Delancey (1981)
Delancey (1981)
Delancey (1981)
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
SCOTT DELANCEY
University of Colorado
Nominative/absolutive case and verb agreement are, in many languages, indicators of
a category which is here called VIEWPOINT: the perspective from which the speaker
describes the event. The order of NP constituents in a sentence encodes ATTENTION
FLOW, which is the order in which the speaker expects the hearer to attend to them.
Split ergative case-marking patterns are shown to reflect conflicts between the most
natural viewpoint and attention-flow assignments. It is argued that the characterization
and grammatical marking of an event as first-hand or inferred knowledge for a speaker,
and as intentional or inadvertent for an actor, can be described in terms of whether the
entire event or only its terminal phase is directly accessible to the conscious mind of the
speaker and the actor, respectively; and that these categories can also be described in
terms of attention flow and viewpoint.*
* The ideas presented in this paper were developed in the course of work done in collaboration
with LaRaw Maran and Lon Diehl; credit for any merit which the hypothesis advanced here may
possess is at least as much theirs as mine. The deficiencies of the paper are, of course, my own
responsibility. Part of this paper was presented at the 1979 Winter LSA Meeting under the title
'Viewpoint, attention flow, and subject-coding properties'.
626
1.2. THE EH-SPLIT PATTERN. The SE pattern which has received the most
recent attention is one governed by the variously-called hierarchy of 'animacy',
'agentivity', 'topicality', 'salience', or 'empathy', by which Ist and 2nd persons
(hereafter SPEECH-ACT PARTICIPANTS, or SAP's) outrank human 3rd persons,
' In much of this paper, I will use the term 'agent' quite loosely, to include roles (such as that
of a perceiver) which are not analysed as being agentive in most versions of Case Theory, but
which in many languages pattern with true transitive agents with respect to the morpho-syntactic
patterns discussed here. The theoretical status of this broad use of 'agent' will be discussed in
?3.3; agentivity in the strict sense will be discussed briefly in ?6.
2 In the light of the discussion in ??3-4, this distinction might be considered criterial for distin-
guishing voice from SE alternations; however, it doesn't correlate perfectly with the standard
criterion, by which voice alternations are those marked with a special form of the verb associated
with one voice alternant. (Cf. the Sinhalese 'passive' discussed in ?6.1.)
3The most common factor governing voice alternations, both active/passive and ergative/anti-
passive, is of course the discourse-based thematicity or 'communicative dynamism' of one or both
of the two NP's in the transitive sentence. This factor clearly is related to the factors discussed
in this paper. The interaction between the 'empathy' or 'animacy' hierarchy and topicality has
long been known; and recent studies (e.g. Hopper 1979, Hopper & Thompson 1980) have shown
an interaction between information structure and aspect. However, the questions implied here are
beyond the scope of this paper.
1.3. THE ASPECTUAL SPLIT. The other SE pattern is the aspectual split, in
which ergative morphology is associated with perfective aspect or past tense,
and accusative morphology with imperfective aspect, or with present or future
tense. Attested in a few Australian, Austronesian, and Mayan languages, this
pattern also occurs in an area extending from North India to the Caucasus-
including a number of Indo-Iranian languages, several Caucasian languages,
a few Tibeto-Burman languages, and Burushaski, a language isolate spoken in
northern Pakistan. A typical case is Gujarati (Mistry 1976):
(6) ramesh pen kharid-t-o ha-t-o.
(masc.) (fem.) buy-IMPF-MASC AUX-IMPF-MASC
'Ramesh was buying the pen.'
4 Not all patients are marked with -lay; however, its distribution is not, as might appear, an
instance of the widely-reported pattern in which all and only patients high on the EH are mark
for accusative case. Rather, the -lay postposition is used generally with definite patients (Watte
1973:199-202).
This shows that, in terms of the analysis to be presented below, Nepali agreement is with semantic
Source rather than with starting-point. This seems to be a fairly unusual pattern.
3.1. The explanation which I propose for the patterns described above is
based on two ultimately psychological notions, ATTENTION FLOW (hereafter AF)
and VIEWPOINT. These notions are invoked within a view of semantics which
takes a significant part of the semantic structure of a language to be a list o
prototype scenes, each specified for a canonical set of participants (cf. Fillmor
1977a,b). A sentence describes a real or imagined event by invoking th
prototype scene of which it counts as an instance, and by identifying th
participant roles in the prototype with entities which exist in the universe of
discourse. In actual communication, not all aspects of the prototype event ar
of equal interest, and all languages have mechanisms for marking the relativ
communicative importance of the various entities and events in a sentence o
discourse. Viewpoint and AF are fundamentally parameters which contribute
to determining the relative interest of various entities involved in an actual
witnessed event; but the terms are also applicable to linguistic mechanisms
which indicate values for these parameters in a sentence, thus allowing it to
be interpreted in a manner analogous to that of an actual event. I will distinguish
these two uses of the terms, where necessary, as NATURAL VS. LINGUISTIC A
and viewpoint-the former referring to perceptual strategies, the latter to lin
guistic mechanisms. As we will see, case-marking, verb-agreement and voice
marking, and constituent order (the mechanisms involved in SE, voice, and
other alternation patterns) are the chief markers of linguistic viewpoint and
AF.
3.2. ATTENTION FLOW determines the linear order of NP's. The NP's in a
sentence are presented in the order in which the speaker wishes the hearer to
attend to them. Alternate NP orderings, as found in voice alternations and
topicalizing shifts, are mechanisms for managing AF.
Events have an inherent natural AF, which recreates the flow of attention
involved in actually witnessing the event. The basis of this natural AF is the
'o Mistry argues that agreement is dependent on case-marking; but without an explanatory
account of the case-marking pattern, this cannot be considered an explanation for either. Mistry's
evidence suggests that, in fact, case-marking and agreement are independently governed by aspect,
rather than one being contingent on the other (cf. fn. 11, below).
" Gujarati has a 'split accusative' case-marking pattern (cf. fn. 4), with the result that, in perfect
clauses with animate patients, both agent and patient are marked for case. In such clauses, agree-
ment is still with patient, which suggests that agreement and case-marking are independent of one
another, though subject to some of the same governing factors (in particular, aspect).
12 The terms Source, Goal, and Theme are taken from the work of Gruber (e.g. 1976): in a
motion event, they refer to the onset point, the terminal point, and the moving entity, respectively.
In other words, the prototype motion event involves a Theme which moves from Source to Goal.
'3 The term 'subject-forming language' is from Anderson 1979; like Li & Thompson's (1976)
'subject-prominent language' and Hale & Watters' (1973) 'subject-object language', this term im-
plies the claim that 'subject' is not a relevant category in all languages.
14 I owe these examples to Lon Diehl.
'5 There is considerable evidence for considering that Agent and giver are subcategories of a
fundamental case-category which also includes Source, and that Patient and receiver constitute
a single category with Goal (see Anderson 1971, 1977, Diehl 1975, Fillmore 1977a). I will use
Source and Goal to refer to these broader categories (as in fn. 7), as well as in their narrower
spatial sense.
16 I have no explanation for the fact that SO is not the universal pattern.
17 As suggested in fn. 3, there are grounds for supposing that the complex of factors called
topicality or thematicity may be analysable in terms of the viewpoint category.
l' This is perhaps in part because linguists have become accustomed to analysing artificial
sentences having no pragmatic connection to any actual event or discourse context. It is interesting
that linguists' examples very seldom involve 1st or 2nd person participants.
'9 Cf. the discussion by Tesniere 1959 of valence, and of causativization as an increase in
valence-in which it is pointed out that all three-place verbs can be considered, at least seman-
tically, as causative versions of two-place verbs; thus give is equivalent to cause to have.
alternative go. This is the most concrete possible instance of viewpoint spec-
ification: the speaker describes an event from a particular location, which is
his actual location in space. Of course, Eng. come and its equivalents in many
other languages are not limited to this concrete use as markers of natural
viewpoint. For various social and narrative purposes (cf. Fillmore 1966, 1975),
a speaker will often take some contextually recoverable location other than
his own as his linguistic viewpoint, and mark a motion event as oriented toward
that point by the use of come.
In English and many other languages, the marking of viewpoint for simple
motion events is entirely lexical. Motion verbs which are semantically more
complex than come/go and bring/take are not specified for viewpoint orien-
tation, though many of them have lexical alternatives, built on go and come,
which are used if viewpoint specification is necessary. It is worth noting that
these specified alternates, e.g. go/come back or go/come out, are much more
colloquial than their neutral counterparts, return and exit; this reflects their
much greater frequency in actual pragmatically constrained speech. Some lan-
guages use morphological or syntactic, rather than lexical, mechanisms for this
function.20 For example, in Jinghpaw, a Tibeto-Burman language of Yunnan
and northern Burma, the deictic orientation of sentences like 25-26 is provided
not by the motion-verb sequence sa wa, which is identical in the two examples
but by the r- and n- morphemes which precede the agreement-markers:
(25) MaGam gat de sa wa n-u 2 ai.
market to go n-3rd IND
'MaGam {is going/has gone} to market.'
(26) MaGam gat de sa wa r-u ? ai.
market to go r-3rd IND
'MaGam {is coming/will come} to market.'
Here the r- morpheme specifies terminal viewpoint; i.e., the speaker's view-
point is the terminal point of the motion. The n- morpheme, like Eng. go,
permits either onset or external viewpoint interpretation. (This and my other
Jinghpaw examples are discussed at greater length in DeLancey 1978, 1980;
see also Maran 1978, 1979.)
Viewpoint considerations can provide the motivation for alternative order-
ings of spatial Source and Goal, as in 18-19. One possible motivation for the
Goal-first order in to Philadelphiafrom Bloomington would be that Philadelphia
was the location of the speech act. This distribution of sentence alternants with
respect to speech situations is parallel to that of go and come. The more marked
lexical alternant come is used when the actual location of the speech act, or
the contextually established viewpoint, is the Goal of the motion event; the
same conditions can motivate the more marked Goal-Source order of con-
stituents. Such a use in 19 represents the sacrifice of natural AF to natural
viewpoint.
20 A few languages have no specific mechanism for indicating viewpoint with verbs of motion;
Russian is a well-known example.
21 This is etymologically a grammaticalized verb 'come'. F. K. Lehman (p.c.) points out that
ex. 31 can also mean 'He will come and give it.'
22 Goal and Source are here used in the extended sense of fn. 15.
23 The vagueness of sentences like 34b, with regard to whether the Source was actually a willing
giver, is irrelevant here-though it is relevant to a complete discussion of the choice of give or
get as natural or inverted AF. I suspect that get sentences in which Source is not mentioned are,
like the analogous agentless passives, far more common than sentences like 34b in which AF is
aztually reversed.
24 This has sometimes been claimed to be a difference in grammaticality, but it certainly is not
(see Kato 1979).
25 The interaction between these and other factors in determining linguistic starting point in
English is discussed in illuminating detail in MacWhinney 1977.
4.2. THE SAP/3RD PERSON SPLIT. Consider again Kham sentences 1-4:
(1)' nga: nan-lay nga-poh-ni-ke.
I yOU-OBJ IA-hit-2P-PERF 'I hit you.'
(2) nan nga-lay na-poh-na-ke.
you I-OBJ 2A-hit-IP-PERF 'You hit me.
(3) nan no-lay na-poh-ke.
you he-OBi 2A-hit-PERF 'You hit him.
(4) no-e nan-lay poh-na-ke-o.
he-ERG you-OBJ hit-2P-PERF-3A 'He hit you.
26 A split may also occur when, for example, agreement codes neither viewpoint nor starting-
point, but a deep case-role, as in Nepali (?2.3).
is also the agent, i.e. the natural starting-point. When it is also an SAP, i.e.
a natural viewpoint locus, it is so marked by being in the nominative ca
Otherwise, it must be marked for ergative case, which identifies it as the natural
starting-point.
Since the Kham verb agrees with two NP's, agreement cannot be associate
with viewpoint in the same straightforward manner as in English or Gujar
(cf. ?6.1). Nevertheless the Kham agreement pattern reflects natural viewpoi
and in a particularly interesting way. SAP patient-markers (glossed 1P, 2P) a
suffixed directly to the verb root; there is no 3rd person patient-marker. S
agent-markers (IA, 2A) are prefixed (as in exx. 1-3). The 3rd person agent-
marker, however, occurs to the right of all other suffixes (including the pati
suffixes), as in 4. Thus unmarked constituent order places natural starting
point first,27 regardless of natural viewpoint; but the order of agreement affixes
places natural viewpoint first, regardless of natural AF. Note that this analy
requires that 1st and 2nd persons count as equally natural viewpoint loci, a
no ranking is reflected in affix order. This is what is predicted by the Viewpoint
Hypothesis, since both SAP's are prototypically located at the deictic cente
of the speech act.28 Note that no ranking of the SAP's is indicated by the ca
marking pattern either; exx. 1-2 show that either SAP, when it is the natu
starting-point, is marked as natural viewpoint (by lack of case-marking), eve
when the other SAP is present. The same pattern is reflected in the distribut
of Sizang/Tiddim (h)ong-, which can occur whenever there is an SAP Go
even when Source is the other SAP. These facts are among the data indicati
that the most natural situation is one in which viewpoint and starting-poin
coincide.
The explanation given above for the Kham affixation pattern receives con-
firmation from an alteration of the pattern which occurs in the passive con-
struction. Here constituent order is reversed,29 and the verb is marked with
an -o passive suffix (examples from Watters 1973):
(39) nga: ao zihmld nga-li-ke.
I this house lA-stay-PERF
'I stayed in this house.'
(40) ao zihmld nga: nga-li-o.
this house I lA-stay-PAss
'This house was lived in by me.'
27 The critical reader will have noted already that my remarks on English in ?4.1 do not consider
topicalization phenomena such as those termed 'secondary' by Fillmore 1968 or 'sentence-level'
by Foley & Van Valin 1977. In sentences like Him I won't listen to, the leftmost NP is marked
for case and does not control agreement. Similar exceptional instances occur in Kham and in most,
if not all, of the other languages discussed in this paper. The relationship of such phenomena to
the primary topicalization phenomena (e.g. passivization) in terms of the framework proposed here
remains to be elucidated (see fn. 3).
28 There are languages which rank the SAP's in one or the other order (Silverstein 1976, Dixon
1979, and see ?4.3 below). I assume such rankings to be arbitrary.
29 The passive verb form also has several uses in which natural constituent order is retained
(see Watters 1973, 1975).
30 In the perfective and negative paradigms, Nocte shows traces of an earlier direct-making
suffix which came after the agreement-marker; unfortunately the traces are not sufficient to indicate
its distribution (in particular, there is no evidence as to whether it marked the lst->2nd or the
3rd-*3rd configurations). Available details are given in DeLancey 1980.
31 In some North American languages, 3rd->3rd configurations are marked. In the Algonquian
languages, proximate A --- obviative P counts as a direct configuration, and obviative A -> prox-
imate P as inverse. Whistler describes a direction-marking system in Nootka which seems to be
sensitive to discourse-based thematicity when two 3rd person participants are involved; this pro-
vides further evidence for the relevance of the Viewpoint Hypothesis to the study of topicality.
32 The data as presented in Jin et al. are under-analysed; the analysis presented here is justified
in DeLancey 1980.
33 It is not exactly the same when dual and plural NP's are involved; according to the paradigms
presented by Jin et al., the distribution of the ergative marker follows a very complicated pattern-
so that, for example, Ist person dual (but not singular or plural) agents take ergative case with 2nd
person dual or plural (but not singular) patients. The distribution of the inverse marker shows no
such sensitivity, but 3rd--3rd configurations are marked as inverse when agent is dual or plural,
but direct when agent is singular (the ergative marker remains throughout).
Both Blackfoot and Ojibwa assign agreement prefixes according to the same
system as Potawatomi; but again, the direction-marking system reflects a less
clear-cut hierarchy. Ojibwa distinctly marks each of the four categories, show-
34 On my analysis, Jyarong also has a direct morpheme, but it does not occur in the examples
cited here, and its explication would be irrelevant. It is described in DeLancey 1980.
35 The 2nd-,1st configuration also has a separate mark. the substitution of kd- for ta-. One of
these occurs in every configuration, transitive or intransitive, which involves a 2nd person. This
series is discussed at greater length in Bauman 1975 and DeLancey 1980.
36 An earlier version of this paper, circulated by the Indiana University Linguistics Club, cited
Blackfoot forms from Uhlenbeck 1938 which were not correct. I am grateful to Allan Taylor for
pointing this out to me and furnishing the correct paradigm.
ing clearly that any ranking of the two SAP's is of a different order than t
ranking of SAP's over other NP's. Of particular interest to the present argum
is the Blackfoot system, which marks 2nd-> st as inverse, so that the direct
system reflects a Ist>2nd ranking, rather than the 2nd> st ranking sugges
by the order of agreement prefixes. Blackfoot thus presents evidence that t
ranking of 2nd>lst not only lacks universal validity (as suggested by Silver
stein), but also lacks strong motivation even in those languages which manif
it. We may conclude that both 2nd>lst and lst>2nd are possible variatio
on the universal SAP>3rd theme.
4.4. VIEWPOINT AND THE EH. I have so far accounted for only the high en
of the EH-the distinction between SAP's and all other NP's, which is equiv-
alent to the distinction between the spatial deictic center and everywhere el
The EH also encompasses a ranking of various types of full NP's. A ful
statement of the hierarchy, incorporating all the widely-attested distinctio
with which I am familiar, is:
SAP's > 3rd pronouns > human > animate > natural forces > inanimate
Only the two highest splits-SAP's over everything else and pronouns o
full NP's-are widely-attested as governing SE marking; and so far as I khow
only the SAP>3rd split ever governs direction-marking. Nevertheless, a nu
ber of other apparently viewpoint-related phenomena are governed by the r
of the EH. Consider, for example, the account given by Hawkinson & Hym
1974 of agreement in Shona, a Bantu language of Zimbabwe. In Shona, as in
many African languages, the verb is marked with a prefix reflecting the no
class of the subject. If the subject is a conjoined NP including nouns of two
different classes, agreement will be plural, but noun-class agreement is wi
the noun which is higher on the EH:
(52) murlume ne imbwa va-ka-famba.
man and dog NC-PAST-walk
'The man and the dog walked.'
(53) *murume ne imbwa dza'-ka-fJmba.
man and dog NC-PAST-walk
The conjoined NP 'man and dog' can be cross-referenced only by the plura
human prefix va, not by the animate plural prefix dza. Moreover, in such
conjoined NP, the noun higher on the EH must be the starting-point of linguisti
AF:
37 The argument in this section is given in more detail and with further exemplification in
DeLancey 1979.
40 Some readers of an earlier draft of this paper objected, correctly, that since the inferred age
in this construction is in dative rather than ergative case (note that Georgian has a distinct ergati
case), the perfect should not be considered an ergative construction. However, the important p
for my purpose is that the agent is marked for a case other than nominative, and thus is mar
as not being the viewpoint NP.
of Kemal's arrival, but has not yet seen Kemal himself; but it could
used if the speaker opens the front door to Kemal's knock and
standing there, providing that Kemal's visit comes as a surprise-i.e.
he opened the door, the speaker had no idea that Kemal might be c
Syuwa, a Tibetan language of Nepal, has a similar semantic ca
which an inferential construction 'is also used when the speaker re
event whose temporal origin is inaccessible to him' (Hoehlig 1978:21
(64) dang kongmu nuphela singha durbar nangla mei chii-d
yesterday night midnight (place name) inside fire burn-P
'Yesterday evening in the middle of the night a fire broke
Singha Durbar [it seems].'
This is spoken by someone who had gone to watch the fire, and thus
hand knowledge that a fire had broken out, but hadn't been there to
VIEWPOINT, ATTENTION FLOW, AND AGENTIVITY
41 The characterization of this verb form as 'passive' is quite misleading, as pointed out by Gair
1970. What Gair calls the 'P' form of the verb can occur with intransitive as well as transitive
verbs, with the same reading of inadvertence. This alternation of verb form in Sinhala is thus
functionally equivalent to the case-marking alternation in the 'active' languages discussed in ?6.3.
42 There is also a capabilitive interpretation, reminiscent of the use of the Ilocano passive
described by Schwartz 1976, the reading of which is that the agent is capable of or good at the act
described.
the event can be taken as the viewpoint only if earlier phases took place outside
the actor's awareness.
43 The 'passive' examples might well be glossed 'got himself V-ed', in order to approximate th
actual force of the Navajo sentences; cf. below and Witherspoon.
CONCLUSION
46 There is some reason to believe that the distinction between old and new information can be
interpreted as a deictic notion, and thus that the pronoun vs. full-NP split pattern may also have
a deictic interpretation. Note, for example, in ?4.3, that some North American direction-marking
systems treat the proximal 3rd -> obviative 3rd configuration as direct, and obviate -- proximal
as inverse.
47 Other manifestations of this interpretation of the event vector have been described in unpub-
becoming real, and the terminal point its culmination in reality. In these
guages, viewpoint placed at the starting-point indicates that the event is tra
from its inception; terminal viewpoint indicates that the event enters consc
awareness only when it is realized. The difference between the marking o
inference vs. first-hand knowledge and inadvertence vs. volition is that t
first distinction represents the point of view of an external observer
speaker-while the second represents a point of view associated with the a
in the event. (In this connection, it is interesting that the marking of volitional
in Batsbi is applicable only to SAP's; in other words, one does not mak
insupportable inferences about the awareness of 3rd persons.)
Thus the framework suggested here allows a unitary account of sev
apparently disparate phenomena. It should be noted that the basic concept
invoked here, viz. viewpoint and AF, do not have to be taken as given in
sense of the 'primes' of Relational Grammar, or of the 'core semantico-sy
tactic relations' named by Dixon (1979:61): transitive subject, transitive obje
and intransitive subject. They are, rather, hypotheses about human cogni
and perceptual structure; as such, they are subject to empirical investigat
by methods other than those of theoretical linguistics.48
REFERENCES
lished work by Lon Diehl. Note, for example, the use of forms meaning 'via' as agent-markers,
as in English. Uhlenbeck apparently came to a similar analysis, based in part on examination of
'active' languages, but considered it characteristic only of the primitive mind. The relevant passage
is cited in Sapir 1917.
48 Work in this direction has been undertaken; see MacWhinney 1977, Zubin 1979, and references
cited by them.