lecture_expected_utility
lecture_expected_utility
Contents
1 Expected Utility representation and use. 1
4 Monetary outcomes. 4
7 Risk Aversion 5
10 Stochastic Dominance 9
13 Further reading 11
1
• Implications of Risk Aversion.
• Stochastic Dominance.
Good alternative sources for the material are Mas-Colell, Whinston, and Green (1995) and Hirshleifer
and Riley (1992)
• A set of states
• A set of acts
• A consequence function giving outcomes as a function of acts and states.
Preference Relation
Let X be the set of possible consumption plans. A preference relation ⪰ is a binary relation on X.
A preference relation is rational if it is
1. Complete: ∀x, y ∈ X, either x⪰y or y⪰x or both.
Definition 1 The preference relation ⪰ on the space of lotteries P is continuous if for any P, P ′ , P ′′ ∈ P:
ifP ⪰P ′ ⪰P ′′ then there are α, β ∈ (0, 1) such that αP + (1 − α)P ′′ ⪰P ′ ⪰βP + (1 − β)P ′′
Definition 2 The preference relation ⪰ on the space of lotteries P satisfies the independence axiom if
∀P, P ′ , P ′′ ∈ P and α ∈ (0, 1),
Definition 3 The utility function U has an expected utility form if there is an assignment of numbers
u1 , u2 , . . . , un to the n outcomes such that ∀P ∈ P we have
U (P ) = u1 p1 + . . . + un pn
A utility function U : P → R with the expected utility form is called a von Neumann–Morgenstern expected
utility function.
2
Proposition 1 (Linearity of U ) A utility function U : P → R has an expected utility form if and only if
it is linear, that is, if and only if it satisfies the property that
K
! K
X X
U αk Pk = αk U (Pk )
k=1 k=1
Proposition 2 Suppose that U : P → R is a v.N-M expected utility function for the preference relation ⪰
on P. Then Ū is another v.N-M expected utility function for ⪰ if and only if there are scalars β > 0 and γ
such that Ū (P ) = γ + βU (P ) for any P ∈ P.
Theorem 1 (Expected Utility Theorem) Suppose that the rational preference relation ⪰ on the space
of lotteries P satisfies the continuity and independence axioms. Then ⪰ admits a utility representation of the
expected utility form. That is, we can assign a number ui to each outcome xi such that for any two lotteries
P and P ′ , we have
n
X n
X
P ⪰P ′ iff ui pi ≥ ui p′i
i=1 i=1
Will not prove this theorem. See the discussion in Mas-Colell et al. (1995) or Huang and Litzenberger (1988).
With some technical additions it can be extended to infinite dimensional outcome spaces.
This theorem is extremely important, since it allows us to do all our analysis in terms of properties of
the utility function u(x), which is very convenient analytically.
0 w.p 0.89
Gamble D:
5mill w.p 0.1
0 w.p 0.9
3
Is this worrying? Depends.
Parallel to optical illusion. Question: Will you want to change your choices if the inconcistency is pointed
out to you?
For more on these worrying aspects of expected utility, see Machina (1987) and Machina (1989).
4 Monetary outcomes.
Will for convenience in most of the analysis work with unidimensional outcomes, which for interpretation is
easiest thought of as money. Alternatively one can think of consumption, measured by the monetary value
of consumption. (Supposing consumption is best choice given constraints.)
If utility is additively separable, time preference can be defined as the rate of substitution required between
consumption in two consecutive periods to maintain utility at a given level when the original allocation was
equal
∂U
dCt+1 − ∂C
ρ(Ct , t) = = t
A further restriction on the utility function is to assume a constant time preference. If we do, which is very
common in economic problems, we can write utility as
T
X
U (C) = β t U (Ct )
t=0
where β is the discount factor that measures the rate of time preference.
4
7 Risk Aversion
We now turn to risk aversion and its measurement and implications.
For simplicity work with unidimensional set of outcomes, easiest thought of as money.
We assume the existence of a v.N-M expected utility function. u(x), which can be used to rank outcomes.
Definition 4 (Risk Aversion) A person is risk averse (displays risk aversion) if he strictly prefers a cer-
tainty consequence to any risky prospect whose mathematical expectation of consequences equals that certainty.
If his preferences go the other way he is a risk–preferrer (displays risk–preference). If he is indifferent between
the certainty consequence and such a risky prospect he is risk–neutral (displays risk–neutrality).
6 6 6
Risk Averse u(x) Risk Neutral u(x) Risk Seeking u(x)
- - -
Definition 5 (Certainly Equivalent) Given a utility function u(x) and a probability distribution F , we
define the certainty equivalent CE(F, u) as the amount of money for which the individual is indifferent
between the gamble F and the certain amount CE(F, u), that is
Proposition 4 For a risk averse investor CE(F, u) ≤ E[x] for all gambles F .
u′′ (x)
RA (x) = −
u′ (x)
Definition 7 (Decreasing Absolute Risk Aversion) The utility function u(x) exhibits decreasing abso-
lute risk aversion if RA (x) is a decreasing function of x.
Definition 8 (Relative Risk Aversion) Given a (twice differentiable) utility function u(), the coefficient
of relative risk aversion at x is
xu′′ (x)
RR (x) = − ′ = xRA (x)
u (x)
5
9 Some common utility functions.
9.1 Quadratic utility.
Exercise 2.
Suppose we are using a quadratic utility function
u(x) = a + bx + cx2
1. What are the relevant restrictions on the coefficients that follows from nonsatiation and risk aversion?
2. Show that the quadratic utility specification for a risk averse individual implies satiation.
Figure 1 illustrates the problem of satiation:
u(x) = a + b ln(cx)
1. What are the relevant restrictions on the coefficients that follows from nonsatiation and risk aversion?
Figure 2 illustrates the utility function
6
Figure 2: Logarithmic Utility Function u(x) = a + b ln(cx), a = 0, b = 1, c = 1
7
9.4 The common utility specifications.
Concave quadratic utility
b
u(x) = x − x2 b>0
2
Negative exponential
u(x) = −e−bx b>0
Narrow power
B 1
u(x) = x1− B x > 0, B > 0
B−1
Extended power
1
A
(A + Bx)(1− B )
1
u(x) = x > max − , 0 , B > 0 A ̸= 0
B−1 B
8
10 Stochastic Dominance
We now consider a way of choosing among assets by comparing their probability distributions.
0.8
0.6
F(x)
0.4
0.2
0
0 5 10 15 20 25
x
Question: By only making weak assumptions about the utility function, can we unambiguously say
whether we prefer one asset to another?
Before looking at the stochastic case, consider the more basic notion of dominance.
Definition 9 (Dominance) An asset A dominates an asset B if the payoff to asset A is always greater
than or equal to the payoff to asset B.
Exercise 5.
There are three possible states, 0, 1 and 2, and two assets A and B, with outcomes:
State 0 1 2
Asset A: 10 5 10
Asset B: 5 0 10
Remark 1 For dominance to apply, don’t need agreement on probabilities, as long as all agree that all states
have positive probabilities of occurring.
Dominance is a very strong condition. In working markets one does not expect to observe dominated
assets. Relaxing the notion of dominance leads to notions of stochastic dominance.
9
11 First order stochastic dominance
Definition 10 (First order stochastic dominance) The distribution F (·) first order stochastically dom-
inates the distribution (G(·) (F ≥F SD G)) if for all u : R → R, u bounded, nondecreasing:
Z Z
u(x)f (x)dx ≥ u(x)g(x)dx
Proposition 5 The distribution of monetary payoffs F (·) first order stochastically dominates the distribu-
tion G(·) iff F (x) ≤ G(x)∀x.
Example
In the following figure, the distribution F dominates the distribution G by the criterion of first order stochastic
dominance.
1
0.8
0.6
G(x) F(x)
0.4
0.2
0
0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8
Remark 2 Let x have the cdf F , and y have the cdf G. Suppose F >F SD G. Then
x=y+α
Remark 3 A >F SD B implies E[A] > E[B], but E[A] > E[B] does not imply A >F SD B.
Exercise 6.
Consider the following outcomes
State 1 2 3
1 1 1
probability 3 3 3
Asset A 10 5 20
B 15 10 20
C 10 20 5
1. Using the concept of dominance, can you rank some of these assets?
2. Using the concept of (first order) stochastic dominance, is it possible to choose one of these assets?
10
Notation: F >SSD G
Proposition 6 F >SSD G if Z x Z x
G(t)dt ≥ F (t)dt ∀ x
−∞ −∞
Example
In the following picture, the distribution F dominates the distribution G according to the criterion of second
order stochastic dominance.
1
0.8
0.6
G(x) F(x)
0.4
0.2
0
0 2 4 6 8 10
x
Remark 4 Let x ∼ f and y ∼ g. If x >SSD y then we can write y = x + ϵ, where E[ϵ|x] = 0. The random
variable y is called a mean preserving spread of x.
Example
As another illustration of second order stochastic dominance, consider the distrubution G, which has the
dotted lines in the figure, and F with straight lines. F >SSD G.
1
A2
0.8
0.6
G(x)
0.4 F(x)
0.2
A1
0
0 5 10 15 20
x
Proposition 7 If y is a mean preserving spread of x, then x is preferred to y by all concave utility functions
u(·).
13 Further reading
Mas-Colell et al. (1995)
11
References
Jack Hirshleifer and John G Riley. The analytics of Uncertainty and Information. Cambridge University Press, 1992.
Chi-fu Huang and Robert H Litzenberger. Foundations for financial economics. North–Holland, 1988.
Mark Machina. Choice under uncertainty: Problems solved and unsolved. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 1:121–54, Summer
1987.
Mark J Machina. Dynamic consistency and non–expected utility models of choice under uncertainty. Journal of Economic
Literature, 27:1622–1668, December 1989.
A Mas-Colell, Whinston, and Green. MicroEconomic Theory. Oxford University Press, 1995.
12