Foucault, Michel - Dream, Imagination, and Existence (1954)
Foucault, Michel - Dream, Imagination, and Existence (1954)
Foucault, Michel - Dream, Imagination, and Existence (1954)
EXistential
Psychology &
Psychiatry
EDITOR'S FOREWORD . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 7
Keith Hoeller
TRANSLATOR'S PREFACE. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .. 19
Forrest Williams
CONTRIBUTORS . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 107
Preparation of this book was aided by a grant from the Publications
Program of the National Endowmentfor the Humanities, an independent
federal agency.
I belong to that generation who as students had before their eyes, and
were limited by, a horizon consisting of Marxism, phenomenology, and
existentialism . . . at the time I was working on my book about the history
of madness [Madness & Civilization]. I was divided between existential
psychology and phenomenology, and my research was an attempt to
discover the extent these could be defined in historical terms. 1
Michel Foucault
September, 1984
7
8 Keith Hoeller
When I was studying during the early 1950's, one of the great problems
that arose was that of the political status of science and the ideological
functions which it could serve .... These [problems) can all be summed
up in two words: power and knowledge. I believe I wrote Madness &
Civilization to some extent within the horizon of these questions. 10
These questions of power and knowledge, and the political status of psy-
chiatry as a science, are all questions which Foucault shares in common
with the existential psychiatrists and with Szasz. However, Madness and
Civilization, Foucault's doctoral thesis, does not explicitly invoke existen-
tialism and phenomenology, and certainly does not abound with references
to Kierkegaard, Husserl, Heidegger, Merleau-Ponty, and Sartre. One finds
only passing reference to the German poet, Friedrich Holderlin, about
whom Heidegger has written so much, and to Nietzsche. This is in spite
of the fact that, as Foucault himself has admitted in the interview cited
at the beginning of this Foreword, he was steeped in the tradition of
existentialism and phenomenology. II This is even more surprising when
EDITOR'S FOREWORD 9
This book, which was originally published in 1954, and which was
Nuhstantially revised for a second edition in 1962, concludes with a second
part. In this second part, published in 1962, Foucault explicitly states the
results of Madness and Civilization, and indeed the words express a con-
clusion in agreement with Szasz' work, The Myth of Mental Illness: 16
In other words, "mental illness" is not in fact an "illness" like any other;
rather, it is a relation between self and other:
The titles of the two parts of the 1962 version of Menta/Illness and
Psychology bear out the evolution in Foucault's viewpoint from 1954 to
1961. The first part (1954), in which phenomenological psychology is
put to work, is entitled "The Psychological Dimensions of Mental Illness,"
while the second part (1962) is called "Madness and Culture." The move-
ment is one from a concentration on the world of the individual subject,
on the history of the individual, to a focus on the subject's relation to
society and the relation between madness and civilization historically. In
other words, one cannot study the individual's history alone and reach
any valid conclusions. One must situate the individual historically and
societally:
In fact, it is only in history that one can discover the sole concrete a
priori from which mental illness draws, with the empty opening up of
its possibility, its necessary figures. 19
Thus the need for an historical account of madness such as Madness and
Civilization.
In the 1984 interview in which Foucault indicates his being tom
between existential psychology and phenomenology while writing Mad-
ness and Civilization, he says "my research was an attempt to discover
the extent these could be defined in historical terms. "20 He goes on to
immediately say, "That's when I discovered that the subject would have
to be defined in other terms than Marxism or phenomenology. "21 All of
this would seem to indicate that in Foucault's discovery of the importance
of history, he felt that phenomenology concentrated on the individual
subject and could not lead him over to a historical determination of the
role of madness, which would explain why Madness and Civilization does
not explicitly invoke phenomenology or the phenomenologists. That
Foucault holds this view of phenomenology is further confirmed by a
1977 interview on 'Truth and Power," where he says:
De Man goes on to say that Binswanger is most at home with the description
of individual clinical cases, and even his more general attempts to outline
such ontological dimensions as "falling" remain less substantial than, for
example, Heidegger's discussions. This shows itself especially in cases
involving artists and the role of the imagination:
This could very well have been written with Binswanger in mind, but it
does not apply to either Husser! or Heidegger, both of whom include this
very danger among the constituents of their philosophical insight. Foucault
himself owes his awareness of the problem to his grounding in
phenomenology.28
*
On its own terms, Binswanger's essay "Dream and Existence" is a
groundbreaking work in existential psychiatry. Published three years after
Heidegger's Being and Time, its very first paragraph raises three concepts
central to Heidegger's major work: existence, world, and Dasein. The
focus on existence clearly places the piece within the existential tradition
from Kierkegaard onward. The quote from Kierkegaard at the beginning
of the essay makes this explicit: "Above all, we must keep in mind what
it means to be a human being.")' The quotation is from the important
section in the Concluding Unscientific Postscript: "The Subjective Truth,
Inwardness; Truth is Subjectivity." Arguing against a Hegelian view of
truth as objective and rational, Kierkegaard relates knowledge back to the
existing individual:
14 Keith Hoeller
The individual's images, his feelings, his mood belong to him alone, he
lives completely in his own world; and being completely alone means,
psychologically speaking, dreaming."
Thus, to get at the truth of the individual, means surpassing Hegel, "As
EDITOR'S FOREWORD 15
*
The Review of Existential Psychology & Psychiatry is extremely
proud to be able to present the first English translation of Michel Foucault's
very first published work, "Dream, Imagination, and Existence," together
with the English translation of Ludwig Binswanger's pioneer essay in
existential psychiatry, "Dream and Existence." It is our hope that the
publication of this work, which has long been out of print and virtually
unobtainable even in France, will help to shed new light on the formative
years of Foucault's thought. It also serves as the occasion for focusing
once more on Binswanger's pathbreaking analyses.
In bringing this special publication to fruition, the Review acknowl-
edges its gratitude to many people. First, we would like to thank Michel
Foucault himself for graciously granting permission for us to publish this
English translation of his work, and allowing us to make this period of
his work available to the English-speaking public. Second, we extend our
thanks to Margot Backas and the Publications Program of the National
Endowment for the Humanities for assistance in the form of a grant to
aid in publication of this special issue. We also thank Jacob Needleman
for kindly allowing us to print his translation of Binswanger's essay. And
we heartily thank Forrest Williams forrendering Foucault's difficult French
into excellent English, and providing an illuminating Preface as well.
16 Keith Hoeller
NOTES
Michel Foucault, Death and the Labyrinth: The World of Raymond Roussel, trans.
Charles Ruas (Garden City: Doubleday & Co., 1986), p. 174.
2 Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, trans. John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson
(New York: Harper & Row, 1962).
3 Ludwig Binswanger, "Dream and Existence," trans. Jacob Needleman, Review ofExis-
tential Psychology & Psychiatry, Vol. XIX, no. I (1984-85). Also in Being-in-the-
World: Selected Papers of Ludwig Binswanger, ed. and trans. Jacob Needleman (Lon-
don: Souvenir Press, 1975).
4 Foucault, Madness and Civilization: A History of Insanity in the Age of Reason, trans.
Richard Howard (New York: Random House, 1965).
5 Thomas Szasz, The Myth of Mental Illness: Foundations of a Theory of Personal
Conduct (New York: Harper & Row, 1961).
6 R. D. Laing, Self and Others (New York: Random House, 1961).
7 David Cooper, "Introduction" to Madness and Civilization (London: Tavistock, 1961),
p. viii.
8 Foucault, Madness and Civilization, pp. ix-xi.
9 Foucault, "Two Lectures," in Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews and Other Writings
1972-77, ed. Colin Gordon (New York: Random House, 1980), p. 83.
10 Foucault, "Truth and Power," in Power/Knowledge, p. 109.
II See also Hubert L. Dreyfus and Paul Rabinow, Michel Foucault: Beyond Structuralism
and Hermeneutics (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1982), pp. xvii-xxvii.
12 Alan Sheridan, Michel Foucault: The Will to Truth (New York: Tavistock, 1980).
I3 Dreyfus and Rabinow, Michel Foucault.
14 Foucault, "Dream, Imagination, and Existence," trans. Forrest Williams, Review of
Existential Psychology & Psychiatry, Vol. XIX, no. I (1984-85); Mental Illness and
Psychology, trans. Alan Sheridan (New York: Harper & Row, 1976; reprinted by
University of California Press, 1987, forthcoming).
15 Foucault, Mental Illness and Psychology, p. 46.
16 Szasz, The Myth of Mental Illness.
17 Foucault, Mental Illness and Psychology, pp. 60 and 63.
18 Ibid., pp. 78-79 and 86.
19 Ibid., pp. 84-85.
20 Foucault, Death and the Labyrinth, p. 174.
21 Ibid.,pp. 174-75.
22 Foucault, Power/Knowledge, p. 117.
23 Edmund Husser!, Phenomenological Psychology, trans. John Scanlon (The Hague:
Martinus Nijhoff, 1977), pp. 178-79.
24 Ibid., p. 170.
25 Paul de Man, Blindness and Insight (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press,
1983 2), p. 48.
26 Ibid., pp. 48 and 49.
27 Ibid., p. 49; Foucault, The Order of Things (New York: Random House, 1970), pp.
325-26. The translation cited is by de Man.
28 Ibid., p. 49.
29 Ibid.
30 Herbert Spiegelberg, Phenomenology in Psychology and Psychiatry (Evanston: North-
western University Press, 1972), p. 204.
EDITOR'S FOREWORD 17
The title "Dream, Imagination and Existence" has been added, but
not arbitrarily, to this translation of the late Michel Foucault's "Introduc-
tion," published in 1954, to Ludwig Binswanger's essay, "Dream and
Existence" (Traum und Existenz; Le reve et l' existence). The nature of
the essay as a whole, as well as the added title, were to have been subjects
of discussion with Michel Foucault in Paris in July, 1984, at which time,
as he had graciously expressed it in a letter a few months earlier, we were
to "continuer cette conversation" begun the previous year during a visit
to the University of Colorado. His sudden death on June 25, 1984, when
he was only fifty-seven, occurred in a particularly prolific period of a
brilliant intellectual career. His works were (and are) in bookstores
everywhere in France and abroad. His newest writings were being trans-
lated as quickly as possible in a number of languages, generating the
highest expectations for the remaining portions of his large-scale History
of Sexuality.
The title assigned here attempts to specify the main themes of this
early essay. And essay by Michel Foucault, not simply introduction to
Ludwig Binswanger, it was. Almost twice the length of the work in clinical
psychology it preceded, it stood as an independent piece of thought.
Indeed, it specifically disclaimed being a mere explication (ad usum
delphinum, as Foucault put it) of "Dream and Existence."
One of two pieces by the 28-year-old French thinker to appear in
1954, it was most likely the earlier of the pair, preceding his first book,
Mental Illness and Psychology (New York: Harper and Row, 1976;
Maladie Mentale et Psychologie, 1954), and therefore was probably his
first extended piece of writing to be published. For so young an author,
Foucault had already engaged in an imposing amount of philosophical
study: figuring in the discussion are Edmund Husserl, Sigmund Freud,
Martin Heidegger, Gaston Bachelard, Jean-Paul Sartre, and of course
Ludwig Binswanger, as well as a variety of observations about dreams
expressed in literature, drama, religion, and philosophies of other times.
In the process of "introducing" the reader to Binswanger's Heideggerean
transformation of Freudian psychoanalysis, Foucault went beyond the
particular clinical concepts of Binswanger toward a more general analysis
of human being, that is, of human being-in-the-world, without thereby
(he insisted) "slipping into a philosophy." He did not wish either to restate
Binswanger's psychology or to restate the philosophy of Being and Time
(Sein und Zeit) presupposed by both Binswanger and himself. Neither
psychotherapeutic theory nor transcendental phenomenology, Foucault's
effort might be thought of as an intermediate essay in the direction of
"existential anthropology," more specific than Heidegger's question of
Being (Seinsfrage), more general then Binswanger's clinical reflections.
19
20 Forrest Williams
once become interesting, not for their pathology alone (however important
that may be), but for their wider revelation of the pre-perceptual structure
of human intentionality and presence to the world. Foucault's essay thus
boldly undercuts the basis of Being and Time and Phenomenology of
Perception. Already the dream "in and by its transcendence ... discloses
the original movement by which existence, in its irreducible solitude,
projects itself toward a world which constitutes itself as the setting of its
history." The dynamic vectors of existence are already discernible in the
dream.
And likewise, the inherent temporality of human existence. Indeed,
one might say that Freudian dream analysis, by concentrating on earlier,
repressed wishes said to be causing dreams, denied the temporality of the
patient as existence. Literary, philosophical, and mystical accounts, even
superstitious beliefs, frequently recognized that the dream is at once an
effect of the past (for example, some past deed), an occurrence in the
present, and an anticipation (e.g., an omen) of the future. Mythological
views and prophecies aside, there was at least in those traditional concep-
tions of the dream an acknowledgment of its temporality and-by impli-
cation-of the temporality of the being of the dreamer.
As an example of the Freudian neglect of the future orientation of
the dream (which is to say, its Freudian detemporalization), Foucault
points to a dream of "Dora," in which Freud had failed to recognize soon
enough the patient's decision, still unknown to herself, to terminate the
psychoanalysis.
One might formulate the issue as follows: Because the classic scien-
tific spirit which animated Freud's thinking characteristically separates
past, present, and future, the psychoanalytic patient's existence is rendered
only abstractly temporal, like an object in the natural sciences. Standing
only in external relations to each other, as mere logical distinctions in a
formal pattern of succession which is abstracted from the concrete
phenomenon of becoming, the so-called "pasts," "presents," and "futures"
of the natural sciences are virtually timeless. This is an entirely appropriate
philosophical (in Heideggerean terms: still ontic) framework for the par-
ticular theoretical purposes of the algorithmic sciences. Only in this time-
less framework does it make sense to speak of causal laws-ideally,
equations with empirical constants. But once conceived in this manner,
as separable, these Pickwickian "pasts," "presents," and "futures" fragment
the phenomenon of time. The so-called "future," for example, is no longer
what is approaching the present, and the present is no longer falling back
into a past. The "future" is already in place, though not yet visible to us,
like the furniture in an adjoining room which we have not yet entered.
Thus, the "grammar" of that "future" which a causal law predicts (more
or less successfully) contains no future tense as such, but only the future
perfect. The "present" event whose "past" causes can be stated, or the
24 Forrest Williams
The work by Michel Foucault translated here from the French appeared originally as
an "Introduction" to the French translation (by Jacqueline Verdeaux) of Ludwig
Binswanger's Traum und Existenz. The latter work was originally published in Neue
Schweizer Rundshau (Ziirich: Fretz u. Wasmuth), v. IX, 1930, and was reprinted in Ludwig
Binswanger, Ausgewiihlte Vortrage und Aufsatze (Bern; A. Francke, 1947, pp. 74-97).
The French volume was entitled Le reve et l' existence, and was published in Paris in 1954
by Editions Desclee De Brouwer in the series Textes el Etudes Anthrop%giqW!s. The
"Introduction" comprised pages 9-128; the text by Binswanger comprised pages 129-193.
28 Forrest Williams
*
The "Translator's Preface" contains some remarks on the occasional use of the special
German term, "Existenz," in the English translation.
*
Translations of passages quoted by Foucault from the works of the French poet, Rene
Char, were most kindly supplied by Mary Ann Caws.
*
Wherever possible, fragmentary footnotes have been completed for the English trans-
lation, and references have been adapted to English-language sources where these exist and
were discoverable. French paragraphing has been modified to conform to American editorial
practice, and some subdividing has been added.
*
I would like to express my appreciation for released time to work on this preface and
translation provided by the Center for Theory in the Humanities of the Uni versity of Colorado
at Boulder.
DREAM, IMAGINATION AND EXISTENCE
MICHEL FOUCAULT
A J'age d'homme, j'ai vu s'elever et grandir sur Ie mur mitoyen
de la vie et de la mort, une echelle de plus en plus nue, investie
d'un pouvoir d'evulsion unique: Ie reve ... Voici que l'obscurite
s'ecarte, et que VIVRE devient sous la forme d'un apre ascetisme
allegorique la conquete des pouvoirs extraordinaires dont nous
nous sentons confusement traverses mais que nous n'exprimons
qu'incompletement faute de loyaute, de discemement cruel et de
perseverance.
When I reached manhood, I saw rising and growing upon the wall
shared between life and death, a ladder barer all the time, invested
with an unique power of evulsion: this was the dream ... Now see
darkness draw away, and LIVING become, in the form of a harsh
allegorical asceticism, the conquest of extraordinary powers by
which we feel ourselves confusedly crossed, but which we only
express incompletely, lacking loyalty, cruel perception, and perse-
verence.
Rene Char, Fureur et Mystere
(Paris: Gallimard, 1984, 2nd
ed.), pp. 82-83 ("Partage For-
mel, XXII"). Translated by
Mary Ann Caws.
Dream, Imagination and Existence*
An Introduction to Ludwig Binswanger's "Dream and Existence"
MICHEL FOUCAULT
31
32 Michel Foucault
*
The theme of this 1930 essay4-the first of the texts of Binswanger
which belong strictly to the analysis of Dasein5-is less dream and exist-
ence than existence as it appears to itself and can be deciphered in the
dream: existence in that mode of being of the dream in which it announces
itself in a meaningful fashion. Is it not a gamble, however, to want to
circumscribe the positive content of Existenz by reference to a mode in
which it is least engaged in the world? If M enschsein does contain meanings
which are peculiar to it, will they reveal themselves in a privileged way
in that dream moment when the network of meanings seems to condense,
where the evidence clouds over, and where the forms of presence are
most blurred?
This paradox constitutes, in our opinion, the major interest of "Dream
and Existence." The privilege of meaning accorded by Binswanger to the
oneiric is doubly important. It defines the concrete progression of the
analysis toward the fundamental forms of existence: dream analysis does
not stop at the level of a hermeneutic of symbols. Rather, starting from
an external interpretation which is still only a kind of deciphering, it is
able, without slipping into a philosophy, to arrive at a comprehension of
existential structures. The meaning of the dream continually deploys itself
from the cipher of the appearance to the modalities of existence. On the
other hand, this privileged status of dream experience silently encompas-
ses, in this text, a whole anthropology of the imagination that requires a
new definition of the relations between meaning and symbol, between
image and expression-in short, a new way of conceiving how meanings
are manifested.
These two aspects of the problem will occupy us in the ensuing
34 Michel Foucault
pages. All the more so to the degree that Binswanger has left them
unclarified. We are not trying to parcel out credit to be sure, but rather
trying to express in this way what it is to "recognize" a line of thought
that brings us even more than it says, while still hoping to remain properly
modest toward its history.
II
former the meaning is basically nothing but the mobility of the image and
the path, as it were, of its trajectory; and for the latter the Imago is but
a muffled world, a moment of silence. In the realm of psychoanalytic
investigation, therefore, the unity between a psychology of the image
which demarcates the field of presence, and a psychology of meaning
which defines the field of linguistic potentialities, has not been found.
Psychoanalysis has never succeeded in making images speak.
*
The Logical Investigations are curiously contemporaneous with the
hermeneutic of the Interpretation of Dreams. Within the rigor of the
analyses conducted the length of the First and Sixth of these investigations,
can one find a theory of symbol and sign which reinstates in its necessity
the immanence of the meaning to the image?
Psychoanalysis had taken the term "symbol" as immediately valid,
without trying to develop or even to delimit it. By "symbolic value of the
dream image" Freud really had two quite distinct things in mind. On the
one hand, he had in mind the set of objective indices which betoken in
the image implicit structures, earlier events, experiences that remained
silent. Morphological similarities, dynamic analogies, syllabic identities
and all sorts of word games, these constitute so many objective indices
in the image, so many allusions to that which the image does not manifest
in its colorful fullness.
On the other hand, there is the global and significant link which
founds the meaning of the dream material and constitutes it as a dream
of incestuous desire, of infantile regression, or of return and narcissistic
envelopment. The set of indices can multiply indefinitely as the meaning
progresses and unifies, and cannot therefore be confounded with the mean-
ing. They arise along the path of inductive probabilities and are never
more than the method of reconstituting the latent content or the original
meaning. As for the meaning itself, it can only be brought to light in a
comprehensive grasp, for it is by its own movement that it founds the
symbolic value of the dream image. The confusing of these two things
has inclined psychoanalysis to describe the mechanisms of the formation
of dreams as the reverse and the correlative of the methods of reconstitution ,
confounding the achievement of meanings with the induction of indices.
In the first of the Logical Investigations , Husserl rightly distinguished
between the index and the signification. 7 No doubt in phenomena of
expression these are intermingled to the point that one tends to confound
them. When someone speaks, we understand what he says not only by a
meaningful grasp of the words he uses and the sentence structures he puts
into play, but we also let ourselves be guided by the vocal melody, which
now modulates and trembles. now assumes the hardness and glow by
DREAM, IMAGINATION AND EXISTENCE 39
united in the unique notion of symbol. The essence of the act of signification
must be sought beyond, and even before, the verbal expression or the
image structure in which it may be embodied.
One thing is certain ... The signified takes part in the accomplishing of
the deed. He who speaks engenders not only the word, but the expression
in its totality. 12
*
To find the foundation common to objective structures of indication,
significant ensembles, and acts of expression, such is the problem posed
by the twofold tradition of phenomenology and psychoanalysis. From the
confrontation between Husserl and Freud has emerged a double problema-
tic: a method of interpretation is needed that reinstates acts of expression
in their fullness. The hermeneutic journey should not stop at the verbal
sequences which have preoccupied psychoanalysis. It should continue to
the decisive movement in which expression objectifies itself in the essential
structures of indication. Much more than verification was needed: a foun-
dation was required.
This fundamental moment in which meanings are knit together is
what Binswanger tried to bring to light in "Dream and Existence."
We will be reproached for having not only gone beyond the letter of
the Husserlian and Freudian texts in this presentation, but for having
constructed from whole cloth a problematic that Binswanger never formu-
DREAM, IMAGINATION AND EXISTENCE 43
lated, one whose themes are not even implicit in his texts. To our thinking,
this charge carries little weight, because we are fallible enough to believe
in history even when it is a question of Existenz. Weare not concerned
to present an exegesis, but to disengage an objective meaning. We believe
that the work of Binswanger is important enough to bear such a meaning.
That is why only its real problematic has occupied our attention. In his
texts will be found the problem which he set for himself; for our part, we
wanted to specify the problem to which he was responding.
III
*
But he also rejoined another tradition, implied in the classical one.
46 Michel Foucault
Thus, the tragic dream for Jansenism. As for Molinism, the dream is no
longer predestination, but warning or signal, more to prevent predetermi-
nation than to declare it. In Benserade's drama, Briseis says:
But we should not be deceived. Beneath this doubtless most literary quarrel,
DREAM, IMAGINATION AND EXISTENCE 47
in which from one tragedy to another the characters answer each other
and throw out arguments borrowed from theological treatises, lies hidden
the problem, more genuinely tragic, of destiny.
*
Man has known, since antiquity, that in dreams he encounters what
he is and what he will be, what he has done and what he is going to do,
discovering there the knot that ties his freedom to the necessity of the
world. In the dream and its individual significance Chrysippus saw the
universal concatenation of the world and the effect of sympatheia which
conspires to form the unity of the world and which animates each fragment
with the same spiritual fire. Much later the Renaissance will take up the
idea again. For Campanella, it is the soul of the world-principle of
universal cohesion-that inspires human instincts, desires, and dreams
together. And to mark the last stage of this great mythology of the dream,
this fantastic cosmogony of the dream where the whole universe seems
to conspire at a momentary and vacillating image, there were also Novalis
and Schelling: "The world becomes dream, the dream becomes world,
and the outcome in which one believes can be seen coming from afar. "28
What has changed from one epoch to another has not been this reading
of destiny in dreams, nor even the deciphering procedures, but rather the
justification of this relation of dream to world, and the way of conceiving
how the truth of the world can anticipate itself and gather together its
future in an image capable only of reconstituting it in a murky form.
These justifications, to be sure, are still more imaginary than philo-
sophical, exalting myth at the boundaries between poetry and abstract
reflection. In Aristotle, the value of the dream is connected with the calm
of the soul, with the nocturnal dream in which the soul is removed from
the agitation of the body. 29 In that silence it becomes sensitive to the most
pervasive movements of the world, to the most distant agitations, and like
the surface of water is all the more disturbed by the agitation at its shores
as its center is the more calm and quiet; similarly, the sleeping soul is
more sensitive than the waking soul to the motions of the distant world.
The ripples get larger as they move and soon take on enough magnitude
to make the whole surface tremble; similarly, in a dream, the weakest
excitations end by distorting the whole mirror of the soul. A noise scarcely
perceptible to the waking ear turns in dream into a roll of thunder, the
least warmth becomes a conflagration. In the dream, the soul, freed of
its body, plunges into the kosmos, becomes immersed in it, and mingles
with its motions in a sort of aquatic union.
For others, the mythic element through which the dream joins the
world is not water, but fire. In the dream, the subtle body of the soul
catches fire from the secret flame of the world and thereby penetrates to
48 MicheL FoucauLt
the intimacy of things. This is the Stoic theme of the cohesion of the
world ensured by the pneuma and sustained by that heat which culminates
in a universal fire. It is the esoteric theme, which reached from medieval
alchemy to the "prescientific" spirit of the 18th century, of an "oneiro-
mancy ," a sort of phlogiston of the soul. Finally, it is the Romantic theme
in which the precise image of fire begins to attenuate, keeping only the
spiritual qualities and the dynamic values; subtlety, lightness, flickering
light casting shadows, ardor which transforms, consumes, and destroys,
leaving only ashes where once had been brightness and joy. Novalis writes
that "the dream teaches us in a remarkable fashion the subtlety with which
our soul insinuates itself among objects and at the same time transforms
itself into each of them."
The complementary myths of water and fire maintain the philosophic
theme of the substantial unity of the soul and the world in the dreaming
imagination. But one can also find other ways, in the history of dream,
to justify its transcendent character. The dream may be the shadowy
apperception of those things one senses all around oneself at night~r
contrariwise, the instantaneous flash of light, the utter brightness of intui-
tion, which completes itself in its very occurrence.
It was above all Baader who defined the dream by the luminosity of
intuition. The dream, for him, was the lightning flash of inner vision
which, beyond all sensory and discursive mediations, attains the truth in
a single movement. He spoke of that "inner and objective vision" which
"is not mediated by the external senses" which "we experience in our
common dreams." At first, inner sensibility stands in opposition to outer
sensibility, but finally, in the full grip of sleep, the former overwhelms
the latter, and the mind emerges into a SUbjective world much more
profound than the world of objects, and laden with a far weightier mean-
ing. 30 The privilege that tradition accords to waking consciousness and its
knowledge is "but uncertainty and prejudice." In the darkest night the
glow of the dream is more luminous than the light of day, and the intuition
borne with it is the most elevated form of knowledge.
We meet with the same idea in Carns: the dream reaches well beyond
itself towards objective knowledge. It is that movement ofthe mind which,
of its own accord, goes unto the world and finds its unity with the world.
It explains in effect that waking knowledge of the world is opposition,
for the receptivity of the senses and the possibility of being affected by
objects are nothing but opposition to the world, "Gegenwirken gegen eine
Welt." The dream, by contrast, breaks down this opposition and goes
beyond it-not in a luminous instant of clarity, but by the slow immersion
of the mind in the night of the unconscious.
By this plunge deep into the unconscious, far more than in a state of
DREAM, IMAGINATION AND EXISTENCE 49
conscious freedom, the soul will play its part in the universal intertwinings
and will allow itself to be penetrated by everything spatial and temporal,
as produced in the Unconscious.'l
"The sort that emerges in our dreams, when the reasonable and humane
part of us is asleep and its control relaxed, and our bestial nature, full of
food and drink, wakes and has its fling and tries to secure its own kind
of satisfaction. As you know, there's nothing too bad for it and it's
completely lost to all sense and shame. It doesn't shrink at the thought
of intercourse with a mother or anyone else, man, beast, or god, or from
murder or sacrilege. There is in fact no folly or shamelessness it will not
commit,HI'"
50 Michel Foucault
The manifesting of desire by dreams remained until the 19th century one
of the most frequently used themes of medicine, literature, and philosophy.
In 1613, seeking out "all the causes of dreams," Andre de Laurent, Physi-
cian to the King, found there movements of the humors and traits of
temperament: "He who is angry dreams only of jousts, battles, fires; the
phlegmatic always thinks he is in water. "35 Literature adopts authoritatively
the pronouncements of the scholars. In Mariane, Tristan has Pherore say,
and, proceeding from the principle to examples, describes the soul of the
thief who
If it were given to our bodily eyes to see into the mind of another, we
would judge a man far more often by what he dreams than by what he
thinks ... The dream, which is all spontaneity, takes and keeps the impress
of our mind. Nothing emerges more directly and with more sincerity from
the very depths of our soul than our unreflective and unconfined aspira-
tions ... Our chimeras are what resemble us the most."
But the closeness of these analogies should not lead us into the sin
of anachronism. What is Freudian in Plato or Victor Hugo, what suggests
lung in Schleiermacher, is not of the nature of scientific anticipation. The
functioning of such intuitions, and their justification, are not to be found
in some unrecognized psychoanalysis. Rather, one finds, at the origin of
the theme of the dream as manifestation of the soul in its inwardness, the
Heraclitean principle:
We share a world when we are awake; each sleeper is in a world of his own."
DREAM, IMAGINATION AND EXISTENCE 51
*
This Heraclitean theme runs through the whole of literature and the
whole of philosophy. It reappears in the various texts we have cited, which
seem so close, at first glance, to psychoanalysis. But what is indicated,
in reality, by this depth of the spirit, these "abysses of the soul" whose
emergence is described in the dream, is not the biological equipment of
the libidinal instinct; it is the originative movement of freedom, the birth
of the world in the very movement of existence. Novalis, more than
52 Michel Foucault
We dream of voyages over the whole world, yet is not this whole world
in us? It is in oneself and nowhere else that Eternity lies with its worlds,
the past and recollections. The external world is a world of shadows and
it casts its shadows on the empire of light. 42
But the moment of the dream does not remain the equivocal instant of an
ironic reduction to subjectivity. Novalis took from Herder the idea that
the dream is the original moment of genesis: the dream is the primary
image of poetry, and poetry, the primitive form of language, the "maternal
language of man. "43 The dream is thus at the very center of becoming and
objectivity. And Novalis added:
To that extent the dream experience cannot be isolated from its ethical
content. Not because it may uncover secret inclinations, inadmissible
desires, nor because it may release the whole flock of instincts, nor because
it might, like Kant's God, "sound our hearts"; but because it restores the
movement of freedom in its authentic meaning, showing how it establishes
itself or alienates itelf, how it constitutes itself as radical responsibility in
the world, or how it forgets itself and abandons itself to its plunge into
causality. The dream is that absolute disclosure of the ethical content, the
heart shown naked. This is the meaning referred to by Plato in Book Ten
of the Republic, and not, in some pre-Freudian fashion, secret manifesta-
tions of instinct. Indeed, the wise man does not have the same dreams as
the man of violence, the "tyrannical" man, governed by the tyranny of
his desires and open to the political tyranny of the first Thrasymachus on
the scene, the man of desire who dreams of impudence and folly. But when
"a man of sound and disciplined character, before he goes to sleep, has
awakened his reason ... , has neither starved nor indulged his desires, so
that they sink to rest and don't plague the higher pan of him ... , has
calmed ... his spirited element so that he goes to sleep without anger at
anyone, thus going to rest with appetite and spirit quieted, while his
reasoning part is stimulated, then he is better than ever in a state to grasp
the truth in visions in his dreams undisturbed by wrong doing.""
Cultural history has carefully preserved this theme of the ethical value of
the dream, while its premonitional import remains secondary. What the
dream declares for the future of the dreamer derives only from what it
DREAM, IMAGINATION AND EXISTENCE 53
discloses of the involvements and ties of his freedom. Jezebel is not there
to predict imminent misfortune to Athalea: though she is told summarily
that "the cruel God of the Jews has overwhelmed you," she is shown only
her freedom chained down by a succession of crimes and bound over
beyond appeal to the vengeance that restores justice. Two sorts of dreams
are considered particularly significant: the dream of the hardened sinner
who at the moment of teetering into despair sees opening before his eyes
the path of salvation (sometimes the dream is transferred to someone less
blind and more disposed to grasp its meaning, viz., the famous dream of
St. Cecilia who can read in the dream that her son is turning to God); and
the murderous dreamer who meets in the dream both the death he deals
out and the death which stalks him, and who discovers the horror of an
existence which has bound itself to death by a bloody pact. Linking the
past to the present in the rehearsing of remorse, and knitting it into the
unity of a destiny, this is the dream that fills the nights of Macbeth, and
that is so frequently found in other classical tragedies.
If the dream is the bearer of the deepest human meanings, this is not
insofar as it betrays their hidden mechanisms or shows their inhuman cogs
and wheels, but on the contrary, insofar as it brings to light the freedom
of man in its most original form. And when, in ceaseless repetition, it
declares some destiny, it is bewailing a freedom which has lost itself, an
ineradicable past, and an existence fallen of its own motion into a definite
determination. We will see later how Binswanger gives a new reality to
this theme, ceaselessly present in literary expression, and how, in taking
up again the lesson of the tragic poets, he restores, thanks to the trajectory
of the dream, the whole Odyssey of human freedom.
*
Such is no doubt the meaning one must give to the idios kosmos of
54 Michel Foucault
Heraclitus. The dream world is not the inner garden of fantasy. If the
dreamer meets there a world of his own, this is because he can recognize
there the fact of his own destiny: he finds there the original movement of
his existence and his freedom, in its achievement or in its alienation.
*
But does not the dream thus reflect a contradiction just where one
might succeed in discerning the cipher of existence? Does it not designate
at one and the same time the content of a transcendent world and the
original movement of a freedom? The dream is deployed, we saw earlier,
in a world which secretes its opaque contents and the forms of a necessity
which cannot be deciphered. Yet at the same time it is free genesis,
self-accomplishment, emergence of what is most individual in the indi-
vidual. This contradiction is manifest in the content of the dream when
it is deployed and offered to discursive interpretation. It even bursts forth
as the ultimate meaning in all those dreams that are haunted by the anguish
of death. Death is experienced as the supreme moment of that contradiction,
which death constitutes as destiny. Hence the meaningfulness of all those
dreams of violent death, of savage death, of horrified death, in which one
must indeed recognize, in the final analysis, a freedom up against a world.
If consciousness sleeps during sleep, existence awakens in the dream.
Sleep, itself, goes toward the life that it is preparing, that it is spelling
out, that it favors. If it is a seeming death, this is by a ruse of life, which
does not want to die; it "plays dead," but "from fear of death." It remains
of the order of life.
The dream is no accomplice of sleep. It ascends again the slope that
sleep descends, towards life, it goes towards existence, and there, in full
light, it sees death as the destiny of freedom. For the dream, as such, and
by virtue of the meanings of existence it bears with it, kills sleep and life
that falls asleep. Say not that sleep makes dreaming possible, for it is the
dream that makes sleep impossible by waking it to the light of death. The
dream, as with Macbeth, murders sleep.
In the depth of his dream, what man encounters is his death, a death
which in its most inauthentic form is but the brutal and bloody interruption
oflife, yet in its authentic form, is his very existence being accomplished.
It is doubtless no accident that Freud was halted, in his dream interpre-
tation, by the recounting of dreams of death. They marked, in effect, an
DREAM, IMAGINATION AND EXISTENCE 55
IV
*
Here is a dream analysis by Binswanger done well before the time
of "Dream and Existence."~J It concerned a young woman, age 33, who
was under treatment for severe depression, with outbursts of rage and
58 Michel Foucault
of these meanings?
*
They are to be found in the first movements of freedom and in its
original directness. If dreams are so weighty for determining existential
meanings, it is because they trace in their fundamental coordinates the
trajectory of existence itself. Much has been said about the temporal
pulsations of the dream, its particular rhythms, the contradictions or par-
adoxes of its duration. Much less about dream space.
Yet the forms of spatiality disclose in the dream the very "meaning
and direction" of existence. Did not Stefan George note that "space and
being-there abide only in the image" ("Raum und Dasein bleiben nur im
BUde")? In lived experience, at its original level, space is not presented
as the geometric structure of simultaneity. This type of space, within
which the natural sciences deploy objective phenomena in their coherence,
is only constituted by way of a genesis whose moments have been analyzed
by Oscar Becker in their psychological aspect,54 and by Husserl in their
historical aspect. ss Before being geometric or even geographic, space
presents itself first and foremost as scene or landscape: 56 it gives itself
originally as the distance of colored plenitudes or of reaches lost in the
horizon, enveloped in the gathering distance; or, it is the space of things
there, resistant to my touch; it is to my right or my left, behind me, opaque
or transparent to my gaze. In contrast to the space of geographical refer-
ence, totally elucidated in the form of a general diagram, the scene is
paradoxically closed by the infinite openness of the horizon. Everything
that this horizon implies in the way of an eventual beyond delimits the
familiarity of the hither and of all the pathways staked out by habit. It
refers thus to the absolute of a situation which gathers in all the affective
powers of the hearth, the native land, the Heimat. And each of these lines,
which vanish into the horizon, is already like a road of return, a familiar
bearing for rediscovering ten hodou oikade, the homeward road. In geog-
raphic space, motion is nothing but displacement: a concerted change of
position from one point to another according to a previously established
trajectory. The path is thus no more than the indispensable intermediary,
reduced as far as possible, the lower limit of time which is indispensable
for going from one point to another. In lived space, the displacement
preserves an original spatial character; it does not cross, it travels along;
until the very moment it stops, it remains a proffered trajectory of which
only its point of departure is known for certain; its future is not prearranged
by the geography of the setting, but is awaited in its authentic historicity.
Finally it is the space of encounters; not merely the intersection of lines
which trace the shortest distance between two points, but overlapping of
journeys, paths crossing, roads which converge to the same place on the
DREAM, IMAGINATION AND EXISTENCE 61
horizon, or which, like Guennantes Way, suddenly arrive, after the widest
turn, at a birthplace. The dream deploys itself in this original spatiality
of the scene and finds there its principal affective meanings.
"L' espace signe de rna puissance." ("Space, sign of my power.")
This is true of lived space only to the extent that the values of this space
are reciprocally ordered. The security that space provides, the solid support
that it lends to my powers, rests on the articulation of near space and far
space: the latter, by which one withdraws and eludes, or which one sets
out to explore or conquer; the fonner, that of rest, of familiarity, that
which is right at hand. But this relation is disturbed in some experiences:
then, far space may press upon near space, penneating it on all sides with
a massive presence, with a kind of grip that one cannot loosen. Now the
distant may slowly enter into the porous presence of near space, mingling
with it, to the complete elimination of perspective, as in those catatonics
who are "in attendance" before what is going on "around them," indifferent,
as if everything were far off, yet concerned, as if everything were close,
confounding the objective displacement of things at the horizon and their
own bodily movement. Now, far space may penetrate the immediate
sphere of the subject like a meteor-witness the patient reported by
Binswanger: 57 he is properly oriented in space, but lying in bed he has
the sensation that a piece of the railroad track, over there, below the
window, separates from the horizon, penetrates the bedroom, traverses
it, bores through his skull and lodges in his brain. In all these metatheses
of the near and the far, space loses its secure character, becomes filled
with stifling threats and sudden dangers, is furrowed by irruptive forces.
Space, sign of my weakness.
The polarity of light and dark is not identical with that of near and
far, even though they are not always distinct. Minkowski has described
that dark space where hallucinatory voices cross and mingle, at once far
and near. 58 In that dark world, spatial implication does not reflect the laws
of juxtaposition, but the special modalities of envelopment or fusion.
Space then ceases to function as a divider, no longer dissociates; it is no
more than moving of shapes and sounds, coming and going according to
the flux and reflux of their apparition. Over against this nocturnal spatiality
one can, like Minkowski, analyze the clear space which takes shape before
the subject, a levelled and socialized space where I experience in the mode
of action all my potentials of movement, and where everything has its
particular place, according to its function and its use. In fact, even more
radically opposed to the space of darkness is a space of pure luminosity,
where all dimensions seem both to be realized and to be eliminated, where
all things seem to find unity, not in a fusion of fleeting appearances but
in the clarity of a presence completely open to our gaze. Experiences of
this sort have been described by Riimke. 59 One of his patients feels some-
thing in her so vast. so peaceful, an immense expanse of water, and feels
62 Michel Foucault
closeness, holds only the imminence of death. For Ellen West, the solid
space of real movement, the space where things come to be, has progres-
sively, bit by bit, disappeared. It has become wholly reabsorbed into limits
of its own, it has become its own suppression, it is exiled into the two
contradictories of which it had been the unifying moment. It exists only
beyond itself, both as if it did not yet exist and as if already it no longer
existed. The existential space of Ellen West is that of life suppressed, at
once in the desire for death and in the myth of a second birth. It already
wears the sign of the suicide by which Ellen West was to attain the
culmination of her existence.
*
A phenomenological analysis, however, cannot stand by itself. It
must be completed and grounded. It must complete itself by elucidating
the expressive act which gives a concrete shape to these original dimensions
of existence. It must ground itself by elucidating that movement in which
the directions of the trajectory of existence are constituted.
We shall put aside, for the moment, the analysis of expression,
leaving that for another inquiry. Let us simply note a few elements that
are easily specified.
Every act of expression is to be understood on the basis of its primary
directions. It does not produce these ex nihilo, but locates itself on their
trajectory, which makes it possible, as from the points of a curve, to
rediscover the whole, completed movement. To this extent, there can be
an anthropology of art which would in no way become psychological
reductionism. One would not refer expressive structures back to uncon-
scious motivations, but reinstate them the whole length of that line along
which human freedom moves.
On this line from near space to far space we will encounter a specific
form of expression: there, existence knows the dawn of triumphal depar-
tures, voyages and circumnavigations, dazzling discoveries, the siege of
towns, the mesh of exile, the stubborn return, the bitterness of coming
back to things unchanged and aged, the whole course of that Odyssey of
existence; on those "great cloths woven ofthe dreamed and the real," epic
expression takes shape as a basic structure of the expressive act.
Lyric expression, by contrast, is possible only in the alternation of
light and darkness where existence plays itself out. By its nature-quite
apart from the topic chosen or the metaphor adopted, even though either
may often be significant-the lyrical is seasonal or a "nyct hemeral,"
day-blinded with night vision, night-blinded with day vision. It is at once
solar and nocturnal, and in its essence, takes on the values of dawn and
dusk. The lyrical does not traverse distances, it is always the others who
depart. There is no return from exile, because its own land is already
64 Michel Foucault
exile. If the lyrical can survey all the changes ofthe world, all its motions,
if it can, itself immobile, search out in every direction, this is because it
seizes everything in a play of light and shadow, in the pulsations of day
and night, which tell, upon the shifting surface of things, the unchangeable
truth.
Finally, the axis of tragic expression is located along the vertical axis
of existence. The tragic movement is always of the order of ascent and
fall. Its special mark is that privileged moment in which it completes its
rise, and balances imperceptibly, still, yet oscillating, before faltering.
That is why tragedy hardly needs time and space in which to extend itself,
nor foreign lands, not even the surcease of the night, for it sets itself the
task of manifesting the vertical transcendence of destiny. 62
Thus, there is an anthropological basis for the characteristic structures
of epic, lyric, and tragic expression. An analysis would be needed to show
both the nature of the expressive act and the anthropological necessities
that dominate and govern it; one could study the expressive forms of exile,
of a descent into an Inferno, of the mountain, of the prison.
Let us return to the only question that can occupy us here: how are
the essential directions of Existenz, which form the anthropological struc-
tures of its entire history, constituted?
*
The first thing to note is that the three polarities we have described
do not have equal universality and the same anthropological depth. And
even though each has its independent status, one at least appears more
fundamental, more originative. Hence, no doubt, the fact that Binswanger,
without broaching the problem of various expressive forms, has scarcely
emphasized anything but the oppositions of ascent and fall. What is the
anthropological privilege of this vertical dimension?
First of all, it brings out, almost nakedly, the structures of temporality.
Horizontal opposition of the near and the far exhibits time only in the
chronology of spatial progression. Time unfolds only between a point of
departure and a point of arrival, and is wholly exhausted in the journeying;
and when it renews itself, it does so in the form of repetition, return,
another departure. In this existential direction, time is in its essence nos-
talgic. It tries to close around itself, to recommence by linking up again
to its beginning. The time of the epic is circular or reiterative. In the
opposition ofthe light and the dark, too, time is not authentic temporality,
but a rhythmic time marked by oscillations, a seasonal time where absence
is always a pledge of return, and death, the pledge of resurrection.
With the movement of ascent and fall, on the contrary, one can grasp
temporality in its primitive meaning.
Let us return to the case of Ellen West. The whole movement of her
DREAM, IMAGINATION AND EXISTENCE 65
existence channels into a phobic fear of a fall into the grave and in the
delirious desire to soar into the ether, finding its gratification in the immo-
bility of pure movement. But this orientation and its affective polarity
designate the very form according to which existence temporalizes itself.
The patient does not take on the future as disclosure of a fullness and
anticipation of death. She already experiences death, there, inscribed in
her aging body which is more burdened each day. Death for her is only
the actual weight of her flesh, is but one and the same thing as the presence
of her body. During the thirteen years of her illness, Ellen West lived
only to flee the imminence of this death attached to her flesh. She refused
to eat or to give life in any form at all to this body, which would transform
into the menace of death. Whatever gives substance, continuity, and weight
to this presence of the body multiplies the deadly powers that envelop it.
She rejects all food, and by the same token rejects her past. She does not
take up her past in the authentic form of repetition, but suppresses it by
the myth of a new birth which is to erase everything she had been.
However, by virtue of this making-present of death in the guise of imminent
menace, the future is emptied of its fullness. It is no longer a future by
which existence anticipates it own death, taking upon itself its solitude
and its facti city , but a future by which existence tears itself away from
everything that grounds it as finite existence. The future into which exist-
ence projects itself is not that of an existence in the world, but that of an
existence above the world, an overflight, where the limits which enclose
its fullness are abolished in order to accede to the pure existence of eternity .
An empty eternity, to be sure, without content, a "bad eternity," as is
"bad" the subjective infinity of which Hegel spoke. This temporalization
of existence in Ellen West is an inauthentic one.
Indeed, it is along this vertical direction of existence, and according
to the structures of temporality, that the authentic and inauthentic forms
of existence can best be allocated. This self-transcendence of the existent
in its temporal movement, this transcendence designated by the vertical
axis of the imaginary, can be lived as a wrenching away from the bases
of the existence itself. Then we see crystallizing all those themes of
immortality, of survival, of pure love, of unmediated communication
between minds. Or it can be lived, on the contrary, as "transcendence,"
as an imminent plunge from the dangerous pinnacle of the present. Then
the imaginary elaborates itself into a fantastic world of disaster. The
universe is but the moment of its own annihilation: this is the constitutive
moment of those deliriums of "the end of the world." Temporality's
movement of transcendence can likewise be covered over and hidden by
a pseudo-transcendence of space. Then the vertical axis is wholly absorbed
into the horizontal trajectory of existence. The future lies in the spatially
distant. Existence defends itself against the menacings of death by all
those obsessional rites which block the free pathways of the world with
66 Michel Foucault
v
Le poete est aux ordres de sa nuit.-Jean Cocteau
its constituting elements; these are not its prime matter, and they do not
constitute its ultimate significance. On the contrary, every act of imagina-
tion points implicitly to the dream. The dream is not a modality of the
imagination, the dream is the first condition of its possibility.
Classically, the image is always defined by reference to the real: thus
locating its origin and its positivisitic truth in a traditional conception of
images as residues of perception. Or else, it defines the essence of the
image negatively, as in the Sartrean conception of an "imaging conscious-
ness" that posits its object as irreal. On the one definition, as on the other,
the image bears in itself, and by a natural necessity, an allusion to reality,
or at least to an eventual content of perception. No doubt Sartre has amply
shown that this content "is not there"; that, indeed, I aim at it insofar as
it is absent; that it offers itself, from the start, as irreal; that it remains
porous and docile to my magical incantations. The image of Peter is the
perception of Peter invoked, but it takes place in, confines itself to, and
exhausts itself in, the irreality where Peter presents himself as absent.
At frrst I only want to see Peter. But my desire becomes a desire for a
certain smile, for certain features. Thus it limits itself and exasperates
itself at one and the same time, and the irreal object is precisely ... the
limitation and the exasperation of this desire. And it is but a mirage: the
desire, in the imaging act, feeds on itself."'
In fact, we must ask whether the image does indeed, as Sartre would
have it, designate-even negatively and in the mode of unreality-the
real itself.
I am trying to imagine today what Peter will do when he gets· such
and such news. Agreed, Peter's absence surrounds and circumscribes the
movement of my imagination. But that absence was already there, before
I imagined; and not in some implicit way, but in the keen mode of my
regret at not having seen him for a year. That absence was already present,
in the very things, the familiar things which today still bear the mark of
his departure. Absence precedes and colors my imagination, but it is
neither the condition of its possibility nor its eidetic index. If I had seen
Peter just yesterday, my imagination today would bring him too close and
would burden me with too immediate a presence. To imagine Peter after
a year's absence is not to confront him in a mode of unreality (that does
not require imagination, the least feeling of bitterness would suffice), it
is first of all to derealize myself, it is to absent myself from that world
where it is no longer possible to encounter Peter. Which is not to say that
I "escape to another world," nor even that I frequent the possible margins
of the real world. The lines of necessity that exclude Peter are smudged,
and my presence, as presence to this world, fades. I undertake to adopt
once more that mode of presence in which the movement of my freedom
68 Michel Foucault
was not yet caught up in this world toward which it moves, where every-
thing still denoted the constitutive possession of the world of my existence.
To imagine what Peter is doing today in some circumstance that concerns
us both is not to invoke a perception or a reality; it is primarily to try to
recapture that world where everything is still conjugated in the first person.
When in imagination I see him in his room, I do not imagine myself
peering at him through the keyhole, or watching him from the outside.
Nor is it quite right to say that I transport myself magically into his room,
where I remain invisible. To imagine is not to actualize the fable of the
little mouse, it is not to transport oneself into the world of Peter. It is to
become the world where he is: I am the letter he is reading; I conjure
myself from that look of attentive reader; I am the walls of his room that
watch him from all sides and hence do not "see" him. But I am also his
gaze and his attentiveness, his dissatisfaction or his surprise before the
letter. I am not only absolute master of what he is doing, I am what he
is doing, I am what he is. That is why imagination adds nothing new to
what I already know. Yet it would be incorrect to say that it brings nothing
and teaches me nothing. The imaginary is not to be confused with imma-
nence, and is not even exhausted in that formal transcendence of whatever
delineates itself as irreal. The imaginary is transcendent. Not with an
"objective" transcendence (as in W. Szilasi's sense of the term), since the
moment I imagine Peter, he obeys me; each of his gestures fulfills my
expectations, and finally he even comes to see me because I want him to
do so. But the imaginary gives itself as a transcendence where, without
learning anything unknown to me, I can "recognize" my destiny. Even
in imagination, or rather, especially in imagination, I do not obey myself,
I am not my own master, for the sole reason that I prey upon myself. In
Peter's imagined return, I am not there, before him, because I am
everywhere, around him, and in him; I do not talk with him, I hold forth;
I am not with him, I "stage" him. And it is because I rediscover and
recognize myself everywhere that I can decipher in this imagining the law
of my heart, and read my destiny there: these feelings, this desire, this
drive to spoil the simplest things, necessarily means my solitariness, at
the very instant in which I try, in imagination, to dispel it. Consequently,
to imagine is not so much a behavior towards others which intends them
as quasi-presences on an essential ground of absence; it is rather to intend
oneself as a movement of freedom which makes itself world and finally
anchors itself in this world as its destiny. Through what it imagines,
therefore, consciousness aims at the original movement which discloses
itself in dreams. Thus, dreaming is not a singularly powerful and vivid
way of imagining. On the contrary, imagining is to take aim at oneself
in the moment of dreaming; it is to dream oneself dreaming.
And just as dreams of death appeared to us to disclose the ultimate
meaning of the dream, no doubt there are certain forms of imagination
DREAM, IMAGINATION AND EXISTENCE 69
which, linked to death, show with the greatest clarity what, at bottom,
imagination is. In the movement of imagination it is always myself that
I derealize as presence to this very world; and I experience this world
(not another one, but this very one) as entirely new to my presence, as
penetrated by my presence, as belonging to me as mine. Through this
world, which is only the cosmogony of my existence, I can rediscover
the entire trajectory of my freedom, fathom its every direction, and totalize
it as the curve of a destiny. When I imagine the return of Peter, to have
an image of Peter crossing the threshold is not essential; what is essential
is that my presence, inclining to dreamlike ubiquity, spread itself out on
this side and on that side of the doorway; find itself wholly in the thoughts
of the arriving Peter and in my own thoughts as I wait, in his smile and
in my pleasure, aiming at this meeting as a fulfillment. The imagination
does not tend to halt the movement of existence, but to totalize it. One
always imagines the decisive, the definitive, that which is thenceforward
going to be closed. What we imagine is of the order of a solution, not a
task. Happiness and unhappiness are inscribed in the imagination's register,
not duty and virtue. This is why the major forms of imagination are aligned
with suicide. Or rather, suicide appears as the absolute of imaginary
behaviors: every suicidal desire is filled by that world in which I would
no longer be present here, or there, but everywhere, in every sector: a
world transparent to me and signifying its indebtedness to my absolute
presence. Suicide is not a way of cancelling the world or myself, or the
two together, but a way of rediscovering the original moment in which I
make myself world, in which space is still no more than directedness of
existence, and time the movement of its history.66 To commit suicide is
the ultimate mode of imagining; to try to characterize suicide in the realistic
terms of supression is to doom oneself to misunderstanding it. Only an
anthropology of the imagination can ground psychology and an ethics of
suicide.
Let us hold on for the moment only to the notion that suicide is the
ultimate myth, the "Last Judgment" of the imagination, as the dream is
its genesis, its absolute origin.
Hence, one cannot define the imaginary as the inverse function, the
negative index, of reality. No doubt it develops readily on the ground of
absence, and the gaps and denials by which it opposes my desires are
above all what refer the world back to its basis. Yet it is also through the
imaginary that the original meaning of reality is disclosed. Therefore, it
cannot exclude reality. At the very heart of perception it can throw into
bright light the secret and hidden power at work in the most manifest
forms of presence. To be sure, Peter's absence and my dismay prompt
me to dream that dream in which my existence goes forth to meet Peter.
But in his presence, too, before that face which today I am reduced to
imagining, I can already summon up Peter in imagination, not as elsewhere
70 Michel Foucault
or as different, but there, where he was, just as he was. This Peter who
is seated there before me is not imaginary in that his actuality might have
duplicated itself and might have assigned me another, virtual Peter (the
Peter I hypothesize, desire, anticipate), but is imaginary in that, at this
privileged moment, he is, for me, precisely himself, Peter. He it is, toward
whom I go, whose encounter promises me certain satisfactions. His
friendship for me is located there, somewhere, on that trajectory of my
existence I am already tracing out. His friendship marks the moment in
which directions will change, or where, perhaps, they will regain their
initial orientation and simply run their course. To imagine Peter when I
am perceiving him thus is not to have, alongside him, an image of him
as older, or as in some other place and time, but to grasp once more that
original movement of our existences whose precocious concurrence can
make up a single world more fundamental than that system of actuality
which today defines our common presence in this room. Then my percep-
tion itself, while remaining perception, becomes imaginary by the sole
fact that it finds its coordinates in the directions of existence itself. Imag-
inary, too, my words and feelings, this conversation I am now having
with Peter, this friendship. Yet not false, for all that, nor illusory. The
imaginary is not a mode of unreality, but indeed a mode of actuality, a
way of approaching presence obliquely to bring out its primordial dimen-
sions.
Gaston Bachelard is absolutely right when he shows the imagination
at work in the intimate recesses of perception, and the secret labor which
transforms the object one is perceiving into an object of contemplation.
"One understands forms by their transformation"; then, beyond the norms
of objective truth, "the realism of unreality holds sway. "67 No one has
better understood the dynamic work of the imagination and the incessantly
vectorial nature of its movement. But should we also follow Bachelard
when he shows this movement culminating in the image, and the thrust
of the image installing itself of its own accord within the dynamism of
the imagination?
*
On the contrary, the image does not seem to be made of the same
stuff as the imagination. The image which takes shape as a crystallized
form and which almost always borrows its vivacity from memory, does
indeed play the part of a substitute for the reality, functioning as the
analogon which we earlier denied to imagination. When I imagine Peter's
return, or what we shall first say to each other, I do not, strictly speaking,
have an image, and what bears me along is solely the movement signifying
this eventual meeting-whatever it may bring, that is, in excitement or
bitterness, exultation or dismay. But here is Peter, all of a sudden, "in
DREAM, IMAGINATION AND EXISTENCE 71
image," in that somber attire and that lurking smile I know him by. Did
this image serve to complete the movement of my imagination and fill it
with what it was still lacking? Absolutely not: for I soon cease imagining.
Even if it should persist for a while, this image does not fail to refer me,
sooner or later, to my actual perception, to those white walls around me
that exclude the presence of Peter. The image is not given at the culminating
moment of imagination, but at the moment of its alteration. The image
mimes the presence of Peter, the imagination goes forth to encounter him.
To have an image is therefore to leave off imagining.
The image is impure, therefore, and precarious. Impure, because
always of the order of the "as if." To a certain extent, it will shape itself
within that movement of the imagination which reinstates the very direc-
tions of existence, but it will feign an identification of these directions
with the dimensions of perceived space, and of this movement, with the
mobility of the perceived object. By presenting my meeting with Peter in
this very room, and a conversation of such and such words, the image
enables me to elude the real task of imagination: to bring to light the
significance of this encounter and the movement of my existence which
bears me toward it with such invincible freedom. That is why the "as if'
of the image turns the authentic freedom of the imagination into the fantasy
of desire. Just as it mimes perception by way of quasi-presence, so the
image mimes freedom by a quasi-satisfaction of the desire.
And by the same token the image is precarious. It completely exhausts
itself in its contradictory status. On the one hand, it takes the place of
imagination and of that movement which refers me back toward the origin
of the constituted world; at the same time, it points to this world, constituted
in the perceptual mode, as its target. That is why reflection kills the image,
as perception also does, whereas the one and the other reinforce and
nourish imagination. When I am perceiving this doorway, I cannot have
an image of Peter passing through it; and yet this room in which I find
myself, with all that is familiar about it, with all the traces it bears of my
past life and my projects, may ceaselessly assist me, by its very perceptual
content, in imagining what the return of Peter and his reappearance in my
life would mean. The image as fixation upon a quasi-presence is but the
vertigo of imagination as it turns back toward the primordial meaning of
presence. The image constitutes a ruse of consciousness in order to cease
imagining, the moment of discouragement in the hard labor of imagining.
*
Poetic expression is the manifest proof. It does not, indeed, find its
greatest expansion where it finds the greatest number of substitutes for
reality, where it invents the most duplications and metaphors, but, on the
contrary. where it best restores presence to itself-where the proliferation
72 Michel Foucault
of analogies well up, and where the metaphors by neutralizing each other,
restore the depth to immediacy. The inventors of images discover
similarities and hunt down metaphors. The imagination, in its true poetic
function, meditates on identity. If it is true that the imagination circulates
through a universe of images, it does notmove to the extent that it promotes
or reunites images, but to the extent that it destroys and consumes them.
The imagination is in essence iconoclastic. Metaphor is the metaphysics
of the image, in the sense that metaphysics is the destruction of physics.
The true poet denies himself the accomplishment of desire in the image,
because the freedom of imagination imposes itself on him as a task of
refusal:
While carrying out the poetic task among the freshly cleared fields of the
Word in its universality, the poet-integral, avid, impressionable, and
plucky-will never welcome any enterprise which might alienate that
marvel which freedom in poetry is."
*
We have not, of course, followed the imagination along the whole
course of its movement. We have only retraced that line that connects it
to the dream as to its origin and its truth. We have only followed it in its.
reference back to the dream by which it breaks away from images, in
which it always risks alienation. But the moment of the dream is not the
definitive form in which imagination takes shape. No doubt, the dream
restores the imagination to its truth and gives it back the absolute meaning
of its freedom. All imagination, to be authentic, must once more learn to
74 Michel Foucault
NOTES
I Cf. for example, Paul Hiiberlin, Der Mensch: Eine Philosophische Anthropologie, "Vor-
wort" (Zurich: Schweizer Spiegel, 1941),7-8.
2 Ibid., passim.
3 Cf. K. Schneider, Fortschritte der Neurologie, Psychiatrie und ihrer Grenzgebiete
(Stuttgart/Leipzig: Thieme), I, 145.
4 In Neue Schweizer Rundschau (Zurich: Fretz u. Wasmuth), IX, 1930; reprinted in
Ludwig Binswanger, Ausgewiihlte Vortriige und Aufsiitze (Bern: A. Francke, 1947),
74-97. English translation by Jacob Needleman, "Dream and Existence," in Needleman,
Being-in-the-World (New York: Basic Books, 1963),222-248.
5 "Uber Ideenflucht" (Schweizer Archiv for Neurologie und Psychiatrie, XXX, 1931-1933)
was the first study of psychopathology in the mode of Dasein-ana1ysis.
6 James Strachey (ed), Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund
Freud (London: Hogarth, 1953), XII (1911-1913), 36, 36n., 63-64.
7 See Edmund Husserl, Logische Untersuchungen (Halle: Max Niemeyer, 1922), v.lI,
Pt. I, "Untersuchung I," "Ausdruck und Bedeutung," Ch.1, sec. 5, pp. 30-31.-Logical
Investigations (New York: Humanities Press, 1970; trans. J.N. Findlay), I, "Investigation
I," Ch.1, Sec. 5, p. 275.
8 Translator's note: The passage in the French text reads: "L'association rappelle a la
conscience des contenus en leur laissant Ie soin de se rattacher aux contenus donnes
suivant la loi de leurs essences respectives." The original German text by Edmund
Husser! reads: "Die Assoziation ruft die Inhalte nicht bloss ins Bewusstsein zUrUck und
uber!iisst es ihnen, sich mit den gegebenen Inhalten zu verknupfen, wie es das Wesen
der einen und Anderen (ihre Gattungsbestimmtheit) geseztlich vorschreibt." (Logische
Untersuchungen, op.cit., p.29.) The English translation by J.N. Findlay reads: "Associ-
ation does not merely restore contents to consciousness, and then leave it to them to
combine with the contents there present, as the essence or generic nature of either may
necessarily prescribe." (Logical Investigations, op. cit., pp.273- 274.) (F.W.)
9 Translator's note: The passage in the French text reads: "Les actes de formulation,
d'imagination, de perception, sont trop differents pour que la signification s' epuise tantot
en ceux-ci tantot en ceux-Ia; nous devons preferer une conception qui attribue cette
fonction de signification a un seul acte partout identique, a un acte qui so it delivre des
limites de cette perception qui nous fait si souvent defaut." The original German text
by Edmund Husser! reads: "Die Akte, welche mit dem Wortlaut geeinigt sind, je nachdem
dieser rein symbolisch oder intuitiv, auf Grund blosser Phantasie oder realisender
Wahmehmung, bedeutsam ist, sind phiinomenologische zu sehr different, als dass wir
glauben ktinnten, das Bedeuten spiele sich bald in jenem, welche diese Funktion des
Bedeuten einem uberall gleichartigen Akten zuweist, der von den Schranken der uns so
oft versagten Wahmehmung und selbst Phantasie frei ist und sich, wo der Ausdruck im
eigentlichc Sinne 'uusdrilckt,' mit dem ausgedruckten Akte nur vereint." (Logische
76 Michel Foucault
Untersuchungen, op. cit., v.II, Pt. 2, "Untersuchung VI," sec.4, pp. 15-16.) The English
translation by J.N. Findlay reads: "The acts which are united with the sound of our
words are phenomenologically quite different according as these words have a purely
symbolic, or an intuitively fulfilled significance, or according as they have a merely
fancied or a perceptually realizing basis: we cannot believe that signification is now
achieved in this sort of act, now in that. We shall rather have to conceive that the
function of meaning pertains in all cases to one and the same sort of act, a type of act
free from the limitations of the perception or the imagination which so often fails us,
and which, in all cases where an expression authentically 'expresses,' merely becomes
one with the act expressed." (Logical Investigations, op.cit., v. II, "Investigation VI,"
Ch. I, Sec. 4, p.681. (F.W.)
10 Translator's note: The passage in the French text reads: "Comrne Ie remarque encore
Husser!, si nous pensons un chiliagone, nous imaginons n'importe quel polygone ayant
beaucoup de cotes."-The original German text by Edmund Husser! reads: "Ebenso
denken wir ein Tausendeck und imaginieren irgendein Polygon von 'Vielen' Seite."
(Logische Untersuchungen, op. cit., v. II, PI. 2, "Untersuchung I," Ch. 2, Sec. 18, p.
65.)--The English translation by J.N. Findlay reads: ..... we think of a chiliagon, while
we imagine any polygon with 'many' sides." (Logical Investigations, op. cit., v. I,
"Investigation I," Ch. 2, Sec. 18, p. 302.) (F.W.)
II Edmund Husserl, Umarbeitung of the "Sixth Logical Investigation." Manuscript M III,
2 II 8a.
12Ibid., p.37.
13 Karl Jaspers, Psychopathologie generale (Paris, Alcan, 1933; tf. A. Kastler), p.230.
14 Karl Jaspers, Philosophy (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970; tr. E.B. Ashton),
v.2, pp. 47ff.
15 F.W.J. Schelling, Werke (ed. Otto Weiss; Munich: Biederstein, 1946), v.l, 657.
16 De Mirbel, Le Palais du Prince de Soimmeil, ou est enseignee l' oniromancie autrement
l' art de deviner par les songes. (Lyons: L. Pavlhe, 1670).
17 Theophile de Viau (1590-1626), Les amours tragiques de Pyrame et Thisbe (Napoli:
Edizioni Scientifiche Italiane, 1967; ed. Guido Saba), Act IV, sc. ii, 11. 852-853, p.1l5.
18 Franz von Baader (1765-1841), Werke (Leipzig: H. Bethmann, 1850-1860), I, 475.
19 See A. Wolf (ed. & tr.), The Correspondence ofSpinoza (London: Frank Cass, 1966),
"Letter 52," p. 272. (Translation by F.W.)
20 Ibid., "Letter 17," p.I40.
21 R.H.M. Elwes (tr.), Chief Works of Benedict Spinoza, v.II, (Dover), "Ethics," Pt. II,
Ax. 3.
22 Ibid., v. I, Ch. 1, p. 15.
23 Ibid., pp. 24-25.
24 Francois Tristan L'Hermite (1601-1655), La Mariane. See Claude K. Abraham et al.
(eds.), Le thetitre complet de Tristan l'Hermite (University, Alabama: University of
Alabama Press, 1975), p.40.
25 Louis Ferrier de la Martiniere (1652-1721), Adraste, tragedie, in Theatre Francois
(Paris, 1737).
26 Isaac de Benserade, La mort d'Achille, et La dispute de ses armes, tragedie (Paris: A.
de Sammaville, 1637).
27 Tristan I'Hermite, Osman, Act II, sc.i, II. 327-332. See Claude K. Abraham, op. cit.,
p.7"->-o-____
28 . .J. SChelling,~erke (op.cit.), IV, 217.
2 Aristotle, The Parv Naturalia (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1908; ed. J .A. Beare), "De
, Divinatione per Somn m," Ch. II, 464a.
30 Franz von Baader, op.\cit., IV, 135.
31 Cf. Eduard von Hartrr\ann. Ausgewiihlte Werke, Bd. 13: Die Moderne Psychologie
(Leipzig: Haacke, 1900, pp. 32-36.
/
DREAM, IMAGINATION AND EXISTENCE 77
32 Ludwig Binswanger, "Der Fall Ellen West," in Schweizer Archiv fur Neurolo/iie und
Psychiatrie, v. 53 (1944), 225-277; v. 54 (1944),69-117,330-360; v. 55 (1945), 16-40;
"The Case of Ellen West," in Rollo May (ed.) Existence (New York: Basic Books,
1958), 237-364.
33 Quintilian, Institutes of Oratory Book l.
34 Plato, Republic (Baltimore, Md.: Penguin, 1958; tr. H.D.P. Lee), pp. 344-345 (Steph.
371 C-D).
35 "Discours sur les maladies melancoliques," Ch. VI.
36 Francois Tristan I'Hermite, La Mariane (loc. cit.), Act I, sc. ii, 11. 61-62, 69-79.
37 Friedrich von Hardenburg (1772-1801; pseudo Novalis), Werke, II, 114.
38 Quoted by Bovet, Intern. Zeitschrift Psychanalyse, VI, 354.
39 See Guy Davenport (tr.) Herakleitos and Diogenes (San Francisco: Grey Fox Press,
1979), Fragment No. 15, p.13.
40 Ludwig Binswanger, "Heraklits Auffassung der Menschen," Die Antike, v. XI, 1935.
Also in Binswanger, Ausgewiihlte Vortriige, op. cit., v. I.
41 Landermann, Die Transcendenz des Erkennens.
42 Friedrich von Hardenburg, op.cit., II, 114.
43 Johann G. von Herder, Ideen zur Philosophie der Geschichte der Menschheit (Berlin:
Deutscher Bibliotek, 1915).
44 Friedrich von Hardenburg, op.cit., III, 253.
45 Plato, Republic, op.cit., p. 345 (Steph. 57ID-572A). (English translation adapted to
reflect French text. F.W.)
46 Arnauld, Agamemnon, 1,1.
47 Frederic Lachevre (ed.), Les oeuvres libertines de Cyrano de Bergerac (Paris: Librarie
Ancienne Honore Champion, 1921), p. 136.
48 Shakespeare, Macbeth, II, ii, 36-40.
49 Shakespeare, Julius Caesar, II, ii, 10-11.
50 James Strachey (ed.), op. cit., v.7 (1901-1905), pp. 118-119.
51 Ibid., pp. 109-110& note.
52 Ibid., p. 120, n.1.
53 Ludwig Binswanger, Wandlungen der Auffassung und Deutung des Traumes von den
Griechen bis zum Gegenwart (Berlin: Springer, 1928).
54 Oskar Becker, "Beitrage zur phiinomenologischen Begriindung der Geometrie und ihrer
physikalischen Anwendung," in Jahrbuch for Philosophie und Phiinomenologische
Forschung (Halle: Max Niemeyer, 1923; ed. Edmund Husserl), 383-560. See Sec. 7,
pp. 446-459.
55 Edmund Husserl, The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology
(Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1970), tr. David Carr; Appendix VI,
"The Origin of Geometry," pp. 353-378.
56 Erwin W. Straus, Yom Sinn der Sinne (Berlin: Springer, 1935). The Primary World of
the Senses (tr. Jacob Needleman; New York: Free Press, 1963), pp. 318 et. seq.
57 Ludwig Binswanger, "Das Raumproblem in der Psychopathologie," in Zeitschrift for
die Neurologie, Ziirich, 1933.
58 Eugene Minkowski, "Esquisses Phenomenologiques," in Recherches Philosophiques
(Paris: Boivin), v. IV (1934-1935), 295-313.
59 Riirnke, Zur Phiinomenoiogie und Klinik des Gliickgefuhls (Springer: 1924).
60 Eugen Fink, Yom Wesen des Enthusiasmus (Freiburg i. Breisgau: Verlag Dr. Hans V.
Chamier, 1947). 12.
61 See n. 32, supra.
62 Cf. Fricdril:h Ilehhcl (11113-11163): "A strange dream: A night in which my seething
imaginulion wenl III its c!(treme in a dream so monstrous and so overwhelming that it
78 Michel Foucault
occurred seven more times. I had the impression that God had stretched a rope between
sky and earth, placed me on it, and proceeded to swing me. I flew up and down
vertiginously. Now I was among the clouds, my hair streaming in the wind, I held on,
shutting my eyes; now I was hurled so close to the ground that I could make out the
yellow sand, and the little white and red pebbles, and I felt as if I could touch it with
my foot. I would want to get off at that moment, but before I could do so, I felt myself
propelled once again into the air, and I could only hang onto the rope to keep from
falling and crashing to the ground." (Gerhard Fricke, ed., Hebbels Tagebiicher (Leipzig:
Phillipp Reclam, 1936.)
63 See n. 5, supra.
64 To the extent to which tragic expression is located on this vertical direction of existence,
it has an ontological root that gives it an absolute privilege over other modes of expression;
the latter are rather anthropological modulations.
65 Jean-Paul Sartre, L' imaginaire (Paris: Gallimard, 1940), p.163. (My translation.-F.W.)
Cf. J.-P. Sartre, The Psychology of Imagination (New York: Washington Square, 1966),
p. 161.
66 In certain schizophrenics, the theme of suicide is linked to the myth of rebirth.
67 Gaston Bachelard, L'air et les songes (Paris: Corti, 1943), p. 13.
68 Rene Char, Fureur et Mystere (Paris: Gallimard, 1948: 2nd ed.), p. 86 ("Partage Formel,
XXXIII"). Translator's note: The passage in the French text reads: "Au cours de son
action parmi les essarts de I'universalite du Verbe, Ie poete integre, avide, impressionable
et temeraire se gardera de sympathiser avec les entreprises qui alienent Ie prodige de la
liberte en poesie." (English translation in text supplied by Mary Ann Caws.)
69 Rene Char, ibid., "Partage Formel, XVII," p.81. Translator's note: The passage in the
French text reads: "Le poete peut alors voir les contraires,--ces mirages ponctuels et
tumultueux,-aboutir, leur lignee immanente se personnifier, poesie et verite, etant,
come nous savons, synonymes. " (English translation in text supplied by Mary Ann Caws.)
70 Rene Char, ibid., "Partage Formel, XXXVII," p. 87. Translator's note: The passage in
the French text reads: "n ne depend que de la necessite et de votre volupte qui me
creditent que j'aie ou non Ie Visage de I'echange." (English translation in text supplied
by Mary Ann Caws.)
71 Rene Char, ibid., "Partage Formel, LV," p.92. Translator's note: The passage in the
French text reads: "Sans doute appartient-il it cet homme de fond en comble aux prises
avec Ie mal dont il connait Ie visage vorace et medullaire, de transformer Ie fait fabuleux
en fait historique. Notre conviction inquiete ne doit Ie denigrer, mais l'interroger, nous
fervents tueurs d'etres reels dans la personne successive de notre chimere ... L'evasion
dans son semblable avec d'immenses promesses de poesie sera peut-etre unjour possible."
(English translation in text supplied by Mary Ann Caws.)