Sufficient
Sufficient
As previously stated, for any proposition, truth is defined by Leibniz in the same way: the
predicate is contained in the subject. It only takes a little thought to realize that for any one
subject (like Peter or Caesar), the number of predicates that are true of it will be infinite (or at
least very large), for they must include every last thing Peter or Caesar did or will do, as well as
everything that did or will ever happen to them. But now it is natural to ask: Why do all these
predicates come together in the one subject? It could be that the predicates are a quite arbitrary or
random collection—although Leibniz does not believe this, and it is certainly not intuitive.
Rather, one predicate or set of predicates explains another. For example, Peter’s coming into
contact with a virus explains his illness. Or, Caesar’s ambition and boldness explains why he
decided to cross the Rubicon. So, many (at least) of the predicates that are true of a subject “hang
together” as a network of explanations.
Leibniz goes further still by claiming that for every predicate that is true of a subject, there must
be a set of other true predicates which constitute a sufficient reason for its being true. This he
calls the principle of sufficient reason—that there must be a sufficient reason for why things are
as they are and not otherwise. This is why he uses words like “foundation” and “reason” in the
quotation above. Unless this were true, Leibniz argues, the universe would not make any sense,
and science and philosophy both would be impossible (see, for example, New Essays on Human
Understanding, preface, p. 66). Moreover, it would be impossible to account for a basic notion
like identity unless there was a sufficient reason why Caesar, for example, with his particular
properties at a given time, is identical with the Caesar who existed a week prior with such
different properties (see “Remarks on Arnauld’s Letter,” May 1686).
The principle of sufficient reason also accounts for why Leibniz uses the phrase “completing the
whole demonstration” in the above quote. If the complete concept of the subject (that is, all of its
true predicates) together constitutes a complete network of explanation, then these explanations
can be followed forward and backward, so to speak, at least in principle. That is, working
forward, one could deduce that Caesar will cross the Rubicon from a all the predicates that have
been true of him; or, working backward, one can deduce from all those predicates true of Caesar
at his death the reasons why he won the battle of Pharsalus. The “whole demonstration,” then, is
the revelation of the logical structure of the network of explanations that make Caesar who he is.
However, this is clearly not something the average person can do. Human minds are not subtle
and capacious enough for a task which may be infinite. Still, in a more limited way, one can
certainly talk about personalities, characters, and causes or reasons for things. The quotation
from Leibniz given above continues:
… [he who completed the whole demonstration would then show] that it was rational and
therefore definite that this would happen, but not that it is necessary in itself, or that the contrary
implies a contradiction (Discourse on Metaphysics, §13).
These qualifications are quite important for Leibniz. It was often suggested by Leibniz’s
contemporaries (and is still being suggested) that his idea of the sufficient reason of all the
predicates of a subject meant that everything true of a subject is necessarily true. This might
entail that Caesar did not choose to cross the Rubicon, but that he was acting in a determined
manner, like a machine. In other words, Leibniz seems to be denying any sort of free will. The
free will problem will be discussed in more detail below, but for the moment, a few observations
can be made.
First, Leibniz claims that Caesar’s crossing of the Rubicon is not necessary in the sense that “A
is A” is necessary. Because while “A is not A” is a contradiction, Caesar’s deciding not to cross
the Rubicon does not imply a contradiction. To be sure, history would have been different—even
Caesar would have been different—but there is no contradiction in that strong sense. Caesar’s
properties are not logically necessary.
Second, any truth about Caesar–indeed, the whole complete concept of Caesar–is not “necessary
in itself.” Caesar is Caesar, but nothing about Caesar in himself proves that Caesar has to be. By
contrast, “A is A” doesn’t need any other explanation for its truth. So, while every property of
Caesar is explained by some other property of Caesar, no property explains why it is true that
Caesar existed. Caesar is not anecessary being.
What the precise details are of Leibniz’s account of free will remain a strenuously debated issue
in Leibniz scholarship (especially what the exact nature is of these distinctions, whether he is
justified in making them, and even if justified whether they yield the results he claims in the area
of free will). More detail will be added to this account below, but the existence of this debate
should be kept in mind throughout.
1. Guiding commitments
o 1.1 Universal intelligibility
o 1.2 Attribute barrier
o 1.3 The priority of an infinite thinker
o 1.4 Philosophy as a way of life
2. Philosophy of mind
o 2.1 Minds
2.1.1 Minds as bundles
2.1.2 Minds as parts
2.1.3 Panpsychism
o 2.2 Human minds
2.2.1 Ideas of bodies
2.2.2 Knowing your pancreas and other problems
o 2.3 Consciousness and ideas of ideas
o 2.4 Willing or affirming
3. Epistemology
o 3.1 Truth and adequacy
o 3.2 Knowledge (cognitio)
3.2.1 Cognition and causation
3.2.2 Kinds of cognition I: Imagination and falsity
3.2.3 Kinds of cognition II: Intellect, common notions and reason
3.2.4 Generality and abstraction
3.2.5 Kinds of cognition III: Intuition
4. Eternity of the mind
Bibliography
o Spinoza’s Works
o Secondary Literature
Academic Tools
Other Internet Resources
Related Entries
1. Guiding commitments
1.1 Universal intelligibility
One of Spinoza’s most fundamental epistemological and methodological commitments is a
commitment to universal intelligibility. In his most influential treatise, the Ethics, Spinoza
expresses this commitment in two ways: first, as the axiom that there is nothing that cannot
be “conceived”, either “through itself” or through “another thing” (Ethics [= E] 1ax2);
second, as the claim that there is a “reason or [i.e.] cause” for the “existence or
nonexistence” of every thing (E1p11atld1).
These formulations immediately raise several questions. What does it mean for something to
be conceived “through itself”, i.e., in some sense be self-explanatory? Does the equivalence
of causes and reasons suggested by E1p11altd1 mean that only appeals to causes can furnish
reasons? Indeed, what counts as a “reason” (cf. Lin 2018)? It’s often assumed that in
Spinoza’s view to give a “reason” for something requires engaging in the sort of apriori
deductions that fill large swathes of the Ethics. The opening definition of the treatise,
according to which something is a “cause of itself” if its existence is implied by its essence
(E1def1), suggests that at least some of the relevant “reasons” will indeed be accessible
apriori. But could sense experience also furnish us with reasons? Is seeing my dog play with
a stick enough of a “reason” to “conceive” of her as existing, or must I deduce her necessary
existence from the infinitely long series of prior causes (E1p28), a task Spinoza admits is
impossible for finite minds like ours (Treatise on the Emendation of the Intellect [= TIE]
§100)?
Controversially but influentially, Michael Della Rocca 2008 has argued that Spinoza’s
philosophy as a whole can be derived from his commitment to intelligibility. (For criticisms
see e.g. Laerke 2011, Newlands 2018, Renz 2018.)
2. Philosophy of mind
2.1 Minds
2.1.1 Minds as bundles
One reason why Spinoza might not care about distinguishing between calling something
God’s “idea” and calling it God’s “intellect” (see 1.3) is that, like Hume, he appears to
endorse what we today would call the “bundle theory” of mind. On this theory, there is
nothing more to “minds” and “intellects” than collections of ideas of various complexity.
(For example, the “idea that constitutes the formal being of the human mind is…composed
of a great many ideas” [E2p15].) In particular, minds do not contain any specialized
“faculties”, such as will or intellect (E2p48). If notions of such faculties are to have any
validity at all, they must be understood as mere abstractions from particular ideas and
particular volitions (E2p48s; G/II/130).
For Spinoza, what individuates one bundle of ideas from another seem to be their intentional
objects, i.e., what they represent (E2p13s; see 2.1.3–4). For example, the aforementioned
highly composite idea that is the “human mind” has a certain “actually existing body” as its
essential object (see 2.2).
(On Spinoza’s bundle view of the mind, see e.g. Della Rocca 1996; Hübner 2019; Renz
2018. On abstraction, see 3.2.4; on the relation between ideas and affirmations, see 2.4; on
the human mind specifically see 2.2.)
2.1.2 Minds as parts
Spinoza’s ground-floor commitment to substance monism (i.e., to the metaphysical
possibility of only one “substance”, or existentially and explanatorily independent thing)
leaves him with the problem of how to understand the ontological status of finite thought. If
only one substance exists, what are we to make of human minds? These cannot be
thinking substances as they are, say, for Descartes or Leibniz. Short of condemning all finite
thinking as illusory, Spinoza seems to have only one option left: to identify certain instances
of God’s own thoughts with finite thinking. And this is exactly what Spinoza does: he
proposes that we regard all finite ideas, and all the finite “minds” these ideas compose (see
2.1.1), as “parts” of the divine “infinite intellect”:
the human mind is a part [pars] of the infinite intellect of God. Therefore, when we say that
the human mind perceives this or that, we are saying nothing but that God, not insofar as
he is infinite, but insofar as he is explained through the nature of the human mind, or
insofar as he constitutes the essence of the human mind, has this or that idea. (E2p11c)
Finite minds are thus for Spinoza both modes of a thinking substance and parts of
an infinite mode that is God’s own “intellect”.
The claim that finite minds are parts of the divine intellect may answer the question of the
ontological status of finite thought, but it creates another puzzle: in what sense can a non-
extended mind or intellect be a “part”, or have “parts”, moreover parts that are themselves
“minds”?
2.1.3 Panpsychism
As we just saw, Spinoza accommodates human minds within his substance-monistic
framework by carving up God’s “infinite intellect” into “parts”. But he isn’t concerned solely
with making room in his metaphysics for human minds:
the things we have shown so far are completely general and do not pertain more to man
than to other individuals, all of which, though in different degrees, are nevertheless
animate [animata]. For of each thing there is necessarily an idea in God, of which God is the
cause in the same way as he is of the [human mind] (E2p13s)
This is Spinoza’s thesis of panpsychism, or universal mindedness (more precisely, universal
at least for all “individuals” or composite entities [E2def; G/II/100]). Panpsychism follows
because all it takes for there to be a finite “mind” in Spinoza’s view is that there be some
“part” of the omniscient divine intellect – some component idea of it – that represents some
discernible bit of being. So not only is there nothing more to minds than ideas (2.1.1), there
is nothing more to creaturely minds than God’s ideas.
Spinoza’s panpsychism may certainly seem more morally appealing than the vivisection-
friendly Cartesian view that animals are just more complex versions of tables and clocks. Yet
one may also wonder whether an account that can explain how human mindedness is
possible only by instituting a general principle – namely, the divisibility of an omniscient
infinite intellect into component ideas – that ushers in also plant and mineral minds has
diluted the meaning of “mind” beyond recognition or usefulness. Can an account that sees
mindedness everywhere explain phenomena that, to all appearances, are particular
to human rationality and self-consciousness? And is Spinoza not guilty here simply of a
profound confusion of categories: how can my mind just be God’s idea of something?
Margaret Wilson expressed the classic version of these worries, pessimistically judging
against Spinoza (1999: ch.9).
(On Spinozistic minds, see e.g. Alanen 2011, Koistinen 2018, Lin 2017, Newlands 2012; on
mind-relativity of representing, see e.g. Matheron 1969, Donagan 1988, Della Rocca 1996;
on individuation of subjects, Renz 2018.)
3. Epistemology
3.1 Truth and adequacy
Spinoza is often taken to endorse the correspondence theory of truth, that is, roughly, the
view that truth consists in some sort of conformity of thought to reality. Spinoza himself puts
the point in terms of “agreement”: “A true idea must agree with [convenire] its object”
(E1ax6).
However, this relational property of “agreement” is not the only way Spinoza characterizes
truth. True Spinozistic ideas also have an intrinsic and, arguably, introspectable (cf. Garrett
2018: ch.5) property which distinguishes them as true without requiring us to look beyond
the ideas themselves. An “adequate” idea is one with this intrinsic property:
By adequate idea I understand an idea which, insofar as it is considered in itself, without
relation to an object, has all the properties, or intrinsic denominations of a true idea. Exp.:
say intrinsic to exclude what is extrinsic, viz. the agreement of the idea with its object.
(E2def4)
Consequently, truth can be “its own standard”, such that “he who has a true idea at the same
time knows that he has a true idea, and cannot doubt the truth of the thing” (E2p43, cf. TIE
§36).
The view is surely puzzling: How is it that just by considering an idea on its own, we can be
certain that it in fact conforms to what it represents? What might these intrinsic signs of truth
be?
One plausible answer is that Spinoza has in mind here something like clarity and distinctness
(cf. e.g. E2p38c), and so is in broad agreement with Descartes’s “rule” that true ideas can
appear to us as clear and distinct. Don Garrett has suggested that, in addition to clarity and
distinctness, we should understand adequacy as the “logical consistency of the represented
object” (2018: ch.6). On this reading, true ideas are self-evidently true insofar as we can
clearly and distinctly perceive the logical consistency of what they represent. This proposal
has the virtue of tying together Spinoza’s two characterizations of truth – the extrinsic and
the intrinsic one – into one neat package: given Spinoza’s commitment to necessitarianism
(E1p33, E1p35), any logically consistent idea will represent not just a possible object but a
necessary and actual one; hence we can know from the logical consistency of an idea alone
that it in fact corresponds to its object.
The above definition of adequate idea in terms of a true idea’s intrinsic or nonrelational
properties is, however, not the only way Spinoza characterizes mental “adequacy”. He also
gives what we could call a mind-relative account of adequacy. It is made possible by his
belief that finite minds are “parts” of the omniscient “infinite intellect” (see 2.1.2). As he
explains, “there are no inadequate or confused ideas except insofar as they are related to the
singular mind of someone” (E2p36d):
when we say that God has this or that idea, not only insofar as he constitutes the nature of
the human Mind, but insofar as he also has the idea of another thing together with the
human Mind, then we say that the human Mind perceives the thing only partially, or
inadequately (E2p11c)
In other words, if ideas constituting a given finite mind suffice for representing x in the same
way that a perfect intellect would represent x, the mind in question represents x “adequately”.
Eugene Marshall has usefully expressed this point in terms of part-whole “containment”:
ideas are adequate iff they are entirely a part of, i.e., contained in, the relevant finite mind
(2013:26).
Here is an example of how this might work. Consider once again Spinoza’s claim that the
idea of the body that essentially constitutes a human mind is “completely confused” (see
2.2.1). We can put this point in terms of inadequacy: a human mind knows its body as a
particular in duration only by perceiving how it is “affected” or changed. This idea of the
body is “inadequate” in Spinoza’s technical sense because God’s conception of that body
includes many components that are not also part of the human mind’s conception of it: God
conceives of all the many bodies that go into composing, preserving, and “regenerating” the
affected human body, as well as of all the affecting external bodies, and of the infinite series
of causes on which these bodies in turn depend (E2p19d).
Confronted with Spinoza’s account of mental adequacy, we might wonder how his two
characterizations of this concept are supposed to hang together: why should an idea entirely
contained in a mind also have certain intrinsic markings of truth, such as clarity and
distinctness? One way to reconcile these two claims is to infer that for Spinoza only ideas
whose “premises”, so to speak, are wholly contained in a given mind can also appear as
manifestly or self-evidently true. (One might also wonder if finite minds like ours can ever
manage to think anything truly “adequately”, if this requires that all of the “premises” of a
given idea be contained in our minds [cf. Della Rocca 1996]. We come back to this question
in 3.2.1.)
Finally, some commentators have concluded, further, that an “adequate” idea must be
contained in a mind insofar as it must also have been “adequately caused” – i.e., self-
sufficiently or autonomously caused – by the mind in question, and as such counts as a true
“action” of that mind, in Spinoza’s technical sense of these terms (E3def1–2). If that’s right,
then adequate ideas must all be innate (LeBuffe 2010, E. Marshall 2013, J. Steinberg 2018a:
ch.8). For having a cause external to the mind – for example, arising from experience –
would be incompatible by definition with having been “adequately caused”. On such
readings, what we might experience as an acquisition of an adequate idea (say, in a
philosophy class) is in fact only a matter of becoming more conscious of it (J. Steinberg
2018a: ch.8; see 2.3).
(See also Kisner 2011.)