founded in the 18th century by British philosophers Jeremy
Bentham and John Stuart Mill.
But the theory has philosophical ancestors in ancient Greek thinkers such as Epicurus.
All of these guys agreed that actions should be measured in terms of the
happiness, or pleasure, that they produce.
After all, they argued, happiness is our final end – it’s what we do everything else for.
Think about it like this: many things that you do, you do for the sake of something else.
There are different answers we could give – like maybe we’re seeking affirmation for our
intelligence, or the approval of our parents, or a degree that will give us a career we
want.
We can keep asking questions, but ultimately our answer will bottom out in,
That’s what we all want – it’s one of the few things everyone has in common.
Like Kant, utilitarians agree that a moral theory should apply equally to everyone.
But they thought the way to do that was to ground it in something that’s really intuitive.
And there’s really nothing more basic than the primal desire to seek pleasure and avoid
pain.
So, it’s often said that utilitarianism is a hedonistic moral theory – this means the good
is equal to the pleasant, and we ought, morally, to pursue pleasure and happiness, and
work to avoid pain.
[Hedonism is the ethical theory that pleasure (in the sense of the satisfaction of
desires) is the highest good and proper aim of human life.]
Egoism says that everyone ought, morally, to pursue their own good.
To put it formally:
“we should act always so as to produce the greatest good for the greatest
number.”
Okay, no one’s gonna argue with a philosophy that tells them to seek pleasure.
But, sometimes doing what provides the most pleasure to the most people can mean
that you have to take one for the team.
It can mean sacrificing your pleasure, in order to produce more good overall.
Like when it’s your birthday and your family say you can choose any
restaurant you want.
The thing that would make you happiest is Thai food, but you know that that
would make the rest of your family miserable.
So, when you choose Chinese – which is nobody’s favorite, but everybody can
make do – then you’ve thought like a utilitarian.
You’ve chosen the action that would produce the most overall happiness for the
group, even though it produced less happiness for you than other alternatives
would have.
The problem is, for the most part, we’re all our own biggest fans.
This isn’t necessarily a bad thing – caring about yourself is a good way to promote
survival.
But where morality is concerned, utilitarians argue, as special as you are, you’re no more
special than anybody else.
So, utilitarians suggest that we make our moral decisions from the position of a
benevolent, disinterested spectator.
Rather than thinking about what I should do, they suggest that I consider what I would
think if I were advising a group of strangers about what they should do.
That way, I have a disposition of good will, but I’m not emotionally invested.
This approach is far more likely to yield a fair and unbiased judgment about what’s
really best for the group.
Now, to see utilitarianism put to the test, let’s pop over to the Thought Bubble for some
Flash Philosophy.
Thought Bubble
20th century British philosopher Bernard Williams offered this thought experiment.
The whole group of indigenous people is about to be executed for protesting their
oppressive regime.
For some reason, the leader of the soldiers offers Jim the chance to shoot one of the
prisoners, since he’s a guest in their land.
He says that if Jim shoots one of the prisoners, he’ll let the other 19 go.
But if Jim refuses, then the soldiers will shoot all 20 protesters.
But, Williams argues, “no moral theory ought to demand the taking of an innocent life.”
Thinking like a Kantian, Williams argues that it’s not Jim’s fault that the head soldier is
a total dirt bag, and Jim shouldn’t have to get literal blood on his hands to try and rectify
the situation.
So, although it sounds pretty simple, utilitarianism is a really demanding moral theory.
And, if we’re the ones who happen to be there, and we can do something to make things
better, we must.
And if I sit by and watch something bad happen when I could have prevented it, my
hands are dirty anyway.
That man was dead already, because they were all about to be killed.
Instead, Jim should think of his decision as doing what it takes to save 19.
___
Now, if you decide you want to follow utilitarian moral theory, you have options.
When Bentham and Mill first posed their moral theory, it was in a form now known as
Act Utilitarianism, sometimes called classical utilitarianism.
And it says that, in any given situation, you should choose the action that
produces the greatest good for the greatest number.
But sometimes, the act that will produce the greatest good for the greatest number can
seem just wrong.
One needs a heart, another a lung. Two are waiting for kidneys and the last needs a liver.
The doctor is pretty sure that these patients will all die before their names come up on
the transplant list.
The doctor knows that no one would miss this guy if he were to disappear.
And by some miracle, the neighbor is a match for all five of the transplant patients.
So, it seems like, even though this would be a bad day for the neighbor, an act-utilitarian
should kill the neighbor and give his organs to the five patients.
Yes, one innocent person dies, but five innocent people are saved.
This might seem harsh, but remember that pain is pain, regardless of who’s
experiencing it.
So, the death of the neighbor would be no worse than the death of any of those patients
dying on the transplant list.
In fact, it’s five times less bad than all five of their deaths.
So, thought experiments like this led some utilitarians to come up with another
framework for their theory.
This one is called Rule Utilitarianism. Philosophers Richard Brandt and Brad
Hooker are major proponents of such an approach.
This version of the theory says that we ought to live by rules that, in general, are likely
to lead to the greatest good for the greatest number.
So, yes, there are going to be situations where killing an innocent person will lead to the
greatest good for the greatest number.
So, rule utilitarianism allows us to refrain from acts that might maximize utility in the
short run, and instead follow rules that will maximize utility for the majority of the time.
But I still gotta say: If Batman were a utilitarian of either kind, it wouldn’t look very
good for the Joker.
References:
2. Ethics for Dummies by Christopher Panza, PhD and Adam Potthast, PhD
Chapter 7 – Increasing the Good: Utilitarian Ethics
Video Reference: