Hacking, Ian - Strange Expectations (1980)
Hacking, Ian - Strange Expectations (1980)
IAN HACKING
Stanford University
562
If you call high, i.e. wager that x > 0, and you are right, you
win 3x dollars, but if you are wrong you lose 5(3X). If you call
low and are right, you win 5(3X) dollars, but if you are wrong,
you lose 3X
Possible outcomes may be partitioned either in terms of values of
x or in terms of values of 0. Now for each 0, the expectation of
calling high is 2(3?8-) dollars, while the expectation of calling low
is minus that amount. In short, for every value of 0 the expectation
of strategy H-call 'high'-dominates strategy L-call 'low'.
Yet for every value of x, L dominates H! For x = 0, the expectation
of calling low is $2. If x > 0, the expectation is 3X/5 dollars, while
, E(U/O) = $9.46
E(U) = $9.46; we could infer that only after proving that E(U)
exists.
Some people, to whom I have propounded this puzzle, are inclined
to say that the mistaken party is not the house but my body of
gamblers, each of whom believes he has positive expectations. The
reasoning is that if we look at the fortunes of the gamblers as a
whole, we shall see that they lose money by their strategy of calling
'low'. This can mean two different things: (a) the mathematical
expectation of a set of gamblers who call 'high'-or equivalently
of the house, when gamblers call 'low'-is positive. Or it can mean
something like (b) a large number of gamblers, calling 'high' will
in fact make an average profit on the stated terms, or, equivalently,
if gamblers call 'low' the house will on average make a profit. Now
(a) is just a mistake, the fallacy of summing expectations stated in
the previous paragraph. But I too am among those who believe (b),
although I am hard pressed to say exactly what I believe.
How can I believe (b)-that averaging the result of a lot of gamblers
calling 'low' will give a net loss per gambler-and still think that
each gambler on his own should call 'low'?
My answer is that this example seems to bring out a quite different
point, namely the difference between gambling in a unique case, and
gambling in repeated trials. Let us describe yet another offer that
the house might contemplate. It will allow for syndicates to play
against it. Like an individual, a syndicate writes off to obtain its
0. Then members of the syndicate arrive. The first member is allowed
to see his value of x, to decide whether to commit the syndicate;
he then commits the syndicate or drops out, on behalf of all his
colleagues. He calls high or low, and so does each member of the
even though this is not the policy which would maximize average
mathematical utility for a lot of similar investigators.
REFERENCES
Enis, P. (1973), "On the Relation E(X) = E(E(X/ Y))," Biometrika 60: 432-3.
Lindley, D. V. (1971), Bayesian Statistics, A Review. Pittsburgh: SIAM.