0% found this document useful (0 votes)
15 views11 pages

Interpretation (Logic)

Uploaded by

joeylee1110
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
15 views11 pages

Interpretation (Logic)

Uploaded by

joeylee1110
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 11

Interpretation (logic) - Wikipedia https://en.wikipedia.

org/wiki/Interpretation_(logic)

Interpretation (logic)
An interpretation is an assignment of meaning to the symbols of a formal language. Many
formal languages used in mathematics, logic, and theoretical computer science are defined in solely
syntactic terms, and as such do not have any meaning until they are given some interpretation. The
general study of interpretations of formal languages is called formal semantics.

The most commonly studied formal logics are propositional logic, predicate logic and their modal
analogs, and for these there are standard ways of presenting an interpretation. In these contexts an
interpretation is a function that provides the extension of symbols and strings of symbols of an
object language. For example, an interpretation function could take the predicate T (for "tall") and
assign it the extension {a} (for "Abraham Lincoln"). All our interpretation does is assign the
extension {a} to the non-logical constant T, and does not make a claim about whether T is to stand
for tall and 'a' for Abraham Lincoln. Nor does logical interpretation have anything to say about
logical connectives like 'and', 'or' and 'not'. Though we may take these symbols to stand for certain
things or concepts, this is not determined by the interpretation function.

An interpretation often (but not always) provides a way to determine the truth values of sentences
in a language. If a given interpretation assigns the value True to a sentence or theory, the
interpretation is called a model of that sentence or theory.

Formal languages
A formal language consists of a possibly infinite set of sentences (variously called words or
formulas) built from a fixed set of letters or symbols. The inventory from which these letters are
taken is called the alphabet over which the language is defined. To distinguish the strings of
symbols that are in a formal language from arbitrary strings of symbols, the former are sometimes
called well-formed formulæ (wff). The essential feature of a formal language is that its syntax can
be defined without reference to interpretation. For example, we can determine that (P or Q) is a
well-formed formula even without knowing whether it is true or false.

Example
A formal language can be defined with the alphabet , and with a word being in if
it begins with and is composed solely of the symbols and .

A possible interpretation of could assign the decimal digit '1' to and '0' to . Then
would denote 101 under this interpretation of .

1 of 11 9/1/2025, 11:41 am
Interpretation (logic) - Wikipedia https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Interpretation_(logic)

Logical constants
In the specific cases of propositional logic and predicate logic, the formal languages considered
have alphabets that are divided into two sets: the logical symbols (logical constants) and the non-
logical symbols. The idea behind this terminology is that logical symbols have the same meaning
regardless of the subject matter being studied, while non-logical symbols change in meaning
depending on the area of investigation.

Logical constants are always given the same meaning by every interpretation of the standard kind,
so that only the meanings of the non-logical symbols are changed. Logical constants include
quantifier symbols ∀ ("all") and ∃ ("some"), symbols for logical connectives ∧ ("and"), ∨ ("or"), ¬
("not"), parentheses and other grouping symbols, and (in many treatments) the equality symbol =.

General properties of truth-functional interpretations


Many of the commonly studied interpretations associate each sentence in a formal language with a
single truth value, either True or False. These interpretations are called truth functional; they
include the usual interpretations of propositional and first-order logic. The sentences that are
made true by a particular assignment are said to be satisfied by that assignment.

In classical logic, no sentence can be made both true and false by the same interpretation, although
this is not true of glut logics such as LP.[1] Even in classical logic, however, it is possible that the
truth value of the same sentence can be different under different interpretations. A sentence is
consistent if it is true under at least one interpretation; otherwise it is inconsistent. A sentence φ is
said to be logically valid if it is satisfied by every interpretation (if φ is satisfied by every
interpretation that satisfies ψ then φ is said to be a logical consequence of ψ).

Logical connectives
Some of the logical symbols of a language (other than quantifiers) are truth-functional connectives
that represent truth functions — functions that take truth values as arguments and return truth
values as outputs (in other words, these are operations on truth values of sentences).

The truth-functional connectives enable compound sentences to be built up from simpler


sentences. In this way, the truth value of the compound sentence is defined as a certain truth
function of the truth values of the simpler sentences. The connectives are usually taken to be logical
constants, meaning that the meaning of the connectives is always the same, independent of what
interpretations are given to the other symbols in a formula.

This is how we define logical connectives in propositional logic:

¬Φ is True iff Φ is False.


(Φ ∧ Ψ) is True iff Φ is True and Ψ is True.
(Φ ∨ Ψ) is True iff Φ is True or Ψ is True (or both are True).
(Φ → Ψ) is True iff ¬Φ is True or Ψ is True (or both are True).

2 of 11 9/1/2025, 11:41 am
Interpretation (logic) - Wikipedia https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Interpretation_(logic)

(Φ ↔ Ψ) is True iff (Φ → Ψ) is True and (Ψ → Φ) is True.


So under a given interpretation of all the sentence letters Φ and Ψ (i.e., after assigning a truth-
value to each sentence letter), we can determine the truth-values of all formulas that have them as
constituents, as a function of the logical connectives. The following table shows how this kind of
thing looks. The first two columns show the truth-values of the sentence letters as determined by
the four possible interpretations. The other columns show the truth-values of formulas built from
these sentence letters, with truth-values determined recursively.

Logical connectives

Interpretation Φ Ψ ¬Φ (Φ ∧ Ψ) (Φ ∨ Ψ) (Φ → Ψ) (Φ ↔ Ψ)

#1 T T F T T T T

#2 T F F F T F F

#3 F T T F T T F

#4 F F T F F T T

Now it is easier to see what makes a formula logically valid. Take the formula F: (Φ ∨ ¬Φ). If our
interpretation function makes Φ True, then ¬Φ is made False by the negation connective. Since the
disjunct Φ of F is True under that interpretation, F is True. Now the only other possible
interpretation of Φ makes it False, and if so, ¬Φ is made True by the negation function. That would
make F True again, since one of Fs disjuncts, ¬Φ, would be true under this interpretation. Since
these two interpretations for F are the only possible logical interpretations, and since F comes out
True for both, we say that it is logically valid or tautologous.

Interpretation of a theory
An interpretation of a theory is the relationship between a theory and some subject matter when
there is a many-to-one correspondence between certain elementary statements of the theory, and
certain statements related to the subject matter. If every elementary statement in the theory has a
correspondent it is called a full interpretation, otherwise it is called a partial interpretation.[2]

Interpretations for propositional logic


The formal language for propositional logic consists of formulas built up from propositional
symbols (also called sentential symbols, sentential variables, propositional variables) and logical
connectives. The only non-logical symbols in a formal language for propositional logic are the
propositional symbols, which are often denoted by capital letters. To make the formal language
precise, a specific set of propositional symbols must be fixed.

The standard kind of interpretation in this setting is a function that maps each propositional
symbol to one of the truth values true and false. This function is known as a truth assignment or
valuation function. In many presentations, it is literally a truth value that is assigned, but some

3 of 11 9/1/2025, 11:41 am
Interpretation (logic) - Wikipedia https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Interpretation_(logic)

presentations assign truthbearers instead.

For a language with n distinct propositional variables there are 2n distinct possible interpretations.
For any particular variable a, for example, there are 21=2 possible interpretations: 1) a is assigned
T, or 2) a is assigned F. For the pair a, b there are 22=4 possible interpretations: 1) both are
assigned T, 2) both are assigned F, 3) a is assigned T and b is assigned F, or 4) a is assigned F and
b is assigned T.

Given any truth assignment for a set of propositional symbols, there is a unique extension to an
interpretation for all the propositional formulas built up from those variables. This extended
interpretation is defined inductively, using the truth-table definitions of the logical connectives
discussed above.

First-order logic
Unlike propositional logic, where every language is the same apart from a choice of a different set
of propositional variables, there are many different first-order languages. Each first-order language
is defined by a signature. The signature consists of a set of non-logical symbols and an
identification of each of these symbols as either a constant symbol, a function symbol, or a
predicate symbol. In the case of function and predicate symbols, a natural number arity is also
assigned. The alphabet for the formal language consists of logical constants, the equality relation
symbol =, all the symbols from the signature, and an additional infinite set of symbols known as
variables.

For example, in the language of rings, there are constant symbols 0 and 1, two binary function
symbols + and ·, and no binary relation symbols. (Here the equality relation is taken as a logical
constant.)

Again, we might define a first-order language L, as consisting of individual symbols a, b, and c;


predicate symbols F, G, H, I and J; variables x, y, z; no function letters; no sentential symbols.

Formal languages for first-order logic


Given a signature σ, the corresponding formal language is known as the set of σ-formulas. Each σ-
formula is built up out of atomic formulas by means of logical connectives; atomic formulas are
built from terms using predicate symbols. The formal definition of the set of σ-formulas proceeds
in the other direction: first, terms are assembled from the constant and function symbols together
with the variables. Then, terms can be combined into an atomic formula using a predicate symbol
(relation symbol) from the signature or the special predicate symbol "=" for equality (see the
section "Interpreting equality" below). Finally, the formulas of the language are assembled from
atomic formulas using the logical connectives and quantifiers.

Interpretations of a first-order language


To ascribe meaning to all sentences of a first-order language, the following information is needed.

4 of 11 9/1/2025, 11:41 am
Interpretation (logic) - Wikipedia https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Interpretation_(logic)

A domain of discourse[a] D, usually required to be non-empty (see below).


For every constant symbol, an element of D as its interpretation.
For every n-ary function symbol, an n-ary function from D to D as its interpretation (that is, a
function Dn → D).
For every n-ary predicate symbol, an n-ary relation on D as its interpretation (that is, a subset
of Dn).
An object carrying this information is known as a structure (of signature σ), or σ-structure, or L-
structure (of language L), or as a "model".

The information specified in the interpretation provides enough information to give a truth value
to any atomic formula, after each of its free variables, if any, has been replaced by an element of the
domain. The truth value of an arbitrary sentence is then defined inductively using the T-schema,
which is a definition of first-order semantics developed by Alfred Tarski. The T-schema interprets
the logical connectives using truth tables, as discussed above. Thus, for example, φ ∧ ψ is satisfied
if and only if both φ and ψ are satisfied.

This leaves the issue of how to interpret formulas of the form ∀ x φ(x) and ∃ x φ(x). The domain of
discourse forms the range for these quantifiers. The idea is that the sentence ∀ x φ(x) is true under
an interpretation exactly when every substitution instance of φ(x), where x is replaced by some
element of the domain, is satisfied. The formula ∃ x φ(x) is satisfied if there is at least one element
d of the domain such that φ(d) is satisfied.

Strictly speaking, a substitution instance such as the formula φ(d) mentioned above is not a
formula in the original formal language of φ, because d is an element of the domain. There are two
ways of handling this technical issue. The first is to pass to a larger language in which each element
of the domain is named by a constant symbol. The second is to add to the interpretation a function
that assigns each variable to an element of the domain. Then the T-schema can quantify over
variations of the original interpretation in which this variable assignment function is changed,
instead of quantifying over substitution instances.

Some authors also admit propositional variables in first-order logic, which must then also be
interpreted. A propositional variable can stand on its own as an atomic formula. The interpretation
of a propositional variable is one of the two truth values true and false.[3]

Because the first-order interpretations described here are defined in set theory, they do not
associate each predicate symbol with a property[b] (or relation), but rather with the extension of
that property (or relation). In other words, these first-order interpretations are extensional[c] not
intensional.

Example of a first-order interpretation


An example of interpretation of the language L described above is as follows.

Domain: A chess set


Individual constants: a: The white King, b: The black Queen, c: The white King's pawn

5 of 11 9/1/2025, 11:41 am
Interpretation (logic) - Wikipedia https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Interpretation_(logic)

F(x): x is a piece
G(x): x is a pawn
H(x): x is black
I(x): x is white
J(x, y): x can capture y
In the interpretation of L:

the following are true sentences: F(a), G(c), H(b), I(a), J(b, c),
the following are false sentences: J(a, c), G(a).

Non-empty domain requirement


As stated above, a first-order interpretation is usually required to specify a nonempty set as the
domain of discourse. The reason for this requirement is to guarantee that equivalences such as

where x is not a free variable of φ, are logically valid. This equivalence holds in every interpretation
with a nonempty domain, but does not always hold when empty domains are permitted. For
example, the equivalence

fails in any structure with an empty domain. Thus the proof theory of first-order logic becomes
more complicated when empty structures are permitted. However, the gain in allowing them is
negligible, as both the intended interpretations and the interesting interpretations of the theories
people study have non-empty domains.[4][5]

Empty relations do not cause any problem for first-order interpretations, because there is no
similar notion of passing a relation symbol across a logical connective, enlarging its scope in the
process. Thus it is acceptable for relation symbols to be interpreted as being identically false.
However, the interpretation of a function symbol must always assign a well-defined and total
function to the symbol.

Interpreting equality
The equality relation is often treated specially in first order logic and other predicate logics. There
are two general approaches.

The first approach is to treat equality as no different than any other binary relation. In this case, if
an equality symbol is included in the signature, it is usually necessary to add various axioms about
equality to axiom systems (for example, the substitution axiom saying that if a = b and R(a) holds
then R(b) holds as well). This approach to equality is most useful when studying signatures that do
not include the equality relation, such as the signature for set theory or the signature for second-
order arithmetic in which there is only an equality relation for numbers, but not an equality
relation for set of numbers.

6 of 11 9/1/2025, 11:41 am
Interpretation (logic) - Wikipedia https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Interpretation_(logic)

The second approach is to treat the equality relation symbol as a logical constant that must be
interpreted by the real equality relation in any interpretation. An interpretation that interprets
equality this way is known as a normal model, so this second approach is the same as only studying
interpretations that happen to be normal models. The advantage of this approach is that the
axioms related to equality are automatically satisfied by every normal model, and so they do not
need to be explicitly included in first-order theories when equality is treated this way. This second
approach is sometimes called first order logic with equality, but many authors adopt it for the
general study of first-order logic without comment.

There are a few other reasons to restrict study of first-order logic to normal models. First, it is
known that any first-order interpretation in which equality is interpreted by an equivalence
relation and satisfies the substitution axioms for equality can be cut down to an elementarily
equivalent interpretation on a subset of the original domain. Thus there is little additional
generality in studying non-normal models. Second, if non-normal models are considered, then
every consistent theory has an infinite model; this affects the statements of results such as the
Löwenheim–Skolem theorem, which are usually stated under the assumption that only normal
models are considered.

Many-sorted first-order logic


A generalization of first order logic considers languages with more than one sort of variables. The
idea is different sorts of variables represent different types of objects. Every sort of variable can be
quantified; thus an interpretation for a many-sorted language has a separate domain for each of
the sorts of variables to range over (there is an infinite collection of variables of each of the
different sorts). Function and relation symbols, in addition to having arities, are specified so that
each of their arguments must come from a certain sort.

One example of many-sorted logic is for planar Euclidean geometry. There are two sorts; points
and lines. There is an equality relation symbol for points, an equality relation symbol for lines, and
a binary incidence relation E which takes one point variable and one line variable. The intended
interpretation of this language has the point variables range over all points on the Euclidean plane,
the line variable range over all lines on the plane, and the incidence relation E(p,l) holds if and only
if point p is on line l.

Higher-order predicate logics


A formal language for higher-order predicate logic looks much the same as a formal language for
first-order logic. The difference is that there are now many different types of variables. Some
variables correspond to elements of the domain, as in first-order logic. Other variables correspond
to objects of higher type: subsets of the domain, functions from the domain, functions that take a
subset of the domain and return a function from the domain to subsets of the domain, etc. All of
these types of variables can be quantified.

There are two kinds of interpretations commonly employed for higher-order logic. Full semantics

7 of 11 9/1/2025, 11:41 am
Interpretation (logic) - Wikipedia https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Interpretation_(logic)

require that, once the domain of discourse is satisfied, the higher-order variables range over all
possible elements of the correct type (all subsets of the domain, all functions from the domain to
itself, etc.). Thus the specification of a full interpretation is the same as the specification of a first-
order interpretation. Henkin semantics, which are essentially multi-sorted first-order semantics,
require the interpretation to specify a separate domain for each type of higher-order variable to
range over. Thus an interpretation in Henkin semantics includes a domain D, a collection of
subsets of D, a collection of functions from D to D, etc. The relationship between these two
semantics is an important topic in higher order logic.

Non-classical interpretations
The interpretations of propositional logic and predicate logic described above are not the only
possible interpretations. In particular, there are other types of interpretations that are used in the
study of non-classical logic (such as intuitionistic logic), and in the study of modal logic.

Interpretations used to study non-classical logic include topological models, Boolean-valued


models, and Kripke models. Modal logic is also studied using Kripke models.

Intended interpretations
Many formal languages are associated with a particular interpretation that is used to motivate
them. For example, the first-order signature for set theory includes only one binary relation, ∈,
which is intended to represent set membership, and the domain of discourse in a first-order theory
of the natural numbers is intended to be the set of natural numbers.

The intended interpretation is called the standard model (a term introduced by Abraham
Robinson in 1960).[6] In the context of Peano arithmetic, it consists of the natural numbers with
their ordinary arithmetical operations. All models that are isomorphic to the one just given are also
called standard; these models all satisfy the Peano axioms. There are also non-standard models of
the (first-order version of the) Peano axioms, which contain elements not correlated with any
natural number.

While the intended interpretation can have no explicit indication in the strictly formal syntactical
rules, it naturally affects the choice of the formation and transformation rules of the syntactical
system. For example, primitive signs must permit expression of the concepts to be modeled;
sentential formulas are chosen so that their counterparts in the intended interpretation are
meaningful declarative sentences; primitive sentences need to come out as true sentences in the
interpretation; rules of inference must be such that, if the sentence is directly derivable from a
sentence , then turns out to be a true sentence, with meaning implication, as usual.
These requirements ensure that all provable sentences also come out to be true.[7]

Most formal systems have many more models than they were intended to have (the existence of
non-standard models is an example). When we speak about 'models' in empirical sciences, we

8 of 11 9/1/2025, 11:41 am
Interpretation (logic) - Wikipedia https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Interpretation_(logic)

mean, if we want reality to be a model of our science, to speak about an intended model. A model in
the empirical sciences is an intended factually-true descriptive interpretation (or in other
contexts: a non-intended arbitrary interpretation used to clarify such an intended factually-true
descriptive interpretation.) All models are interpretations that have the same domain of discourse
as the intended one, but other assignments for non-logical constants.[8]

Example
Given a simple formal system (we shall call this one ) whose alphabet α consists only of three
symbols and whose formation rule for formulas is:

'Any string of symbols of which is at least 6 symbols long, and which is not infinitely
long, is a formula of . Nothing else is a formula of .'

The single axiom schema of is:

" " (where " " is a metasyntactic variable standing for a finite string of " "s )

A formal proof can be constructed as follows:

1.
2.
3.
In this example the theorem produced " " can be interpreted as meaning
"One plus three equals four." A different interpretation would be to read it backwards as "Four
minus three equals one."[9]

Other concepts of interpretation


There are other uses of the term "interpretation" that are commonly used, which do not refer to the
assignment of meanings to formal languages.

In model theory, a structure A is said to interpret a structure B if there is a definable subset D of A,


and definable relations and functions on D, such that B is isomorphic to the structure with domain
D and these functions and relations. In some settings, it is not the domain D that is used, but rather
D modulo an equivalence relation definable in A. For additional information, see Interpretation
(model theory).

A theory T is said to interpret another theory S if there is a finite extension by definitions T′ of T


such that S is contained in T′.

See also
Conceptual model

9 of 11 9/1/2025, 11:41 am
Interpretation (logic) - Wikipedia https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Interpretation_(logic)

Free variables and Name binding


Formal semantics (natural language)
Herbrand interpretation
Interpretation (model theory)
Logical system
Löwenheim–Skolem theorem
Modal logic
Model theory
Satisfiable
Truth

Notes
a. Sometimes called the "universe of discourse"
b. The extension of a property (also called an attribute) is a set of individuals, so a property is a
unary relation. E.g. The properties "yellow" and "prime" are unary relations.
c. See also Extension (predicate logic)

References
1. Priest, Graham, 2008. An Introduction to Non-Classical Logic: from If to Is, 2nd ed. Cambridge
University Press.
2. Haskell Curry (1963). Foundations of Mathematical Logic (https://archive.org/details/foundation
sofmat0000unse_o5q2). Mcgraw Hill. p. 48.
3. Mates, Benson (1972), Elementary Logic, Second Edition (https://archive.org/details/elementar
ylogic00mate/page/56), New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 56 (https://archive.org/details/el
ementarylogic00mate/page/56), ISBN 0-19-501491-X
4. Hailperin, Theodore (1953), "Quantification theory and empty individual-domains", The Journal
of Symbolic Logic, 18 (3), Association for Symbolic Logic: 197–200, doi:10.2307/2267402 (http
s://doi.org/10.2307%2F2267402), JSTOR 2267402 (https://www.jstor.org/stable/2267402),
MR 0057820 (https://mathscinet.ams.org/mathscinet-getitem?mr=0057820), S2CID 40988137
(https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:40988137)
5. Quine, W. V. (1954), "Quantification and the empty domain", The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 19
(3), Association for Symbolic Logic: 177–179, doi:10.2307/2268615 (https://doi.org/10.2307%2
F2268615), JSTOR 2268615 (https://www.jstor.org/stable/2268615), MR 0064715 (https://math
scinet.ams.org/mathscinet-getitem?mr=0064715), S2CID 27053902 (https://api.semanticschola
r.org/CorpusID:27053902)
6. Roland Müller (2009). "The Notion of a Model". In Anthonie Meijers (ed.). Philosophy of
technology and engineering sciences. Handbook of the Philosophy of Science. Vol. 9. Elsevier.
ISBN 978-0-444-51667-1.
7. Rudolf Carnap (1958). Introduction to Symbolic Logic and its Applications (https://archive.org/d
etails/introductiontosy00carn). New York: Dover publications. ISBN 9780486604534.
8. Hans Freudenthal, ed. (Jan 1960). The Concept and the Role of the Model in Mathematics and
Natural and Social Sciences (Colloquium proceedings). Springer. ISBN 978-94-010-3669-6.

10 of 11 9/1/2025, 11:41 am
Interpretation (logic) - Wikipedia https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Interpretation_(logic)

9. Hunter, Geoffrey (1996) [1971]. Metalogic: An Introduction to the Metatheory of Standard First-
Order Logic. University of California Press (published 1973). ISBN 9780520023567.
OCLC 36312727 (https://search.worldcat.org/oclc/36312727). (accessible to patrons with print
disabilities (https://archive.org/details/metalogicintrodu0000hunt))

External links
Stanford Enc. Phil: Classical Logic, 4. Semantics (http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logic-classic
al/#4)
Sakharov, Alex. "Formal Language" (https://mathworld.wolfram.com/formallanguage.html).
MathWorld.
Weisstein, Eric W. "Connective" (https://mathworld.wolfram.com/Connective.html). MathWorld.
Sakharov, Alex. "Interpretation" (https://mathworld.wolfram.com/interpretation.html).
MathWorld.
Sakharov, Alex. "Propositional Calculus" (https://mathworld.wolfram.com/PropositionalCalculu
s.html). MathWorld.
Sakharov, Alex. "First Order Logic" (https://mathworld.wolfram.com/First-OrderLogic.html).
MathWorld.

Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Interpretation_(logic)&oldid=1267476322"

11 of 11 9/1/2025, 11:41 am

You might also like