Legalizing Misandry

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 903

LEGALIZING MISANDRY

Legalizing Misandry
From Public Shame to Systemic
Discrimination against Men

PAUL NATHANSON and


KATHERINE K. YOUNG
© McGill-Queen’s University Press 2006
ISBN-13: 978-0-7735-2862-8 ISBN-10: 0-7735-2862-8

Legal deposit first quarter 2006


Bibliothèque nationale du Québec

Printed in Canada on acid-free paper

This book has been published with the help of a grant from the Canadian
Federation for the Humanities and Social Sciences, through the Aid to
Scholarly Publications Programme, using funds provided by the Social
Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada.

McGill-Queen’s University Press acknowledges the support of the


Canada Council for the Arts for our publishing program. We also
acknowledge the financial support of the Government of Canada
through the Book Publishing Industry Development Program (BPIDP) for
our publishing activities.

Library and Archives Canada Cataloguing in Publication

Nathanson, Paul, 1947–


Legalizing misandry : from public shame to systematic
discrimination
against men / Paul Nathanson and Katherine K. Young.

Includes index.
ISBN-13: 978-0-7735-2862-8 ISBN-10: 0-7735-2862-8

1. Misandry – Canada. 2. Misandry – United States. 3. Sex


discrimination against men – Canada. 4. Sex discrimination against men
– United States. I. Young, Katherine K., 1944– II. Title.

HQ1090.N367 2006 305.32′0971 C2005–902483–6

Typeset in 10/12 Sabon with Frutiger display by True to Type


Contents

Acknowledgements

Introduction

PART ONE MEN ON TRIAL: THE COURT OF PUBLIC OPINION

1 Children v. Demons: The McMartin and Other Witch Hunts

2 Wives v. Abusers: The Bobbitt Affair

3 Workers v. Harassers: The Hill-Thomas Debate

4 Martyrs v. Murderers: The Montreal Massacre

PART TWO RIGHTS ON TRIAL: MONEY MATTERS

5 Women’s Rights v. Human Rights: The Case of Entitlements

6 Maternal Rights v. Paternal Rights: The Case of Children

PART THREE SEX ON TRIAL: FROM LIBERATION TO SEPARATION

7 Power v. Pleasure: The Case of Pornography/Prostitution

8 Separatists v. Integrationists: The Case of Sexual Harassment

9 Female Victims v. Male Victims: The Case of Violence against


Women
PART FOUR SOCIETY ON TRIAL: FROM CLASSROOM TO LEGISLATURE

10 Ideological Feminism v. Scholarship

11 Misandry v. Equality

APPENDICES

1 Responding to Our Critics: Spreading Misandry Revisited

2 Birth of the Bogeyman: One Subtext of Modern Witch Hunts

3 Misleading the Public: Statistics Abuse

4 Silencing men: The Trouble with Political Correctness

5 Respectable Porn: The Debate over Romance Novels

6 Bargaining at Beijing: United Nations or United Women

7 Paved with Entitlements: The Road to Caste

8 Here Come the Feds: Studies of Affirmative Action and Pay Equity

9 Dissing Dads: The Debate over Custody

10 Gynotopia: Feminism at Academic Conferences

11 A Front by Any Other Name: Ideology, Gender Studies, and Women’s


Studies
12 What’s Sauce for the Goose: Double Standards in a Government
Report

13 Take That! Comparative Victimology

Notes

Index
Acknowledgments

We would like to thank the many people who helped make this book
possible. Some responded to our requests for legal and statistical
information: Augustina J. Kposowa, Grant Brown, and Brian Jenkins.
Christopher Gray read several chapters and offered his comments. Jane
Aiken has granted us permission to publish some of her material. Nicolas
Lambe and Tara McPhail helped us with our legal citations. Our editor, Ron
Curtis, read the manuscript very carefully; he not only corrected typos but
also provided many worthwhile editorial suggestions. Finally we are
grateful to the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council for its
financial support.
Introduction

One sure sign of danger at any time and in any place is a segment of the
population that society considers unworthy of attention. No wonder more
boys than girls face the future with apathy and drop out of school.1 Worse,
far more young men than young women are committing suicide. Ditto for
old men and old women.2 Males are not faring well at all in a society that is
now focused explicitly on the needs and problems of females and is often
hostile to the very possibility that males might have any distinct needs and
problems of their own. Rapid social change and depression have been listed
as causes of these problems, but the question is why these factors affect
men, especially young men, much more than they do women.
These are complex problems, to be sure, and have more than one
explanation (as we will show in Transcending Misandry, the third volume
of this trilogy; the first volume, Spreading Misandry, was published in
2001). Underlying many explanations, though, is a distinctly gynocentric
world-view. Being woman-centred, by definition, gynocentrism ignores the
needs and problems of men. (The irony is that it was originally adopted to
correct the biases of an androcentric, or man-centred, worldview.) And
because gynocentrism now has both official status (in law) and quasi-
official status (in institutional policies), its bias has become deeply
embedded in public policy. That status has created and even
institutionalized a new double standard, one that favours women instead of
men and that, in turn, has created many additional problems: psychological,
political, and – above all – moral ones. It is hard to know precisely how
these problems affect boys and men personally, but it is worth noting that
no large-scale study has ever been done to find out. It would be folly to
ignore the warning signs mentioned above, in our opinion, but that is
precisely what has been happening.
At least one bar association has seen fit to threaten male dissenters,
concluding a report on women with a stern warning. Men, it says, will try to
stop affirmative action, deny their bias, refuse to understand the nature of
systemic barriers to women, or even institute a backlash with stereotypes
embedded in misogynistic messages, anecdotes, myths, and homilies or
“accusations … [that women are] ‘whining’ or being ‘provocative’ when
legitimate complaints are raised.”3 From our point of view, this report – one
that relies on its own stereotypes – has gone beyond gynocentrism and
embraced misandry.
Gynocentrism is the self-centred counterpart of androcentrism, and
misandry is the sexist counterpart of misogyny. From the very beginning of
this volume, we must be as clear as we were in the earlier volume about one
thing. We define hatred as a collectively shared and culturally propagated
worldview, not a personal emotion such as dislike or anger. Ultimately, this
worldview is always expressed as “our” contempt for “them.” Misandry, as
such, has never been either legal or illegal. In a technical sense, therefore, it
cannot be legalized in the same way that, say, marijuana can be legalized.
Nonetheless, overt expressions of hatred toward specific groups are indeed
illegal. Our point here is that hatred toward men is just as unacceptable
morally as hatred toward any other group and should therefore be just as
unacceptable legally.
Some people are aware of misandry but fervently believe that hatred
toward men should be regarded as a legitimate exception to the general rule
against hatred toward other groups. Most people find it hard even to notice
misandry. The very idea seems counterintuitive. Men, according to
conventional wisdom, have all the power. Therefore, presumably, they are
immune to all serious harm. Besides, no one has ever called explicitly for
discrimination against men or against any other segment of the population.
After all, modern democracies and their legal systems are based explicitly
on the rhetoric of equality. Yet many people have called explicitly for
discrimination in favour of women – that is, legal measures to solve
problems faced only by women. As a result, women have gained special
protections: for example, the right to job security and benefits during
pregnancy. These reforms, which were originally welcomed in the name of
fairness, were soon extended to include measures such as affirmative action.
Designed to “level the playing field,” these measures were supposed
ultimately to create equality by institutionalizing temporary inequality
(although it was by no means self-evident that they could ever be
terminated, no matter how much conditions might change, without a major
political upheaval).
The goal was to raise the prospects of women, advocates explained, not
to lower those of men. The result, nonetheless, was that gynocentrism and
even misandry entered through the back door. Feminists explained the need
for these legal measures by blaming the problems of women directly and
exclusively on men, who were the scapegoats. Women were a victim class,
said feminist lobby groups, and men the oppressor class. If men suffered
from the new discrimination, they added, then so be it; men were
collectively guilty and deserved collective punishment. No wonder many
people, including some men, accepted the notion that it was morally
acceptable to impose legal obligations, penalties, and restrictive conditions
on men but not on women. No wonder, also, that they found it morally
acceptable to use hate legislation as a way of protecting women and
minorities from negative stereotypes but not to as a way of protecting men
from equally negative stereotypes.
By now, our legal systems are based firmly on double standards. No
matter how liberal, no matter how complacent, men who end up in court
over conflicts with women soon discover these double standards not only in
connection with custody and child support but also in connection with
accusations of domestic violence and even in the reversal of such basic
legal principles as the presumption that they are innocent unless proven
guilty. Discrimination against men is by now so pervasively
institutionalized that it is best described as systemic and characteristic of the
legal system as a whole. Here, then, is the connection between the attitudes
generated by misandry in popular culture and their institutionalization in
policy and law.

Before proceeding, it is worth pausing to review what we said in Spreading


Misandry. That book was primarily about the various ways in which men
are seen by society and the negative stereotypes of men that became
pervasive during the 1990s. Our goal was to demonstrate that misandry had
become deeply embedded in popular culture. Though by no means the only
interesting pattern that could be found in popular culture, it was very
common and had not yet been explored systematically by other scholars.
Popular culture takes many forms. We discussed it in connection with
the entertainment industry and some of its offshoots: movies, television
shows, comic strips, greeting cards, and so on. Even though the productions
we examined revealed a profoundly misandric worldview, they usually did
so indirectly, implicitly, and unintentionally (except, of course, for talk
shows and newsmagazines). As feminists had been doing for thirty years
(not without initial resistance from skeptical commentators), we pointed out
their sexist subtexts, according to which men may be stereotyped as either
evil or inadequate; a few exceptions are allowed for “honorary women”
(that is, either minority men or men who have “converted” to feminism).
Most of Spreading Misandry was devoted to description. But toward the
end of it (and leading directly to this book), we discussed what underlies
misandry. This phenomenon did not originate spontaneously at the grass-
roots level but was initiated and is still promoted by a segment of the
academic elite that is affiliated with one branch of feminism. We called that
branch “ideological feminism,” for two reasons.
First, we wanted to distinguish it from the egalitarian feminism of the
1960s, which is probably still the most popular form of feminism, at least
on the conscious level and in theory. Equality is a noble ideal. After
publishing our first book, in fact, we found that many egalitarian feminists
– especially those with sons – were willing to take seriously our
observations on the negative portrayal of men in popular culture and even
on the origin of that negativity in other forms of feminism. Although they
supported the reforms that had improved women’s lives over the past
century, they recognized that reforms carried too far were creating injustices
for men and boys (which would not bode well for society as a whole in the
long run). Two wrongs, they agreed, did not make a right.
Second, we wanted to link ideological feminism with other political
ideologies on both the political left and the political right. Throughout
Spreading Misandry, we referred specifically to ideological feminists or
feminist ideologues. And of course it was understood that some women are
indifferent to feminism and others hostile to it.
Ideological feminism is the direct heir of both the Enlightenment and
Romanticism. From the former it takes the theory of class conflict, merely
substituting “gender” for “class” and “patriarchy” for “bourgeoisie.” From
the latter it takes the notion of nation or even race, focusing ultimately on
the innate biological differences between women and men. The worldview
of ideological feminism, like that of both Marxism and National Socialism
– our analogies are between ways of thinking, not between specific ideas –
is profoundly dualistic. In effect, “we” (women) are good, “they” (men) are
evil. Or, to use the prevalent lingo, “we” are victims, “they” are oppressors.
This particular feminist world-view reveals several additional and closely
related features that are characteristic of ideologies on both sides of the
political spectrum: essentialism (in this case, calling attention to the unique
qualities of women), hierarchy (alleging directly or indirectly that women
are superior to men), collectivism (asserting that the rights of individual
men are less important than the communal goals of women), utopianism
(establishing an ideal social order within history), selective cynicism
(directing systematic suspicion only toward men), revolutionism (adopting
a political program that goes beyond reform), consequentialism (asserting
the belief that ends can justify means), and quasi-religiosity (creating what
amounts to a secular religion).
We defined ideological feminism very precisely. Trouble is, discussing
feminism is often tantamount to discussing personal and collective identity.
And identity is seldom established and never defended on the basis of
argument or negotiation. No matter what we say, some feminists are going
to accuse us of attacking all feminists or even all women. Yet doing that
would be counterproductive, because it would imply that some of our
offending claims are indeed true of all feminists or all women and must
therefore be defended.
Our larger point was that gynocentrism and its misandric fallout – the
cumulative results of ideological feminism – have transformed elite culture.
They have become pervasive enough in academic, legal, and political
circles to pass for conventional wisdom. They have become ways of
thinking that seem self-evident and thus require no explanation, let alone
justification.
In view of all this, it is worth remembering our primary conclusion: that
contempt for men – the idea that men can be classified only as evil or
inadequate, or as honorary women – has been a recurring theme in popular
culture for over a decade. We did not conclude that contempt for women
has been absent from popular culture, by the way, although we did point out
that misogyny, unlike misandry, has been carefully monitored, declared
politically incorrect, and publicly excoriated.
When Spreading Misandry was published in 2001, the topic was hot
enough for journalists to cover – we were interviewed for many
newspapers, radio shows, and television shows – but not hot enough to be
taken seriously by most of them. In some cases, it was the equivalent of a
publicity stunt; the goal was to hook readers or viewers with sensationalism
– prejudice against men, of all people! – not to explore a social problem
with profound moral implications. Print journalists often admitted that men
had been portrayed unfairly in popular culture during the 1990s but pointed
out that the situation had changed. The culture wars, they declared, were
over. Misandry (though not necessarily misogyny) was gone, they opined,
along with titillating jokes about Bill Clinton. Men and women were now
getting along just fine, thank you very much. How did they know that? By
asking a few of their co-workers at the water cooler. Their attitude might be
explained as naive optimism, unconscious denial, political strategy,
ideological ridicule, or whatever. The point is that many – not all, by any
means, but many – of those who direct public opinion found it either
desirable or necessary to trivialize our warning about the increasing
polarization of men and women (along with other groups making use of
identity politics) in our society. We respond to our critics in appendix 1 of
this book.

In this second volume, Legalizing Misandry, we focus on the interface


between popular culture and elite culture at the end of the twentieth century
and the beginning of the twenty-first. This is the realm not of movie moguls
and media mavens but of lawyers, legislators, and journalists, a realm that
not merely reflects a worldview created by others but creates,
institutionalizes, and even enforces that worldview.
To create a symbolic, or structural, framework for all this, we use two
closely related metaphors: litigation and revolution. The early stages of
most great revolutions of the last few hundred years – those of the English,
the French, and the Russians, for instance – were marked by litigation
(trials of monarchs blamed for the misery) that led to revolution.
First, consider the metaphor of litigation. In part 1 we show that men as a
“class” have been put on trial in the court of public opinion by journalists
exploiting the emotions generated by sensational events, and that they have
been found guilty by a hung jury of academics or professionals
manipulating evidence to fit their postmodern or ideological theories but
undermining scholarship in the process. These first four chapters describe
an important cultural phenomenon that pervaded society in the late
twentieth century and therefore provide a historical context for the
discussions of legal theory that follow.
Parts 2 and 3 are specifically about men in the courts of law, the ways in
which public perceptions of men (and women) have been translated into the
legal codes and public policies of both the United States and Canada. Why
two countries? Because public perceptions of men and women in both
countries are almost identical. Unlike legal and political structures, they do
not stop at the border. But our comparative study does two things. First, it
shows that Canadian ideologues have been able to extend the influence of
feminism much more deeply than American feminists into education, law,
bureaucracy, and society at large, with the result that it is undermining the
very structure of liberal democracy. Second, it shows that some American
feminists are trying to achieve precisely the same things and often in very
similar ways. This should be a wake-up call to American legislators and
justices, who might still have enough legal or political clout to do
something.
Beginning with part 2, then, we move from the metaphor to the daily
reality of litigation. Leading the way are ideological feminists. But because
they have carefully disguised their role by using euphemisms and other
fronts, their influence has often gone unnoticed. Chapters 5 and 6, which
are about men and rights, show that the prevalent legal rhetoric favours
rights of women and undermines rights of men. Whether intentionally or
not, feminists who support that point of view have placed the whole notion
of human rights on trial. Part 3 (chapters 7, 8, and 9) is about the prevalent
legal rhetoric on sex – that is, the male sex. Intentionally, ideological
feminists have placed the whole notion of sex, or at least sex between
women and men, on trial.
Part 4 is about men and society from a more theoretical perspective. In
chapter 10, we show that the scholarship on which society depends has been
severely undermined by feminist ideology. As a direct result, equality has
been severely undermined, not merely because of public “debates” over
sensational or grotesque public scandals and not merely because of
legislation promoted by interest groups but also – ultimately – because of
an ideological worldview that has been actively promoted for several
decades in schools, colleges, and universities. The result is a gynocentric
worldview (ostensibly a mere correction of the older, androcentric one)
accompanied by misandry (ostensibly an unfortunate side effect).
That brings us, in chapter 11, to the metaphor of revolution. This has
been a “quiet revolution” and thus both less costly and more effective than
most of the noisy ones that end up in bloody streets and coups d’états. The
doctrines of ideological feminism have been introduced so quickly, so
cleverly, and so subtly that most citizens – including most lawyers and
legislators – have not even recognized what has been happening. And most
of those who have are quickly silenced by a reign of terror uniquely suited
to the needs of a quiet revolution: that of political (and sexual) correctness.
Bear in mind that what follows is about the moral and philosophical
implications of law, not law per se. Even though this or that ruling can be
legitimated by legal precedent or legal analogy, for instance, it cannot
necessarily be legitimated morally or philosophically. Lawyers, judges, and
even legislators more and more often ground their opinions, interpretations,
or reinterpretations, either directly or indirectly, on questionable ideological
principles. And feminist ideologues (some of whom happen to be lawyers,
judges, or legislators) have done precisely the same thing by arguing that
the fundamental premises of legal theory must be reexamined in view of
their own theories or even epistemologies. In fact, it is precisely the attempt
to legalize and bureaucratize – and thus institutionalize – feminist
epistemologies that constitutes the essence of what we call a quiet
revolution.
PART ONE
Men on Trial: The Court of Public
Opinion

We begin this book with several high-profile legal or quasi-legal cases that,
one way or another, put men collectively on “trial” in the court of public
opinion. We focus on journalism – with its reliance on the expertise of
academics and other experts – instead of the entertainment industry and
examine more closely not only the interaction between popular and elite
culture but also content as distinct from form (cinematic conventions, say,
or the manipulation of symbols). Moreover, we focus on direct, explicit, and
intentional manifestations of misandry instead of indirect, implicit, or
unintentional ones.
The case studies here reveal public perceptions not only of the real
problems faced by many women but also perceptions of the alleged evils or
inadequacies that characterize all men. We discuss the McMartin witch hunt
(child abuse, or satanic-ritual abuse) in chapter 1, the Bobbitt affair (wife
abuse) in chapter 2, the Hill-Thomas debate (sexual harassment of women)
in chapter 3, and the Montreal Massacre (murder of women) in chapter 4.
The men in these cases were conceptualized by journalists and other
commentators as oppressors, the women as victims, and the men were
presumed guilty until or unless they could defend themselves.
Each of these events immediately took on a life of its own, apparently
arising spontaneously from popular outrage but in fact arising partly or even
mainly from perceptions that had been promoted for years by ideological
feminists and had gradually been absorbed by many other people, including
men. Some were the usual suspects, including journalists, say, and talk
show hosts. Others, however, were professionals: social workers,
psychologists, psychiatrists, other clinicians or therapists, and so forth.
They were featured in the mass media as “expert witnesses” – that is,
interpreters of events that were sometimes not merely sensational but often
grotesque and bizarre.
For some of the ideological feminists involved, evil was the result of
male biology. (We will explore that topic elsewhere.) For others, however, it
was “merely” the result of masculine socialization, which had convinced
men of their own superiority and turned women into objects that may be
sexually exploited or even killed. And even though ideological feminists
did not manage to convince everyone that all men were implicated in the
crimes of a few, they did establish the generally accepted rhetorical
framework of public debate.
By the end of the century the verdict seemed clear: guilty as charged. As
a result, these social problems, which had always evoked fear in women,
became political trump cards among ideological feminists. No matter what
the individual men involved actually did, they were generally believed to
represent men as a class. Consequently, the accused were presumed guilty
before court proceedings had ended, or had even begun, and their guilt was
maintained even when the courts decided otherwise.
1
Children v. Demons: The McMartin and Other
Witch Hunts
If you are unable to remember any specific instances like the ones
mentioned above but still have a feeling that something abusive has
happened to you, it probably did.1

Sensational cases like that of “Sybil”… [were] welcomed by feminists who


saw it as the ultimate consequence of women’s victimization and loss of
self.2

Believe it or not, public furore over satanic ritual abuse during the 1990s
was at least partly a public referendum on the status of men, even though
some women, too, were caught in the web of fear mongers. According to
Mary deYoung, this was really a “new type of sex crime … discovered
during the 1980s: the abuse of very young children in rituals performed by
robed and hooded satanists who also happened to be their day care
providers. Satanic-ritual abuse appeared to be epidemic … and the
McMartin Preschool was its first locus delicti. The cultural response to the
McMartin case had all of the characteristics of what sociologists call a
moral panic: it was widespread, volatile, hostile, and overreactive.”3
But the sudden emergence of satanic-ritual abuse – that is, of attacks on
people for allegedly engaging in it – was only one manifestation of a
problem. Others, very closely related in both time and description, were
associated with multiple-personality disorder, recovered-memory syndrome,
boy molesters, and predator priests. They all manifested themselves as what
could be described metaphorically as either witch hunts (when focusing, as
we do here, on the targets) or moral panics (when focusing on those who
target them). No matter how grotesque in form and dire in effect for the
accused and their families or communities, these were surface phenomena,
symptoms of an underlying disease: a pervasive and pathological anxiety
over sexuality in general and male sexuality in particular.
In this chapter (which is linked with chapter 7), we discuss how these
witch hunts unfolded, how they spread so quickly, and why some of them
eventually subsided. Before concluding, we discuss the two underlying
anxieties – the moral panics – that generated these witch hunts: collective
stress coupled with perceptions of guilt over sexual urges and an ideological
worldview that identifies men with evil.

The most dramatic witch hunt, the one that became paradigmatic, began
with accusations of satanic-ritual abuse against the McMartin Preschool, a
family-owned business in Bakersfield, California. Most of the parents were
respectably middle class and upwardly mobile. Judy Johnson was a recently
separated mother living in the district. When she found out that there was
no opening for her son at McMartin, she dropped him off in the school-yard
anyway. One day the boy came home with a reddened anus. Johnson,
immediately jumping to the conclusion that he had been molested by
someone at the school, accused Raymond Buckey, the only male teacher at
McMartin. When a medical examination of the boy proved inconclusive,
Johnson hired a detective. She informed him that her son had told her of
perverse sexual activities at the school, activities that involved not only him
but other children as well. At this point, the boy was given another medical.
The doctor, though inexperienced in these matters, gave a cautious
diagnosis: the boy, he said, might have been molested.
Johnson’s detective sent letters to approximately two hundred families.
Parents were asked to question their children about activities that might
have occurred under the pretence of having their temperatures taken – oral
sex, fondling, sodomy, and so on. In addition, the letter named Buckey as
the primary suspect. After repeated questioning, many of the children
confirmed what their parents suspected. Now, the legal system was called
in. A similar case had already occurred, by chance, in Bakersfield. Parents
were advised immediately to take their children for professional evaluation
by social workers. Buckey and other members of the McMartin family were
eventually indicted by a grand jury.
Once the story was publicized by journalists, a feeding frenzy ensued.
With every retelling of the story, its details became more lurid and more
horrific. Further questioning of the children revealed that they had been
molested in a specifically satanic context. The children now told
tales about the ritualistic ingestion of feces, urine, blood, semen, and human
flesh; the disinterment and mutilation of corpses; the sacrifices of infants;
and orgies with their day care providers, costumed as devils and witches, in
the classroom, in tunnels under the center, and in car washes, airplanes,
mansions, cemeteries, hotels, ranches, gourmet food stores, local gyms,
churches, hot air balloons. And they named not only the seven McMartin
day care providers as their satanic abusers, but their soccer coaches,
babysitters, next-door neighbors, and even their own parents, as well as
local businesspeople, the mayor’s wife, who was said to drive around town
with the corpses of sacrificed infants in the back of her stationwagon, news
reporters covering the story, television and film stars, and members of the
Anaheim Angels baseball team.4

Johnson mobilized for war with the help of other parents, journalists,
psychiatrists, lawyers, government officials, community activists, and so
on. All of them took this bizarre nonsense very seriously.
It was also taken very seriously by Congress. In 1984 the social worker
who had diagnosed satanic-ritual abuse testified that the McMartin Pre-
school “was an ‘organized operation of child predators’ that ‘serves as a
ruse for a larger, unthinkable network of crimes against children’ that has
‘greater financial, legal, and community resources than any of the agencies
trying to uncover it.’”5 By the time Johnson died of alcoholism, two years
later, approximately fifty other McMartinesque events had taken place. And
after another five years, approximately fifty more.
While all this was going on, a closely related witch hunt was emerging
that involved an apparent epidemic of multiple-personality disorder. The
personalities of patients are supposedly fragmented, two or more of them
being said to co-exist within the same body; patients believe that they are
“possessed” by one or more of these personalities. This phenomenon has a
long history in the imagination of Western civilization. In Mark 5:5–15, for
example, Jesus heals someone who has been possessed by many demons.
More recently, the idea has taken secular and fictional form in the story of
Dr Jekyll and Mr Hyde. The most recent parallel of all, which has been
presented in several movies, takes psychiatric form. Among the earliest was
The Three Faces of Eve (1957), starring Joanne Woodward as a woman who
has taken on two additional personalities as a way of escaping from painful
memories of sexual trauma in her childhood. But as Carol Milstone points
out, it was Sybil (1976), starring Joanne Woodward (once again, though not
the protagonist) as a woman with no fewer than sixteen personalities, or
“alters,” that generated widespread interest among psychiatrists and other
professionals.6 One thing, though, had changed radically during the
previous twenty years. Then, the problem was considered extremely rare.
Now, it was considered extremely common. The same thing happened in
Canada. By 1990 the province of Manitoba had set up the Satanic Cult
Committee, whose mandate was not only to heighten public awareness of
these “epidemics” but also to train therapists, counsellors, and other health
care professionals. In 1994, Milstone writes, there were no fewer than three
thousand of them.
According to Elizabeth Gleick, witch hunts for satanic-ritual abuse and
multiple-personality disorder were closely related to a third and
simultaneous witch hunt. Targeted were those ostensibly responsible for
“recovered memories” of incest.”7 Many thousands of parents, almost
always fathers, were accused of molesting their own children. So horrific
were the experiences of these children, apparently, that they had repressed
all memories of them. But many could “recover” these memories as adults,
experts said, with the aid of psychologists or psychiatrists. Among the most
infamous cases was that of George Franklin, whose daughter, Eileen
Lipsker, suddenly “recovered” her memory of a childhood trauma and
accused him of having raped and killed her friend more than twenty years
earlier. Although Franklin was convicted in 1990, the court decided in 1995
to overturn the conviction because no corroborating evidence had ever been
presented.
After the Sybil case was investigated by the American Psychiatric
Association, Milstone observes, “repressed” and “recovered” memories
became part of common parlance and the focus of an “industry” – in the
derived sense of networks of professionals in cooperation with bureaucrats.
They began to spin off textbooks, scholarly articles, college courses,
academic conferences, public workshops, training videos, talk shows, and
highly profitable lecture tours. The “experts” told the public – mainly in the
United States and Canada – that curing the disorder could involve up to
eight or even ten years of expensive therapy, including long-term
hospitalization in specialized wards. They did not always tell the public,
however, that therapy involved hypnosis and injections of the drug Amytal
(often called truth serum and known for increasing suggestibility). Nor did
they tell the public that diagnostic features could include not only startling
symptoms such as “lost time,” hallucinations, panic attacks, schizophrenia,
and manic depression but also a host of symptoms so common that they
could apply to almost anyone: “glancing around the therapist’s office,
frequent blinking, change of posture or voice, rolling the eyes upward,
sudden laughter or anger, covering the mouth, hair falling forward,
scratching an itch, touching one’s face or chair, changing hairstyles, or
wearing a particular colour of clothing or jewellery … drinking alcohol.” In
children, diagnostic features could be equally common: having “imaginary
playmates, being lonely, truant, sexually precocious or delinquent.”8
Because information was so readily available to the public, not all
patients even waited for specialists to diagnose this problem. In any case,
some reported not merely two or three “alters” but dozens or hundreds. And
they reported not only incest and molestation but also satanic rituals, out-of-
body experiences, near-death experiences, and alien abductions (the latter,
for some reason, were seldom taken seriously by the public as real events).
Not all patients got well, either; some became more depressed or even
suicidal.
The stakes were very, very high. And it was all taken very, very
seriously. “Hokey as the MPD [multiple-personality disorder] field is starting
to sound, one must be reminded that North America’s post-Sybil MPD wild-
fire is fueled not by fringe elements but by the most powerful institutions in
the medical establishment – the American Medical Association, the
National Institute of Mental Health, the World Health Organization, the
Canadian Psychiatric Association, the Canadian Medical Association, the
International Society for the Study of Multiple Personality Disorder and
Dissociation, and university medical schools such as Harvard.”9
Another witch hunt, not as pervasive but continuing and still worthy of
headlines, erupted over an alleged epidemic of boy molesters. In Harmful to
Minors: The Perils of Protecting Children from Sex, Judith Levine discusses
the case of a boy named Tony, his younger sister Jessica, and their mother
Diane.10 In 1993 Tony, then twelve years old, was doing well at school,
although he sometimes got into trouble (hardly an unusual problem). He
had a “fierce” relationship with Jessica, fiercely affectionate and fiercely
antagonistic (hardly unusual among siblings). One night, he and Jessica
played at touching each other. And before you could say “molestation,”
Tony was accused by social workers of having made inappropriate advances
toward her. Their case was based on statements from Jessica at school,
statements that she later recanted (although officials explained her
recantation away as a result of “accommodation syndrome”) and that, in
any case, could not be supported by any evidence. Jessica accused her
mother Diane, too, of behaviour that was construed as inappropriate. In a
flash, the children were removed from Diane’s home and given to foster
parents. The case dragged on for years. In the end, due to the efforts of at
least one appalled social worker, Diane regained custody of her children.
The family had been fractured for three years, though, and the children had
“learned” a few things. Tony had learned that the adult world would betray
and punish him for no reason, and Jessica had learned how to take
advantage of her sexual power: how to intimidate others by threatening to
accuse them of inappropriate behaviour and how not to feel “bad guilt” for
being an informant (even, presumably, if the information was based on
fantasy or malice). Which was worse, one might well ask – as we will on
more than one occasion in this book – the disease or the cure?
Other cases, Levine points out, did not have such “happy” endings.
Preadolescent children, usually boys, were institutionalized routinely for
displaying what adult professionals considered an untoward interest in sex,
even though no one had ever made an adequately scientific study of
“normal” sexual behaviour in children. Once incarcerated in “therapeutic”
settings, these children were classified officially as child molesters – the
alleged molesters were almost always boys – and expected to confess as
quickly as possible. Those who failed to do so were said to be in denial and
subjected to behaviour modification techniques of a kind that would result
in law suits among adults, denied personal privacy of any kind, and forced
into humiliating acts of “atonement” such as apologizing on their knees.
Given their pathologized identity, many of these children actually came to
believe that they would end up as adult molesters. And a few, no doubt,
would.
Thousands of people who are still very upset over the episode of
“predator priests,” or “priest pedophiles,” would be outraged that we
classify it as a witch hunt. The major difference between this phenomenon
and those that are now commonly known in retrospect as witch hunts is that
most of the accused in this case might really have been witches – that is,
guilty. We say “might,” because the number of priests who actually
molested children, at least 80% of whom were boys,11 will never be known
despite the official tally, since most of these cases have been settled out of
court (although many civil suits are still pending) and most of the accused
have never been tried and either convicted or acquitted.12 This problem is
no mere technicality, even though we usually assume that an admission of
guilt is conclusive. Ignoring it, in fact, would be tantamount to ignoring due
process. And that is a major feature of every witch hunt. Even so, it would
be foolish – and certainly foolhardy – to claim that most of these priests
were actually innocent of the charges against them; most of them, in all
likelihood, really were guilty.
But that was true also of the McCarthy witch hunt of the late 1940s and
early 1950s. Whether the McCarthy hearings were necessary or not, one
thing is clear: some of those accused by the House Committee on Un-
American Activities really were guilty of the charge against them; they
were either Communists themselves or knew of Communists but did not
reveal their names. What defines a witch hunt is not the innocence or guilt
of those charged but the emotional intensity, the loss of control, that
accompanies charges and corrupts the process of deciding on innocence or
guilt. According to that definition the church scandal is just the most recent
in a long line of witch hunts that overtook society in the late twentieth
century and that continue into the twenty-first.
It is hard to ignore the fact that the moral panics over satanic-ritual
abuse, multiple-personality disorder, recovered-memory syndrome, and boy
molesters were multiplying rapidly just when stories of alien abduction
were also multiplying and just before panics over predator priests. Was this
entirely a coincidence? If the other phenomena are taken seriously, no
matter how bizarre, why not alien abductions as well? In a recent book,
Elaine Showalter has noted some distinct parallels, as has Stephen Rae, in
an essay for the New York Times Magazine.13 “Abductees” are subjected to
sexual abuse (experiments involving their sexual organs, say, or being
forced to mate with the aliens), and like their counterparts, they repress
their memories for two reasons. First, they find their experiences too
horrifying. Second, they know that no one will believe them. They
consequently experience intense but inexplicable emotional pain and are
now offered forms of therapy similar to the therapy given to their
counterparts (notably, hypnotic regression). Rae discusses the work of
Harvard’s John Mack:

To help abductees shed their isolation, Mack set up the Program for
Extraordinary Experience Research. He helped them recover memories in
hypnotic screamathons. When combined with breathwork, Mack says,
hypnosis undoes the repression of memory imposed by the aliens. As the
traumas are brought to consciousness, relived with “feelings of terror, rage
and grief as intense as any I have encountered as a psychiatrist,” their
power was dissipated … [Mack] acknowledges that it is possible to implant
false memories under hypnosis, but only memories of inconsequential
events – an issue at the center of fierce debates over recovered memories of
Satanic cults and childhood sexual abuse.14

It could be argued that those who consider themselves abductees are, in


reality, merely denying more mundane forms of sexual abuse. Yet people in
both groups have made precisely the same claim: that what they
experienced was true, not a delusion, no matter how impossible or
unacceptable it might sound. And people in both groups have demanded to
be taken seriously on the same grounds: their demonstrated intelligence,
social respectability, civic responsibility, mental health, and so forth. In that
case, the argument could be reversed: the victims of satanic cults and incest
were denying more bizarre traumas.
In fact, both advocates for and detractors of people who claim to have
recovered memories of sexual molestation might be wrong. Hallucinations
are common experiences that occur to ordinary people under ordinary
circumstances but also in connection with sleep paralysis, a disorder
experienced by at least 8% of the population during that twilight state
between waking and sleeping. It involves three elements: a sense of
paralysis, the presence of strange and sinister beings, and sexual
stimulation. This condition, says Carl Sagan, results when less oxygen than
usual flows to the brain. At one time the sinister beings were called succubi
and incubi or fairies. Nowadays they are called “aliens.” Whatever they are
called, these beings are said to have sexual relations with their human
victims. Sagan might have added that a far more acceptable name, these
days, would be that of the victim’s father, brother, uncle, or even mother. “Is
it possible,” asks Sagan, “that people in all times and places occasionally
experience vivid, realistic hallucinations, often with sexual content with the
details filled in by the prevailing cultural idioms sucked out of the
Zeitgeist?”15 Obviously, it is possible in some cases.
In its coverage of this topic, CBS’s 48 Hours noted in 1994 that some
twenty-five million Americans claimed to have been abducted by
extraterrestrials! At a meeting of alleged victims, the camera noted a
bulletin board with this quotation from William James: “A new idea is first
condemned as ridiculous and then dismissed as trivial, until finally, it
becomes what everybody knows.”16 The point is this: maybe the alleged
abductees really are a bunch of crackpots, but those who had recently been
called crackpots themselves – those whose claims about incest had been
dismissed for decades by experts under the influence of Freud17 – were
hardly in a position to call others crackpots for making almost identical
claims. On the contrary, they were in an ideal position to demand extensive
research on behalf of those who claimed to have been sexually molested by
extraterrestrials. Fortunately, they did not.
The “alien abductions” did not lead to a witch hunt. After all, no one
could take an alien from outer space to court. And very few people ever
took the alleged victims seriously. Moreover, they have included both
women and men in roughly equal numbers. This episode fills out the social,
cultural, and historical background against which to examine the witch
hunts and raises an interesting question: Why are millions of people willing
to take some bizarre phenomena seriously but not others? Because some
phenomena have more political clout than others do.

Why did the witch hunts spread so quickly? Several explanations have been
offered. Referring to Elaine Showalter’s “hystories,” Carol Tavris notes that
they are “constructed by vested interests protecting their professions and
incomes, ignorant psychologists, greedy opportunists who see a way to
make a fast buck on the insecurities of the vulnerable, ideologues of the
right and left, and clergy and politicians drunk on elixir of moral
righteousness.”18 In the case of satanic-ritual abuse, panic was spread by
both professional and grassroots groups. Among the former, the most
obvious were journalists, who, not surprisingly, adopted hyperbolic imagery
and a somewhat hysterical tone. The television industry had a vested
interest in dramatic exposés and provocative interviews, all of which were
“politically correct.” (Although the term truly belongs within ironic
quotation marks, we must use it so often that adding them every time would
be irritating; for a discussion, see appendix 4.)
Then, as now, being a victim was actually a badge of pride. Those who
embarked on their twelve-step programs were well aware of this. The
ceaseless parade of victims – especially the victims of childhood sexual
traumas – was a fascinating sequel to the spectacle of an earlier time.
Unlike the bearded ladies and alligator men once exhibited at freak shows
to evoke curiosity and pity, these survivors were exhibited on the talk show
circuit to evoke pity and solidarity. The former had been victims of nature,
after all, but the latter were victims of evil. The old side shows had been not
only bizarre but also edifying, so that a viewer could think, There, but for
the grace of God, go I. The new ones were still bizarre, but they were also
edifying in a different way. A viewer could now think, There, by the grace
of God, go I. “Sympathetic professionals” also appeared on television.

During the bitter years of McMartin, they not only received a great deal of
local, national, and international news attention, but also appeared on
television talk shows and primetime newsmagazines. They took to the
lecture circuit, gave testimony in government-sponsored hearings,
addressed conferences of child abuse professionals, consulted with other
professionals as other satanic day care cases began cropping up across the
country, and testified as experts in the criminal trials of day care providers.
And in each interview, each presentation, each consultation, the story of
McMartin was told and re-told in communities that were being primed for
the moral panic by the telling.19

As Richard Gardner points out in Sex Abuse Hysteria: The Salem Witch
Trials Revisited, accusations were encouraged by the therapy industry,
which had a vested interest in fanning the flames of hysteria and a constant
supply of new cases.20 Levine makes it clear that the flood of accusations
against boy molesters, like those against other targets, was led by
professional experts with financial interests, apart from any others. At first,
in the early 1990s, there were no treatment facilities for “children who
molest.” Just over a decade later, there were 50 residential and 390
nonresidential ones in the United States. The head of one told Levine that
establishing a program was a “business decision.”21 The programs were not
based on any empirical data. A few cases were reported, and the experts
declared a state of emergency, having diagnosed an “epidemic” of juvenile
molestation. There was a great deal of anxiety over the “negative pairing”
of sex and aggression (even though both are universal features of human
existence in both adults and children and not necessarily “negative”). Once
the mass media took up this new cause, the number of demands for
solutions increased. That encouraged other experts to set up new treatment
programs and to seek massive funding. An industry was born.
Popular therapeutic self-help books came into their own at this very
moment. Potential accusers did not have to consult psychotherapists to
conclude that they had been victims of horrific treatment at the hands of
their fathers or even grandfathers. They had only to pick up a self-help
manual. One of these was particularly popular. The Courage to Heal, by
Ellen Bass and Laura Davis, functioned as a modern equivalent of the
Malleus maleficarum, the primary textbook used by witch hunters of the
late Middle Ages.22 The new version was available to millions, though, not
only to an educated ecclesiastical elite. According to Bass and Davis, any
woman who even suspects that she was sexually molested, even if she
cannot actually remember the event, probably was molested. (Bass and
Davis referred only to women; the fact that men, too, reported being
sexually abused by their parents, even by their mothers, was clearly of no
interest to them.) The book provides a simple checklist of symptoms and
explicitly encourages readers, with leading questions, to diagnose recovered
memory syndrome. The book was soon accompanied, says Showalter, by
countless “hystories” spread over the Internet, talk shows, and the self-help
networks of the “recovery community,” stories that quickly developed
“their own conventions, stereotypes, and structures.”23
Grassroots groups participated, too, in the spread of witch hunts, both
willingly and ably. By 1984, parents had formed an organization called
Believe the Children. Their activism had grown “in sophistication from
wearing buttons and carrying hand-painted signs to establishing a clearing
house on satanic ritual abuse, replete with a speakers’ bureau, a support
network for parents, police, and prosecutors involved in other satanic day
care cases, and a referral list of sympathetic professionals.”24
Because the spread of mass hysteria at the end of the twentieth century,
as in earlier centuries but much more quickly and effectively, was no
accident, we should take it very seriously as a symptom of social pathology.
“The stories we tell,” writes Gleick, “say a lot about our fantasies, our fears,
and our preoccupations.”25 Even if only for that reason, Showalter refrains
from urging the abolition of psychiatry.26

Some patients have remained sincerely and profoundly convinced that the
events in question occurred, even though no evidence was ever found to
substantiate widespread incest or satanic cults – let alone victims murdered
for ritual purposes. But the hysteria generated by some of these witch hunts
has subsided. At any rate, multiple personality disorder, along with satanic-
ritual abuse and recovered-memory syndrome, are now cultural and
historical memories that intelligent people would like very much not to
recover. (The priest pedophiles have been stopped, although the emotional
impact of their discovery has not yet receded, and the boy molesters are still
“discovered” now and then.) We are left to pick up the pieces.
The witch hunts ended for at least three reasons. First, they had gotten
out of hand. As in the Salem witch hunt of 1692, too many people were
threatened by the possibility of false accusations. And too many
professionals, both legal and therapeutic, realized that they had better save
their personal and collective reputations by returning to the status quo ante.
Second, it was too hard to convict people without evidence. Worse, both the
alleged victims and the alleged malefactors began to sue for damages. Mil-
stone is by no means the only one to suggest that respectable professionals
were either unprofessionally gullible and negligent or criminally
responsible for destroying countless lives. Some former patients, now
convinced that they had been duped, have initiated lawsuits against
therapists and institutions. Others have made formal complaints to medical
organizations. The False Memory Syndrome Foundation has been
established in Philadelphia by accused parents, who encourage other
parents in their situation to challenge courts that produce no hard evidence
of molestation.
And what about McMartin? By 1986, 80% of the surveyed residents of
Los Angeles County believed that the McMartins were guilty of crimes
almost inconceivably horrific. Nevertheless, charges were dropped against
five of the seven who were originally charged, due to lack of evidence.
Raymond Buckey and his mother Peggy McMartin were sent to trial. This
ordeal lasted twenty-eight months, then the longest criminal trial on record.
It consumed 64,000 pages of transcripts and cost $13 million. After nine
months of deliberation, McMartin was acquitted of all charges and Buckey
of most. A hung jury on eight charges, however, meant that he had to be
tried a second time. Finally, all charges were dropped against him. And
what of Judy Johnson herself? “The mother of the little boy who never
shared his dark secrets with anyone, and who never could even pick out
Raymond Buckey’s picture form a photo lineup, was institutionalized for a
while with the diagnosis of paranoid schizophrenia after she told detectives
that her ex-husband had also sodomized her son, and that an intruder had
broken into her house and sodomized the family dog.”27
The third reason for the end of the witch hunts was that professionals
and clinicians began to rethink the theories that had led to, or at least had
been used to explain, them. With growing criticism of the therapeutic
movement’s contribution to the witch hunts, the Sybil case itself was
investigated. One of two psychiatrists who had written it up, Herbert
Speigel, said in an interview that “Sybil” had been highly suggestible and
that all her “alters” had been created under hypnosis by his colleague on the
case, Cornelia Wilbur. Speigel had come to have serious doubts, in any
case, about the patient’s abuse by her mother. Being cautious, he attributed
her false memories to some unconscious interaction between her and her
therapist. He wanted to challenge the dubious notion of recovered
memories, in short, but he did not want to risk accusing anyone of immoral
and illegal behaviour.
It was only in the late 1990s that psychiatrists themselves began to
challenge the whole theory of recovered memories. Some recognized that
the therapies offered were providing disturbed patients with an attractive
but also a powerful and false explanation for their suffering and that many
of their professional colleagues were exploiting these patients. As a
therapeutic device, “remembering” childhood traumas was very effective. It
did what all therapies must do, by providing a powerful explanation for
suffering: my pain has a cause that can be identified and thus eliminated. It
replaced chaos with order: bad things do not just happen; bad people make
them happen. It replaced neurotic guilt with what was considered healthy
rage: the bad person is someone else, not me. Unfairly blaming others, even
parents and usually fathers, offered an irresistible alternative to anxiety,
confusion, and even mere regret about the vicissitudes of everyday life. On
talk shows, observers in studio audiences often said that the fathers must
have done something to cause so much unhappiness. And this was often
true, because people are never perfect. But did they cause it in this
particular way? Were there no other causes for unhappiness? Do adults have
no responsibility for making choices leading to their own unhappiness?
Finally, must we rely on the old adage that “where there’s smoke there’s
fire”? There might be, sure, but there might not be.
Any patient who sought this kind of therapy might indeed have suffered
childhood distress or even trauma of some kind, possibly, though not
necessarily, of a sexual nature. But were the therapists beyond scientific, let
alone moral or legal, accountability? As Richard Gardner points out, the
crusade mounted on behalf of the new therapy provoked a witch hunt not
merely in the metaphorical sense of the postwar McCarthy hunt but in a
quite literal sense.28 The parents of the patients were accused of having
worshipped the Devil, in other words, of being witches according to the
definition of that word held in old Salem. Then, as now, the “experts” relied
on testimony that sounded plausible in the immediate cultural context but
had little or nothing to do with hard evidence. There was only one major
difference between this witch hunt and those of the sixteenth and
seventeenth centuries: the people accused and destroyed by unverifiable
allegations were usually men, not women. We will return to that topic.

Professionals and clinicians re-examined some case studies of parents,


moreover, including fathers who had been unjustly attacked in court and
even imprisoned. Evidence of the rethinking could soon be found not only
in books and articles29 but also on television.30 One segment of Prime-Time
Live, for example, indicated that the psychiatrists were now divided
between those who specialized in satanic-ritual abuse therapy and those
who challenged the professional competence, the moral integrity, and even
the mental health of their colleagues. The former believed that members of
Satanist cults, who, they claimed, indulged in the torture and ritual murder
of their own children, numbered somewhere between the tens and hundreds
of thousands. Due to the trauma of watching these sinister events, or even
being forced to participate in them, survivors repressed the memories. Later,
as disturbed adults, they turned to therapists who helped them remember.
But it took more than some rethinking by professionals to end the hysteria.
Eventually, patients changed their minds and accused their therapists of
implanting false memories through suggestion, hypnosis, and other
manipulative techniques. Police departments admitted that they could not
come up with any corroborating evidence.
Child abuse, even if it has nothing to do with Satanism and is not an
epidemic, remains a serious problem. But must we take at face value
virtually any story of childhood molestation? Elizabeth Loftus – often
called as an expert witness in court because of her research on memory –
says no.31 Her research on twenty thousand subjects showed that memories
of any kind are distorted in about one quarter of the subjects merely through
the power of suggestion or if they are supplied with incorrect information.
Moreover, says Loftus, violent events actually decrease the accuracy of
memory. Memories are weakest when associated either with low levels of
arousal (such as boredom or sleepiness) or high levels of arousal (stress or
trauma). In short, memory is fragile and disintegrates gradually. It is prone
to suggestion, moreover, not autonomous. Loftus and colleagues have also
shown that even imagining a false event increases subjective confidence
that the event happened and that subjects can confuse dreaming and waking
events when presented with a list of them. She writes that “63 percent can
‘recover’ nonexistent memories of being exposed [as infants] to colored
mobiles while in their hospital cribs – a literal impossibility since the
nervous system is not developed enough to lay down explicit memories in
the first few years of life.”32
Other scholars eventually began to sift the wheat from the chaff. In
Suggestions of Abuse: True and False Memories of Childhood Sexual
Trauma, Michael Yapko claimed that many of the charges were probably
the result of hypnosis.33 In Victims of Memory, Mark Pendergrast told the
story of his own experience with an accusation of incest.34 Like Yapko,
Pendergrast refrained from consigning all accusations to the category of
false memories, but he did describe memory as “plastic” and subject to
unwitting manipulation for various purposes. His experience with his two
daughters is a case in point. They were in their early twenties when they
began “feminist therapy.” Shortly thereafter, they accused him of having
molested them as children. Their therapist advised them to change their
names, move to other cities, and cut off all contact with him. But when
Pendergrast went into therapy himself, in an effort to retrieve his own
memories of what had happened, he could only remember one occasion on
which he had wept in front of his daughters. This, they claimed, was
evidence of “emotional incest.”
In Remembering Satan, Lawrence Wright discusses the bizarre case of a
man who developed his own false memories of molesting his daughters and
the consequent guilt, under the impact of accusations.35 According to one
reviewer, John Goddard, Wright fails to make a necessary distinction
between sexual trauma and other traumas. Wright points out that children
who witnessed the most horrific scenes in Nazi death camps remember
them vividly in adult life. Why, he asks, should only sexual scenes be
repressed? But according to Goddard, “Wright is mixing apples and
oranges. Witnessing a parent’s murder might be shocking, but the event has
nothing in common with being sexually violated by the very person on
whom the child depends for love, nourishment and physical survival.”36
Might be shocking? Nothing in common? Please! Adult notions of sexuality
make the advances of parents seem shocking, not anything inherent in
caressing.37 Children themselves often play or experiment with their sexual
organs until they are warned not to do so by adults. (Children’s
experimentation is a complex problem, though, and responsible parents
provide their adolescent children with cultural guidelines for sexual
behaviour.) The motifs of reversal and betrayal are by no means confined to
sexual encounters between parents and children. In the Nazi death camps,
children learned that adults were ready to kill them instead of protect them.
A world that had once made sense, moreover, now made no sense at all.
And yet they remembered everything! To claim that anyone would find it
easier to live with memories of Auschwitz than to live with memories of
sexual encounters is not merely a psychological absurdity. It is a moral
outrage.
But were there any underlying factors involved in the witch hunts and
moral panics? Were millions of people actually predisposed to believe that
such bizarre scenarios were actually occurring? If witch hunts result from
underlying social tensions and anxiety projected outward onto convenient
targets, which anxiety was projected onto the particular targets discussed in
this chapter?38 There were indeed at least two underlying factors. In this
section, we will consider one of them: pervasive and enduring stress at the
collective level.39
The series of witch hunts that began with McMartin lasted a decade.
Taken together, they could be described as a “collective stress reaction in
response to a belief in a story about immediately threatening
circumstances.”40 This is how DeYoung, in particular, explains the
perplexing hysteria over satanic-ritual abuse.41 During the 1980s, she
explains, more and more women were moving into the work force and had
to depend on day-care for their children. Yet they became deeply
ambivalent over what was happening. On the one hand, they and their
children had “covenantal relationships,” which were based on bonding and
emotional expressiveness. On the other hand, they and their employers had
“contractual relationships,” which were based on negotiation and exchange.
Many women felt guilty, either consciously or subconsciously, for not
taking care of their own children, and they worried about the quality and
safety of their arrangements. They felt trapped, in short, between necessity
and risk. It was a no-win situation. The tension that all this generated made
those who worked at day-care centres convenient targets, scapegoats.
Almost overnight, the situation became highly combustible; only a single
lighted match was necessary to provoke an explosion. And that was
provided in 1983 by McMartin.
Eventually parents found ways of exerting more control over daycare
centres. They could drop in at any time, observe or participate in activities,
chaperone outings, sit on boards, and so on. Many states enacted legislation
to screen potential daycare workers, moreover, checking for psychiatric
problems and character flaws. Once the original and underlying
psychological problem had been resolved, there was no longer any need for
the remedy.
But the demise of that witch hunt, says Levine, did not mean the end by
any means of a more generalized anxiety. The sexual revolution had made
sexual activity freer from restraint and more visible than ever before. A
flood of pornography was now accessible to both adults and children on the
Internet, cable television channels, and even (in slightly toned down form)
on network television. One possibility haunted parents: if other people got
the idea that anything goes, and they surely would in such a permissive and
hedonistic age, then they would see no reason to refrain from pedophilia.
Not many parents drew the further conclusion, at least not consciously, that
they and their children might actually want to indulge in forbidden sexual
activities. That possibility would have threatened the longstanding cultural
taboo on incest, the relatively recent notion of childhood innocence, and the
fragile accommodation that society had reached in connection with deeply
rooted ambivalence toward sexual activity of any kind at all.
According to historian John Demos, the late medieval and early modern
witch hunts occurred after crises.42 During the crises themselves, people
were so busy coping that they had no time to think about causes or rail
against scapegoats. The witch hunts began only after things had calmed
down. Only then did they kill those whom they perceived as instigators or
their surrogates. Bear in mind that witches were closely associated not only
with deviant religious activities but also with deviant sexual ones. As we
have said, modern witch hunts differ from earlier ones in only one
significant way: the targets are much more likely to be male than female.

All the witch hunts discussed here were linked, we have already suggested,
by a sexual subtext that was represented within the family circle by the
parents’ molestation of their own children43 and outside the family circle by
molestation of other children.44 Not so obviously, the witch hunts were
linked by an ideological subtext as well, the ideological manipulation of
stress to advance feminist political goals. The source of evil was
symbolically represented by men (the victimizers) and the source of
goodness by women and children (their victims). Yet at no time during the
controversy did the specific topic of gender come up for public discussion;
no one noticed that most of the people attacked (and many of the victims)
were either men or boys.
Although it was easy to deny that millions of people were fiendishly
sacrificing babies in their suburban basements, it was not so easy to identify
the connection between ideological feminism and a witch hunt that targeted
primarily men. So far, that connection has remained hidden, and ideological
feminism has remained fashionable in academic and political circles.
The ideologues who intentionally or unintentionally, directly or
indirectly, encouraged the accusations against men purported to explain the
world in terms of victims and oppressors and therefore made victimhood
politically useful. When victims go public even today, they do not merely
elicit support from other victims or potential victims but also reinforce the
ideological claim to collective victimization, along with its supposed
corollary of collective righteousness and its actual consequence of
collective power. In this case, the fact that some of the accusers were men
was ideologically irrelevant as long as most of the accused, too, were men.
Who would have had a vested interest in connecting repressed memories
with sexual misconduct, especially incest? Although some mothers were
accused of heinous sexual misconduct, or at least of having done nothing to
prevent it, fathers were the primary suspects. Anyone who wanted to heap
suspicion on fathers, or on men in general, would have found the
phenomenon politically useful. And some feminists – not all, but some –
fell into precisely that category. Their demonization of men had already
surged by the 1990s, as we will show throughout this book, and the witch
hunts provided an ideal opportunity to score political points. Not only were
there reasons to suspect all or most men of wanting to rape women,45 it
seemed, but there were reasons to suspect in addition that all or most fathers
wanted to rape their own children. Carol Tavris has noted that “[s]ensational
cases like that of ‘Sybil’ … [were] welcomed by feminists who saw it as the
ultimate consequence of women’s victimization and loss of self.”46
The ideological worldview of activists was highly dualistic, a
characteristic feature of ideology. At the individual level, troubled people –
and those who “recovered” memories of sexual traumas were always
troubled people, which is why they sought out psychologists or psychiatrists
– found the source of their troubles in what had supposedly been done to
them by others, rather than in their own attitudes or behaviour. At the
collective level, too, they found the source of suffering not within their own
group but in another one – that is, in men (although, in cases involving
daycare, where very few men worked, many women were accused). The
source of evil was externalized, in other words, and the world was polarized
between “us” and “them.” Another characteristic feature of ideology is
essentialism. In this case, women or girls were stereotyped as innocent
victims by nature and men or boys as sinister molesters by nature. Yet
another characteristic of ideology is the belief that ends can justify means.
In this case, advocates for the victims of satanic ritual abuse and incest were
convinced that any measure – even distorting the justice system to make
prosecutions easier – could be justified.
That a movement devoted to “survivors” of incest and a generalized
suspicion that all men, just beneath the surface, are rapists and molesters
originated almost immediately after the advent of ideological feminism was
almost certainly not a coincidence. Nor, given the number of cases based on
false memories, was it due to the fortuitous discovery of a hidden problem.
Incest has always existed, no doubt, but it was widely believed in the 1990s
to be prevalent.
DeYoung points out that male teachers were accused far out of
proportion to the number working in daycare.47 In 1983, only 5% of
daycare workers were male. But in a survey of thirty-five major cases, 49%
of those charged were male. As a result, men fled the field to find greater
security in fields conventionally assigned to them. Daycare was even more
feminized, in short, and men even more demonized. If feminists can argue
that it was no accident that women were the primary targets of witch
hunters several centuries ago, we can surely argue that it is no accident and
hardly surprising that men are the primary targets of modern witch hunters.
Consider the rhetoric generated at precisely this moment in history by
ideological feminists, according to whom all of history is a conspiracy of
men against women. The hysteria generated by this modern witch hunt has
contributed in no small measure to the creation of misandry. American
society, thanks at least partly to the Puritan tradition, has never been
comfortable with sex. But now, thanks at least partly to the beliefs of
ideological feminists, the level of discomfort has reached an unprecedented
high – unprecedented even in Victorian times.
This is not to say that even the most ideological feminists deliberately set
out to create a panic. But they did contribute significantly to an atmosphere
in which it was easy to single out men or boys as scapegoats, as the chief
suspects for any social problem – especially those in which girls or women
were likely to be identified as the primary victims. In addition, many
feminists promoted pop psychology, which had become a characteristic
feature of talk shows that were addressed primarily to women. Hence the
extensive use of psychotherapeutic language. Without both the feminist
movement itself and the recovery movement that was closely associated
with it, in short, we would probably not have been engulfed in the hysteria
over satanic rituals and recovered memories.
It is not entirely surprising, therefore, that Showalter received death
threats from those with emotional or political investments in the notion of
“recovered memory syndrome.”48 Loftus received similar treatment. “She
has been called a whore by a prosecutor in a courthouse hallway, assaulted
by a passenger on an airplane shouting, ‘You’re that woman!’ and has
occasionally required surveillance by plainclothes security guards at
lectures.”49

Men were the main targets of the witch hunters discussed here, though not
the only ones. In the following chapters, we discuss episodes in which
major segments of the population targeted only men as the collective source
of evil. The polarization of society along sexual lines was so obvious and so
pervasive, in fact, that many journalists and other cultural observers could
not help but comment on it.
2
Wives v. Abusers: The Bobbitt Affair
The retail clerks who send [Lorena Bobbitt] letters of support, the
homemakers who cackle wildly every time they sharpen the butcher knife,
are neither “tired of hearing about victims” nor eager to honour them.
They’re tired of being victims. And they’re eager to see women fight back
by whatever means necessary.1

Sitcoms routinely portray women hitting men, almost never portray men
hitting women. When he fails to leave, it is not called “Battered Man
Syndrome”; it is called comedy.2

On 23 June 1993, Lorena Bobbitt sliced off the penis of her husband John.
Journalists immediately went into a feeding frenzy. What case could
symbolize more graphically, they must have thought, the war between the
sexes? In the trial that followed, Lorena was found not guilty of maliciously
wounding John. The reason? She had been driven, during a moment of
“temporary insanity,” by an “irresistible urge.” After four years of physical
and sexual abuse from John, it was argued officially, she had suddenly gone
berserk. Unofficially, though – and this is very important – it was said that
she had acted in self-defense, even though John had been fast asleep at the
time and had already been found not guilty of raping his wife, at least on
that occasion.
The trials of Eric and Lyle Menendez took place at almost exactly the
same time, and their attorneys used almost exactly the same defense. The
brothers had been driven during an irrational interlude to kill their parents.
After years of physical and sexual torment by their parents, the boys had
suddenly gone berserk. They believed, however, that they were acting in
self-defense, even though their parents were watching television and eating
ice cream at the time. In the Menendez trials, neither jury was able to reach
a verdict. But the pleas of self-defense in the two spectacular Menendez
trials generated a storm of controversy.
In this chapter, which is linked with chapter 9, we discuss comments on
the trials from various sources within popular culture and comments on
domestic violence from a panel of experts in social work. These comments
reveal misandry as a fundamental premise of ideological feminism.

On 4 February 1994, Ted Koppel’s Nightline, presented a special “town


meeting” on the implications of the three trials, one for Lorena Bobbitt and
one for each Menendez brother.3 “Is Abuse an Excuse?” was the title of the
meeting, and in the opinion of some guests, but not others, abuse clearly
was an excuse. This conflict reflected widespread disagreement between
men and women. The men on Eric’s jury wanted a verdict of guilty, for
instance, and the women did not. Several of the latter made it clear,
moreover, that the dispute among jurors was unusually bitter. What
accounts for all this?
From the very beginning of the show, it was clear that no one really
cared about the people actually involved in these lurid trials. What everyone
did care about were the social, legal, and political (but not, unfortunately,
the moral) implications. The discussion on the show – and everywhere else
– might have been clarified considerably if everyone had acknowledged
this. Several supporters of Lorena tried to trivialize the controversy over
temporary insanity. Why, they asked, is everyone so concerned about a few
unrepresentative cases? After all, the temporary insanity defense is risky
and used only by those who can afford to pay for the most expensive
lawyers, investigators, psychologists, or other expert witnesses. And even
then, they are usually unsuccessful.
Alan Dershowitz, a controversial professor of law at Harvard, noted the
obvious by observing that those most anxious to legitimate prior abuse as a
factor mitigating guilt were politically motivated: “These aren’t
psychologists,” he said in connection with some of the expert witnesses
called in by defense lawyers; “these are advocates, and this is advocacy
psychobabble. What we’re hearing is people who are politicians, who have
a political agenda. It’s not that we’re learning more about the mind, we’re
learning more about the politics of certain movements.”4 Dershowitz
carefully refrained from identifying the particular movement. He received a
smiling but rhetorical reply from Lenore Walker, the psychologist from
Rutgers who gained fame in some quarters and infamy in others for
introducing the legal notion of Battered-Woman Syndrome (which we
discuss in appendix 3)5. “And what is that political movement,” she asked
rhetorically, “to end violence?”6
At issue during this debate was not compassion for Lyle and Eric
Menendez, two men who took the law into their own hands, but compassion
for Lorena Bobbitt and other women who do the same thing. It was clear to
everyone that the underlying topic was ideological feminism. Not all
panelists even bothered to substitute “abused people” for “abused women.”
Although many feminists had seen the Menendez brothers and their trials as
nothing more than sideshows, they felt an urgent need to legitimate the
Menendez defense strategy, which they would have liked to see used more
often on behalf of women.
Their political motivations notwithstanding, psychologists must be taken
seriously in cases of this kind. One expert noted that suffering leads women
such as Lorena to lose control. But the same argument could be applied to
almost everyone. It could certainly be applied to most of the men now
locked away in prisons for crimes such as murder and rape, crimes
generated at least partly by extremely stressful home environments
involving hopeless poverty, alcohol or other drugs, gang violence, and the
absence of fathers. Some were driven by irresistible urges that could not be
cured even after years of therapy. Nevertheless, these men are seldom
declared to have been temporarily insane. Men who injure women are
always evil, it would seem, no matter what their state of mental health.
Women who injure men are always out of control, on the other hand, no
matter what their state of moral awareness.
Lisa Kemler, Lorena Bobbitt’s lawyer, tried to place the discussion of
abused women in a different, presumably less controversial, context: “I
don’t think that anybody sitting around here would have any trouble with a
death-camp inmate who reacted, finally, and struck out at his guard and
killed him.”7 Although it is true that a few inmates in the Nazi death camps
did kill their guards, these acts were the result of remarkable control, not
loss of control. No one would dream of arguing for the temporary insanity
of inmates at Auschwitz or Treblinka who used violence to escape. Lorena’s
defenders, on the other hand, were inconsistent. The official argument,
which held sway in court, was that she had lost control and therefore
deserved pity. The unofficial argument, however, which held sway among
her supporters in the court of public opinion, was that because Lorena had
taken control by defending herself, she deserved admiration and even
emulation by women in similar circumstances. But logic would not have
allowed the argument to go both ways. Either Lorena was out of control, or
she was not.
Some feminists on Nightline who understood the logic and
acknowledged it openly were not satisfied with the temporary insanity
defense. For them, it was merely an expedient measure made necessary by
the current state of legal practice. They would have gone further. Although
she later contradicted herself, Walker probably spoke for millions: “I’m not
sure I would have used an insanity defense in this case. I think you could
have made just as good an argument that this was self-defense.” “Most
battered women,” she observed, “are not mentally impaired.”
Why, then, had the notion of temporary insanity become so widely
accepted in the present? “For years,” according to Jeff Greenfield’s voice-
over on the show, “American culture has been heavily influenced by the
language of therapy, of recovery, the language that defines millions of us as
victims of one sort or another. And it’s language that has come to dominate
… the American talk show.”8 No wonder people had come to believe that
much or even most of their unhappiness can be blamed on others. As a
result of the incessant talk about sickness, evil had been abolished and sin
medicalized. “Maybe what we’re really worried about,” said Greenfield, “is
that a culture that seems more comfortable with explanations than with
judgments is a culture that’s losing its sense of what is right and what is
wrong.”9
Greenfield might have been right, in one sense, but precisely the
opposite could be said in another sense. The rhetoric of victimization
inevitably takes on moralistic overtones. How could it be otherwise? For
every victim, after all, there must be a victimizer – or, more to the point, a
class of victimizers. Even though victims had come to be seen in ever more
complex terms, victimizers had come to be seen in ever more facile ones.
Victims had come to deserve nothing other than compassion, in popular
opinion, and victimizers nothing other than denunciation and punishment.
Victims had come to seem thoroughly or even innately good and victimizers
thoroughly or innately evil (even though neither makes any sense, because
moral agents must by definition be free to choose between good and evil).
Victims had come to have no moral responsibility for their own behaviour,
but victimizers had come to have total moral responsibility for theirs. The
result was a bizarre combination of moral relativism in relation to “us” (that
is, victims of childhood trauma, physical or psychological addictions, low
self-esteem, or whatever) and moral purism in relation to “them” (the
victimizers). Charles Sykes, who wrote Nation of Victims, put it very
bluntly: “In a sense,” he said, “we’ve sanctioned revenge for people who
can claim to be victims.”10 Even though a few social commentators do
speak out now and then, no evidence suggests that much has changed in this
respect since the 1990s.
It would be folly, as Greenfield pointed out, to underestimate the
symbolic significance of law. Some panelists were therefore careful to
adopt moderate positions. Instead of agreeing with the verdict of not guilty,
which would have legitimated revenge and vigilantism, they advocated a
verdict of guilty but with extenuating circumstances to mitigate
punishment. This was the position, for example, of two legal experts: Lynn
Tepper, a judge of the Florida Circuit Court and member of the governor’s
Battered Women’s Clemency Review Board, and Patricia King, a law
professor at Georgetown University. “I personally am appalled at the
message we’re sending in these cases,” said King, “I’m a hardliner. You
commit a crime, you kill somebody, you mutilate them, you go to prison.
Maybe you get mitigation in the sentencing.”11 Yet she said also that “we
are putting [all] the weight on the criminal justice system … The jury is
stuck with the fact that we have not dealt, up until that point, with any of
these issues, at any other place in our system, effectively.”12
And this is surely true. The legal system itself cannot possibly solve
every problem; many other social and cultural systems must be brought into
action. The answer is not to look the other way when citizens take the law
into their own hands, therefore, but to provide them with shelter and
assistance before they resort to violence.13
The immediate problem created by the Bobbitt verdict was not
vigilantism, however – millions of women were not ready to copy Lorena
by castrating men physically14 – but they were ready to exploit her by
castrating men psychologically. Whatever their political leaders considered
expedient to say on national television, the fact is that millions of ordinary
women revelled vicariously in the lurid symbolism of revenge. For them,
Lorena’s behaviour was unfortunate, perhaps, but expedient nevertheless as
a message to men. What message did they want to send? Presumably, it was
simply this: abuse us at your own risk. But what message were men likely
to hear? The most benign was surely that we had already moved one step
beyond the debate over legalizing castration as a way of dealing with sex
offenders toward legitimating it legally and even morally as a symbol of
rage. A more sinister one was that we had already moved one step beyond
acknowledgment of the anger inspired by injustice toward promotion of the
revenge inspired by hatred. As a result, the level of moral, legal, and
political discourse was lowered beyond recognition.
Although men were certainly anxious about the implications of Lorena’s
case, they were reluctant to call into question their security and identity as
men – let alone their sympathy for women – by saying so. The prevailing
atmosphere thus inhibited men still further in their search for the distinctive
“voice” they would have needed in order to participate in any genuine
dialogue with women. As so many observers noted, all that most men could
do was to make “nervous jokes” about John Bobbitt, someone who was
supposed to represent them as a class – that is, as potential victims in the
eyes of men and as potential rapists in the eyes of women.
Lorena Bobbitt was the only participant in her sordid case that anyone –
either women or men – even tried or appeared to take seriously. Some
feminists were diplomatic enough to dissociate themselves from her. For
example, on one segment of NBC’s newsmagazine Now, Susan Estrich,
herself a victim of rape and an author on the subject, said that: “Mrs Bobbitt
is no hero of mine. And I don’t think she should be the hero of any woman
in this country who believes in the law. Mrs Bobbitt is a woman out of
control. I have a lot more respect for women than to make her our
symbol.”15 Many other feminists, though, allowed Lorena to merge with the
very icon that ideologues had been promoting for twenty or thirty years: the
innocent female victim of men who fights back against one of them. And if
the way that she fought back was emotionally and morally repugnant to
men, or even to many women, then so be it – or so much the better. To us,
this was the really disturbing thing.
According to Jamie Lee Evans, a rape crisis counsellor in San Francisco,
we “don’t need a judge or jury to tell us whether or not Lorena’s telling the
truth. Lorena came forward herself, said this man was battering her, this
man was raping her. That’s all we need to know to know that Lorena’s
telling the truth.”16 Never mind that, as mentioned, a jury had already found
John Bobbitt not guilty of raping his wife, at least on that occasion, a fact
that seems to have escaped every one of the jurors.17 Never mind that the
whole point of a trial in our legal system is to replace subjectivity with
some measure of objectivity in the search for truth. Never mind that those
who bypass the legal system are nothing more than vigilantes. Evans
observed also that “John Wayne Bobbitt is a big deal, because it’s a man’s
penis being mutilated. If it was a woman’s vagina being mutilated, no one
would care.”18 Really? Had she been living on Mars for the previous ten or
fifteen years? Had she never heard of the furore over the ritualized genital
mutilation of African girls? If a man had mutilated his wife’s vagina – or,
more to the point, cut off his sleeping wife’s breast and thrown it out the
window – he would have been burned in effigy throughout the country and
hunted down by vigilantes. Besides, how would public indifference in either
case make retaliation morally acceptable?
Answering that question was irrelevant to Barbara Ehrenreich and, if her
analysis was correct, to most other women as well. Her essay “Feminism
Confronts Bobbittry” appeared in Time, which no one can accuse of being a
marginal magazine, an organ of political radicals; on the contrary, it has
always been the mainstream newsmagazine par excellence. The article was
extremely revealing. Ehrenreich made it clear that Evans was by no means
an extremist and was not, therefore, fair game for trivialization as a member
of some lunatic fringe. Lorena’s trial indicated the existence of a “huge
divergence … between feminist intellectualdom, on the one hand, and an
average female cafeteria orator, on the other.” According to her, “feminist
pundits are tripping over one another to show that none of them is, goddess
forbid, a ‘man hater.’” Obviously, Ehrenreich saw nothing wrong with
being a man hater. “And while the pundits are making obvious but prissy-
sounding statements like ‘The fact that one has been a victim doesn’t give
one carte blanche to victimize others,’ the woman in the street is making V
signs by raising two fingers and bringing them together with a snipping
motion.”19 Well, what if it did sound “prissy” to remind people of
fundamental moral principles? Fear of ridicule has certainly never stopped
ideological feminists from making “obvious but prissy” statements in the
interest of women. (Consider the familiar dictum that no man ever has a
right to force himself on a woman, even a woman who suddenly changes
her mind about having sex.) If the statements Ehrenreich attributed to
pundits were so obvious, moreover, how could she have explained the fact
that so many women, by her own account, were oblivious to them?
According to Ehrenreich, feminist intellectuals were a bunch of elitists.
Internal conflicts had rendered them out of touch with ordinary women.
Among these conflicts was “the great standoff over the subject of victim-
hood.”20 On one side were the specialists in domestic violence, such as
Walker, who saw Lorena Bobbitt as a martyr. On the other side were those,
such as Naomi Wolf, who believed that women should stop whining and get
on with the business of seizing power.21 But this conflict was based on a
false dichotomy; it was a red herring. The two positions were not mutually
exclusive but, on the contrary, mutually reinforcing. The easiest way to
attain power in our society, after all, is still to attain the sacred status of
victimhood. Women do not have to stress either victimhood or power. They
can stress both. They can have their political cake, in other words, and eat it
too.
Millions of women understood that the rhetorical conflict meant nothing.
As Ehrenreich pointed out, they saw no need to wait around while the
ideological theorists and political strategists figured out a politically correct
way of acknowledging this. She admitted that “organized feminism” had
fostered a new “beyond bitch” attitude. Ignoring the stereotypes of men that
had become prevalent after more than two decades of ideological ranting,
she explained the new attitude as a result of nothing more than impatience
created by raised expectations. Of great importance, in any case, was the
fact that so many ordinary women identified themselves with Lorena not
only as a victim but also, mainly, as one who took revenge by taking the
law into her own hands, who fought back “by whatever means necessary.”22
If this last phrase sounds familiar, it is because ideologues on both the
political left and the political right are far from being the only ones to use it.
So do terrorists.
The terms of this controversy were usually limited on both sides to
practical ones: how to advise jurors, what effect sensationalism has on the
administration of justice, whether a verdict was likely to polarize the nation,
and so forth. If Lorena had been found guilty, for example, how could
women have been expected to protect themselves? If Lorena had been truly
not guilty, on the other hand, how could we have expected to endure as a
society based on the rule of law? Underlying these problems, though, was a
question of profound importance. Can ends justify means? The belief that
they can has always been attractive and has been applied, overtly in the
cases of national socialism and communism, although it was seldom openly
proclaimed before modern times. If ends can justify means, however, then
virtually nothing can be inherently wrong and virtually anything can be
justified for one reason or another.
In itself, the unofficial verdict in the Bobbitt trial was not morally
problematic, because even the most traditional moral systems recognize
self-defense in the context of immediate physical danger as the one end that
really can justify what would otherwise be an unacceptable means. In other
words, it is the lesser of two evils. However, many cases that come to court,
including Lorena’s, do not involve immediate physical danger. As long as
potential assailants are doing something else – as long as they are sleeping,
for instance – no physical response is necessary. Because the ideologues
refused to admit this, they had to argue that a good end (the elimination of
potential danger) had justified an evil means (a pre-emptive strike). But
what they really meant was that the collective end (helping women as a
class) justified the collective means (punishing or threatening men as a
class).
Ehrenreich herself, it should be clearly noted, really did believe that ends
could justify means. She challenged her colleagues in the feminist
establishment not for accepting this idea, after all, but merely for doing so
surreptitiously. Why, she wondered, were they ashamed of accepting it? In
fact, she argued, most women knew better. Those who rejected the label
“feminist” did so not because it carried the connotation of hating men, she
opined, but because “it has come to sound just too damn dainty.”
Ehrenreich’s concluding paragraph made her moral and legal position clear.
“Personally,” she wrote, “I’m for both feminism and nonviolence. I admire
the male body and prefer to find the penis attached to it … But I’m not
willing to wait another decade or two for gender peace to prevail. And if a
fellow insists on using his penis as a weapon, I say that, one way or another,
he ought to be swiftly disarmed.”23
This mentality, which supposedly makes sense not only in emotional
terms but on practical grounds as well, is, ironically, most likely to prove
very impractical – unless, of course, practicality is defined in terms that
exclude gender peace or even gender interaction. If a relationship can be
maintained only on the basis of fear felt by either the woman or the man, it
is hardly worth maintaining at all.

The debate over Lorena Bobbitt did not occur in a vacuum. How to
understand the reasons for domestic violence and what to do about
offenders had been hotly debated by social workers and academics in the
preceding decade. Ideological feminists, many of whom were themselves
professionals in the field, were actively involved in these debates. They
promoted their cause with statistics on the extent of domestic abuse by men
– some of which, as we observe in both chapter 10 and appendix 3, were
highly dubious – challenged the interpretations and clinical practices of
others in the field, and mobilized public opinion by playing on the fears of
women. (For a detailed examination of the ideological “discourse” on
domestic violence, see the case study in appendix 13.)
On one level, this chapter (along with that appendix, which is closely
related) has been about hostility expressed physically in the home. On
another level, it has been about hostility expressed verbally in both popular
and elite culture. What happens when people who might have engaged in
dialogue turn instead to something resembling warfare? It is especially in
the context of domestic violence that ideological feminists have encouraged
the rhetoric of victimization. By far the most successful and important of
their projects, one that combines therapeutic and moralistic features, has
been the political movement focused on victims of domestic violence.
Feminists have brought it to public attention as an urgent social problem,
and with good reason, but they have done so by supporting three extremely
dubious assumptions: that almost all human beings except white
heterosexual men can claim to be victims of abuse for one reason or
another, that victimhood can be equated with innocence, and that
victimization in the past can eliminate moral responsibility for losing
control in the present.
Where there are victims, presumably – but not always logically – there
are victimizers. Ideological feminists have denied, trivialized, or excused
the abuse of men by women. If they had not, they realize, some central
pillars of their worldview would have collapsed: that all social problems
can or even must be explained in terms of power, that men have all the
power, and that men are encouraged to use it against women. As we have
argued, profound essentialism and dualism – “we” are by nature good;
“they” are by nature evil – are characteristic of every ideology, including
feminist ideology. No wonder the debate over domestic abuse has been so
fierce!
The debate goes on and on and on. Arguments for one side are refuted
with counterarguments and those, in turn, with other counterarguments. One
side of the debate has produced websites with extensive bibliographies and
links on “husband battering”24 and the other on “gender asymmetry.”25
Given how much both men and feminists have at stake here, it seems clear
that this debate will continue for a long time. But the game of “comparative
suffering” (a topic that we will discuss in Transcending Misandry) is of
very dubious moral value. It assumes that human suffering can be
quantified and then exploited for political purposes. We suffer more, each
side says, than you do. We deserve compassion, therefore, and you do not.
As if one premise follows logically and morally from the other.
Of importance here, in any case, are not the precise numbers. By now,
everyone agrees that some men are battered by women. No matter what the
numbers are on either side, the problem would still be serious and would
still undermine some key planks in the political platform of ideological
feminism.
3
Workers v. Harassers: The Hill-Thomas Debate
What the hearing lacked and what I and others found missing was balance
in terms of credibility – mine certainly equalled Thomas’ – in the matter
and balance in terms of process – the weight of the Senate and the
Executive should not have been used against an individual citizen called
upon to participate in a public process.1

This is a circus! A national disgrace! … a high-tech lynching for uppity


blacks who in any way deign to think for themselves.2

The problem of sexual harassment, like other problems studied by


feminists, is a serious one. We will discuss various legal remedies for it in
chapter 8 and some closely related topics in chapters 7, 9, and 10. For the
time being, consider an event that crystallized public opinion on the topic.
Between 11 and 13 October 1991, millions of people huddled around their
television sets to watch the confirmation hearing of Clarence Thomas, a
black man who had been nominated several weeks earlier as a justice of the
Supreme Court. A seismic event, it was reported on the news all day and
every day and discussed on every talk show. It was said to have changed
America. It certainly polarized America: men versus women, blacks versus
whites, conservatives versus liberals. Almost anything that could be said
about any public event was said about this one.
In this chapter, we discuss the hearing itself and its immediate aftermath,
the problems that surfaced in connection with it, some responses from
women, and some of the effects.

Thomas had never been a popular candidate for a job on the Supreme
Court. During the evaluation hearing, he evaded some controversial
positions – he actually claimed never to have discussed abortion with his
friends and fellow lawyers – and glossed over earlier statements about legal
principles such as natural law. Still, his confirmation was all but assured by
11 October. Then, suddenly, he was struck by a bolt of political
lightning: an accusation of sexual harassment made by Anita Hill, a law
professor at the University of Oklahoma who had once worked for Thomas
at the Equal Employment Opportunities Commission.
According to Hill, Thomas had repeatedly asked her for dates. After
being rejected on each occasion, he subjected her to offensive discussions
of pornography. Hill had hoped that her accusations would remain
anonymous and confidential. When someone leaked her story to the press,
though, she defended her position in the full glare of public debate. The
climax, as it were, came when Hill accused Thomas of boasting about the
size of his penis. This confirmed a common stereotype of black men. With
that in mind, Thomas accused her, or at least her supporters, of racism (even
though Hill herself was black). His confirmation hearing, he observed, had
turned into “ a high-tech lynching of an uppity black man” who dared to
take unpopular positions. According to Jean Bethke Elshtain,

those who were hoarse in their defense of Hill, and more generally in their
pious and politically correct assertions about gender and power and
knowledge, might have taken the trouble to observe that they themselves
were complicit in the construction of the black male as a paradigmatic
sexual suspect. The tendency to portray black men as sexually rapacious,
with a propensity to rape, has long been an unsavory theme in many (white)
feminist tracts. In Susan Brownmiller’s Against Our Will, for example, the
“feminist classic” that helped to spur the obsession with rape, and the
conflation of rape with sex in the minds of radical feminists, it is asserted
that the allegations of white women against black men in the Jim Crow
South were to be credited, because white women and black women formed
a single oppressed category against men. In Brownmiller’s words, “The
sexual oppression of black women, and all women is commonly shared,”
under slavery and into the present.3

Overnight, this confrontation became the hottest story since, well, since
anyone could remember. Most viewers agreed that an already acrimonious
and politicized hearing had turned into an even less edifying spectacle. Had
the charges of sexism and racism not been so serious, it might indeed have
been what many were already calling it: a circus, a sideshow, or, as one
commentator put it, a sequel to Sex, Lies, and Videotapes that could have
been called Sex, Lies, and Stereotypes.4 At least some viewers must have
wondered what people in Europe and elsewhere were thinking as they
watched senators listening intently to fantastically lurid stories about pubic
hair, penises, and pornography. Millions of viewers dropped everything
else, even baseball games, to avoid missing a single sordid detail. When it
was all over, on 14 October at 2:00 A.M., the committee adjourned after
having only achieved a stalemate. The decision itself came on 16 October:
Thomas was confirmed by the smallest margin since 1881.
But there was nothing amusing or trivial about this bizarre and even
grotesque “ordeal by word.” The hearing itself bore more than a passing
resemblance to the McMartin witch hunt of the 1990s, the McCarthy witch
hunt of the 1950s, and even to the Salem witch hunt of the 1690s. Not
surprisingly, many people came away more cynical than ever about the
processes and institutions that supposedly sustained justice. Moreover, there
was nothing edifying or encouraging about the public response, which
would have been far less disturbing had it been motivated merely by the
kind of self-righteousness generally associated with prurience. Instead, it
was motivated largely by the kind of self-righteousness generally associated
with political ideologies of both the political left and the political right. As a
result, what might have been an opportunity for a public debate between
men and women (though probably not a genuine dialogue) turned into a
public harangue directed against men by women. What happened, in fact,
provides an ideal case study of precisely what we hope this book will help
us avoid in the future.
Elected officials have always tried to be politically correct (a topic that
we discuss in appendix 4), especially when they appear every day on
television. Yet some are convinced that politically correct positions are also
morally correct. No wonder sanctimonious posturing was common in the
Hill-Thomas case and intellectual probing rare. The situation was similar in
living rooms, newsrooms, offices, cafeterias, and bars across the land (in
Canada no less than the United States). Not surprisingly, it was the subject
of monologues on late-night talk shows and at least one episode of a
situation comedy.
Given the overtly feminist worldview of Designing Women, it was
almost inevitable that one episode would include some explicit comments
on the Thomas hearing.5 No attempt was made to ensure that both sides
were given a fair hearing. On this episode, Mary Jo and Julia have a fight
with Allison over the Hill-Thomas affair. Mary Jo and Julia support Anita
Hill, and Allison supports Clarence Thomas. Mary Jo and Julia are the
moral and political heavyweights on this show. Allison is the pretty but
ditsy “belle” who need not be taken seriously. She is the proverbial “straw
man” whose statements are all stereotypical, uttered only to be refuted by
polemical declamations from the others. The studio audience responds to
everything Allison says with hoots or boos, of course, but to everything
Mary Jo and Julia say with applause. In a way, the atmosphere of this
episode is like that of a revival meeting, replete with testimonials and
denunciations. Even Anthony, the token (black) man, is exploited for
political purposes to assert that Thomas does not represent black people.
The ostensible story for this episode, Allison’s birthday party, all but
disappears under the weight of these diatribes; the characters are merely
mouthpieces for ideological rhetoric. The show concludes with a montage
of snapshots from the Thomas hearing. At the very end is a still photo of
Anita Hill. Her head downcast, her eyes closed, she looks like a perfect
martyr for the faith.
During the hearing itself, the senators obviously had to hear all the
evidence in public if they were to avoid the accusation of not taking women
seriously, but going public meant that they could be accused of pandering to
popular opinion and political pressure. How, one might well ask, could they
have allowed a public trial – and this was a kind of trial – without the
slightest shred of evidence to support the testimony of character witnesses
on either side? In the end, the illusion of justice was preserved but, as
partisans on both sides have angrily observed, though for different reasons,
not necessarily justice itself. The allegations had been discussed openly, but
both the process and the result were widely condemned. Some
commentators argued that merely being exposed to such a hideous invasion
of his personal life made Thomas a victim of injustice. Others argued that
the same was true of Hill, and in addition, of course, they were outraged by
the final decision.
Either Hill or Thomas must have been lying, it was said over and over
again, because the two stories contradicted each other. If either of them was
lying, nobody will ever know which one (although it is safe to say that
everybody has an opinion on the matter). Because no substantive evidence
was introduced on either side, the whole trial was based entirely on her
word against his. The good senators eventually had to come down on one
side or the other, based at least in theory solely on who had given the better
performance. Some proclaimed Hill’s performance more “credible” or
“powerful” than that of Thomas. Others proclaimed the reverse. No wonder
so many people over so many years have commented on the unreality or
theatricality of public life in America.
The senators, along with many viewers and commentators, made
assumptions that can be summed up in a syllogism: either Thomas or Hill
was lying; people lie to cover up improper behaviour; ergo, either Thomas
or Hill had behaved improperly. As a result, the senators speculated about
possible motivations that Hill might have had for lying. No other way of
solving the case occurred to them. But what if the initial assumption was
based on a superficial examination of the possibilities? Suppose that
Thomas really had said what Hill reported, that he really was lying and Hill
really telling the truth. Would knowing that have truly settled the matter to
everyone’s satisfaction? Probably not. Consider the following two
scenarios.
Thomas and Hill might indeed have discussed pornography and
disagreed, as lawyers and academics often do, about its legal, sociological,
political, and psychological significance. In view of the controversy
surrounding this subject, Thomas could legitimately have urged Hill to
examine it more carefully. If so, his refusal to acknowledge any discussion
of pornography at all would indeed have been a lie. But how else could he
have defended himself in the self-righteous atmosphere of this hearing and
the increasingly puritanical atmosphere of this society?
On the other hand, Thomas might indeed have found discussions of
pornography erotically entertaining. Does everyone really agree that
discussing pornography is inherently either immoral or unhealthy (which
we discuss in chapter 7)? If not, should a discussion of the kind reported by
Hill be considered sexual harassment? For those who could answer yes to
the question, the only matter worth considering was the truth of Hill’s
allegations. For those who could answer no to the same question, on the
other hand, the situation was far more complicated. What mattered for them
was not what Thomas had said to Hill but how she interpreted what he had
said. Since her interpretation now corresponds to the law of the land, the
legitimacy of laws governing sexual harassment is at issue here.
To be effective and legitimate, laws must be based on consensus. If they
are not – prohibition of liquor under the Volstead Act comes to mind – they
are ignored, flouted, or resisted in one way or another by large segments of
the population. This, in turn, generates cynicism and brings both the courts
and the legislature into disrepute. Judging from the public response to this
hearing, it is clear that no consensus underlay current laws defining sexual
harassment. Ideological feminists had already succeeded in attaining a very
broad legal definition of it, but they had failed to convince many men and
even some women that this definition was appropriate. And these feminists
were willing to hold Thomas responsible for events of ten years earlier,
even though both cultural and legal standards had been very different then.
This presents us with the problem of anachronism. Support for Thomas was
possible even for some who believed that he was lying, consequently, and
hostility toward Hill was possible even for some who believed that she was
telling the truth.
Had either scenario been considered, much of the resulting anger might
have been avoided. There would have been no need to protect Thomas by
trying to prove that Hill was motivated to lie about him, either by political
malice or by neurotic fantasies. She might have been telling the truth about
events, in fact, but interpreting them from a point of view that was, to judge
from the public response, highly debatable. Moreover, there would have
been no need to protect Hill by trying to prove that she had remained silent
for fear of losing her job. Instead, it would have been necessary to find out
when she had adopted her current point of view. Ten years earlier, she might
have considered her situation uncomfortable but not serious enough to
require legal attention. Finally, there would have been no need to accuse
her, as distinct from some supporters, of political opportunism or cynicism.
Like many other women during those ten years, she might have become
deeply convinced of a moral responsibility to speak out. Even though this
scenario would not have provided any explanation for the larger ideological
struggle in which both Hill and Thomas were pawns, it would have
provided a perfectly reasonable explanation for both Hill’s initial delay in
coming forward with the accusation and her strong desire to come forward
with it later.
Although both Hill and Thomas were subjected to inquiries about their
private lives and attacks on their personal integrity, many observers felt
sympathy for only one of the two “stars” in this production. Hill’s
supporters claimed that she was the chief victim – indeed, the only victim.
And she was a victim in some ways. For instance, she was accused of
fabricating the entire case out of romantic delusions. This was both
demeaning to her and frightening to all women whose jobs were threatened.
Moreover, Hill had to risk her personal and professional reputation by going
public without any supporting evidence. We believe that her status as a
victim was greatly exaggerated. And some women, including Elshtain,
agree. She observes that the melodrama

was presented as the primal and prototypical engagement between a


powerful male and a “passive” female. “Passive,” that is, by Hill’s own
account. Although Thomas insisted on seeing Hill as a resourceful,
energetic and competent woman, she staked out the ground of her own
helplessness, which extended even to her conversations and acquaintances.
“I was very passive in the conversation,” she reported, referring to a casual
discussion with several people about her reaction to the news that Thomas
had been nominated to the Court. When Senator Arlen Specter asked,
“Excuse me?” she repeated the sorry but, as it turned out, politically shrewd
refrain: “I was very passive in the conversation.” Hill’s representation of
herself in such reactive terms struck me at the time as pretty unbelievable. I
could not help noticing that she was seen by others (not only by Thomas) as
a woman quite capable of making her own way through the world and
pressing her own case. A female co-worker testified that “when I worked
with Anita Hill and I knew her … she was not a victim. She was a very
tough woman. She stood her ground. She didn’t take a lot of anything from
anyone, and she made sure you knew it.” Clearly Hill was, and is, not only
capable, but also ambitious.6

Elsewhere, Elshtain notes one implication of this focus on female


passivity. “Dusting off hoary stereotypes of male lust and female
sexlessness, presenting a world in which sex is what men ‘do’ to women, is
one of the more disturbing features of contemporary feminist
argumentation; and now, in the wake of the Hill-Thomas affair, it is
working its way into our government and our politics.”7
At some level of consciousness, Hill must have realized that beyond her
immediate difficulties, she had an ultimate advantage over Thomas. If he
was found guilty, she would become a heroine. And if he was found
innocent, she would become a martyr. No matter what happened, in other
words, Hill would be glorified by a large and vocal segment of the
population for having given maximum visibility to the cause of women.
Thomas, on the other hand, would be tainted for having been unable to
prove that he had not indulged in some hideously wicked behaviour.
In view of this situation, some comments by Hill’s supporters were
tendentious. It is true that witnesses talked about her private life, but what
they said paled by comparison with what she said about the private life of
Thomas. After all, it was his allegedly monstrous penis and the most
intimate details of his allegedly vile and disgusting personal life that the
whole nation was talking about.
Again, it is true that one senator accused Hill of perjury, which later
brought indignant cries of “shame” from Senator Edward Kennedy. But if
we reject the old stereotypical notion that women lie in cases of this kind,
why accept the new stereotypical notion that women don’t lie? Obviously,
both women and men are capable of lying, especially when they believe
that doing so can be justified politically. And this truly was an ideal
opportunity to promote political goals, because Thomas was known to
oppose not only new legislation against sexual harassment but also abortion
and affirmative action. In the absence of any concrete evidence, how could
the senators ignore this possibility?
In several disturbing ways, this event followed the script of a rape trial.
First, given the lack of concrete evidence, lawyers have often questioned
the female plaintiff’s personal integrity and credibility, as they did with
Hill. Second, given the same lack of evidence, these trials focus heavily on
performance in court. Some people might have supported Hill not because
of her evidence but because of the way in which she conducted herself.
Third, notwithstanding ideological claims to the contrary, public opinion
nowadays is usually with the alleged victims of men. This alone would have
worked against Thomas, but still, because of his positions on abortion or
affirmative action, many people already disliked him. Finally, some people
support the alleged victim merely because of group solidarity. In this case,
Hill’s supporters knew that many women really are victims of sexual
harassment and many of them probably believed that “women don’t lie.”
Even though it was Hill who attacked Thomas, therefore, many viewers
were convinced that he had originally attacked her. As the “true victim,”
she was attacking him only in retaliation.
Whatever Hill’s intentions – let us assume here that they were sincere
and even altruistic – the fact remains that both she and the cause she has
come to represent benefited from this experience in the following years.
Even as she arrived back home at the University of Oklahoma, students and
colleagues were ready to welcome her as a martyr for the cause of women.
And millions of people all over the country – not a majority, but a very
sizable minority – joined them in spirit. For years now, she has been sought
eagerly for speaking engagements not only by talk-show hosts but by
serious journalists, academics, and feminists. From the beginning, it was
clear that any publisher would jump at the chance to work with her. And she
did publish a book in 1997.8 In some very important ways, then, Hill’s
prospects have been greatly enhanced by this trial.9
Now, though, think about all this from the perspective of Clarence
Thomas. Although Thomas had some advantages over Hill, since he was a
man (albeit a black man) of considerable authority, he was also a man
openly attacked by many for his political beliefs. Moreover, since the
accused is presumed innocent unless proven guilty, the burden of proof was
on Hill, not Thomas. It was perfectly appropriate, therefore, that the
senators gave him the benefit of their doubt. In the court of public opinion,
on the other hand, Thomas was being accused by someone who, as Hill’s
supporters pointed out, spoke for millions of innocent victims. By virtue of
this fact alone, it was he who had to dispel initial suspicion, not Hill. In the
end, Hill could not prove beyond a reasonable doubt that he was guilty. But
neither could Thomas prove that he was innocent. The senators were less
willing than the nation to give him the benefit of the doubt. Just over half of
the former found Thomas innocent, but two-thirds of the latter did. Clearly,
most people chose to ignore their lingering doubts. But, as Thomas himself
sadly observed, those doubts would always remain and continue to cast a
shadow over his moral integrity (and over the integrity of the Senate and the
Supreme Court as well).
As one savvy journalist put it, “What we had here was a victim-off, a
contest to see who was the most convincing victim. And I think that
Clarence Thomas won that in that he was the more immediate victim of the
lynch mob that was coming after him and he was also a more passionate
victim than … Anita Hill. But I think that the search for victim status which
is probably the highest status a public figure can aspire to in America right
now was really what was going on.”10
One more question. Assuming for a moment that Thomas had really said
some offensive things to Hill, would that justify the penalty that might have
been imposed on him? Although Hill herself did not intend to humiliate him
before the entire nation, once word had leaked out, her supporters
demanded that he be tried publicly, knowing that one false move in his own
defense would destroy him. Can we really compare what Hill might have
endured temporarily because of Thomas to what he would have had to
endure permanently because of her? No matter how unpleasant her
experience might have been ten years earlier, Hill had prospered over the
years. Had she won this case, though, his career would have been utterly
ruined.
From the start, it was obvious to everyone that more important matters
than the conduct of either Hill or Thomas were at stake. Unfortunately, only
two were actually discussed in any depth: the brutal process of confirming
nominees to the Supreme Court, including the fact that feminists were
mobilizing to prevent the addition of a conservative Republican to the
Supreme Court, and the fact that many women want protection from sexual
harassment. Other matters, including many that underlie these, were usually
ignored.

The hearing presented several problems. One was defining “sexual


harassment.” According to one survey of popular opinion in the aftermath
of this case, 41% of Americans believed that sexual harassment occurs
when a woman’s boss or superior flirts with her; 64%, when he is
accustomed to putting his arm around her; 74%, when he tells sexual jokes
to her; 77%, when he pressures her for a date; 80%, when his speech
includes either direct or indirect sexual references; 87%, when he asks her
to have sex with him; and 91%, when he insists on discussing pornographic
acts with her.11
Of great interest here is the fact that listening to the boss discuss
pornography is considered an even more definitive feature of sexual
harassment than actually being asked to have sexual relations!
Thomas was not accused of raping Hill or even of touching her. And he
could not truly be accused of intimidating or blackmailing Hill, because her
job was never at risk; on the contrary, he continued to promote her
throughout her career.12 He was accused, actually, of nothing more than
repeatedly asking Hill for a date and saying vulgar things to her. His alleged
use of language was called “outrageous,” “unspeakable,” “grotesque,”
“vile,” “perverted,” “appalling,” “heinous,” “psychopathic,” and even
“insane.” Although some commentators argue that offensive talk can indeed
be a crime for which the culprit ought to be punished, their argument can be
challenged. The world is not always a nice place. Consequently, adults must
be expected to face at least some degree of adversity or conflict with
courage and dignity. The Constitution guarantees all Americans the right to
pursue happiness but not happiness itself.13
Moreover, a double standard was clearly at work in the Thomas case,
since it was and still is considered politically correct for women to make
what used to be called lewd remarks. This is demonstrated every night of
the week on television in reruns of The Golden Girls. Three of the
characters – Blanche, Dorothy, and Sophia – say hardly anything without
making crude sexual innuendoes. Blanche speaks incessantly of her lovers
and their physical endowments, along with her own. One aim of the early
feminist movement was precisely to abolish the double standard by which
men, but not women, were free to indulge in sexual play and sexual talk.
But a new double standard has replaced the old. We are now asked to
believe that women are liberated when they talk about male bodies, no
matter how crudely, but that men are sexist when they do the same thing
about female bodies.
Why should anyone assume that men, unlike women, will tolerate a
double standard? If women may use the term “sexual harassment” in
connection with something beyond intimidation or blackmail – indecent
exposure, assault, rape – then surely men may do so as well. (Whether
women or men should use the law to do so is another matter, though,
because not everything that is immoral must be illegal as well.) For women,
sexual harassment has come to mean the creation of an atmosphere in
which men either directly or indirectly express their sexual interest in
women. To be harassed in this sense might mean having to reject repeated
advances, feeling discomfort due to crude discussions of sex, being exposed
to posters of nude women, or merely finding copies of Playboy around the
office. For men, however, sexual harassment might mean the creation of an
atmosphere in which ideological stereotypes of men are commonplace or in
which men are made to fear questioning prevalent ideological assumptions,
including those on which company policies are based. Underlying the
feminist movement is the assumption that conditions need to be improved
precisely because they were created by men. To varying degrees, therefore,
every branch of feminism is also a movement dedicated to the critique of
this or that group of men or of men as such. Which raises an interesting
question: If men should not be allowed to keep copies of Playboy in their
offices, why should women be allowed to keep copies of Ms. in their
offices? In fact, it would be hard to find an issue of any mass-market
magazine addressed to women that fails to include at least one article that
would be offensive to men by implying that they are not merely different
from women but inferior. And many of these magazines go further, focusing
attention on the ways in which men victimize women. Why should men not
feel intimidated by women who reflect this worldview even in casual
conversations and who believe that men have no reason for resenting
repeated attacks on “the male model” of working, thinking, feeling,
speaking, and so forth?14
Those men and women who want to be part of the solution rather than
the problem will have to acknowledge that gender-related stress in the
workplace – or, to use the current expression, “sexual harassment” – is a
problem for both sexes. It might take different forms in each case, but its
effect is the same: feeling threatened, manipulated, trivialized, or
disrespected as men or as women. From what was said during and after the
Thomas hearing, though, it is obvious that the old double standard has not
merely been turned on its head but also institutionalized by law. How can
any moral or legal definition of sexual harassment work unless it is
acceptable, or at least tolerable, to both women and men?
Another problem was the current glorification of political correctness,
which was a serious impediment to freedom of speech. It would have been
political suicide for any journalist or commentator even to question a
feminist position; for a senator it would have been like questioning biblical
authority in a fundamentalist community. Although the senators themselves
were male, they made every attempt (though sometimes unsuccessfully) not
to speak as men on national television. In one way, that was helpful; they
had to address the needs of women as well as men. In another way, though,
it was not: they effectively “silenced the voice” of men per se in an
extremely important public debate that concerned men no less than women.
Yet another problem with the hearings was created by feminist
interpretations of harassment. These draw, says Elshtain, on critiques of
objectivity in scholarship (which we will discuss in chapter 10). “I and my
reality,” said Hill at the hearing, “did not comport with what they accepted
as their reality.”15 Commenting on this statement, Elshtain remarks that
“these words pithily and a little chillingly capture a controlling idea of our
blinkered cultural and academic life … To go beyond the reality of
perspectives to the claim that there are only perspectives, that facts
themselves are arbitrary inventions and that there is only ‘my reality’ and
‘your reality’ is to embrace nonsense. And to go still further and argue that
the conditions of knowledge change with a change of gender, that men and
women inhabit disparate epistemological universes, is to embrace not only
nonsense, but dangerous nonsense.”16 (More about all that in chapters 8 and
9.) “If the controversy about Hill and Thomas has been so susceptible to
ideological distortions,” Elshtain continues, “and if the dogma that
knowledge is power has lent itself so smoothly to the discussion of sexual
harassment, it is because knowledge is elusive in this particular instance,
not because knowledge is generally impossible. There are such things as the
facts.”17 It is very hard to establish the facts; witnesses are seldom
available. There might be only circumstantial evidence, which is often
based on “perceptions.” “That is why Hill can continue to say, in some of
her post-hearing public talks, that ‘women should be supported regardless
of proof.’ She is hiding a political statement behind an epistemological
hardship.”18 In short, harassment cases are almost always ambiguous. Even
the official terminology – defining words such as “unwelcome” and
“pervasive” – are understood in various ways. The result, says John Cloud,
“is a thicket of rulings. Since 1991 juries have returned well over five
hundred verdicts on sexual harassment decisions that often contradict one
another and send mixed signals about how we should behave any time we
meet a co-worker we’d like to see after five.”19
America’s legal system rests on a fundamental premise: that the accused
is innocent unless proven guilty beyond a reasonable doubt. This premise
does inhibit prosecution to some extent, but it also prevents persecution.
Supporters of Hill pointed out correctly that the difficulty in finding
evidence to substantiate claims in cases of this kind means that many
victims prefer to remain silent. But what is the appropriate solution to this
problem? Must we overturn the moral and legal basis of our society by
declaring that accusations with nothing more substantial than hearsay to
support them should be believed merely because they are made by women?
Or that the accused should be presumed guilty instead of innocent? Some
ideological feminists would answer both questions in the affirmative.
Already convinced from the beginning that Hill had a legitimate case,
therefore, they were outraged that not everyone came to the same
conclusion. Justice, they said, had been denied. We have always known that
guilty people are sometimes exonerated and innocent people sometimes
convicted. Our legal system is not perfect. But Anita Hill did have her day
in “court.” As it happened, she lost. Citizens are guaranteed the right to be
heard, not some right to be believed.

Several years after the Hill-Thomas hearing, its legal and political fallout
had still not settled. Women did not stand idly by. Dissatisfied with the fact
that not everyone believed Hill (although an increasing number did), Jane
Mayer and Jill Abramson reopened the “national dialogue” with another
look at the case in Strange Justice.20 Of primary interest to them are the
“other women” who were not allowed to testify in 1991. The authors
conclude that Thomas was the liar, not Hill. As mentioned, this, in itself,
could not prove that he had been a sexual harasser. Much of the evidence
discussed, however, has nothing to do with events that either did or did not
take place.
The authors focus attention on Thomas’s character. For them, the mere
fact that Thomas enjoys porn is enough to qualify him as someone with an
evil character. They interview the owner of a video store, who says that
Thomas was a regular in the x-rated section. They report that he could find
nothing worth salvaging from his first marriage except his collection of
Playboy magazines and that his own mother had once called him a bully.
The implication is obvious: any man who likes to look at beautiful women
must be the kind of man who would harass them.
By 1996, Hill herself had written a book, Speaking Truth to Power,
which includes an “Open Letter to the 1991 Senate Judiciary Committee.”
“What the hearing lacked and what I and others found missing,” writes Hill
in her letter, “was balance in terms of credibility – mine certainly equalled
Thomas’ – in the matter and balance in terms of process – the weight of the
Senate and the Executive should not have been used against an individual
citizen called upon to participate in a public process.” Well, should the
weight of institutions such as the Senate and the Executive have been used
instead against Thomas? He, too, was a citizen. “Neither the issue of
harassment nor the nomination,” writes Hill, “was served by a presumption
of my untruthfulness.” Indeed, this presumption should not have been
made. But Hill implies that it should have been made against Thomas.
Elsewhere, Hill writes that “anything less than a balanced approach
condemns women to second-class status and the Court to members who
abuse power and authority granted to them in a public trust.”21
The problem of balance underlies Hill’s whole discussion, but judging
from what she writes elsewhere, it is clear to us that she understands
balance from the perspective of ideological feminism. Would a more
balanced approach of this kind not merely turn the problem on its head by
condemning men to second-class status? Hill writes that “since sexual
harassment was central to the nominee’s qualifications, the members of the
committee should have educated themselves on the issue before them.
Evidence that you failed to do so lies in your use of social myths to explain
my testimony, your refusal to utilize information provided by experts on
sexual harassment, and your deviation from your own procedural rules in
hearing the testimony as presented.” But how should the senators have
educated themselves? Obviously to Hill, by exposing themselves to
feminist indoctrination. Hill argues that the experts in question should have
been formally trained in the psychology and sociology of sexual
harassment. Because the ones who get that training are almost always
feminists, she clearly refers to them. Hill does not actually say that, of
course. What she does say is that the investigation “should be handled by a
non-partisan body or individual in the role of neutral fact finder,
experienced in investigating sexual harassment.”22
Hill writes that the committee should have considered only “competent
information.” When there is no clear-cut evidence that favours the female
plaintiff’s case, she implies, the assessment should be based on women’s
general integrity, a recommendation that is based, in turn, on the “finding”
of one survey that only 3% of the harassment claims filed are baseless and
that 97% of the cases go unreported. “Women rarely use harassment claims
to escape responsibility for the problems in their lives,” Hill continues.
“However, when, without fully investigating it, you presumed that my
claim was a frivolous or spite claim, you advocated action based on the
exception rather than the rule.”23 But statistics are notoriously unreliable in
political controversies and thus cannot provide a very firm foundation for
justice. That “97%” is not even a statistic of actual cases, moreover, but an
estimate of experiences that were never reported. Given current debates
over the inflation of statistics by feminist and other ideologues (appendix
2), should at least think twice before using even statistics as evidence.
“One of the greatest disservices that the Judiciary Committee did,”
writes Hill, “was to unnecessarily blur the lines between the nominee’s
public and private behavior.” But following the feminist dictum that “the
personal is political,” she considers it justifiable to assess the personal lives
of candidates, especially if they are seeking jobs that involve law – jobs at
the Supreme Court, say, or the Department of Justice. It is one thing when
homicide or sexual assault is involved. In those cases, even private matters
are appropriately discussed in public. But Hill refers specifically to sexual
harassment. Must we assume that her private dealings with Thomas should
be discussed in public? Elsewhere, she makes the same point: “Thus, the
information about his behavior was relevant regardless of whether it fit
within the definitions of behavior which was outlawed.”24
Hill’s strategy, a common one among ideologues, is to expand
definitions and thus encourage the broadest possible legal interpretation (a
strategy that we discuss in chapters 8 and 9). By making anything and
everything in the private domain subject to public scrutiny, of course, you
can increase the likelihood of finding some source for a smear campaign. It
is true that the private and public domains do intersect in some legal
contexts, and the former can be relevant when assessing candidates for
public leadership. But this does not mean that the personal should
necessarily be political. If Hill’s case had been one of quid pro quo, if she
had been able to prove that Thomas had offered professional advantages or
job security in return for sexual favours, okay, case closed. But that was
hardly the case. What she advocates, therefore, is a radical change in the
judicial system. Any change of that kind should surely be a topic of public
debate, not merely of a declaration.
Here is another of Hill’s claims: “Often, absent a court ruling, a person
offering evidence of illegal activity cannot establish with certainty that the
information that they are seeking to present represents a violation of the
law. Placing the burden of obtaining a court ruling or otherwise establishing
a violation with absolute certainty does not serve the public interest in
making a thorough determination about the nominee.”25 This approach
relies on a reversal of the ad hominem argument. It is based on the
assumption of her integrity in particular and that of women in general, not
on actual evidence of illegal or even immoral behaviour.
Had there been an adequate sexual-harassment procedure in place, Hill
believes, her claim could have been processed within seven to ten days.26
Nevertheless, it took Hill herself ten years to make that claim in the first
place. And had there been an adequate sexual-harassment procedure in
place, Hill believes, there need not have been a public hearing. This would
have prevented embarrassment for both her, she says, and the government
(although she obviously does not care about that of Thomas). But the
danger of procedures without hearings – and that is precisely what some
feminists want – is the absence of cross-examination, which becomes
especially important if sexual-harassment officers have been trained to
think in a particular way and thus to control the process for ideological
purposes.
Ironically, the feminists who were so vociferous in their condemnation
of Clarence Thomas behaved very differently when two other political
leaders – Senator Robert Packwood and President Bill Clinton – were
charged (one formally and the other informally) with sexual harassment. At
least some commentators have explained this double standard in connection
with political opportunism: Packwood and Clinton, unlike Thomas, used
their legislative power in ways approved of by feminists.
Gloria Steinem played the social constructionist card – that is, the political
card – by proclaiming that Packwood’s actions should be explored and
judged “in context.” And what context might that be? The answer is simple:
the context in which Packwood [could] be counted on to deliver the votes
that various women’s groups (naral) [National Abortion and Reproductive
Rights Action League] and the Women’s Legal Defense Fund, among
others) wanted delivered on abortion, affirmative action and other matters.
Politics and politics alone accounted for the reluctance of these national
tribunes of the weaker sex to respond to a blatant, egregious and (finally) an
admitted string of offenses. Eventually their hands were forced by local
outrage and national publicity. No such patience, however, with Clarence
Thomas.27

Feminist opinion on Clinton’s escapades was very divided. “What is


immoral is not President Clinton’s having normal sexual impulses,” argues
one. “What is immoral is hating someone as much as Clinton’s detractors
do, just for the purpose of destroying him.”28 Wendy Kaminer presented a
less emotional argument for letting Clinton off the hook: “Instead of
quaintly accusing Clinton of defiling women, feminists should reconsider
their commitment to policing minor instances of sexual misconduct at the
expense of sexual privacy, free speech and a view of adult women as
independent beings capable of discouraging, initiating or consenting to
sex.”29 For some reason, these arguments were never applied to Clarence
Thomas. One female observer put the opposite point of view very bluntly:
“Not one of the women involved in the Clinton soap opera took legal action
at the time they claim they were sexually harassed. Now they appear to be
on the bandwagon to enrich themselves one way or another. They make me
feel ashamed to be a woman.”30

Sometimes art imitates life. Men, too, had their say – at least in the movies.
Since the Hill-Thomas affair, at least two movies were about sexual
harassment: Disclosure and Oleanna. Both have been discussed as if they
were sociological textbooks. In fact, of course, they are not. The former
could be classified as entertainment and the latter as art. Neither claims to
be a definitive statement, covering every possible situation that could be
identified with sexual harassment. Each presents one situation in particular
and asks viewers to find room for it in their perception of the problem. How
well each one succeeds depends not on how closely it adheres to statistics
but on how closely it adheres to human nature – or, to put it another way, on
how much viewers actually care about the characters (a criterion that
applies no less to popular entertainment than to high art).
Disclosure, which is based on a novel by Michael Crichton,31 was
reviled by critics, who were chiefly interested in it as a political statement.
They were annoyed by the fact that it oversimplifies a complex social
problem by making its victimized male protagonist too innocent and its
female villain too guilty. Never mind that the latter allows someone to stick
his penis in her mouth before running off, which could be interpreted – as it
certainly would be in connection with a female victim – as an insidious
suggestion that the protagonist “enjoys” being sexually harassed and thus
deserves it.
In real life, the critics argued, innocence and guilt in connection with
sexual harassment are not so easily identified. Considering the political and
ideological rhetoric surrounding this problem, however, it is hard to avoid
the conclusion that these critics were being both disingenuous and
opportunistic. How often is the charge of oversimplification used to defend
men accused of sexual harassment or to attack the women who accuse
them? Very seldom. In fact, this approach would itself be attacked
relentlessly as “blaming the victim.” What the critics truly disliked about
this movie was the mere fact that it shows a man being the victim of a
woman’s sexual harassment. Anyone who lives in the real world knows that
women are neither more nor less capable than men of using power,
wherever they find it, to manipulate or intimidate. The possibility of women
using it in the office more and more often as they attain positions of power
would surprise no one were it not for the constant stream of rhetoric from
ideologues who claim that only men are selfish and “hierarchical.” Thank
God for Amanda on Melrose Place and Samantha on Sex and the City!
Not all feminists agreed with the attack on Disclosure. Not all agreed, in
other words, that either the author or the director felt threatened by an
unpleasant “fact” of their sex: that men routinely flirt with, and thus harass,
women at work. In one editorial, Eve McBride offered some good reasons
for thinking twice about this problem.32 Whether intentionally or otherwise,
she suggested, women are just as likely to flirt as men. Only 5% of the
cases that end up in court involve men suing women for harassment. On the
other hand, only 5% of the corporate supervisors are women. Men
complained only about harassment, which they defined in connection with
an imbalance of power, not about flirting. Can we assume that all the
women complained about harassment? Maybe they complained merely
about flirting but interpreted flirting with their equals as harassment. Unlike
harassment, flirting really is about sex rather than power.
In view of all this, consider what has been said about Oleanna, which is
both a play and a movie. Critics acknowledge that this work opens up the
discussion of sexual harassment. Here, too, a man is falsely accused by a
woman of sexual harassment. In this case, though, the woman (a confused
student) is emotionally appealing and the man (a self-centred academic) is
emotionally unappealing. Ideally, viewers would feel at least some
sympathy for both. In fact, they seldom do. This egregious situation is due
more to the social and political context, however, than to anything lacking
in author David Mamet’s artistry. Many men are too defensive to admit that
a woman might have good reasons for deciding to take control of her life.
Many women, on the other hand, are too defensive to admit that doing so
dishonestly and maliciously is morally unacceptable. Unfortunately, critics
often discourage the defensiveness of men but encourage that of women.
Even Oleanna, which is nothing if not a sincere attempt to see both sides of
a complex problem, has been dismissed as “male-driven.”33 The
implication here is that complexity itself constitutes the problem. On the
subject of sexual harassment or any other gender problem, in other words,
the only worthwhile works are those that present only one side – the side of
women. Male-driven productions are bad, but female-driven ones are just
fine. So much for the “national dialogue” supposedly initiated by the Hill-
Thomas affair.
Sometimes, on the other hand, life imitates art. Sexual harassment does
work both ways. Even at the risk of being ridiculed or trivialized, more and
more men are willing to sue for damages. One man sued the University of
California for $2.5 million after a lecture in which the female students were
taught how to masturbate in order to avoid the “hardship” of sexual
relations with men. Craig Rogers said that he had felt “raped and trapped”
when a “psychology professor told intimate anecdotes about her sex life and
allegedly made flippant remarks about male genitalia.”34 Another high-
profile case involved eight male employees of the Jenny Craig diet
company. The men claimed to have been denied promotions and subjected
to a hostile work environment involving demeaning remarks about them
because of their sex.35

The effects on men of the entire debate about sexual harassment were
negative, to say the least. On trial for sexism in the Hill-Thomas case,
according to virtually every journalist and commentator, was not merely
one man but all men. But defending men even then was like defending
black people in the South of fifty years earlier. It was just not done by
respectable folks. The fourteen senators hearing this case were all men, but
as everyone knew, their interpretation had to be politically correct. If
Thomas had been found guilty, therefore, few senators would have dared to
challenge the current ideological interpretation of sexual harassment.
Indeed, Thomas himself said that anyone guilty of the allegedly heinous
behaviour attributed to him should be severely punished. If the fallout from
his ordeal had been confined to vague attitudes that surfaced on sitcoms,
there might be no need for this book. As we intend to show, however, it
settled like radioactive dust over the entire legal system.

Moreover, not only men were on trial. Even boys, young boys, were.
How else can we explain some of the absurd accusations that were taken
very seriously by both lawyers and journalists at the same time? In 1996,
for instance, Jonathan Prevette (in North Carolina) and De’Andre Dearinge
(in New York) found themselves at the heart of a national debate over
sexual harassment in elementary schools. Prevette, who was six years old,
had kissed his female classmate. Dearinge, who was seven, had not only
had the audacity to kiss a female classmate but also to pull a button off her
skirt (in homage to a story-book bear whose coveralls were missing a
button). Prevette was suspended from school for one day, Dearing for five.
Their schools relented, in the wake of massive public scorn, but the debate
continued on every talk show. Schools have found it necessary to crack
down on sexual harassment, and sexual harassment has been defined ever
more broadly. Where do we draw the line? And on what basis?36
Sexual harassment is by no means a one-way street even in elementary
schools. Not only are some boys victims, but some girls are victimizers.
Girls indulge in harassment just as often as boys, even though their ways of
harassing boys are seldom understood or acknowledged. Girls shame boys
by calling them sissies, fairies, wussies, and so on. Any boy who performs
inadequately in sports – and most boys do – is well aware of that. So are
effeminate boys, shy boys, frail boys, sensitive boys, intellectual boys, or
even just boys who are near-sighted enough to require glasses. And gender
stereotypes are by no means the only ones to be exploited by children. But
as one commentator observes, schools have “singled out certain kinds of
bad behaviour for harsher treatment than others. If every 7-year-old who
struck another during school hours was suspended, classrooms would be
half empty. Yet even though hitting is surely more serious than a kiss on the
cheek, sexual-harassment policies tell children that boys who kiss girls are
committing a graver offense than girls who strike one another.”37 According
to an official notice distributed to high schools in Ontario, sexual
harassment includes calling another student some demeaning name such as
“chick” or “babe.” It advises the “victims” to call either an emergency
response number or a rape-crisis centre!

During the Thomas hearing, women across the country were interviewed.
Over and over again, they said incredulously: “After twenty-five years of
feminism, men still don’t get it.” Clearly, there is something these women,
too, still “don’t get”: the obvious fact that hostility between men and
women, or any other groups, can be resolved only through negotiation, not
by presenting one side with an ultimatum. But if only the position of
women is granted legitimacy, how can men participate in negotiation? After
twenty-five years of feminism and increasingly ideological rhetoric, men
and women are further apart than ever.
It is true that women have won many legal and political battles. And it is
true that they are better off in many ways than ever before. Even so, the
conflict with men goes on. And that, in itself, is one of the chief problems
still facing women. It would be naive to imagine that this kind of conflict
can ever be completely eliminated, but have we done all we can do? And if
not, what has gone wrong? Why was the golden opportunity of the Hill-
Thomas affair, not taken to explore the possibility of a new approach? Even
if women win every battle and punish every offending man, after all, their
victories will not be worth much if they generate sullen resentment from
men. The goal of social harmony will continue to elude us unless, by some
miracle, the opportunity is taken for a true dialogue between men and
women. Even during the hearing, some commentators called for dialogue
on sexual harassment. Judging from what they said, though, it became clear
that what they really wanted was a monologue by women addressed to men,
not dialogue between two groups with two legitimate points of view. No
one, for example, suggested that women, along with men, might have to
rethink their definition of sexual harassment (let alone their assumptions
about freedom of speech, pornography, and sexuality itself).
So far, there is no obvious reason for optimism. Sexual harassment was
less noticeable in earlier generations, partly because there were fewer
women in the workplace. What changed, beginning in the 1960s, was not
merely the fact that more women were working outside the home but also
the fact that many of those women wanted – and still want – two things in
particular: exciting careers and exciting sex. This mentality has been most
consistently and evocatively represented by the magazine founded by Helen
Gurley Brown, Cosmopolitan, but it has been expressed also in other
magazines and on every talk show. Even the most hidebound men must be
aware by now that many women do see the workplace as a venue for
seduction or flirtation. Those who want men to agree that the work-place is
not an appropriate context for sexually charged talk (let alone flirtation or
seduction) will have to convince women to do more than lobby for new
regulations or new laws. They will have to convince women to stop giving
men double messages – that is, to reject, publicly and consistently, the
“Cosmo girl” mentality. That mentality has recently been widely
disseminated by Sex and the City, a television show about the sexual and
emotional lives of four working women in New York.38 Because this show
is massively popular among women – even as we write these words, no
doubt, feminists doing graduate work in “gender studies” and “cultural
studies” are preparing dissertations on it as a “transgressive” or
“subversive” show that has provided an effective “site” for the
“empowerment” of women – and because they see nothing wrong with
women being on the make in any setting, it is clear that advocates of stricter
rules of decorum in the workplace have a tough job waiting for them.
The Hill-Thomas affair made apparent what had long been hidden: not
so much the lamentable fact of intimidation or blackmail in the workplace
but the fact of sexual polarization almost everywhere. Merely by making an
unsubstantiated accusation, one woman had the power not only to delay the
confirmation of a judge to the Supreme Court and not only to precipitate a
nationwide campaign for her point of view but also to stop the entire nation
in its emotional tracks. And yet supporters of Hill shouted the message that
women have no “voice” in America. A healthy society might have been
able to avoid polarization. Although many were ready and able to challenge
old assumptions about women and their needs, no one was ready to
challenge current assumptions about men and their needs.
At the very least, the Hill-Thomas affair has focused attention on how
complex sexual harassment cases can be. It is no easy matter to sort out the
facts when evidence consists of “he said, she said” and when the hearing
process is procedurally flawed. But the Hill-Thomas affair should focus
attention also on the ways in which some feminists exploit high-profile
media events for ideological ends. In this case, that means allowing women
alone to define harassment and doing so in a way that classifies
heterosexuality in general and male sexuality in particular as inherently
dangerous for women or even evil. From our perspective, only one scenario
is unambiguously in the category of sexual harassment – arrangements
made on the basis of quid pro quo – and should remain illegal.
Ultimately, it was not merely what Thomas was alleged to have said that
outraged many feminists but what he thought or felt. Many people now
believe that straight men harass women simply by expressing admiration
for female beauty (a controversy that we discuss in chapter 7). For a straight
man to do so, they say, is not merely inappropriate in some contexts –
inconvenient, clumsy, or even vulgar – but also oppressive and thus evil.
We disagree. And if there is nothing inherently wrong with thinking about
heterosexual attraction, how could there be anything inherently wrong with
talking about it? At issue are only two matters: the extent to which sexual
behaviour can be controlled and the extent to which it should be controlled.
So far we have heard a great deal about what can happen with too little
control and very little about what could happen with too much control.
Contrary to what commentators have said repeatedly, the ultimate result of
the Hill-Thomas affair might not be more men who are reluctant to hire
women for fear of being sued on the slightest pretext – employers can be
sued for sexual discrimination if they refuse to hire qualified female
applicants – but more men who are reluctant even to fraternize with women
(let alone “commit” to women). At some point down the road, more than a
few men might decide that pursuing relationships with women is no longer
worth the risk of being sued for speaking incorrectly.39 As one observer
noted, “The use of the terms ‘unwanted’ or ‘unwelcome’ sexual attention
creates a catch-22 for males, who rarely know whether a pitch will be
‘welcomed’ until it has been made.”40 Even so, only those who are
psychologically naive or ideologically pure could ever imagine that men
and women can work together without being attracted to each other from
time to time. Therefore, we will have to find a way of negotiating the
acceptable limits of sexual behaviour.

Men will abandon forms of behaviour that fail to attract women, but they
will not become trained seals. Both men and women will have to rethink
their positions, because no lasting and genuine reconciliation has ever been
dictated by an ultimatum from one side. We do need to recognize that the
workplace is not a proper context either for vulgarity or for flirting that
involves physical contact. But we need to recognize also that the new
etiquette must be based on something other than prissiness at best or
ideology at worst. And we need to establish mechanisms, such as mediators
or ombudsmen, to resolve most conflicts before employees resort either to
sexual harassment policies or to legal measures. Apart from avant-garde
lesbians, feminists generally refrain from arguing explicitly that
heterosexuality (or male sexuality) is inherently evil. Nonetheless, they
attack things associated with it. This will never do.
4
Martyrs v. Murderers: The Montreal Massacre
[It is] not an individual act. It is not just one man hating women. It is the
social and political reality we live in.1

This incident is very unusual. If people are going to use this as a political
issue, they are missing the point … I don’t feel this is a continuum of
persecution.”2

Feminists have separated violence against women from other forms of


violence. For ideologues, in fact, it has become both the ultimate and the
original sin. We discuss the specifically legal aspects of violence against
women in chapter 9, but for the time being, we focus on one particular
event of this kind and its fallout in public opinion.
Americans are familiar by now with the phenomenon of high school
shootings, and some observers have wondered why the shooters are always
maladjusted boys.3 The victims, however, are both boys and girls. But in a
case of mass murder at a university in Canada, not only was the victimizer
male but all his victims were female. Consequently, the event became a
touchstone not only of public debate but also of ideological rhetoric. We
refer to the murder of fourteen women by Marc Lépine at the University of
Montreal’s École Polytechnique. This event sent shock waves through
every segment of Canadian society and was discussed even on American
talk shows.
In this chapter, we discuss the massacre itself and its immediate
aftermath, the public response to it, the institutionalization of its ideological
interpretation in quasi-religious forms, its institutionalization in political
form, and the extent to which the feminists involved in promoting that
interpretation have contributed to sexual polarization.
Journalists told this story over and over again for weeks. It was described as
follows in a local newspaper:
At first they viewed it as a prank, some kind of collegiate farce in keeping
with the festive spirit that marked the second-last day of classes at the
University of Montreal’s École Polytechnique. The man was young, about
the same age as most of the roughly 60 engineering students gathered in
Room 303 on the second floor of the yellow-brick building sprawled across
the north slope of the mountain in the heart of the city. He entered the
classroom slowly a few minutes past 5 on a bitterly cold afternoon. There
was a shy smile on his face as he interrupted a dissertation on the
mechanics of heat transfer. In clear, unaccented French, he asked the
women to move to one side of the room and ordered the men to leave. The
request was greeted with titters of laughter. “Nobody moved,” recalled Prof.
Yvan Bouchard. “We thought it was a joke.” An instant later, Bouchard and
his students discovered that what they were confronting was no joke.
Shots: The young man who would later be identified as a 25-year-old
semirecluse named Marc Lépine, lifted a light, semiautomatic rifle and fired
two quick shots into the ceiling. “You’re all a bunch of feminists, and I hate
feminists,” Lépine shouted at the suddenly terrified occupants of Room
303. He told the men to leave – they did so without protest and, as one of
the young women attempted to reason with him, the gun-toting man opened
fire in earnest. Six of the women were shot dead. Over the course of the
next twenty minutes, the young man methodically stalked the cafeteria, the
classrooms and the corridors of the school, leaving a trail of death and
injury in his wake. In four separate locations scattered around three floors
of the six-storey structure, he gunned down a total of 27 people, leaving 14
of them dead. Finally, he turned his weapon against himself, blowing off the
top of his skull. Most of the injured and all of the dead except for the
gunman himself were women. This week, the city and the nation will
mourn again … as a funeral service is held for 11 of the victims at
Montreal’s Notre Dame Roman Catholic church.
It was the worst single-day massacre in Canadian history. And the very
senselessness of the act prompted an outpouring of grief, indignation and
outright rage. The City of Montreal and the Province of Quebec declared
three days of mourning. Vigils were mounted in cities and towns from coast
to coast. Churches held memorial services. Prime Minister Brian Mulroney
and his wife, Mila, travelled to the school to offer their condolences on
behalf of the rest of Canada. “It is indeed a national tragedy,” he said.
Earlier, with the flag atop Parliament fluttering at half-staff, the Prime
Minister had asked a hushed House of Commons: “Why such violence in a
society that considers itself civilized and compassionate?”4

We have no way of knowing precisely what was in Lépine’s mind when he


resorted to mass murder, let alone what was in his mind during the years
leading up to that event. His friends and relatives, moreover, have for
obvious reasons been reluctant to talk about him. Anyone who discusses
Lépine at all, therefore, must rely to some extent on hypothesis. And every
hypothesis must rely to some extent on invading the privacy of his family.
On the other hand, we have several reasons for proceeding to walk where
devils fear to tread. For one thing, journalists and psychiatrists began almost
immediately to speculate on who or what could have produced this person.
We are interested here in public perceptions, moreover, rather than
biographical data. And the public perceptions generated a fierce and
politically motivated debate over whether Lépine was an ordinary man or a
highly aberrant one. It would be irresponsible to avoid speculating,
therefore, even if we must resort to words such as “could have” or “might
have.” We are willing to suggest that Lépine was severely disturbed by
perceptions of himself in relation not only to women but also, and perhaps
more significantly, to men.
Strangely enough, Lépine’s relationships with women were not
particularly problematic. Although he is not known to have had sexual
relations with any women, he did enjoy casual friendships with several. He
liked Gina Cousineau, Jean Bélanger’s girlfriend. When he and Bélanger
got together, she often came along. “We were always together,” she
recalled, “the three of us.”5 At a high school reunion, Lépine expected to
meet Bélanger. The latter never showed up, but Cousineau did. Lépine
spent the evening with her and her new fiancé. Lépine’s friendship with
Dominique Leclair, on the other hand, could have been based on the fact
that she felt sorry for him. Unlike many of the others who worked at St Jude
de Laval Hospital, she took a protective interest in him. His third female
friend was Sylvie Drouin. Hoping to become an engineer, Lépine began a
prerequisite evening course. Drouin was his lab partner, and he became
particularly fond of her. But she describes the relationship as difficult at
first. He was very severe with her, constantly giving orders, calling her
“Fraülein.” After two weeks she told him to back off or get another partner.
After that, they got along well. He helped her with her work; he walked her
home. Occasionally, she visited him.
Lépine’s relationships with the women in his own family were more
problematic. He was probably not very close to his sister Nadia, who used
to taunt him by calling him Gamil, his legal but unwanted name. His
mother, Monique, probably presented him with a deeper problem. After her
divorce, she resumed her career as a nurse, which meant that she had to
place her children in the care of relatives, and saw them only on weekends,
when she expected them to do housework. Even as a child, Lépine was
asked to take care of the house. “He never really had a summer job or
anything like that,” according to Bélanger. “Instead, his mother paid him to
stay at home and do the chores.”6 He might have blamed her for moving the
family from Pier-refonds to Cartierville, thereby ending his friendship with
Bélanger. In his suicide note, Lépine described this move as the beginning
of the end.
Even though Lépine showed hostility toward women only at the very
end, he might well have always envied them. His mother was the
breadwinner; he was the househusband. His mother was the director of
nursing at St Jude’s; he washed the floors there. Sylvie was accepted by the
University of Quebec in Trois Rivières; he was rejected. There is some
evidence to suggest that Lépine found this situation shameful and
compensated through fantasy. For example, he invented a story for
Cousineau about being fired from St Jude’s and a woman taking his place
there. Moreover, he invented a story for Drouin about being accepted for
engineering at the University of Montreal.
Lépine’s anxiety over his own inferiority to women, over the
replacement of men by women, might well have resulted in his hostility
toward women who took on nontraditional roles. Reacting to the story of a
policewoman who had saved a man trapped inside a burning house, he
observed that women should not be on the police force; he thought that they
were not “big enough or strong enough.” This troubled him so much that he
made the effort to find out the names of all six women on the Montreal
force. The last straw for him might have been the fact that Drouin, whom he
had tutored, would be able to study engineering but that he would be unable
to do so. If Lépine had been romantically interested in her, moreover, he
might have interpreted their last meeting as a rejection. After the massacre,
she observed that “I had come away … with a very strange feeling like I
would never see him again, that I didn’t want to see him again, and I didn’t.
I told him I might call in the summer but I never did.”7
Bear in mind that Lépine blamed feminists in particular, not women in
general, for ruining his life. He might have harboured some resentment
toward the women in his own life, either because he thought that they had
rejected him or because they were successful and took jobs away from men.
Before the massacre, nevertheless, there is no evidence of deep hostility
toward them. There is evidence, on the other hand, of severe hostility
toward some of the men in his life.
Bélanger was the only friend that he retained from childhood. As
children, they had bought old gas masks and an old helmet at an army
surplus store. According to Bélanger, “It wasn’t that he had a fascination
with war … it was just things we found interesting, like, hey, they actually
wore this stuff.”8 He and Bélanger used to shoot pigeons with their pellet
guns. “It wasn’t for the killing, though,” observed Bélanger. “He wasn’t like
that, ‘yeah, I want to kill.’ It was just fun. We were kids.”9 As they got
older, the two designed and built electronic gadgets and sound-effects
systems from abandoned radios. They were close friends. Nevertheless,
Bélanger’s friendship ended when the Lépine family moved to another part
of town. Lépine made no other lasting friendships with men. During the last
summer of his life, Eric Cossette was his roommate. When Cossette moved
out, Lépine’s cousin Michel Thiery took his place. There is no indication
that either relationship was a particularly close one. In all these cases,
circumstances intervened and prevented the continuation of relationships.
Lépine might have interpreted these circumstances as rejection.
Several things stand out about Lépine’s father, Liass Gharbi. An
immigrant from Algeria, he eventually became a successful businessman.
According to Stanley Selinger, he “was a very bright guy. He spoke a
number of languages and was a fantastic salesman. A slick dresser. He
could sell the Brooklyn Bridge to anyone.”10 At first, the family lived well.
They had big cars, glitzy parties, and a thirty-room mansion rented at a
country resort. But Gharbi lost everything when his company collapsed.
Even before that, he had showed signs of severe psychological problems.
Gharbi had been abused as a child. As often happens in these cases, he
abused his own child Marc by beating him. Moreover, Gharbi had a habit of
rubbing his crotch against women at parties and even against complete
strangers. These sexual proclivities made relationships with women
problematic, especially with his wife. He ignored her in public and cut her
off in conversation. Sometimes, he beat her. Gharbi confessed to having had
children outside of marriage. When Lépine was seven and his sister five,
their parents divorced. Gharbi cut off all contact with the family. Lépine
hated his abusive father to the point of refusing to take his name.
Monique realized that her son needed a surrogate father. When he was
fourteen, therefore, she enlisted the help of Ralph, a Big Brother. For about
three years, Lépine, Bélanger, and Ralph had good times together, but
Ralph disappeared late in the fall of 1981, when the boys were seventeen.
When Bélanger asked Lépine what had happened to Ralph, Lépine
shrugged and said that he had gone back to Europe. But when Bélanger
persisted, Lépine told him that Ralph was gay, had assaulted a child, and
was in jail. Although no official charge against Ralph has been traced, it
could be that Lépine himself had been sexually approached or seduced. If
there was any truth to his allegation against Ralph, though, yet another man
had betrayed his trust.
To understand the role of men in Lépine’s life, we must also consider his
interest in that classic collectivity of men: the army. In the years
immediately following the separation of his parents, Lépine had enjoyed a
good relationship with his uncle, a former paratrooper who had trained with
an elite group of special forces in the United States. He taught Lépine how
to use a gun. Shortly after the incident with Ralph, Lépine returned to his
old interest in military life. Hoping to sign up with the armed forces, he
went to the local recruiting office. No one knows exactly what happened.
According to official military records, Lépine had been interviewed,
assessed, and found to be unsuitable. He himself acknowledged in his
suicide note that he had been rejected for antisocial behaviour. At least
someone, therefore, had noticed that Lépine was something other than a
healthy, well-adjusted, ordinary young man. Shortly before the massacre,
his room was filled not with sadistic pornography in which women are
portrayed as victims but with videos, books, and pictures about war in
which men are the victims.
This seems to be an anomaly. He killed women, after all, not men. It
could be explained, at least partly, as projection of the extreme negativity he
felt for men (including himself) onto women – more specifically, onto
women who seemed to be prospering at his expense and especially onto
those who were accepted into engineering. “Why should women be
engineers,” asked Lépine of one victim, “and not men?”11 He must have
realized that feminism had successfully promoted the presence of women in
nontraditional jobs such as engineering or police work. This realization
could explain why he singled out for attack female students who were
studying engineering.
Clearly, Lépine had difficulty assimilating the notion of manhood. It is
reasonable to suggest, therefore, that he had a very inadequate sense of
masculine identity and, moreover, an inadequate sense of personal identity.
Even though some people have described him as ordinary, it is clear on
closer examination that he was maladjusted even in childhood. Except when
in the company of his friend, Bélanger, he was extremely withdrawn. He
always wore a baseball cap pulled down over his forehead as if to make his
face invisible. Years later, he was still wearing a baseball cap to work and to
school. Judging from the comments by fellow workers about his
inappropriate behaviour, we conclude that Lépine’s self-esteem was not
very high. According to Dominique Leclair, “I was kind to him because he
was so hyperactive and nervous. Everyone else tried to avoid him because
he was a bit strange because of his shyness … He was always rushing
things. He would never be calm.” He raced the food carts the same way he
did everything else. Always in a hurry. Soup got spilled. Dishes got broken.
Finally, he was put on the food serving duty in the cafeteria. But the steamy
kitchen atmosphere made his acne worse. Dominique recalls: “The
employees would say they didn’t want him to serve them their lunch
because of his acne … Lépine was becoming loud, always making cracks
and telling jokes. No one laughed.”12
Even so, Lépine did well in high school. At junior college, he took
courses in the pure sciences. He did not do well in the first term, failing
several courses, but he did very well in the second. During the final term,
nonetheless, he suddenly quit and applied to the University of Montreal for
engineering. After being rejected, he went to work as a menial in St Jude’s
Hospital. This same pattern – quitting after succeeding – was repeated
seven years later. Having almost completed his studies in computer
programming, he abruptly quit. Was his self-esteem so low that he was
willing to quit within sight of success in order to confirm his own sense of
himself as a failure? Why would anyone want to confirm something so
negative? Because it provides at least one consolation, albeit a neurotic one:
life is painful but nonetheless consistent and comprehensible.
Not one but two events took place at the University of Montreal on 6
December 1989: a massacre and a suicide. And the two are clearly
connected. The former was consciously associated with Lépine’s experience
of women. Both the former and the latter might have been subconsciously
associated with his experience of men. Lépine was a boy who had long
suspected that he could not become a man. Even so, he was attracted to
machismo. And it is precisely those men who feel unsure of their manhood,
those who have “something to prove,” who often resort to machismo. To
Lépine, the only way to prove himself might have been to kill the enemy. In
doing so, however, he defied society. Killing himself was his last act of self-
loathing, his last act of defiance, or both.
At least some people will be reminded here of what happened, albeit on
the collective level, in Germany just before the Nazis rose to power.
Because of their catastrophic defeat in the Great War, many Germans had
come to see themselves not only as losers but also as victims. Needing a
scapegoat to maintain their identity, especially since German soldiers had
not been defeated in the field, they came to see the Jews (traditionally
defined by their otherness) as those who had “stabbed Germany in the
back.” The solution, they believed, was to reverse this situation.
Consequently, they came to believe that the Jews were, in fact, an inferior
race and that they themselves were the master race. In that case,
exterminating those who were trying to subvert the natural order seemed to
make sense. Although some of the Nazis were opportunists, others were
true believers. They truly believed that the Jews were a sinister and
threatening force that had to be destroyed in the interest of German
survival. Using this as a model, we can better understand Lépine’s
pathological behaviour. He could well have seen himself as both a loser and
a victim. If so, he would have tried to reverse the situation by attacking
those he perceived as winners and victimizers: namely, feminists.

At least one feature of the public response to this event is beyond debate:
the tragedies of fifteen human beings were deliberately exploited by some
feminists, both male and female, for political purposes. Those who led the
way exploited not only the grief of bereaved families but also the confusion
of society as a whole.
Lépine’s attitude toward women was of little or no importance,
according to some people, even though all his victims were women. The
mass murder, they argued, could be explained best in terms of one
individual’s psychosis – his inner demons, in other words, as distinct from
his thoughts about social organization or political conflict or any other
aspect of the outside world. “This incident is very unusual,” said Helen
Morrison, a psychiatrist whose specialties for almost two decades had been
serial and mass murders. “If people are going to use this as a political issue,
they are missing the point … I don’t feel this is a continuum of
persecution.”13
Some feminists, on the other hand, focused exclusively on the fact that
all Lépine’s victims were women. This, they believed, was of crucial
importance. His behaviour could be explained only in terms of the
widespread misogyny that Lépine supposedly shared with many or even all
other men. “It is not accidental in this misogynous society,” said Maria
Eriksen, a professor of women’s studies at the University of Calgary, “that
men kill women.”14 Similarly, Erin Graham of Vancouver Rape Relief said,
it “is not an individual act. It is not just one man hating women. It is the
social and political reality we live in.”15 Jennifer Bankier, writing in a
bulletin of the Canadian Association of University Teachers, put it this way:
“Commentators who attempt to reduce Lépine’s rampage to the act of an
insane and isolated individual don’t understand the nature of madness.
Insanity begins with a human being who holds values and assumptions
about the world. Madness often operates by distorting this person’s sense of
proportion so that they act on their preexisting views in extreme ways that a
sane person would not.”16
Actually, though, madness operates far more often by distorting
perceptions, not merely the sense of proportion. The result might have little
or nothing to do with any pre-existing views, moreover, unless perception is
distorted suddenly at some point after infancy. In that case, though, it would
do much more than merely give permission, as it were, to act on long-
repressed urges. Even sane people, after all, have malevolent fantasies from
time to time. What prevents them from acting on these fantasies is not
merely external constraints but the complexity and ambivalence of their
inner worlds. People hate and love at the same time. It is by no means self-
evident, in short, that Lépine did only what sane men – ordinary men –
would have done had they lost their sense of proportion.17 Indeed, many
sane people do lose their sense of proportion, adopting all sorts of crazy
ideas, but still never resort to murder and suicide. No matter how hard it
often is to distinguish between the sane and the insane, between the neurotic
and the psychotic, there is a qualitative and crucial difference. Deliberately
blurring this distinction for political purposes is not only contemptible but
dangerous.
Bankier goes on, though, to blur other distinctions as well. “Although
Lépine’s murderous actions attract universal condemnation, his underlying
objection to women (and, by analogy, members of other equity-seeking
groups) who move out of their traditional spheres to occupy or transform
‘white men’s jobs’ is shared and acted upon by many sane individuals
through more moderate but nevertheless destructive behaviour. Such
conduct is discriminatory but not irrational.”18 Bankier’s main point is that
any discriminatory act is tantamount, morally, to murder. Once again,
though, she ignores a crucial distinction. Murder is not like any other act.
Murder involves death, not merely malice. Murder is ultimate, therefore,
not merely extreme. We have all committed murder “in our hearts” at one
time or another. Does that mean we all belong on death row or in some
institution for the criminally insane? Bankier’s argument clearly makes
sense on ideological grounds and therefore works very effectively to
mobilize resentment, but it makes no sense on moral or psychological
grounds.
Please note, however, that women were not the only ones to jump on this
ideological bandwagon. According to one Larry Finkelman, a psychologist
at the University of New Brunswick, Lépine was just an ordinary man who
lost control. “We need to recognize that there is a spectrum of violent
behaviour towards women and that most of us occupy, or have occupied, a
place on that spectrum. We need to look at ourselves honestly and
acknowledge the discomfort that part of ourselves may be more like Marc
Lépine than we care to admit.”19 According to Edward Renner (along with
two female co-authors), “it is common, ordinary men who are dangerous to
women and children … Being an ordinary man cannot continue to be the
basis for a discount, because it is ordinary men who are a clear and present
danger to women and children. That danger exists in the context of
everyday social relationships, but rarely results in visible external physical
harm.”20 Men become “male feminists” for various reasons. Some, no
doubt, are truly altruistic. Others find it professionally useful to ally
themselves with the academic avant-garde. Still others find it
psychologically useful to separate themselves from the negativity
associated with maleness.
In politically correct circles, gay men are almost always considered
exceptions, honorary women, even though gay people are by no means
immune to violence.21 Facts notwithstanding, they are excused as an
“equity-seeking group.”22 As one observer put it, “[t]he whole absurdity of
making Lépine representative of anyone other than himself is revealed if we
review the groups which could be inculpated by these tactics. Lépine could
be held to represent 1. males; 2. white males; 3. North American males; 4.
Canadian males; 5. québécois males; 6. Montreal males; 7. École
Polytechnique males. The only grounds for choosing “white males” over
the other possibilities is that this happens to be the group one wishes to
inculpate.”23
Those who identified all or most men with Marc Lépine pointed to the
statistics of violence against women. They told people that one woman in
four would be sexually assaulted at some time in her life, half of them
before the age of seventeen, and that one million Canadian women would
be abused by their partners every year.24 However imprecise these figures
might be and however tendentious the research methods behind them might
have been (topics that we discuss in appendix 3), they should not be
ignored. In a study of homicides of women in eighteen industrialized
nations between 1950 and 1980, moreover, Rosemary Gartner, a professor
of sociology at the University of Toronto, found that women who move into
nontraditional roles run a higher risk of being killed.25 Gartner explained
this finding in terms of a violent backlash. The fact that Lépine killed
women in engineering would support her position. Just after the massacre,
indeed, there were several phone calls from men who either approved of
what Lépine had done or threatened similar acts. At Mount St Vincent
University in Halifax, for instance, security was increased for a vigil after
anonymous callers threatened violence against its largely female student
body. At its office in Ottawa, the National Action Committee on the Status
of Women received a call from a man who said, “Marc is not alone.” When
Montreal psychologists established a hotline to counsel people shaken by
the tragedy, they were shocked to receive calls from a handful of men with
comments such as this: “I am very happy Lépine did it. You psychologists
are just like those women, and I am coming to your office to kill you all.”26
Clearly, there is a major problem. At issue here, once again, is only how to
interpret the problem and thus solve it.
We believe that neither extreme position – that this tragedy was the
result of one crazed individual or that it was the result of pervasive
misogyny – is adequate. To understand Lépine, we must consider him as
both an individual and a member of society. He fitted the classic definition
of a psychotic: someone who is utterly out of touch with reality. No wonder
his letter included references to his return, after death, for revenge. He used
bizarre fantasies to cope with paranoid delusions. What actually went on in
Lépine’s mind can never be known. And as one individual, in any case, he
is of no historical or cultural importance. Of great importance, though, is
the particular form that his psychosis took.
In this sense, we agree with those who focus attention on the fact that his
targets were women. In another sense, however, we disagree with them.
Granted that the victims were all women and that this says something
important about our society. But precisely what does it say? In the opinion
of some, this case of mass murder says that we live in a society
characterized by the hostility of men toward women. In our opinion, the
mass murder and public response to it say that we live in a society
characterized by profound polarization between men and women (but also
between other groups). It could be argued that the targets of hostility
selected by individuals are likely to be those identified by the collectivity in
any particular time and place. Scapegoats thus reflect major social or
cultural “fault lines,” which are given various names. In Quebec, there
were, and are, two major ones: the gulf between speakers of French and
English and the gulf between men and women (the old gulf between
Catholics and Protestants having become insignificant due to
secularization). It is not surprising that a severely disturbed person,
whatever the biographical origin of his pathology, would express his fear
and anger in terms of one targeted group or the other.
Some feminists used the event as an excuse to propagate their own
position: that men, as a class, are sinister beings involved in a historic
conspiracy against women. Lépine, they argued, merely did what most men
would like to do, what most men believe that they have some moral right to
do. The only difference between him and most other men, they claimed,
was that the latter are too inhibited by fear of the consequences. According
to this interpretation, Lépine was not deranged in any way but just an
ordinary man, a man like all other men. Those who proclaim that all men
are mass murderers at heart, of course, could be accused of sexism just as
easily as those who claim that all women are whores or witches at heart.
The notion that all men are murderers under the skin is not a new idea,
but it raises an interesting question. If the underlying humanity of men is
perverted by evil, if our society teaches men to hate women, how can we
explain the fact that most men do not, in fact, resort to murdering women?
Can it be seriously maintained that these men are restrained merely by fear
of being thrown in jail? If so, the only sensible solution would be to get rid
of men altogether by locking them up in concentration camps or killing
them in death camps. If not, then what does prevent these men from acting
on their sinister impulses?
It would be very hard indeed to prove that most men hate women and
take delight in fantasies of women writhing under torture. Some women
explain this anomaly in terms of gynocentrism. If there are good men, from
that point of view, they are good only due to influence by women or
feminism. But it would make much more sense simply to acknowledge that
men, like women themselves, are not all alike. Moreover, it would make
sense to acknowledge that our culture itself is not uniformly malevolent
toward women (or, for that matter, benevolent toward men).
According to a woman interviewed on Canada AM, this mass murder
was of interest to feminists for proving that men see women as appropriate
victims or targets. A cartoon made the same point in graphic terms. In one
box, identified by the biological symbol for maleness, is a collection of
violent and pornographic videos along with a machine gun. The latter is
pointed at another box, identified by the biological symbol for femaleness,
which contains nothing but a dart board.27 Ignored by both the interview
and the cartoon is the fact that men have been trained for centuries to
believe precisely the opposite: that other men, but not women, are the
appropriate targets of aggression. Even schoolboys are usually well aware
that hitting other boys in the playground might earn them prestige, but not
hitting girls. Whenever atrocities occur, moreover, journalists routinely
describe them as events in which women and children (as distinct from
civilians) or men, women, and children (as distinct from people) are killed.
What makes these events tragic, apparently, is that women or women and
children are killed rather than merely men.
Women have been, at least until very recently, protected by a powerful
taboo. Like all other taboos, this one was sometimes broken. Until now,
though, it remained a taboo. But when taboos break down, they do not
always fade away gently and gradually. Sometimes, the process releases a
powerful urge to do precisely what had once been forbidden. Even so, the
fact that women are the objects of violence does not necessarily indicate
that men have singled them out as desirable targets. It might simply mean
that women have lost their special protected status. That makes them more
like men, not more unlike men. No longer protected by a taboo, they are
subject to the same violence to which men have always been subject. Says
Helen Morrison, “I see violence as an equal-opportunity behavior.”28
The idea that women have come of age – that women no longer want or
need to be protected, like children, or placed on the proverbial pedestal –
has been actively promoted by feminists. This might not be the only reason
for their loss of protected status, but it is surely one of them. Popular
culture, too, has promoted the idea of “empowered” heroines. They fight
like men and kill like men. Think only of movies such as Charlie’s Angels
and television shows such as Dark Angel and Alias. The message to men
has registered: women want to be treated just like men. The problem, of
course, is the way that men are taught to treat other men.
The kind of violence that assumes most political importance is invariably
violence against women. Indeed, it is usually listed as a distinctive or even
unique social problem. But what about violence against men, who are still,
after all, the majority of those killed as a result of violent crime?
Apparently, murder is only heinous when women are singled out as the
victims. “The initial accounts were horrifying … But the national revulsion
increased dramatically when it became clear that the 25-year-old killer,
Marc Lépine, had deliberately singled out women as his victims and spared
the men.”29 No one recalled the TWA flight that had been hijacked only a
few years earlier in Lebanon. In that case, it was the men who were singled
out as victims; the women were allowed to leave with the children (who
were not necessarily their own children). Even at the time, no one asked
about this sexual differentiation.
One answer to this question, which no one ever asks, is that masculine
identity, both historically and cross-culturally, has been predicated partly on
men’s function as protectors of women and children. Men have been
socialized, in fact, to sacrifice their lives if necessary to maintain this ideal.
This is why many observers wanted to know why none of the male students
in Lépine’s class risked their lives to save the female students (although
some observers did realize that, despite the cultural rhetoric, these young
men were utterly unprepared for heroism).30 The most obvious, direct, and
dramatic example of the twentieth century was recalled in the movie
Titanic, which is historically accurate enough to show the authorities
placing women and children into the lifeboats but barring men.
Unfortunately, it blunts the impact of this custom, somewhat jarring to the
self-consciously egalitarian mentality of later generations, by showing the
female character Rose rushing below deck – and thus risking her life – to
save Jack. He drowns in the end, but the politically correct point has been
made that women can be just as heroic as men – even though the event
itself went down in history as a moment of specifically masculine heroism
par excellence.31
Why would the murder of women be more significant than the murder of
men? One feminist answer would probably be that the former is the
paradigm of all violence. But is it? A gynocentric ideology, as we say,
encourages women to believe that all of history revolves around
themselves. Consequently, they often find it difficult to accept the
possibility that men might be motivated by needs, desires, or problems that
have little or nothing to do with women. Lépine said that he was
specifically motivated by hostility toward feminists, however, so feminists
were correct in arguing that this particular event should not be dismissed as
just another act of random violence. But was their own analysis of it any
less superficial or biased than the others?
Underlying the exclusive preoccupation with female victims might be
the belief that male victims deserve no attention, because men are the
victimizers, the chief culprits as well as the chief victims of murder. This
attitude is highly problematic for two reasons. First, it is based on the old
notion of collective guilt. This or that male victim might be innocent as an
individual, some would argue, but this makes no difference in view of the
“fact” that men are guilty as a class. Feminists have argued persuasively
that there is something inherently wrong with the whole idea of blaming
victims (at least when the victims are women). But these arguments are
based on logic. In our society at this time, feeling is more important. Those
who ignore male victims want revenge, in short, not justice.
Over and over again, Marc Lépine’s example has been used to prove that
boys are socialized in destructive ways. And we agree. But Lépine’s
example raises a very interesting question. Precisely why are boys
socialized in destructive ways? Even though parents might not be aware of
any link, the attitudes and even games that they themselves have inherited
and passed on to their sons are related to the skills that their sons might
need someday. These skills might be useful to society on the battlefield and
in the boardroom, to be sure, but not necessarily to individual men in daily
life.32 Just as girls are encouraged to develop the relational skills necessary
for promoting social harmony (the ability to communicate feelings, for
example, and the ability to intuit those of others), many boys have been
encouraged to develop the combative skills considered necessary to protect
society and provide for their families. The hippies, who withdrew into
themselves and thus failed to change the basic structure of society (or vice
versa), were thus doomed to become aberrations. Their notion of
masculinity, a relatively peaceable ideal, was overtaken by earlier ones,
although it should continue to provide us with an expanded sense of the
possibilities inherent in manhood.
An event as dramatic and shocking as the Montreal Massacre might have
provoked real discussion. A few people did write books and articles, many
of them heavily ideological, about this event and its aftermath.33 Others
relied on political ranting and ideological slogans. Many commentators
relied on the obvious, instead, solemnly declaring that the socialization of
boys eventually has destructive effects on women. Few, if any, observed
that it eventually has destructive effects on men as well. According to
Herbert Pascoe, a forensic psychiatrist at Alberta Hospital, many men share
Lépine’s resentment against successful women. “The fact is,” he observed,
“that many men feel inadequate and inferior in their relations to the
opposite sex. And this can show up in some very unpleasant activities.”34
But precisely why do men feel so threatened by women? According to
Gartner, the movement of women into higher-paid occupations once
reserved for men might “be perceived, consciously or unconsciously, as a
threat to the traditional male dominance in society.”35 As far as it goes, this
explanation makes sense. Lépine did say that he felt threatened by women
in nontraditional occupations. But, once again, why?
Gartner’s explanation was ideological. Men have all the power,
according to her, and are unwilling to share it with women. Case closed.
What immediately and obviously threatens many men, however, is not so
much loss of dominance as loss of security. When affirmative action means
that men are excluded on biological grounds from jobs that would otherwise
have been open to them, for example, feeling threatened is a realistic
response to injustice. But for most men, we suspect, the threat is also a loss
of identity — that is, the loss of any remaining sense that they can make a
distinctive, necessary, and valued contribution as men to society. Not all
men are intellectually inclined, and thus not all think about these things in
connection with social and cultural problems. Not all men are graduates of
what could be called the Oprah Winfrey School of Psychology, moreover,
and thus not all are aware of their own emotional vulnerability.
Nevertheless, there really is no obvious solution to the pressing problem of
masculine identity in a society that allows men to choose only between a
negative identity – all men are Marc Lépine – and no identity at all.
To grow up, children must become increasingly independent from their
parents. We all need at least some autonomy. Yet too much autonomy
represents pathology, not maturity. To be a mature human being cannot
mean complete self-sufficiency; we live in communities, not in isolation.
We depend on each other, not only ourselves. We must be prepared not only
to serve the needs of others, therefore, but also to receive the services of
others. To put it another way, we not only need others but also need to be
needed. When men are told that women are autonomous, that women do not
need men, anger (though not hatred) is a perfectly reasonable response. And
the overwhelming message to men from feminists really has been that
women do not need them.36 Because no healthy identity can be formed
unless it is based on the possibility of making a distinctive, necessary, and
valued contribution to society – we will repeat that point several times, no
matter how irritating it becomes, because it lies at the heart of our thesis –
men have good reasons for finding this situation extremely threatening.
They are neither “unmanly,” therefore, nor paranoid. Usually men are either
unwilling or unable to admit that they feel threatened by women (or anyone
else, for that matter). But Lépine did just that.
In Lépine’s world there was still one sphere of activity that had not yet
completed the process of sexual desegregation: combat. Like many other
boys, therefore, he turned to the only role model that had not yet been
claimed by women and that was, therefore, still distinctively masculine. The
fact that he was fascinated by movies about men who are reduced to
dangerous beasts or machines of destruction – these often have titles such
as Predator, Terminator, and Lethal Weapon – should be taken as a dire
warning of what can happen when boys are denied the possibility of
forming identity in healthier ways.

Lépine’s act of mass murder was only the first act of a drama that was to be
enacted on radio and television, in the newspapers, and in the collective
imagination. And it should certainly be remembered in the way that
similarly shocking events are publicly remembered. The only question is
how to do that in a responsible way. In this section, we examine two
particular manifestations of this phenomenon: quasi-religious liturgies and
shrines.
Even two years after the event, it had already been institutionalized
through public ritual: gathering at monuments, ringing church bells on 6
December at precisely the moment when Lépine opened fire, presenting
anniversary editorials in newspapers and on television, and attending
religious or secular memorial liturgies. These liturgies are very revealing.
We went to one in 1991 at McGill University. It focused on a contrast
between the current nightmare of a world designed by men and the dream
of one designed by women.
The room was filled with women; approximately 10% of those who
attended were men. On the “altar” were fourteen candles, which were lit,
one by one, before each speaker sat down. This corresponded, hardly by
coincidence, to the use of six candles at events commemorating the Nazi
Holocaust. In both cases, the result amounts to a ritual of the community’s
civil religion.37
From beginning to end, music played an important part in creating the
atmosphere of a religious event. The liturgy was preceded by a musical
prelude, followed by a musical postlude, and divided by a musical
interlude. The latter, Beethoven’s String Quartet, op. 18, no. 1, Adagio,
began on a funereal note but ended with a light movement that, in this
context, suggested the triumph of women, of ideological feminism, or both.
Music is a highly emotional element in every liturgy, and it was used on this
occasion for precisely that reason.
Central to this event was a seemingly less traditional feature: ribbons.
Like the poppies handed out at memorial services on 11 November,
Remembrance Day in Canada, these white ribbons identified those with the
approved attitudes or beliefs and united them in solidarity. Both poppies
and ribbons are reminiscent of the ashes distributed in churches on Ash
Wednesday. And both are reminiscent, ultimately, of the bread and wine
distributed at every eucharist. As with all sacraments, the ribbon is held
(albeit implicitly) to be an “outward and visible sign of an inward and
spiritual grace.” Putting on ribbons, not surprisingly, reminded us of
exchanging the peace just after confession and just before receiving
communion.
The liturgy proper began with a musical prelude by Bach (Partita in a
Minor, op. BMV 1013), which was played on the recorder by a man. This
was followed by a “liturgy of the word.” It consisted of verbal
presentations, almost all of them by women. One speaker, a man,
represented McGill’s Internal Students’ Society. His presentation, of the
kind commonly found in evangelical services, took the form of a
testimonial against male violence. He told his story to let others know that
redemption was still possible for all who accept the true faith. Converts to
the cause, those who saw the light, were presumably saved at this point.
Then, during a “liturgy of the table,” the ribbons were distributed and
exchanged. Just before leaving, participants sang a hymn, “Bread and
Roses,” which had been adapted from a 1912 poem by James Oppenheim.
The liturgy concluded with believers being sent out into the world on their
mission to save others from the Original Sin, as it were, of patriarchy.
Men were visibly and literally marginalized on either side of the altar
and pulpit. On one side of the altar stood a man filming the event for
television. One piece of equipment, whispered someone nearby, looked
“phallic.”
One speaker, who represented the Jewish Women’s Circle of McGill’s
Hillel House, presupposed both dualism and essentialism: violent men
versus nonviolent women. From the pulpit she observed “how dangerous” it
is for women to live in our society (even though statistics show that it is
even more dangerous for men). Women and men, she averred, do not share
the same outlook and the same power (presumably because men are all
powerful and brutal, while women are all powerless and loving). “We as
women really are victims,” she went on, “and we as men really are the
perpetrators of violence.” Next, she observed that women are “angry and
that we need to be angry.” Calling attention to the white ribbons worn by
supporters, she asked those present to “pledge our lives to end that
violence.” In conclusion, she noted that people must first mourn (although
two years had passed) and then work for change.
The next speaker, equally dualistic and essentialistic, represented the
McGill Women’s Union. Continuing the polarizing rhetoric, she argued that
men and women have different notions of honour. Male honour has to do
with killing, whereas female honour has to do with fidelity. Moreover, men
are concerned with facts and women with feelings. And men lie, women do
not. “Even about the facts,” she observed, “they have continually lied.”
Women must “take seriously the truthfulness between women and among
women.” For several minutes, she continued to rant ideologically,
discussing the differences between “them” and “us.”
Another speaker, who represented McGill’s Department of Philosophy,
noted that it is consistent with feminism to use events of this kind for
political purposes. In fact, she referred indirectly to an analogy between the
mass murder by Lépine of women and the mass murder of Jews by Hitler.
Remembering these events, memorializing them, is a strategy for survival.
It counteracts the tendency to forget, which would make everyday life more
tolerable. Because (ideological) feminists base their worldview
(exclusively) on the experience of women, she argued, they are surely
correct in appropriating Lépine’s victims for political purposes. She was
saying the obvious, but it had the effect of empowering those who might
still feel queasy about exploiting personal tragedies for political purposes.
At least some of us wondered, however, if all this was consistent with moral
principles. Besides, the same way of thinking could be – and has been –
used by men to acknowledge their own collective experience of
vulnerability and pain during the two world wars. That, however, was
deliberately ignored. The speaker concluded with the (unrelated) thought
that love is stronger than death and hope better than despair. This was
followed by applause.
Yet another speaker, who represented McGill’s Sexual Assault Centre,
made use of “linguistic inflation” (a political strategy that we will discuss in
chapters 8 and 9), as if there was any need to inflate the impact of this
particular event. First, she said that Lépine’s act constituted “violence on
the largest scale” (thus ignoring the violence at Passchendaele, say, or Iwo
Jima). Then, moving in a different direction, she discussed other problems
faced by women: everything from the loneliness of being at home to the
alienation of “family conspiracies” of father and son versus mother. For her,
these problems were suitable parallels with Lépine’s mass murder. Finally,
she noted that women suffer from self-hatred. They cannot protect
themselves, she argued, because they think that they deserve to suffer. But
since events like this one, as she well knew, have precisely the same effect
on men, we must assume that she was hoping for deeper polarization
between the sexes, not deeper understanding between them.
Pilgrimages, too, are part of the civil religion under discussion here.
Every year on 6 December, people gather at Montreal’s memorial park on
Queen Mary Road and Decelles – only a block from the University of
Montreal. Seven stone markers, each engraved with a victim’s name, are
arranged on each side of a path. Benches are provided for visitors. That is
all. This memorial park is very understated, though not ineffective,
especially when compared to the one in Vancouver. That city’s Thornton
Park has been turned into a much more dramatic pilgrimage site. Fifteen
stone monuments, shaped like coffins, form a circle. The fifteenth is not a
coffin for Lépine, of course, but a focus for the others. An inscription on it
begins as follows: “Murdered, December 6, 1989, University of Montreal.”
On the other side is a list of the fourteen names. These are repeated, one by
one, on the other stone coffins. The inscription continues by noting that this
monument is dedicated to “all women who have been murdered by men.
For women of all countries, all classes, all ages, all colours.”
Forming a second circle are several hundred small tiles, each donated to
pay for this park. Some are from government departments. The “Ministry of
the Attorney General”38 has this to say: “That this tragic event served to
raise awareness and educate us all about violence against women.” Some
tiles sound more like promos or commercials than anything else: “Human
Resources Development Canada is pleased to have supported the Women’s
Movement Project through the Canadian Jobs Strategy Operations.” The
Public Service Alliance of Canada adopts a more humble tone: “Local
20088.” Some tiles convey simple messages: “Ministry of Women’s
Equality: stopping violence against women.”39 Others are more
longwinded: “In loving memory of the women killed on Vancouver’s
downtown East Side, we dream a different world, when the war on women
is over.” We find it striking that one tile says, “Creating a lesbian.”
In Ottawa, the flag on Parliament Hill now flies at half mast every 6
December. On that day, citizens are exhorted to remember not only the
fourteen women killed by Lépine but also other women who have been
“murdered by men.” This gesture is supposed to parallel one on 11
November. On that day, citizens are exhorted to remember Canadian
soldiers killed not only in World War I, after which the custom began, but
also in World War II and any other wars.
On 6 December 2001, the flag was lowered not only on Parliament Hill,
however, but also on every federal building across the country. Because that
never happens on 11 November, it was obvious immediately that an
ideological battle had been waged and won behind closed doors by
feminists. Their female victims, apparently, were more important than male
victims. An enormous debate erupted, forcing the minister responsible,
Sheila Copps, into crisis-control mode. She simply denied having had any
connection with this travesty.40
A few weeks earlier, on 11 November, a similar problem had gone
virtually unnoticed. According to one newspaper editorial, “the poppies are
reminders of man’s weakness as well as of men [sic] and women’s strengths
and sacrifices in difficult times.”41 A few decades ago, the word “man’s”
might have referred to the human race. But not now. The word “weakness”
refers explicitly to male human beings as distinct from female ones, to men
as distinct from women. “Strengths and sacrifices,” on the other hand,
refers explicitly to both men and women. Men had caused the war, in other
words, but men and women together (and supposedly in equal numbers)
had done what they could to end it. But this editorial was hardly the first to
indulge in historical revisionism. For years, journalists have referred to the
men and women who fought in wartime for their country by choice, even
though Canadian women have never done so and have never been expected
or even allowed to do so and even though American women have only
recently begun to enter combat zones.42

We turn now from quasi-religious memorials for the victims to overtly


political assaults on the alleged victimizers. From the very beginning,
public response to the slayings was profoundly divisive among both men
and women. In fact, Montreal was engulfed in a hurricane of hatred. Like a
sudden squall of racism or anti-Semitism, the forces set in motion were very
soon beyond the control of anyone. Provoked by sorrow, fear, and anger,
fed by ideological malice and opportunism, and sustained by ignorance and
confusion, it provided a brief glimpse of an abyss swirling in darkness just
beneath that surface of the civility that is necessary to maintain social order
of any kind.
There was never any doubt that this event would have political
repercussions. Overtly political statements were made at the mass funeral
itself and are still made at every annual memorial service. What follows is a
discussion of one: the parliamentary debate over a royal commission on gun
control in the specific context of violence against women, which was
published in 1991 as a government report called The War against Women.43
Implicit in the title itself was the very dubious assumption that violence
against men is not a serious problem, as if men were somehow guilty by
virtue of being male and thus members of an oppressor class unworthy of
the public concern expressed in the form of a government study.44 The title
would have been unthinkable without one underlying belief: that violence
against women, or the threat of it, is the true foundation on which our
society rests. And that belief, in turn, was based on another assumption: that
the behaviour of men can be explained solely in terms of their attitude
toward women. From the gynocentric perspective of those who instigated
this report, in short, all of history revolves around women – that is, around
themselves.45 Consequently, all of history can be seen as a conspiracy of
men against women, a conspiracy to keep women helpless by threatening
them with violence. Almost by definition, women were classified as
innocent victims and men as evil oppressors. Because the rhetorical gauntlet
had been thrown down, as it were, everyone had to take this title seriously.
Unfortunately, not many actually questioned its legitimacy in the first place.
Obviously, there was no literal war going on between men and women.
The report’s title was intended only as a metaphor, to be sure, but was that
metaphor helpful? The authors clearly hoped that readers would take the
title seriously not only on the individual level of Marc Lépine and his
female victims but also on the collective level of all men and their female
victims.
Metaphors are analogies, not equations, and on the collective level this
metaphor works more effectively in reverse. It could be argued that
ideological feminists acting in the name of women have declared war on
men. The former are heavily armed, as it were, with very sophisticated
political and academic weapons. They have organized themselves
politically in opposition to “the patriarchy.” More specifically, they have
established a wide variety of organizations to coordinate their efforts and
achieve their goals. They have leaders to represent them. They raise money
through both private agencies and government bureaucracies. They are
proud to acknowledge their affiliations and goals. And one of these, for a
particular group of women, is to establish the idea that men are responsible
for virtually all of human suffering. The parallels with ideological wars of
the twentieth century, albeit metaphorical ones, are not exactly hard to
imagine.
The use of military language is dangerous, however, because it
encourages people to take extreme positions. Once war is declared, people
have no choice but to defend themselves. And once this rhetoric is endorsed
by the state, what had been a psychological and moral conflict becomes a
legal and political one. But raising the stakes is a risky business. The
women who proposed this government study wanted to send several
messages. To women they wanted to say, The best way to defend ourselves
as a class is to attack men as a class. To the nation, they wanted to say,
Women are justified in attacking men, because we do so in self-defense. To
men, however, they wanted to say, We consider you enemy aliens, and if the
best defense is an attack, then so be it. In that context, why should men not
take legal steps to protect themselves? Do we really want to move into a
situation like that? If not, we will have to abandon the rhetoric of war.
It is clear to us that even though both random physical attacks on women
by men and organized political attacks on men by women are common,
there is no war between the sexes. And even though millions of men and
women continue to marry, on the other hand, there is no peace between the
sexes. On the contrary, there is escalating conflict, whether it is expressed in
terms of physical violence or political exhortation. Both men and women
are locked into the paradoxical and illusory rhetoric of self-defense.
Canadians merely gave it official status in The War against Women.
Ironically, though, some women have actually declared war against men.46
It was in this atmosphere, only one month before the government study
was proposed, that Andrea Dworkin had urged members at a conference of
the Canadian Mental Health Association “to stop men who beat women …
get them jailed or get them killed.”47 In other words, she had supported
vigilantes. Soon afterward, the same measure – arming women – was
advocated by the National Firearms Association, Canada’s gun lobby.48
This approach would have reintroduced capital punishment through the
back door, as it were, long after it had been abolished by the government.
Moreover, it would have legitimated vigilantism long after it had been
abolished in virtually every industrialized nation.49 Although some
participants at Dworkin’s conference later admitted that killing offenders
might not prove acceptable to most people, the fact is that a court acquitted
a woman for doing precisely that only five days after the study had been
proposed in Parliament.50 Because the woman in question had been
terrorized by her husband on a regular basis, no one dreamed of charging
her with first-degree murder. Because he had already put the gun aside,
though, shooting him was not quite an act of self-defense. Nor was it, as she
claimed, “accidental.” No matter how difficult or painful, she did have
some choices to make at that point. Shooting him was only one of these.
The point here is that by acquitting her, the jurors legitimated a prevalent
desire for (at least vicarious) revenge.51
Unfortunately, justice and law are not synonymous; the two might or
might not coincide. Even in this secular age, after all, the ethical heritage of
Judaism and Christianity remains reasonably intact and accessible. Neither
Christians nor Jews (since the early rabbinic period, which began
approximately 2,500 years ago) believe in equating “an eye for an eye” with
justice. On the contrary, justice is possible only in a context of
reconciliation. No justice worthy of the name, in other words, can be said to
exist unless it leads to peace, unless both parties in a dispute are satisfied
that many of their needs have been fulfilled. It would be a serious mistake
to underestimate the enduring power of this idea whether in its original
religious context or translated into a secular one.
Because the purpose of a government study is to promote law reform and
because the effect is to provide symbolic recognition for the official values
of society, its implications must be taken very seriously. The War against
Women undermined at least two legal principles that are fundamental to any
democratic society. One is that no group should be singled out for attack by
the state. In this case, the citizens of an entire class identified by a
biological characteristic – maleness – became the object of governmental
suspicion and therefore of public prejudice. Another principle is that the
accused are presumed innocent unless proven guilty. In this case, an entire
group was clearly presumed guilty unless it could be proven innocent. And
no attempt was made to do that.
In view of all this, what alternatives might have been considered by
Parliament? There were at least two: a government study of the causes of
violence in general (including, but not restricted to, violence against
women), and a government study of the increasing polarization of men and
women (including, but not restricted to, hostility of men toward women).
Neither was suggested. And neither would have been taken seriously even
if it had been proposed, in all likelihood, except as an alleged example of
misogyny masquerading as liberalism.52
The first alternative would have allowed the study of specific biological
and cultural factors leading to violence against women but without making
the following assumptions even before research began: that the world
revolves around women (which is to say, the attitude of men toward
women); that history is nothing other than a pervasive conspiracy or war of
men against women; and that men might as well have been programmed by
nature to be violent. There is a profound difference between deliberately
promoting a preconceived position (no matter how noble it might sound)
and sincerely trying to describe reality in all its complexity (no matter how
imperfectly) before proposing a solution. The former is usually called
“propaganda.”53 The latter is scholarship.
But many would have objected to this alternative. They would have
raised two main questions. First, would it not have diverted attention and
tax dollars away from women? Sure, to some extent. But since we have
reason to believe that the problem does indeed extend beyond the scope of
any inquiry on violence against women alone, no amount of attention or
money spent on more specific problems would have sufficed.
Second, would a more general inquiry not have trivialized women by
turning their distinctive problems into examples of a larger one? Actually,
no. Like every other social problem, violence against women has its own
distinctive features, and if they were the only victims of violence, it would
make sense to focus attention on them alone. But since women are not the
only victims or even the primary ones, it follows logically that additional
variables must be involved. Ideologues would deny this, of course. They
believe that violence against women is caused by some unique or primal
hatred; therefore, it is the model for all other forms of violence. But neither
of these beliefs can be established on a foundation of hard evidence.
Consequently, the government study of violence against women was
seriously compromised from the very start by ignoring or setting out to
eliminate all factors apart from the attitudes of men toward women and all
explanations apart from those based on a conspiracy theory of history or the
notion that (male) biology is destiny. But if the answer is known even
before research begins, why bother to have a government study in the first
place?
Relating the problem of violence against women to that of violence in
general merely acknowledges the obvious. Both women and men are human
beings. Their experiences can be understood, therefore, in terms of
principles applied to everyone by historians, psychologists, anthropologists,
and so forth. To argue otherwise would mean claiming that the experience
of women is not merely unique but “uniquely unique.” And that claim, an
ontological or even metaphysical one, could be supported only by theology.
To assert that women are victims in a “uniquely unique” way, for example,
would mean that they are the victims of some “uniquely unique” force of
evil. That would make all men demonic beings or satanic agents of some
kind, an implication, as we showed in Spreading Misandry, that can be
found even in popular movies. It is precisely by insisting that violence
against women is like other forms of violence, having many causes and
many variables, that we can avoid the kind of witch hunts familiar from the
pages of history.
The second alternative would have been a government study of the
increasing polarization of men and women. Consider the advantages of this
approach. It would have acknowledged reality, no matter how inconvenient
some people might have considered it: a conflict with active participants of
both sexes. Moreover, it would have acknowledged additional problems:
violence against women, violence against men (whether by other men or by
women), and reasons for violence by men such as genetic abnormalities,
developmental problems, divorce, alcoholism, and drug addiction. In other
words, it would have encouraged the consideration of factors and points of
view that were ignored in the published report. At the very least, this
approach would have raised the fundamental question of why so many men,
conditioned by the same society, do not resort to violence against women or
even against other men. By examining culture as well as nature, it would
have avoided the implication that one segment of society, biologically
defined, was being morally attacked from the outset and would have
included the specific problem of sexism in both forms, misogyny and
misandry. The scope would thus have been neither too broad nor too
narrow. It would have helped us to understand why more men than women
kill, for instance, but without succumbing to stereotypes and the
propagation of hatred.
Given the realities of political life, though, how would a government
study of that kind have functioned? For one thing, both men and women
would have required equal representation. Merely insisting on an equal
number of male and female experts would not have done the trick, however,
because political leanings do not necessarily correspond to physiological
types. Some men, for example, consider themselves feminists. To make this
kind of study work would have meant either of two solutions: eliminating
(male or female) commissioners known to have already adopted political
positions or balancing them with (male or female) commissioners known to
care about the condition of men as well as that of women – and also, of
course, to have studied the condition of men no less thoroughly than that of
women. This would have generated acrimonious debate, to be sure, but
debate is part of both scholarship and government. The experts would have
been in a better position to produce sound scholarship, in short, than
believers in the same ideology. A government study of this kind might have
gone beyond debate. If chosen wisely, commissioners could have fostered a
different form of communication. It would have been an experiment, sure,
but so are all attempts at social engineering.
The problems noted in this government report were very serious ones,
requiring both study and action. To argue against this or that explanation for
a problem afflicting women is not to deny its existence, its gravity, or the
need for a solution. A government report on either violence in general or
the polarization of men and women might have been very useful (to the
extent that any government report is more than just an exercise in political
expediency). This one, on violence against women alone, was of value only
to those who wanted a particular political position endorsed by the state.
Any government study, though, would have proven self-defeating unless a
significant number of the commissioners, not merely a few token men, were
both willing and able to challenge all partisan claims. And potential
commissioners of that kind would have been – and still would be –
extremely hard to find.
The potential response of men, of male citizens and taxpayers, was
considered irrelevant. Men are in a no-win situation. They can either be
politically correct but ineffective or politically incorrect and equally
ineffective. From the very beginning, when the study that resulted in The
War against Women was first proposed in Parliament, the situation was
engineered in such a way that few would have dared to present an opposing
point of view. And those who did could have expected to pay a heavy
political price: public ridicule.
But there is nothing shameful in feeling threatened, certainly not when
the threat is real. And men are increasingly willing to acknowledge this.
Ironically, ideological feminism has caused more and more men to think of
themselves, as women now do, in terms of their identity as a group. Fewer
and fewer men, therefore, will be manipulated into silence by anyone who
accuses them of being “unmanly” or “insecure” for defending their identity
as male human beings.
Despite its divisive rhetoric, the immediate effect of The War against
Women was less than dramatic. Included among its recommendations to
Parliament, after all, were some sensible but hardly revolutionary
suggestions. One, for instance, was that more emphasis should be placed on
putting dangerous criminals behind bars and keeping them there. Another
was that the sale of guns should be more strictly controlled. Many of these
suggestions were legislated. But has the result been peace negotiations
between men and women? Hardly. The level of violence against women did
go down, to be sure, but so did the level of violence in general. The level of
rhetoric, on the other hand, went up. Way up. And even as the rhetorical
stakes were raised, moreover, so were the ideological ones. A significant
cultural and emotional boundary was crossed. Those who might have
hesitated before using extreme language no longer have any reason to do so
– not after the government of a liberal and reputedly staid, even polite,
society used it in official documents.

No event could possibly have illustrated more dramatically than the


Montreal Massacre, along with its aftermath, the extent to which men and
women had become polarized. Because Lépine targeted not merely women
but feminists, moreover, it raises an important question: To what extent
have ideological feminists contributed to the general climate of hostility
between men and women? Because the advocates of any revolution are
bound to generate fear and anger, it is logical to conclude that the rise of
increasingly hostile forms of ideological feminism has had at least some
historical impact on men. Some men feel profoundly threatened by it, and
sometimes – when they are threatened by loss of identity or loss of custody,
say, and not loss of illegitimate privileges – with good reason. It is at least
conceivable that this partly explains the fact that male suicides have
increased dramatically over the past twenty years. Is it entirely coincidental
that “the rate of suicides among Canadian women remained nearly constant
over the same period”?54
Ideological feminists believe that women are fundamentally autonomous
and have no need for men, except as sperm donors; men, they add, are
fundamentally dependent on women and therefore make demands on them
(the result being oppression). Apart from anything else, this means that
women are not only innocent bystanders in the conflict between the sexes
(wanting only to leave men alone) but also passive (wanting only to be left
alone by men). Ideological feminists deny, however, that women are
passive. In fact, they say, history revolves around women. But that raises
questions about even the alleged innocence of women. As active historical
agents, after all, they cannot leave men alone; at least sometimes, they make
demands that conflict with those of men.
Ideological feminists have produced several theories to explain social
problems, but these are hardly the only theories. One member of Parliament
described the debate over The War against Women as a “very painful
experience.”55 In a democratic society, though, it would surely be even
more painful for reports to go through Parliament without any opposition or
debate. Our way of life, represented by the legislature, recognizes no way of
thinking that is beyond challenge. It is far from self-evident, at any rate, that
those who opposed the report did so out of indifference. No one could deny
that something had to be done about violence against women. What should
have been denied were ideological theories that purported to explain or
solve the problem. It should not have been acceptable to assume that any
man who questioned ideological positions or proposals was too “insecure,”
too stupid, or too evil to be taken seriously as a responsible citizen. At that
point, theory became doctrine.
Women really do need to defend their lives. But men, whether they
realize it or not, need to defend their lives as well. Moreover, they need to
defend some sense of identity, no matter how that might be defined, without
which their lives would be meaningless. We do not believe that women
have no reason to protest when their safety is endangered – they surely do –
but we do claim two closely related things in addition. First, women
sometimes choose very inappropriate ways of doing so. Second, men have
good reasons for protesting. In short, both men and women, as groups, have
something vital to defend.
Despite a pervasive fear that thousands of other Marc Lépines were ready to
murder women, or feminists, nothing like that actually happened. Yet
everyone realized that something very significant had taken place – even in
the United States, where the Montreal Massacre was discussed on news and
talk shows – and that nothing would ever be quite the same again.
For Canadian men, at any rate, the time had come to think seriously
about maleness and masculinity. A few men agreed with the feminist theory
that all men were rapists and killers under the skin, but many more men
reacted to that theory with revulsion. At least some of the latter, in fact,
began to realize the urgent need for articulate and sophisticated forms of
self-defense – that is, new gender theories and new political or legal
strategies. For Canadian women, the time had come to translate radical
theories into action. Most feminists believed that they had reached a turning
point in their struggle to change society. And they were correct. During the
next few years, they redoubled their efforts to rewrite every law governing
relations between the sexes and thus bring about a new society. The rest of
this book is about what they achieved. American feminists did not write a
great deal about what had happened in Montreal, but it might not be entirely
coincidental that their legal efforts to change society reached a new height
at precisely that historical moment.
PART TWO
Rights on Trial: Money Matters

In part 1, we discussed widely accepted perceptions of men in popular


culture, continuing what we began in Spreading Misandry but focusing on
the interface between popular culture and elite culture. We argued that those
perceptions are, in fact, shaped primarily by the ideological branch of
feminism. In part 2, we examine the ways in which these perceptions have
affected the fundamental structures of society – that is, national
constitutions, legal systems, and bureaucracies. Our basic point is that
ideological feminism is no longer merely a point of view adopted by a few
pretentious journalists or ranting academics. It has been institutionalized. It
has become the law. And this has taken place largely due to the pressures
exerted by feminist interest groups.
In stable democracies, those who want radical change do not require
violent revolution. There are much easier and more effective ways for them
to achieve their goals or at least to enhance their power. Constitutional
modification – a formal amendment, say, a new rule, or a judicial
interpretation – can be a very effective mechanism. This was certainly true
for American blacks, who have used litigation to improve their position.
According to Christopher Manfredi, the most successful interest groups
have reliable sources of money and expert legal advice. They work toward
long-term goals, accumulating valuable experience at each stage of the
game. Political bargaining, sponsoring test cases, intervening in cases,
infiltrating the courts as researchers and judges, and litigating for a new
framework by which to settle disputes, redistribute goods, or introduce new
court-ordered policies are furthered by lobbying, making political
contributions, or influencing the mass media. Gradually, in short, outsiders
can become powerful insiders.
Everyone knows that interest groups, or lobby groups, play a major role
in democracies, but not everyone knows how effective those of women
have been. In some cases, that is all to the good; women really have
required reforms. In other cases, it is not. The reforms have either
intentionally or unintentionally punished men (which is a moral problem)
and thus contributed heavily to social fragmentation or even polarization
(which is a political problem). In the name of reform and equality, we have
institutionalized revolution and inequality. Gynocentrism has replaced
androcentrism. Misandry has replaced misogyny. New problems have
replaced old ones. Or old ones have remained and merely taken on new
forms. For instance, many new laws – or new interpretations of old ones –
discriminate against men instead of against women. They do not do so
directly or explicitly, of course, because that would mean formal
renunciation of anything remotely recognizable as equality. And that would
require, apart from anything else, tearing up constitutions and barricading
the streets. Instead, they do so indirectly or implicitly.
Our aim here is to examine the constraints, if any, that are placed on
feminist lobby groups in the United States and Canada. The two countries
have somewhat different legal systems (even though both are rooted, apart
from civil law in Quebec, in the British legal tradition). Why discuss both
here? Because both countries have been heavily influenced in the recent
past by a common worldview promoted by the United Nations. Based either
explicitly or implicitly on postcolonialism, the international version of
postmodernism, it is highly receptive to what we have identified as
ideological feminism, along with various national, racial, and ethnic
ideologies. But one country is less constrained by political structures than
the other is. Canadians have found it easier than Americans to implement
the legal changes that are promoted by the United Nations. Canada, in short,
is what the United States would be like with a twentieth-century
constitution instead of an eighteenth-century one.
In both countries, using different mechanisms, advocates of feminist
ideology have secured the collective economic interests of women and
either ignored or attacked the collective economic interests of men: the
individual women and men involved, their particular circumstances, have
been considered of little or no importance. Because the resulting systemic
discrimination against men has been achieved in subtle ways –
incrementally, for instance, rather than suddenly – many people, including
men, have either failed or refused to recognize that a major shift has taken
place. As a result, misandry has been legalized – that is, misandry has taken
the form of systemic discrimination against men.
In chapter 5, we discuss the transformation of rights (originally defined
in terms of freedom from state interference) into entitlements (defined as
state obligations). And in chapter 6, we do so in connection with child
support.
5
Women’s Rights v. Human Rights: The Case of
Entitlements
If you interpret the term “equality” as it has typically been interpreted …
you will maintain the inequality of the sexes. Women, in particular, will
remain the perpetual economic, social, and political underclass that women
now are.1

If Stanley Fish really means what he says [about affirmative action], he


should immediately resign his ill-gotten, unmerited position as professor of
English and law at Duke University so that it can be filled by someone from
a group that has been “bought, sold, killed, beaten, raped, excluded,
exploited, shamed, and scorned for a very long time.”2

Men and women are biologically different in a few – not many, but a few –
basic ways. This was considered self-evident throughout human history
until circa 1965. Women can bear children, for instance, and men cannot.
Men are more muscular and slightly bigger, on average, than women. And
men have more testosterone than women do. Feminists have debated the
relevance of these differences incessantly. Some trivialize them, arguing
that the sexes are interchangeable for all practical purposes and should
therefore qualify for equality under the law. Other feminists (or sometimes,
when it suits their needs, even the same ones) exaggerate these differences,
arguing that women are innately vulnerable to men and should therefore
qualify for either special protection or even special advantage under the law
in order to level the playing field. Still other feminists, ideological ones,
often add that women are innately superior to men – more caring, more just,
more peaceful, more knowing, or whatever – and therefore qualify as the
vanguard of a radically new order.
Men and women are (still) culturally different, too, for various reasons.
In the past, androcentric biases relegated elite women to the domestic
sphere and the masses of women to unpaid labour in the fields or poorly
paid labour in the factories (although the masses of men were hardly better
off in those very same fields and factories). This gender system left most
women unprepared to participate fully in society. They were disadvantaged
in connection with jobs, divorce, remarriage, widowhood, single
motherhood, and so on. Ideological feminists go beyond this observation
and insist that these cultural differences are not merely the accidental results
of biology or the exigencies of history but the intended results of an
oppressive patriarchal society. Men deliberately exploit biological
differences or invent cultural differences, they claim, in order to subordinate
women. In other words, these differences reveal a misogynistic conspiracy.
Whatever the reason – and there is plenty of room for debate on that
score – the fact is that women have had some serious disadvantages in the
public realm and have therefore needed reforms. (Men have had some
serious disadvantages of their own, which we will discuss in Transcending
Misandry.) Most feminists use the rhetoric of equality, which is our political
lingua franca, to discuss these reforms. And who would ever oppose
equality? Trouble is, there are two or three competing paradigms of
equality. Each has been used as a framework in which to solve the problem
of intentional or unintentional discrimination against women by increasing
their rights.
After an introduction on the problem of how to define words such as
“discrimination,” “rights,” and “equality,” we review the legislation on
equal rights, the moral status of affirmative action programs and pay equity
programs, and how these programs affect men and human rights. Our goal
is to move beyond both gynocentrism and androcentrism.

The word “discrimination” is problematic because it can be used in both


descriptive and pejorative senses. Like most people today, we use it in a
pejorative sense; for practical purposes, we refer to discrimination against
this or that. But the word need not be used in that way, because the ability
to discriminate, to make distinctions, is a necessary part of human
existence. The law discriminates with good reason, for example, between
criminal and acceptable forms of behaviour.
As for the word “rights,” the story is more complicated. It was originally
used in connection with freedom from tyranny by the state. The goal was
personal liberty. This perspective gained momentum throughout the
eighteenth-century Enlightenment and was first institutionalized in the new
American republic. According to the Declaration of Independence, every
American has a right to “life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness.” The
implications were eventually spelled out more precisely in the Bill of
Rights. From the beginning, it was clear that not all Americans actually
enjoyed liberty. Slaves, for instance, did not have the rights of other
Americans. This brings up the closely related word “equality.”
After the Civil War, legal inequality was much harder to justify (except,
for almost a hundred years, in the South). One group after another
demanded practical access to equality of opportunity, which is what most
theorists now call “formal equality” or “procedural equality.” How to
achieve that? Until very recently, the answer was clear: by applying the
same rules, in the same ways, to all citizens. American feminists followed
the same pattern, at first, as American blacks had followed. They demanded
legal and social adjustments so that women could pursue their goals,
especially in the public sphere, just as effectively as men could. They
wanted a gender neutral society, in the language of today, or a gender blind
one – the hallmark of a liberal democracy.
But things have changed. Michael Ignatieff and others have argued that
we are witnessing an international rights revolution, a significantly new
way of thinking about rights and equality that has evolved over the past few
decades.3 The rhetoric among feminists has changed profoundly as they try
to liberate women from all traditional roles and to redesign society
accordingly. This has meant acquiring and then mobilizing a new set of
rules to advance their own understanding of women’s rights and gender
equality. These changes have become embedded in the institutional
structures of the governments of Europe and Canada and in international
treaties and conventions.
According to the new rhetoric, rights are primarily about entitlements
and protections granted by the state. The new goal, which most theorists
call “substantive equality,” amounts to equality of result. (Both “formal
equality” and “substantive equality” are manipulative terms. By
implication, only “substantive equality” is “substantial” and thus legitimate
or acceptable. Also by implication, “formal equality” is reduced to
something that can be dismissed as merely “pro forma” or “procedural” and
thus illegitimate and unacceptable.) The ultimate model for equality of
result, in any case, is Marx’s classless society, in which personal merit has
little or nothing to do with the distribution of wealth, although that model
has come down to us in Western countries as the slightly less utopian
welfare state.
How to achieve equality of result? Precisely by not applying the same
rules in the same ways to all citizens as individuals – that is, by applying
them differentially to correct for disadvantages due to race, sex, language,
or whatever. Many feminists now demand “gender balance,” or “gender
equity.” Closely related is the narrower demand for “pay equity,” a scheme
to redress the fact that women as a group earn less than men as a group.
That problem has involved either systemic wage discrimination or
occupational segregation because of historical notions about women’s work
and men’s work.
The new way of thinking is most fully exemplified in documents
produced by the United Nations that we discuss in appendix 6. As a result,
new policies are expanding the political power of women. Ideological
feminists lobby both that organization and their own governments to
institute equality of result. Because they have trouble getting this done
through the front door of legislative change, they introduce it through the
back door of bureaucratic change. First, they attain incremental changes in
documents of the United Nations. Once they are signed by their own
governments, the road ahead is clear. Bureaucrats modify policies
accordingly with “guidance” from women’s organizations that are affiliated
with the United Nations. Only those directly involved know what is going
on.
Many of the most influential American feminists are eager to adopt the
new rhetoric, but the Constitution places some constraints on them. Some
politicians contend that even the Equal Rights Amendment would only
reinforce equality of opportunity, although that conservative interpretation
could be their way of selling the amendment. Because the new rights
rhetoric has become deeply embedded in public opinion, thanks partly to
the talk shows, legislators have managed to change at least some laws
accordingly. But they do meet strong resistance from those who point to a
long constitutional tradition. The most influential Canadian feminists are
just as eager to adopt the new rhetoric, and the Canadian system places few
constraints on them. We could sum up the difference as follows. The
American position is characteristic of both liberalism and conservatism,
ironically, with its focus on the individual. The Canadian position is
characteristic of ideology, on the other hand, with its focus on the
collectivity. By the latter, note well, we refer not to society as a whole but to
fragments of it defined by race, sex, and so on.
Between these two positions is a third, one that has already been widely
institutionalized in both countries but has never been acknowledged by
those who demand equality of result. This position adapts equality of
opportunity to accommodate pregnant women and new mothers in the
workforce, allowing a few exceptions to general rules but without endorsing
equality of result. Those who insist on the latter have incorporated these
accommodations into their own program, which makes equality of
opportunity seem less inclusive. In any case, they remain dissatisfied. They
still demand equal representation. The law, they claim, must require that
women fill at least half of all managerial jobs in the public world:
corporate, legislative, judicial, and so on.

Equality of opportunity was institutionalized first in the United States. Both


before and just after the Revolution, however, only elite white men were
eligible to vote; most men, along with all women, were not. But things
began to change in the mid-nineteenth century. In 1848, the first Woman’s
Rights Convention was held in Seneca Falls, New York. Twenty years later,
the Fourteenth Amendment was passed. It guaranteed equal protection to
men and women under the law. According to section 1, “No state shall …
deprive any person of life, liberty, or property, without due process of law;
nor deny to any person within its jurisdiction the equal protection of the
laws.”4
The Fifteenth Amendment, ratified in 1870, declared that “the rights of
citizens to vote shall not be denied or abridged … on account of race, color,
or previous condition of servitude.”5 This amendment gave the vote to some
black men – those who were literate, say, or owned property – but to neither
white nor black women. Some feminists were vocally hostile, in fact, to the
possibility that black men might get the vote before white women.6 After
decades of political agitation, women finally won the right to vote in 1920.
According to the Nineteenth Amendment, the “right of citizens of the
United States to vote shall not be denied or abridged by the United States or
by any state on account of sex.”7 This remains the only specific
constitutional guarantee of equal rights for American men and women.
It all adds up to equality of opportunity, and the Constitution is thus
consistent with classical liberal theory. According to Anne Peters,“ the
American Constitution does not explicitly provide for equality of men and
women before the law. Differential treatment based on gender must
conform to the general equal protection principles under the Fourteenth and
Fifteenth Amendments. These clauses do not explicitly spell out a specific
standard of protection.”8 Still, they have been interpreted by the Supreme
Court to solve the problems faced by women. “The Supreme Court stressed
that the Constitution proscribes ‘archaic and overbroad generalizations,’ or
‘overbroad generalizations based on sex which are entirely unrelated to any
differences between men and women or which demean the ability or social
status of the affected class.’”9 Accordingly, the functional position of the
United States is equality of opportunity in a modified form. Included in that
category are modifications to ensure that women do not lose their jobs and
benefits due to pregnancy, for instance, or for being mothers of infants.10
As we say, though, many feminists want more than that. They want
equality of result and government-sponsored measures to achieve it. The
best-known measure is affirmative action. Because of their constitutional
documents, says Peters, some Americans oppose affirmative action in
theory but often allow it even so. This anomaly can be traced back to the
Kennedy administration’s attempt to deal with the racial crisis by
establishing affirmative action for blacks, which led women to demand
affirmative action for themselves. But many feminists are unwilling to
admit that equality of opportunity has been attained by modifying it in a
way that “realistically reflects the fact that the sexes are not similarly
situated in certain circumstances.”11 Instead, they appropriate these
modifications as examples of “substantive equality.” This makes it easier
for them to continue struggling toward their ultimate goal: officially
recognized equality of result. They want explicit references in the
Constitution to special “protections” for women, presumably for the
additional security but also because of the additional status that they would
confer.
American feminists have spent more than 150 years campaigning for the
Equal Rights Amendment. A precursor was first introduced as the Lucretia
Mott Amendment in 1848 and revised in 1943 as the Alice Paul
Amendment. Inspired by the civil rights movement, feminists mobilized
again in the 1960s. In 1972, it was approved by Congress as a proposed
Twenty-seventh Amendment, which had to be ratified by three-quarters of
the states within seven years.12 Section 1 reads as follows: “Equality of
rights under the law shall not be denied or abridged by the United States or
by any state on account of sex.” Section 2 adds that Congress “shall have
the power to enforce, by appropriate legislation, the provisions of this
article.” And section 3 concludes that “[t]his amendment shall take effect
two years after the date of ratification.”13
The amendment was not ratified by enough states, but supporters
agitated for – and won – an extension. By the new deadline, 1982, they still
lacked three states. Since then, the Equal Rights Amendment (minus any
deadline on the ratification process) has been reintroduced as a bill in each
session of Congress. And advocates point out that one amendment
originally proposed by James Madison in 1789 (and sometimes called the
Madison Amendment), took 203 years to ratify. In that case, they would not
need to campaign once more for the original thirty-five states; they would
need only three more states. This position was deemed worthy of
consideration by the Congressional Research Service in 1996. Ratification
bills intended to test this “three-state strategy” have been introduced into
the fifteen states that have not yet ratified it.14
Even though some feminists claim that the Equal Rights Amendment
would promote a narrow, or conservative, interpretation of gender
discrimination in order to facilitate its ratification – justices could use the
test of strict constitutional scrutiny in deciding whether equality has been
denied or abridged on account of sex – it has not been ratified by the
required number of states, partly because of considerable tension between
equality of opportunity and equality of result. Nevertheless, American
women have secured the passage of many laws on affirmative action and
pay equity. Although polls have shown considerable American support for
affirmative action, those who advocate equality of opportunity (even in a
modified form) have criticized it for undermining individual freedom, being
unfair to white men, coming in through the back door of administrative
guidelines and court decrees rather than through direct political processes,
undermining competition by benefiting minimally qualified candidates,
making it hard to deal with competing group interests in a nation of
immigrants, and conferring greater benefits on white women than blacks of
either sex, for whom affirmative action was originally designed.15 This
antipathy toward entrenched affirmative action could explain why the
United States has never ratified a document that was signed back in 1980:
the United Nations Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of
Discrimination against Women (which we discuss in appendix 6).
Affirmative action did get in, gradually, through the back door. The term
was first used in 1935 by the National Labor Relations Act, or Wagner Act,
which was part of the New Deal. According to that legislation, the National
Labor Relations Board was required to insist that employers stop unfair
employment practices. This could mean taking “affirmative action,”
reinstating employees either with or without back pay. In 1961, President
Kennedy’s Executive Order 10,925, which set up a committee on equal
employment opportunity, redefined affirmative action as an active way of
counteracting discrimination. Even this, however, was expressed in partially
negative terms: “The [government] contractor will take affirmative action to
ensure that applicants are employed … without regard to their race, creed,
color, or national origin.”16 In 1965, President Johnson amended that order
with Executive Order 11,246, which made the following statement
mandatory for all government contracts: “[T]he contractor will take
affirmative action to ensure that all applicants are employed, and that
employees are treated during employment, without regard to their race,
color, religion, sex or national origin.”17 In 1971, under President Nixon, a
revision of Implementing Order 4 to Executive Order 11,246 defined
affirmative action as the commitment by contractors to specific procedures
and goals that would give preference to particular sexes and races (also
described as “women and minorities”) in order to achieve equal
employment opportunity in federal jobs according to a schedule.
Affirmative action-plans required by this legislation targeted women and
four ethnic groups.18 Meanwhile, in 1963 the Equal Pay Act was passed to
prohibit sex discrimination for similar work in similar conditions.19 All
these laws and their subsequent amendments provided a federal mandate for
affirmative action. Legislation referred to “targets” and “goals,” however,
rather than to quotas, although quotas were sometimes required by courts.
Affirmative action was buttressed in 1978 by guidelines on sex
discrimination. Government contracts were now awarded on the basis of
affirmative action policies. To qualify for contracts, institutions had to file
reports if they found an inadequate number of women or minorities, redress
any “imbalance” by active recruitment, include these new recruits in
management training programs, and so on.20 In short, affirmative action
came in largely through “administrative agencies and courts, not the
legislature.”21 It has been embraced by the private sector, moreover, which
has established independent affirmative action programs.
Minority businesses gained government support with the Public Works
Employment Act of 1977 and Public Law No. 95-507 of 1978. This
legislation authorized set-aside programs, so that some procurement
contracts would go to these businesses. But after these programs were
challenged under the Clinton administration, the Supreme Court eliminated
them both in the military and elsewhere.22
Title VII, an amendment of 1997 to the Civil Rights Act of 1964,
included a statutory prohibition of employment discrimination on the basis
of race, colour, religion, sex, or national origin.23 But this prohibition, too,
had to meet several criteria. Advocates had to demonstrate some legitimate
need to correct an “imbalance” in the workplace (although evidence of
earlier discrimination was irrelevant), provide empirical evidence to support
their claim, avoid “unnecessary burdens” on or unnecessary infringements
on the rights of those who were “dispreferred” (a euphemism for
“discriminated against”), demonstrate that this mechanism would be more
effective than other ways of correcting the problem, and make it “flexible”
enough to be discontinued if the labour market was negatively affected. It
would be negatively affected if the need to reach hiring “targets” because of
affirmative action conflicted with the need to fire people because of
economic conditions, for instance, or if people hired on the basis of race or
sex were less qualified than other candidates.
Affirmative action has been introduced in education, too, especially in
connection with policies governing admission to universities. These policies
have been challenged. One of the major cases, in 1978, was Regents of the
University of California v. Bakke.24 The Supreme Court struck down
explicit quotas for minority applicants (16% in this case), although it did
allow universities to include “birth” traits such as skin colour as “plus
factors” (along with other traits such as special talents, having parents who
had attended the university, and region of residence) to create a “good mix”
of students. These policies were once more under attack by the late 1990s,
this time in two cases at the University of Michigan.25 In June 2003 the
Supreme Court supported Michigan’s affirmative action policy for law
students but overturned the one for undergraduate students. According to
the justices, the former considers race or ethnicity (African Americans,
Native Americans, and Hispanics) as nothing more than a “plus” factor, one
variable among others, and therefore passes the constitutional test of strict
scrutiny. The latter, by contrast, automatically awarded twenty points out of
one hundred for race or ethnicity, thus making it a decisive factor for
minimally qualified applicants.
American judges analyze the merits of affirmative action claims
according to constitutional and statutory provisions. Policies must comply
with the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment and be
assessed by the appropriateness of goals and means – taking into
consideration race or sex. When the government mandates affirmative
action, it uses a strict test, or standard, of legitimacy. The government must
have a compelling interest, in other words, and the means must be narrowly
tailored, although justices have often debated which standard should be
used, because the choice of test greatly influences the outcome.26
All this legislation resulted in a new bureaucracy. According to a list of
all departments in the government, several are devoted explicitly and
exclusively to women.27 The Department of Justice’s Violence against
Women Office does research involving statistics, suggests ways of ending
violence against women, staffs hotlines, provides links to coalitions and
advocacy groups, lobbies for better laws or policies, and gives grants to
state governments.28 The Department of Labor’s Women’s Bureau is
intended to “promote profitable employment opportunities for women, to
empower them by enhancing their skills and improving their working
conditions, and to provide employers with more alternatives to meet their
labor needs by advocating for equitable employment standards, policies,
and programs” and “to empower women to enhance their potential for
securing more satisfying employment as they seek to balance their work-
life needs.”29 Two more agencies are devoted explicitly to the wives of
federal officials: the Office of the First Lady and the Office of Mrs Cheney
(or the wife of any other vice-president).
Canada, too, began by recognizing equality of opportunity, and, as in the
United States, it was achieved in stages. But Canada, unlike the United
States, has officially replaced that ideal with equality of result. Its
institutionalization is due largely to one ideologically oriented feminist
organization: the Legal Education and Action Fund, or LEAF.30 Here is the
story.
The Canadian feminist movement began in the nineteenth century with
demands for suffrage (achieved in 1928 for the women of every province
except Quebec, where it was achieved in 1940) and recognition as
“persons” under Canadian constitutional law (achieved in 1928).31 But the
big push for feminists began during the 1970s, when Parliament officially
adopted a national policy of “multiculturalism.” This policy was originally
intended, in the form of federal bilingualism – the Official Languages Act
was passed in 1969 – primarily as a way of dealing with sharp conflict
between Canada’s two founding communities: the English and the French.
But the underlying notion of “pluralism” was soon extended to women.
In 1970, the Royal Commission on the Status of Women made 167
recommendations. To lobby for their implementation, about thirty feminist
groups created the National Action Committee on the Status of Women. It
now represents approximately seven hundred groups.32 This organization
became closely linked with government through the Canadian Advisory
Council on the Status of Women, which was established by the federal
government as a privileged channel by which feminist groups could make
their demands directly to the government. As Christopher Manfredi has put
it, this is a political advocacy group within the government itself.33
Two major legal cases in the 1970s did not bode well for women. In
Lavell v. Canada, the Supreme Court upheld Canada’s Indian Act, which
said that Indian women, but not men, would lose their Indian status (with its
entitlements) if they married non-Indians.34 In this case, equality before the
law was defined by the Court as “equality of treatment in the enforcement
and application of the laws.”35 In other words, they applied equality to
enforcement but refused to challenge the law’s inherent inequality. In Bliss
v. Canada, the Supreme Court denied benefits under the Unemployment
Insurance Act to women who stopped working during pregnancy.36 There
was no discrimination, said the justices, because the problem was caused by
nature. Both decisions were understood as restrictive interpretations of
equality.
But Canada ratified the United Nations Convention on the Elimination of
All Forms of Discrimination against Women in 1980. And it was partly
with this convention in mind that a joint parliamentary committee held
hearings between 1980 and 1981 to encourage feedback from major interest
groups on Canada’s proposed Charter of Rights and Freedoms. Several of
these groups – among them the National Action Committee on the Status of
Women, which was by then a coalition of 230 groups, the Canadian
Advisory Council on the Status of Women, the National Association on
Women and the Law, and several aboriginal women’s groups – presented
briefs. They wanted most of all to change the draft of section 15, the one on
equality, and they were successful on most but not all counts. They lobbied
with other groups, according to Manfredi,37 for a charter with very general
language and hence interpretive flexibility.38 Due to the efforts of these
groups, the term “non-discrimination rights” (which connotes negative
ones) was changed to “equality rights” (which connotes positive ones).
Moreover, these groups convinced the government to include “sex” in the
affirmative action clause of section 15(2). They did not, however, convince
it to include “marital status,” “sexual orientation, ” or “political belief” in
that clause; eliminate the “reasonable limits” clause;39 or insist on an equal
number of women and men on all courts. Even so, women had won a major
constitutional victory.
Of interest here are two sections of the Charter, which became law in
1982. Sections 15 and 28 must be seen as operating together. According to
the first part of section 15, “[e]very individual is equal before and under the
law and has the right to the equal protection and equal benefit of the law
without discrimination and, in particular, without discrimination based on
race, national or ethnic origin, colour, religion, sex, age or mental or
physical disability.” According to the second part, that “does not preclude
any law, program or activity that has as its object the amelioration of
conditions of disadvantaged individuals or groups including those that are
disadvantaged because of race, national or ethnic origin, colour, religion,
sex, age or mental or physical disability.” Now consider section 28:
“Notwithstanding anything in this Charter, the rights and freedoms referred
to in it are guaranteed equally to male and female persons.”40
In Charter cases, the courts must decide whether your claim of
discrimination is “‘reasonable,’ given the important factors in the social
environment affecting your case.”41 The key words, for us, are “reasonable”
and “social environment.” To interpret the Charter, authorities use the
Oakes test, which defines “reasonable” in connection with section 1 of the
Charter, which “guarantees the rights and freedoms set out in it subject only
to such reasonable limits prescribed by law as can be demonstrably justified
in a free and democratic society.”42 The limits are
• that the government had an important social goal or good in mind
when it made the problematic policy or law (a “pressing and
substantial object”);
• that the violation of your rights actually advances this goal (the
“rational connection” between the action which limits your right to
equality and the furthering of this important goal);
• that your rights were not affected more than is reasonable or
necessary (the “minimal impairment” of your right to equality);
• that there is a balance between the good done by the law and the bad
effect on your rights (the balance between “salutary” (positive) and
“deleterious” (negative) effects of the law).43
The Canadian government actually helps some of those who want to
challenge its own laws. Under the Court Challenges Program, it provides
funding for cases intended to challenge laws that might be considered
discriminatory according to the Charter.44 “The Court Challenges Program
is committed to realizing the equality rights of Canada’s historically
disadvantaged groups and the language rights of Canada’s official language
minorities.”45 The term “historically disadvantaged groups” is extremely
important in this context as a de facto amendment to the Charter. It has been
used to qualify some groups for special protection – women but also
“visible minorities” (whom we discuss in appendix 7) – and disqualify
others regardless of individual need or even of collective need in the
present.
In 1989, Law Society of British Columbia v. Andrews became one of the
most important cases on equality.46 Ostensibly about whether noncitizens
may practise law in Canada, it was really about the definition of equality.
Justice William McIntyre “defined discrimination as a distinction, whether
intentional or not but based on grounds relating to personal characteristics
of the individual or group, which has the effect of imposing burdens,
obligations, or disadvantages on such an individual or group not imposed
upon others, or which withholds or limits access to opportunities, benefits,
and advantages available to other members of society.”47 He said also that
some group characteristics might be added to those listed in section 15 of
the Charter. If so, anyone having those characteristics would be classified as
part of a “distinct and insular minority” that deserves protection such as
affirmative action. This position was reaffirmed several months later,
according to Manfredi, when Justice Bertha Wilson defined minorities as
groups subject to “stereotyping, historical disadvantage or vulnerability to
political and social prejudice.”48
That definition led in 1989 to the unanimous decision of Brooks v.
Canada Safeway, which overturned Bliss. The Court argued that the
“capacity to become pregnant is unique to the female gender.”49 It is
discriminatory, therefore, not to provide pregnant women with benefits.
Bliss had argued that the law was not responsible for biological differences.
Brooks admitted the need to eliminate systemic discrimination caused by
biological differences, which is precisely what Americans had done by
interpreting amendments on equal protection in ways that allowed them to
modify equality of opportunity so that they can accommodate the special
needs of women.
In its 1985 “reference document” on the United Nations Convention on
the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination against Women, which
Canada had signed, the government agreed that “discrimination” means
“differentiations based not directly on sex, but rather on traits correlated
with it, such as height or pregnancy or being a part-time worker (or, to put
the issue in another way, whether discrimination in both effect and intent is
prohibited).”50 This definition includes systemic discrimination: “indirect,
impersonal and unintended discrimination that is a result of inappropriate
standards which have been built into employment systems over the
years.”51
Because discrimination against women is pervasive and affects every
aspect of women’s lives, feminists claimed, society must use every means at
its disposal to correct the problem. And because the effects of
discrimination can be expressed quantitatively – with statistics on
employment, benefits, crime, and so forth – it is easy to document the
negative effects of discrimination and eliminate them. To do that is to
institutionalize equality of result. Canadians have been more successful
than Americans in introducing the term “substantive equality” into
government documents and thus institutionalizing it. According to the
Court Challenges Program, for instance, funding is given for “cases that
advance substantive equality as opposed to formal equality. A formal
equality approach considers that equality is achieved when individuals or
groups are treated the same, even if the impact of a certain policy is not
equal. A substantive equality approach, however, requires that a law be
examined to determine whether it has a differential impact on individuals or
groups.”52 Never mind, once again, that equality of opportunity can be
modified to accommodate particular circumstances.
Canadian officials have been less ambivalent than American officials
about affirmative action. With the demand in Canada for equality of result
came the demand for affirmative action. Among the first steps to be taken
was the Federal Contractor’s Program, which was initiated in 1986. This
program applies to local organizations that employ one hundred or more
people and receive $200,000 or more annually in federal goods or services.
These organizations must hire preferentially from four groups that have
historically been the victims of discrimination: women, visible minorities,
aboriginal people, and people with disabilities. And they are required to
meet “targets” on schedule.
Justice Canada (also known as the Department of Justice) has been a
major player in the debate over equality. In the 1980s it began to argue for
the need to correct systemic discrimination, eliminate discrimination based
on sexual orientation, and establish affirmative action and pay equity.53 Its
Human Rights Section produced a paper on systemic discrimination and
began to pay for briefs by various “equality seeking” groups. These groups
claimed that courts are authorized under section 15 of the Charter to order
the implementation of affirmative action programs.54 (These programs are
constitutionally based in Canada, unlike the United States, because of the
Charter.) In 1991, Justice Canada organized a National Symposium on
Women, Law and the Administration of Justice, which led to the
publication of a three-volume work.55 Leading feminist academics and
organizations were invited to participate. The results included many
recommendations on how to change laws, the legal process, and work in the
legal profession. They amounted to a blueprint for social revolution.
Among the changes demanded were the following: establishing “zero
tolerance” for discriminatory behaviour; ending systemic discrimination
and reviewing all government laws and policies with that in mind; including
“sexual discrimination” among the grounds for discrimination; and
declaring that “heterosexual privileges must be amended (tax law, family
law, and so on) including … the definition of ‘spouse’ and ‘family’ to
include common law and same-sex partners and family units.”56 In
response came the “Action Plan of the Department of Justice on Gender
Equality,” which required more bureaucratic appointments for women,
more “feminist” judges and justices on the Supreme Court, enforceable pay-
equity legislation, and so on (although it did not demand that women should
hold 50% of all jobs or refer explicitly to “substantive equality”), as
recommended by the United Nations.
In 1993, the Canadian Bar Association produced a report called Touch-
stones for Change, which explicitly rejected formal equality, even in
modified form, and explicitly endorsed substantive equality.57 The former
“fails to address the reality of existing inequality and results therefore in the
perpetuation of these inequalities.”58 The latter’s aim, by contrast, is “the
redress of existing inequality and the institution of real equality in the
social, political and economic conditions of different groups in society.”59
In fact, this report confidently predicts a radical transformation of the legal
profession in precisely these terms.
In 1995 pay equity was given legal status under Canada’s Employment
Equity Act. “The purpose of this Act is to achieve equality in the workplace
so that no person shall be denied employment opportunities or benefits for
reasons unrelated to ability and, in the fulfilment of that goal, to correct the
conditions of disadvantage in employment experienced by women,
aboriginal peoples, persons with disabilities and members of visible
minorities by giving effect to the principle that employment equity means
more than treating persons in the same way but also requires special
measures and the accommodation of differences.”60
Before the third World Conference on Women, held by the United
Nations at Beijing in 1995 (which we discuss in appendix 6), Status of
Women Canada formed two committees: the Canadian Beijing Facilitating
Committee and the Canadian Preparatory Committee. Together, they
prepared a national report. After Beijing, the Canadian government – more
specifically, Status of Women Canada – produced Setting the Stage for the
Next Century: The Federal Plan for Gender Equality.61 This document
revealed plans to implement Beijing’s Platform for Action within five
years.62
In 2001, Status of Women Canada made available a document called
“Canadian Experience in Gender Mainstreaming.”63 Judicial decisions and
policy debates under sections 15 and 28 of the Charter, it says, have led to
the recognition that identical treatment of women and men does not produce
equal outcomes. Therefore, it continues, we need to demand them.
Arguments for equality of result “have been made in relation to
employment opportunities and pay, spousal support, sexual assault, sexual
harassment, sexual orientation, pregnancy, pensions and violence against
women.” (Status of Women Canada is a government office, remember, but
it acts also as a lobby group for women. Note the link between “equal
outcomes” and “substantive equality.”) In addition, a new argument
follows: “Gender-based analysis can prevent costly legal challenges under
the Charter and at the same time promote sound and effective public
policies.”64 In other words, forget litigation. Bureaucracy itself can take
care of everything. Just leave it to us!
The following statement of commitment leaves no doubt that gender-
based analysis is really woman-based, or gynocentric, analysis: “The
federal government is committed through the Federal Plan [Setting the
Stage for the Next Century, which we have already mentioned] … to
ensuring that all future legislation and policies include, where appropriate,
an analysis of the potential for different impacts on women and men.
Individual departments will be responsible for determining which
legislation or policies have the potential to affect women differentially and
are, therefore, appropriate for a consistent application of a gender lens.”65
The word “men” appears, to be sure, but – as the very next line indicates –
only as a token gesture.
Interpretations of the Charter have institutionalized equality of result as a
goal. This clearly distinguishes Canadian law from American. (Passage of
the Equal Rights Amendment, the struggle for which is far from dead,
would open up very similar possibilities in the United States. This is why
feminists still want it). But all legislation that results from feminist agitation
for equality of result, whether in the United States or Canada, is based on
the assumption that women constitute a victim class. (Some feminists
believe that women constitute the original and even the ultimate victim
class.) Ergo, women both need and deserve special protection. And by
“special” we refer to protection that infringes on the rights of other citizens.
Like every other segment of society, women are indeed victims in some
ways. But not because they have no power today as a “class.” On the
contrary, few segments of society have more political clout than women. In
fact, women have become one of Canada’s unofficial victim classes. And
men, by implication, have become Canada’s official oppressor class. Male
citizens may be denied equality under the law, in other words, by virtue of
the nefarious activities of their ancestors – which is to say, by virtue of the
biological characteristics that they share with male ancestors.66
It is true that feminists have not had it all their own way. Wary of
increased government expense, the courts have sometimes used section 15
of the Charter to eliminate specific benefits, to level downward rather than
upward.67 Feminists have not yet made dramatic gains in the purely
political realm, although, during the Meech Lake talks on constitutional
reform, they almost succeeded in creating a Senate with equal numbers of
men and women. Nonetheless, the courts have generally complied with
feminist demands. From framing the Charter to litigating successfully, with
important gains even in unsuccessful cases, feminists have taken the
offensive.68 They have made tremendous gains in both the legal and
economic realms.
“In effect,” says Manfredi, “a key institution of the state – the Supreme
Court of Canada – has given positional support to the collective aims of a
significant social movement. The advantage of using this technique
compared to other tactics – such as lobbying, advertising, and electoral
support – is that the policies associated with these legal victories have
acquired a preferred status by virtue of their association with important
constitutional principles. Once achieved, policy victories based on
constitutional litigation … endure remarkably well.”69
Not surprisingly, Canada appointed several strong feminists to the
Supreme Court. Bertha Wilson, the first woman appointed, explicitly called
for radicalism: “I would like to ask you where would we be without the
strident voice of the extremists who have the pristine courage to call ugly
things by their proper names … Just look at history – it is the vigour and
energy of the extremist who paints issues in bold colours that has been the
engine of historical change, whose voice has been a clarion call to action
and who will brook no delay.”70
No wonder American feminists see Canada as a success story. Consider
timing. The Charter was written and debated when the feminist lobby was
already well established and ready to take up legal and political challenges.
Canada was already a welfare state, more like European countries in this
respect than the United States. And that suited many Canadians, who had
long sought an identity to distinguish themselves from Americans. (In fact,
it could be argued, Canadian identity consists primarily of whatever makes
them unlike Americans.) By 1986, Catharine MacKinnon (who is discussed
in chapters 7, 8, and 9) could comment that under

the Charter, Canadians have a unique opportunity to advance sex equality.


You have a chance to make it real in Canada. I contrast this with the
existing situation in the United States, where there is not even one equal
rights amendment. Canada has two, section 15, the more abstractly framed
provision, and section 28, the more substantively framed provision. Each
has many separate sub-clauses conferring guarantees in various
metaphorical relations to the law: beneath it, before it, and so on … If you
interpret the term “equality” as it has typically been interpreted – including
by American courts and mainstream commentators in the Anglo-American
jurisprudential tradition – you will maintain the inequality of the sexes.
Women, in particular, will remain the perpetual economic, social, and
political underclass that women now are. Our inferiority, our powerlessness,
our relative negligibility, will be maintained as it has been, both by acts of
positive government and by acts which are so socially systematic that they
have seldom needed positive law to guarantee them, for example, spousal
rape and the pornography industry.71

MacKinnon urged Canadian feminists to reject equality of opportunity


because, judging from the American experience, it gave white men the few
advantages that women already had. Custody law had been dramatically
changed for the worse, in her opinion, because fathers had now been given
equal opportunities in court (a claim that we discuss in chapter 6).
Moreover, husbands could now be awarded alimony. In fact, men now had
access to women’s schools and jobs. She lamented the prevalent belief that
the best way to improve things for women was to do so for men as well –
even though she admitted that this approach has given women “nominal
access” to traditional domains of men, including blue-collar jobs and
military jobs, along with more than nominal access to athletic activities.
MacKinnon believed that this approach – men and women are
fundamentally alike – could never work, because it fails to account for the
fact that men and women are fundamentally different. Moreover, it does not
take into account

the most systematic social disadvantages, the sex-differential abuses of


women. In these abuses are included not only segregation into less valued
jobs, but also the range of issues of violence against women which have
been systematically tolerated by virtually every government in the world,
despite cultural differences or formal equality guarantees. These include the
massive amount of rape and attempted rape about which virtually nothing is
done; the sexual assault of children apparently endemic to the patriarchal
family; the battery of women which is systematic in our homes;
prostitution, women’s fundamental economic option; and pornography,
which makes inequality sexy to the tune of $8 billion a year in the United
States alone … The fundamental issue of equality is not whether one is the
same or different. It is not the gender difference, it is the difference gender
makes … To be on the bottom of a hierarchy is certainly different from
being on the top of one, but it is not simply difference that most
distinguishes them. It is, in fact, the lesser access to resources, privileges,
credibility, legitimacy, authority, pay, bodily integrity, security, and
protection that is effective for you: less of all of what is valued in society …
It is an issue of systematic male supremacy and how it shall be ended.
Confronting this problem leads to a much more substantive approach to the
notion of equality. It leads to the principle that to be equal is to be non-
subordinate: not to be subordinated.72

Given her long involvement with the Canadian women’s Legal


Education and Action Fund ((LEAF)),73 it should come as no surprise that
MacKinnon’s interest in Canadian law is revealed in several books and
articles.74
Another American, Carol Gilligan, has entered the annals of Canadian
legal history. The proceedings of a conference organized by the Canadian
Bar Association in 1992 included a paper by Kim Campbell, who was
minister of justice and attorney general (but would later, briefly, become
Canada’s first female prime minister). Campbell drew directly on the work
of Gilligan, especially In a Different Voice.75 In that book, says Campbell,
the feminist icon “got us thinking in a new way about the differences
between men and women. The response of two eleven-year-olds to a moral
dilemma suggests that boys have an ‘ideal of perfection’ and that girls have
an ‘ideal of care’ … Although we have to be careful about importing
analysis from the United States and making blanket assumptions, I believe
that in Canada, today, men and women do live different realities which give
each sex a unique perspective. Women can and do bring something different
to the practice of law, to judging, to the political process.”76
Campbell elaborated by quoting Annette Baier, who had said that if
Gilligan “is right about the special moral aptitudes of women, it will most
likely be the women who … are the ones with more natural empathy, with
the better diplomatic skills, the ones more likely to shoulder responsibility
and take moral initiative, and the ones who find its [sic] easiest to
empathize and care about how the other party feels.”77 She believes that
women are morally superior to men, in other words, not merely different
from men. After observing that men were becoming more open to
“women’s ideas, voices and realities,” Campbell concluded by noting that
many men were taking responsibility for their violence by wearing white
ribbons on 6 December, when, as we saw in chapter 4, Canadians remember
the fourteen women shot by Marc Lépine.
According to an influential report by four psychologists – Faye Crosby,
Aarti Iyer, Susan Clayton, and Roberta Downing – affirmative action can be
justified on several grounds.78 For one thing, they argue, numerous surveys
show that it is popular; students approve of it – or, if not of affirmative
action itself, then at least of its goal (which, however, is not exactly the
same thing). This is not a moral argument, of course, because anything can
be popular but still not be morally justifiable. The authors argue primarily
not on moral grounds but on grounds of pragmatism or expediency.
Affirmative action works, they say; other mechanisms, such as high school
or even undergraduate grades and aptitude tests, do not.

Specifically, we contend that all measures of merit include an element of


subjectivity and that they are, therefore, influenced by both historical and
current prejudice. We also see that psychological factors such as stereotype
threat influence how members of target groups perform, causing some tests
to underestimate their actual merit. On the basis of numerous social
psychological studies, we claim that members of the target groups cannot be
relied on to come forward themselves and that other, fair-minded people are
usually unable to detect unfairness in the absence of aggregate data. The
implication is that affirmative action, with its reliance on the analysis of
systematic aggregate data, is needed if fairness is to be achieved by
rewarding and utilizing merit, regardless of gender or ethnicity.79

This pragmatism is actually a slightly veiled form of postmodernism, the


philosophy that is routinely exploited by feminist and other ideologues. The
key word here is “subjectivity.” Because no test is perfectly objective,
ideologues say, we should embrace subjectivism – this is a characteristic
and even fundamental requirement of postmodernism – by deliberately,
albeit somewhat indirectly, selecting students according to sex and race or
ethnicity. Crosby and her colleagues use verbal magic to state their point.
They declare that fairness involves “rewarding and utilizing merit,
regardless of gender or ethnicity.” This goal is attainable, they add, only
after affirmative action has done its work by eliminating prejudice. But
because postmodernism denies that the requirement for eliminating
prejudice – objectivity – can ever exist, it follows that affirmative action
can never complete its work. No matter what they say in public, therefore,
ideologues consider affirmative action a permanent necessity and not
merely a temporary expedient.
Elsewhere, Crosby and her colleagues move in precisely the opposite
direction. They find it expedient to argue for “the importance of using
objective methods for identifying discrimination rather than relying on the
good intentions of individuals for rectifying such problems. The studies also
show the specific importance of implementing practices that require
organizations to collect and examine systematic, aggregate data for
comparative purposes. Systematic comparisons based on aggregated data
are at the core of affirmative action.”80 People can be objective when
selecting and analyzing data for affirmative action, apparently, but not when
grading or testing.
However, the very idea of aggregate data (in this case, the total
percentage of men compared to that of women) highlights a serious
problem that is often mentioned in connection with admitting students and
also with hiring members of the faculty. The truth is that female
undergraduate students, and even female graduate students in some fields,
outnumber their male counterparts at many universities. So why not
establish affirmative action for male students in specific fields? Because,
say advocates of affirmative action, men still dominate the university as a
whole – that is, when you consider the “aggregate” of all those who make
up a university, including members of the faculty who began teaching long
before women began entering their fields. Aggregate data can be used to
show that male students are advantaged, although the reverse can be used in
the context of hiring. Is using the former really a measure of objectivity?
Remember that affirmative action has been used to correct for fewer women
than men in some fields but not for fewer men than women in fields such as
social work, education, or nursing.
Crosby and her colleagues are inconsistent. They say that most law
schools give more weight to LSAT scores (60%) than to undergraduate
grades (40%). This is a problem for women, they add, because the LSAT
scores of female students are lower than those of their male counterparts,
even though their undergraduate grades are higher. But they argue
elsewhere that both grades and tests are inherently subjective. On what
basis can they say, therefore, that female undergrads are actually better
students than male undergrads and are thus more deserving of entry to law
school? Besides, would Crosby and her colleagues have even noticed a
problem in the reverse situation – that is, if male students were getting
higher grades but lower LSAT scores? Not likely.
Everyone knows that affirmative action “works” in the sense of
promoting the interests of target groups. How could it be otherwise, when
the state uses law deliberately to favour them? It does not necessarily work,
however, in the sense of fostering good education. Success comes with a
cost. Crosby and her colleagues actually admit that in a study of eighty
thousand students at twenty-eight prestigious universities, “the special
admits graduated from college, attended and graduated from professional
and graduate schools, and held professional jobs at the same rate as did the
other students. The special admits did, however, differ from the other
students in two salient ways. First, they had lower grade-point averages
than did the comparison groups both during their undergraduate education
and during their professional or graduate training. Second, decades after
graduation, those who were special admits were more likely than their
White counterparts to be active civic leaders.”81 But who knows what
“civic” means? It could mean political activism for more affirmative action.
The stated goal of affirmative action is always a “diverse” student
population. Why? Because that produces a wider variety, advocates say, of
opinions and perspectives. And that, in turn, makes students more adept at
“problem solving” or coping with the real world after leaving university.
What sounds good in theory, though, does not always work so well in
practice. This defense of affirmative action in the name of diversity is
problematic for several reasons (apart from the fact that it relies on the
notion that ends can justify means).
In the first place, we do not know that sexual or ethnic diversity actually
adds up to intellectual diversity. And that, presumably, is more to the point
in a university than the genetic pool of its students. Sexual or ethnic
diversity might lead to tolerance. On the other hand, it might lead to
stronger support for sexual or ethnic ideologies. If so, the end result would
be greater polarization and therefore greater intolerance than ever before.
Indeed, ideological intolerance is already rampant in the university and has
been during the entire period of affirmative action. In this conformist and
censorious atmosphere, not many university teachers actually encourage
independent thought that is based on critical analysis of fashionable
political ideologies. On the contrary, many encourage students to stamp out
whatever can be classified as politically incorrect (see appendices 4 and 7).
Some students might report teachers who create a “hostile environment,”
for instance, even if only by questioning a feminist doctrine. Other students
might launch or participate in hate-mail campaigns against teachers who
write books or articles that challenge gay ideology. This might well prepare
students for an increasingly polarized society beyond the university, true,
but only by exacerbating the problem.
In both the United States and Canada, universities and other institutions
are eligible for government-funded research grants only if they adopt
affirmative action programs. This approach is based on two assumptions.
First, men and women are equally intelligent. In other words, men are
inherently no more capable than women and should not outnumber women
on the faculty. Okay, we can live with that. Second, the unequal numbers of
men and women can be explained only by discrimination. This assumption
is debatable, to say the least. Hostility toward women might explain the
rejection of female applicants in a few cases today, but that is by no means
the only possible explanation, because equal numbers of men and women
might not apply in the first place.82 Not all graduates actually want to teach
in universities, after all. This is particularly true of those with professional
training in fields such as medicine, dentistry, nursing, social work, law,
architecture, education, occupational health, physical and occupational
therapy, psychology, library science, engineering, management, and
ordained ministry. Although some of these fields are indeed still dominated
by men, others have long been dominated by women. And some of the
newer ones are now identified by both women and men as ideological
rather than academic. Besides, many women decide to interrupt their
academic careers and, for a few years after graduation, stay home with their
children. Even if the relative paucity of women on the faculty of any given
department really could be traced directly to sexual discrimination,
however, the most obvious solution would surely be to discourage sexual
discrimination and not to promote it by substituting one kind of
discrimination for another. According to Grant Brown,

Preferential employment practices meet none of the normal conditions for


compensatory justice: that the very person who perpetrated a civil wrong
must compensate the very person who was harmed, and that the
compensation must be commensurate with the harm suffered. Treating
individuals merely as members of groups, and transferring employment
benefits and harms between them willy-nilly on that basis, cannot be
deemed “compensatory justice” or “rectification” for past wrongs, without
doing violence to the concepts of compensation and rectification. Indeed, it
is the very essence of bigotry to wish to bring harms upon a person simply
because he belongs to the same group as someone who (let’s suppose) has
harmed a member of a group to which you belong.83

It could be argued that opposing affirmative action is tantamount to


supporting those who, no matter what they say in public, are motivated by
bigotry. But Jews who oppose affirmative action know better, because they
have experienced its dark side. Stephen Stern points out that Jews have
“never proposed or favoured legislation forcing employers to preferentially
hire them in order to make amends for over two thousand years of past
suffering. Indeed, they have fought tirelessly for the removal of all quotas
and all references to one’s skin colour or ethnic heritage in matters
pertaining to hiring, firing, or promotion. They have, to their eternal credit,
simply demanded that merit be the only criterion.”84
Actually, “never” is not the best word. Jews did not seek affirmative
action in earlier times, it is true, because no state offered to the Jewish
community or any other minority community the possibility of improving
its condition. More recently, some Jews have ignored their own history by
supporting affirmative action for minority groups or women. But Stern’s
point is worth taking seriously. Jews, represented disproportionately among
liberals in most public debates, tend to be more skeptical about affirmative
action than many other communities. In living memory, after all, it was
used against them. Our own university, McGill, maintained a quota to limit
the number of Jews until the early 1960s.85
But suppose that the unbalanced sex ratio really was a result of
discrimination and required correction. The underlying assumption is that
the end (encouraging departments to hire more women) could justify the
means (discouraging them from hiring men). As we have mentioned, this
principle is an essential premise of all ideologies, whether on the political
left or the political right. In every case, adherents believe that their own
particular end is worthy enough to justify what would otherwise have to be
considered immoral conduct. Not surprisingly, many of the worst
catastrophes in history have been done in the name of some greater good.86
In a famous article for the Atlantic Monthly, Stanley Fish threw down the
academic gauntlet to those miscreants who persisted in opposing
affirmative action.87 He implied that oppressed communities have some
moral right to oppress other communities, although he did not phrase it so
blatantly. For him, official discrimination against white Americans is
justifiable because of official discrimination against black Americans in the
past. Never mind that no one alive today either experienced centuries of
slavery or inflicted it. Moreover, as John Field pointed out in his letter to
the editor, Fish ignored the historical fact that most communities engaged in
the persecution of other communities have always tried to justify
themselves by pointing back to their own persecution. That creates two
moral problems.
First, the target population might or might not have been involved in the
original persecution. From Fish’s point of view, Jewish (Israeli) injustice
toward Palestinians could be justified on the grounds not of Palestinian
injustice toward Jews (Israelis) but on those of Nazi injustice toward Jews.
Second, the original persecution might or might not have been real at all.
Hitler and at least some other Nazi leaders sincerely believed that Jews had
been persecuting Germans through economic exploitation, capitalist (or
communist) manipulation, or whatever. Albeit unwittingly, Fish justified the
Nazi persecution of Jews.
It all amounted, said Field, to a rejection of the golden rule and all our
efforts, no matter how inadequate, to create a more egalitarian society. “The
idea was to be color-blind. It is a great … ethical principle … and it should
not be so lightly cast aside. We may be terribly flawed, but we are at least
trying to figure out how not to be in spite of advice like Fish’s.”88 The idea
of colour-blind justice is not without problems, however, which we will
discuss in a moment.
But from Fish’s point of view, and that of many others who support
affirmative action, what appears to be discrimination is not really
discrimination at all, because discrimination is motivated by malevolence
but affirmative action is motivated by benevolence. For this reason, Fish
dislikes the term “reverse discrimination,” which “fails to distinguish
between inequities whose production is intentional and inequities that
follow in the wake of a policy not designed to generate them.”89 Actually,
the term “reverse discrimination” really is inappropriate but not for that
reason. Discrimination is discrimination, no matter what the motivation,
and it should not be disguised by suggesting that it is somehow a second-
order phenomenon, a reversal of the real thing.
No wonder, as Steven Yates points out, public discourse has been
contaminated by Orwellian euphemisms: “equal opportunity” now refers to
preferential treatment, for instance, and “racism” to a statistical
imbalance.90 It is true that motivation must be considered in any moral
debate. Because people are moral agents only to the degree that they can
actually make moral choices, the motives for those choices must always be
considered in assigning guilt or innocence. But motivation is notoriously
hard to establish, partly because people are not necessarily open about it,
partly because they are not necessarily aware of it, and partly because it is
not necessarily unambiguous in the first place. Fish tried to finesse his way
out of this attack, in any case, by responding that “oppression is not the
agenda here; affirmative action is not a revenge strategy even if it is
experienced as such by those who are caught up in the backwater of its
effects.”91 In other words, a legitimate interest of some unfortunate citizens
– in this case, their ability to earn a living – is expendable.
Motivation notwithstanding, the result is not only “justice” for some but
also injustice for others. There is no moral basis for this trade-off unless you
argue that affirmative action is a necessary evil. To make that point, you
must use the analogy of a just war in which killing the enemy is a necessary
evil. But no one could seriously argue that affirmative action is a
spontaneous reaction to the threat of being attacked or killed by ruthless
enemies, a reaction unmediated by the subtle moral considerations required
in everyday life. On the contrary, advocates of affirmative action claim that
it is founded precisely on subtle moral considerations. No matter. There is
for many an ideological basis to affirmative action. Men (or at least white
men), they believe, make up an oppressor class and therefore deserve to be
punished.
But this presents another extremely disturbing moral problem:
eliminating the individual as a significant factor in moral debate. People are
no longer individual moral agents. They are nothing more than
representatives of some collectivity – a class, say, or a race. This focus on
the collectivity would be perfectly consistent with totalitarianism, but it is
an utter contradiction of the moral framework of liberal democracy in the
modern Western world. For affirmative action to be effective, the individual
rights of men must be sacrificed in favour of the collective rights of women.
This particular problem can hardly be dismissed as a remote or irrelevant
abstraction by Canadians, in particular, since it lies at the very heart of the
enduring conflict between Quebec (which favours collective rights in order
to support the notion of its own sovereignty as a “nation”) and the rest of
Canada (which presumably favours individual rights, including those of
anglophone Quebecers, but which actually favours collective rights when
doing so seems politically correct).
Besides, the notion of collective rights is only one side of this coin. Flip
it over, and you find the notion of collective guilt, which has had a long and
depressing history of its own. One of the more notorious examples has been
the belief among some Christians that their Jewish contemporaries, no less
than those of the first century, were ontologically defiled by guilt as the
“deicide people.” More recently, this idea has been used to legitimate a
variety of profoundly dualistic worldviews in which the source of evil is
projected onto some easily identifiable group of “others,” whether defined
by their class, race, language, or sex. If the problem is solely due to “them,”
of course, then “they” are rightly punished en masse as scapegoats for all of
“our” suffering. Even innocent individuals are thus considered guilty for
being members of a class or race. Lee Dembart asked the obvious question:
If Fish insists that white male aademics are living off ill-gotten gains, why
does Fish himself not resign?92 Fish responded by claiming that Dembart
took the idea too far, that race or sex should be merely “one ingredient” in
hiring decisions, “not as a special favor but as a recognition of the positive
contribution such groups might make to an ongoing enterprise that has not
one but many goals.”93 Sure it does. And none of these goals, presumably,
gives political goals priority over academic ones.
Affirmative action for women is intended to end discrimination against
women. To that end, it institutionalizes, at least for the time being,
discrimination against men. One underlying assumption is that
discrimination itself should not be identified as the problem. For the sake of
social justice, some would argue, governments routinely discriminate in
favour of some groups and against others. Using this analogy, it would
seem that opposing a policy of discrimination at a university would be
tantamount to opposing any government intervention and, by implication,
any attempt to attain social justice.
Consider one of the most obvious examples of government
discrimination: taxation as the redistribution of income, which is also the
foundation for every service provided by the state. In one way, to be sure,
the analogy holds. Taxation can be used against one class (the rich) in
favour of another class (the poor). But the analogy is too seriously flawed to
be morally useful. Citizens are taxed on the basis of their incomes as
individuals, after all, not their membership in a biological category.
Theoretically, every individual who is required to pay really can afford to
pay, and every individual who is supported really does need to be
supported. The goal of taxation is to distribute wealth more fairly among
classes, but it operates at the level of individual responsibility and need.
This is not the case with affirmative action. If a man and a woman were to
apply for the same job under those conditions, it could not be argued that
the woman needs it more than the man. The man would be rejected in
favour of the woman simply because of the biological fact that he is a man,
not because of anything to do with him as an individual. The discrimination
involved in taxation is calibrated according to individual circumstances, in
short, but the discrimination advocated for universities and other
institutions involves targeting people according to innate characteristics.
Even those who find affirmative action disturbing on moral grounds
often argue that it is the lesser of two evils: either continuing the current
“policy” of covert discrimination against women, in this case, or adopting a
new policy of overt discrimination against men. But this principle is
legitimate only when the two evils are very different. Waging war against
Hitler involved incalculable suffering for the soldiers and civilians on both
sides, but the alternative was to cooperate with a form of evil that would
have destroyed everything worth living for in the first place. It would be
very hard, on the other hand, to differentiate on moral grounds between the
evil of discriminating against men and that of discriminating against
women. Both are evil for precisely the same reason and in precisely the
same way. If it is wrong to discriminate against women, then it is wrong to
discriminate against men. In fact, it is inherently wrong to discriminate
against any group of human beings.94
Some argue that the ultimate goal of affirmative action is to hire people
on the basis of personal ability, not sex. Because the proper sex ratio had
not yet been achieved, its immediate goal – to be achieved by “interim
policies” – is to correct the imbalance. Equality, in other words, is to be
achieved through inequality. Morally, though not pragmatically, that is a
contradiction in terms. We say that it is impossible to honour the principle
of equality in one situation by mocking it in another.
Returning now to the case of affirmative action in the university, it might
be argued that the primary academic objective is to recruit and hire
“excellent women scholars.” That objective is clearly a political priority,
however, not an academic one. Using the term “excellent women” cleverly
disguises the fact that this proposal has nothing to do with academic
priorities (promoting excellence) and everything to do with political ones
(promoting women). Why elide these two principles? To answer this
question, we must examine an underlying belief about the university, the
academic institution par excellence: that it is a microcosm of the larger
society. Because this belief is now so commonly held that it passes for
conventional wisdom in some circles, many people imagine that they no
longer need to support or even state it. It has become an assumption.
But the university is not and never can be a microcosm of the larger
society.95 It represents one particular segment of society with one particular
task: the search for truth. (In the age of deconstruction, it must be reasserted
that truth, no matter how elusive under the finite conditions of human
existence, no matter how ambiguous and incomplete it remains in our
perception, must remain the goal.) From this it follows that the distribution
of various social groups in the larger society need not be mirrored perfectly
in the university (just as they need not be on, say, a basketball team). From
the same premise, moreover, it follows that the university need not be and
indeed should not be directly involved in social engineering – if it were, it
might easily be reduced to nothing more than a government agency or an
ideological factory, acting on the basis of whatever is considered politically
expedient. Tax dollars are used to support universities, true, which is why
politicians argue that the student body should represent the taxpayers
demographically. But tax dollars are used to pay for highways, too, even
though not all taxpayers own cars. Ditto for primary and secondary schools,
even though not all taxpayers have children. Inherent in the democratic
system, no matter how cynical it can be, is a residue of altruism. Some
things, including universities, are so valuable to society as a whole – unless
they are undermined by ideology masquerading as scholarship – that
everyone should participate in paying for them.
At this point, we must acknowledge a belief of our own. We believe
(although we cannot prove) that truth leads to justice. We believe that there
is no such thing as justice, in fact, unless it is based on truth. Consequently,
seeking truth is an indirect way of seeking justice. Those who seek justice
make use of scholarship as graduates or as participants in the larger world.
The university itself, however, must not be turned into a tool by or for those
who think that they know best how to reorganize society.
Even those who accept the primacy of political considerations over
academic ones – in this case, the principle of proportional representation in
the university as a microcosm of society – are surely both logically and
morally obliged to apply them consistently and thoroughly. After all, the
composition of society can be classified according to many criteria, not
only according to sex or race. Using the same arguments, it would be
reasonable for every group that considers itself distinct on grounds of
ethnicity, religion, political affiliation, geographical region, class, language,
disability, or whatever to demand the same preferential treatment as women
in order to ensure their proportional representation on university faculties. If
the mere fact of belonging to these groups were the ultimate criterion, the
one that trumps purely academic criteria, they should be satisfied with
nothing less. But would that help the university fulfill its distinctive
mandate or justify its specific raison d’être? To answer that question, think
of the bureaucratic and political nightmares that would ensue if every job
were to become the potential prize sought by dozens of competing groups.
Once the principle of proportional representation is accepted, then it must
be applied consistently. Otherwise, every identifiable group, no matter what
the criterion on which its identity is based, would have cause for charges of
immoral or illegal discrimination.
Now, what if femaleness is not entirely unrelated to scholarship?
Scholarship thrives in the context of intellectual debate, and intellectual
debate can occur only in the context of differing points of view. It is true
that the life experiences of women can generate distinctive points of view.
Some might argue, therefore, that giving them preference makes sense even
in scholarly terms. But advocates of this position often ignore several
problems (which we discuss more fully in chapter 10). For example, this
idea would not apply to women alone. If the distinctive perspectives of
women are sought by means of quotas or targets, why not those of every
other group that can claim some distinctive point of view?
Besides, the mere fact of having a distinctive point of view means little
or nothing in itself. When hiring teachers and researchers for a university, it
is the ability of applicants to subject their own points of view to critical
analysis, to use them in scholarly ways, that should be of primary concern.
Otherwise, a distinctive point of view would be synonymous with an
ideological one. And in some fields – mathematics, say, or electrical
engineering – different life experiences should make no difference
whatsoever to the outcome of research. Not unless we agree with Hitler,
who demanded that “Jewish physics” be replaced by “Aryan physics.”
Some say that female students and teachers are at an inherent
disadvantage because they find fewer mentors or role models on the
faculties of universities than their male counterparts. Even if only for that
reason, they say, universities should make the hiring of women a priority.
But this idea makes no sense – except, of course, to ideologues who believe
that “feminist scholarship” (based on the notion of a “female
epistemology,” which we discuss in chapter 10) is inherently different from
(read: superior to) “masculinist scholarship.” There is no reason why
scholars must have some biological qualification to serve as mentors.
Mentors are scholars, not icons of sex, race, ethnicity, religion, or anything
else. At issue is not whether scholars can serve as role models for life itself
but only whether they can serve as models for scholarship. It is good for
women to see other women succeed in attaining high academic offices, but
this alone is not a prerequisite for women to become scholars themselves.
Otherwise, how could we explain the existence of female scholars in the
past and present? There was a time, not so long ago, when very few Jews
were highly placed or even present in the university. (In those days, quotas
were used to keep Jews out, not to get them in.) Very few Jewish students
allowed that to prevent them from becoming scholars. For specifically
Jewish role models, they turned to the Jewish community. For academic
ones, they turned to the academic community. It should be noted, moreover,
that some men have been successfully “mentored” by women. Our point
here is not that the presence of female scholars should make no difference
at all to female students but that it should not be a factor in evaluating the
actual scholarly potential of female candidates for jobs.
Should the criteria for assessment be the same for male and female
applicants? Some people say no. In doing so, they raise the old spectre of a
double standard. But, they add, have universities not always used double
standards for one reason or another? Why not be honest about it? Because,
in our opinion, that line of “reasoning” makes no moral sense. Openly
acknowledging a vice does not turn it into a virtue; the latter does not
follow from the former. Those who deliberately and overtly institutionalize
unfairness are in no way morally superior to those who do the same thing
unwittingly or covertly. Otherwise, we would have to admit that legalized
apartheid in South Africa was somehow more acceptable than the informal
racial segregation in other places. But wait. The new double standard, say
advocates of affirmative action, discriminates in favour of the vulnerable
instead of the powerful. Should that not make it morally acceptable? No,
because the vulnerability of one group is merely foisted onto another. That
amounts to nothing more than playing musical chairs.
Ignoring the need even to argue the case for a double standard, some
claim that because of family responsibilities, women often take longer to
complete their degrees than men. That looks bad on a résumé. But why
should length of time be a criterion for hiring someone – female or male –
in the first place? Surely it is the degree itself that indicates scholarly
ability, not the length of time it takes to complete. (We should be able to
assume that those who linger too long without a good reason will not be
awarded degrees in the first place.)96 Of course, those who do take longer to
complete their degrees are older than other candidates. But why should
anyone – female or male – be rejected on the basis of age? Insisting on
scholarship as the sole criterion would solve the problem without creating a
new one, without adding a biological criterion that has nothing to do with
effective performance on the job.
According to another claim, hiring committees should recognize
explicitly that the career paths of female applicants are often different from
but as valuable – “equally valuable” – as those of male applicants. But what
does “equally valuable” actually mean? Is it a reference to working part-
time versus full-time? To taking several years off versus continuing without
interruption? To teaching alone versus teaching, publishing, and sitting on
committees? How can it be said that all these choices are equally valuable?
Equally valuable to whom? To the women in question? To society? To the
students? To the university? To the academic world? Making these choices
should be possible, yes, but not pretending that one choice is as good as
another from any perspective at all. Life always involves choices. No one
can have it all, not even men. When men choose to devote their lives to
scholarship alone, they choose also, by default rather than by intent, to have
minimal contact with their families.
The term “equally valuable career paths,” moreover, refers primarily to
the establishment of “alternative” criteria for promoting women with no
time for research and publishing, partly because women often feel obliged
to sit on many committees just to ensure female representation.97 Although
universities do reward academics who make truly outstanding contributions
to administration – they are run primarily by academics who choose this
career profile – they still maintain the fundamental importance of research
and publications, especially for tenure. But if women refuse to be bound by
the expectation of research and publishing, why not men? Given a real
choice, men might indeed want to spend more time with their families (or
their hobbies, or anything else). Unless we want to continue sending the
message that fatherhood is irrelevant, we will have to encourage men, and
not only women, to consider “equally valuable career paths” and entice
men, not only women, with the provision of daycare facilities. On the other
hand, many men and women might simply feel better suited to teaching or
administration than to research or publishing.
In addition to moral problems affirmative action creates some purely
practical ones. Like so many medical cures, after all, this one can bring with
it some very unpleasant side efects. Some of these might prove even worse
than the original disease – and not only for men but for women as well.
Why, for instance, should men not express resentment over discrimination
against them? You would have to be very naive, for instance, to imagine
that men do not resent affirmative action for women. At a relatively abstract
level, it is easy to agree that access to jobs should be no more difficult for
women than for men, even if that means the gradual displacement of men as
a dominant group in the academic world – as long as the process of
displacement reflects scholarly integrity. It is not so easy to agree that they
themselves, or their sons and the male students whom they have been
preparing, should be sacrificed in the interest of social engineering. That
would amount to their displacement as individuals – and by a process that
makes a mockery of both scholarly and moral integrity. No one willingly
becomes a pawn to be moved around in the interest of others. Even martyrs
always choose to sacrifice themselves for others, after all, which is why
they are considered holy and not crazy. Similarly, no man, unless he has a
name such as Trump or Rockefeller, is going tell a woman: Here, take my
job, I don’t need it. To ignore that simple fact of life is folly for women who
are hoping for a genuine improvement in relations between the sexes. They
cannot reasonably expect to institutionalize discrimination against men and
receive respect from those men.
If practical considerations were the only ones that mattered for
institutions, there would be no controversy over affirmative action. It is
precisely because the easiest and most practical solutions are often
questionable on specifically moral grounds that we need to discuss them in
the public square. Otherwise, why not embrace some form of
totalitarianism? There was some truth in the old saying about Mussolini,
that he at least made the trains run on time. If efficiency were the main
criterion in matters of this kind, then we would have to declare democracy
itself hopelessly inefficient and replace it with some other system.
Fish and other advocates of affirmative action have surely been correct
in complaining that many opponents react to it blindly and, in some cases,
even maliciously. That “discourages any serious consideration of the
injuries affirmative action seeks to redress.”98 The idea of affirmative action
arose for a reason; discrimination was a major problem. Moreover, as many
advocates of affirmative action have pointed out, the bias that causes
discrimination is often subtle and even unintentional. Standardized tests, for
example, have been found to favour those with specific cultural
backgrounds. The only question is how to remedy that situation.
Why not fight fire with fire, replacing one form of bias or discrimination
with another? Those who ask that question might not be cynical themselves,
but they rely on arguments that are inherently cynical. Others say that we
should fight fire with water, as it were, using insight to replace bias and
prevent discrimination. They might be naive, to the extent that they believe
in a system based on equality, or at least the quest for equality, but they rely
on arguments that are inherently moral.
For some people, justice means that resources must be shared in amounts
proportional to the size of each segment of the population. That premise
underlies equality of result, once again, and of proportional representation.
For others, even a right to freedom from discrimination should be limited if
another group’s constitutional right to the same thing is ignored when
collective goals conflict with individual ones. Governments may use
corrective measures such as affirmative action, they argue, but only if some
attempt is made to balance competing interests, only if these corrective
measures are limited in scope and duration.
But we suggest that affirmative action creates a moral problem even
when limitations really are in place. Why? Because the same problem can
be solved in other ways, assuming that safeguards are in place to ensure
selection on the basis of merit. Proper education from an early stage to
make everyone competitive on the basis of merit would surely be preferable
on a moral level to the introduction of a double standard and, on a practical
level, to the devaluation of beneficiaries as second raters. The same would
be true of remedial education and training programs.99
Once group identity is linked with special treatment, how can the latter
be ended without attacking the former, even after the original problem has
been solved? Once claims are defined in nebulous and unverifiable ways,
how can any outsider tell when the original problem no longer exists? And
once groups are allowed to operate without checks and balances, how can
the principle of “justice for all” be maintained? Advocates of affirmative
action seldom even acknowledge these problems. (We discuss them in
appendix 7.)

Closely related to affirmative action is pay equity. This, too, involves many
moral problems. No discussion of pay equity should avoid its verbal
context. Some feminists like to replace the word “equality” with the word
“equity.” They associate “equality“ with an abstract or even mathematical
way of thinking, that way of thinking with historical notions of “blind”
justice, and those notions, in turn, with maleness. These same people
associate “equity,” on the other hand, with a more personal and allegedly
more humane way of thinking (never mind its common use in the world of
finance, which is not notably humane), that way of thinking with fairness or
caring, and that caring, in turn – thanks partly to Gilligan – with
femaleness. Besides, this rhetoric renders slightly less harsh or obvious the
inherent contradiction that underlies affirmative action: creating inequality
in the name of equality. But the two are by no means synonymous. The
notion of equality supports “equal pay for equal work,” but the notion of
equity supports “equal pay for work of equal value.”
Various criteria are used to establish work of equal value. Every scheme
classifies jobs into various tasks – categories and subcategories – and
assigns each a numerical value. These are added up to indicate appropriate
salaries.

Pay equity requires the use of gender neutral job evaluation methods.
Gender neutral job evaluation is intended to assess the relative value of all
jobs within a work-

place based on a common set of factors. In general, the most common


evaluation factors used include skill, effort, responsibility and working
conditions. The reported aggregate gender wage gap is a statistical indicator
of women’s wages relative to men’s wages. It is usually calculated by
dividing the average annual earnings of women by the average annual
earnings of men. The gender wage gap varies depending on labour market
experience, unionization, occupation, industry, educational attainment, and
age, among other factors. The pay equity wage gap is that portion of the
wage gap that is not explained by factors such as labour market experience,
hours of work, educational attainment and unionization. It is commonly
understood that the pay equity wage gap results from systemic wage
discrimination.100
Critics have pointed out that “disaggregation” – separating every task
and assigning it a numerical value – makes it easy to skew the scale in
favour of women. Without actually labelling jobs as women’s jobs, for
instance, equity agencies can list the skills required – skills that are often
still associated primarily with women – and give them higher status. This
means that employers would have to pay higher salaries for them.
Collectively, these upgraded “gender-neutral” jobs would improve the
economic status of women as a group (or, to use the jargon in a slightly
different way, as an “aggregate”). Moreover, the advocates, or watchdogs,
are always members of women’s groups.
In any case, the whole system of collective bargaining between employer
and employee is breaking down under the weight of pay-equity schemes.
Unions use market-survey data to bargain for men’s wages and then run to
human rights tribunals on behalf of the women who are thus left behind.
The unions want their female members to cash in, of course, and have
supported pay equity in a big way. Listen to this comment from the AFL-CIO:

Equal pay has been the law since 1963. But today, nearly 40 years later,
women are still paid less than men – even when we have similar education,
skills and experience. In 2000, women were paid 73 cents for every dollar
men received. That’s $27 less to spend on groceries, housing, child care and
other expenses for every $100 worth of work we do. Nationwide, working
families lose $200 billion of income annually to the wage gap. It’s not like
we get charged less for rent or food or utilities. In fact, we pay more for
things like haircuts and dry cleaning. Over a lifetime of work, the 27 cents-
on-the-dollar we’re losing adds up. The average 25-year old working
woman will lose more than $523,000 to unequal pay during her working
life. And because we’re paid less now, we have less to save for our futures
and we’ll earn smaller pensions than men. Half of all older women
receiving a private pension in 1998 got less than $3,486 per year, compared
with $7,020 per year for older men. These figures are even worse for
women of color … Equal pay helps men, too. Men in jobs usually or
predominately held by women – sales, service and clerical positions, for
example – are also victims of pay bias. The 4 million men who work in
predominately female occupations lose an average of $6,259 each year …
The 25.6 million women in these jobs lose an average of $3,446 a year.101

But this figure of 73% is an “aggregated” one. It does not mean that any
particular woman earns that much less than any particular man. Nor does it
account for any global discrepancy. The implication is that discrepancies
are due to sexist discrimination against women, but discrepancies can be
due to other factors. Given the educational patterns of earlier generations,
for instance, older women are still less often part of the workforce than
older men. Not all women, moreover, either have or want full-time jobs.
When their salaries are factored in with all others, the resulting figure
indicates only that women as a group earn less than men as a group. The
fact is that women themselves have made choices: to have children or not to
have children, to work or not to work, to work part-time or to work full-
time. Unions come out ahead either way, but the system does not. Because
of the enormous sums of money at stake, a whole industry has grown up
around pay equity: researchers, job evaluators, consultants, and so forth.
In a society that is truly interested in fairness, equity agencies would
have to demonstrate fairness to citizens of both sexes. Otherwise, the
situation could become dire. Some men would eventually fight back. Others
would withdraw into cynical isolation. Still others, to judge from the
statistics on suicide among boys and young men, would give up hope in life
itself. Neither scenario would enhance democracy, which depends on the
transparency of justice for all citizens. Any agency with the authority to
oversee pay equity or to inform the public about it, in short, must represent
the public as a whole.
Someone should examine the various “options” proposed by equity
programs with precisely this goal in mind. Doing so would mean analyzing
documents submitted to them with the aim of identifying explicit or implicit
biases against either women or men. This approach would evaluate
definitions of “gender,” underlying ideological presuppositions or sources
of authority, double standards, openness to manipulation, and so on.
Nothing of the kind is likely to happen.
Pay equity is supposed to increase the value of women’s traditional paid
work. At the same time, it decreases the value of men’s traditional paid
work. We are thinking of work traditionally assigned to men and based on
characteristics of the male body. Manual labour, historically done by men,
is sometimes considered less valuable than clerical labour or of no value at
all, due to mechanization (although it is also necessary and sometimes
dangerous, factors that should make it valuable). Even before the Industrial
Revolution, physical labour had a relatively low social status; upper-class
men and even middle-class men shunned it. (We will discuss the history of
the male body in Transcending Misandry). Until very recently, though, it
could still provide at least lower-class men with a healthy sense of identity.
It was still based on some contribution to society that was distinctive,
necessary, and publicly valued. And that, as we have already said several
times, is the sine qua non of any healthy identity. Cross-cultural and
historical evidence indicates that no society has been able to ignore this
need. Our society, far from trying to solve the problem of ignoring it, has
actually found ways to exacerbate it. At the very least, we need programs to
help men retool for the information age. Should the government take steps
to upgrade workers in male ghettoes just as it now does to upgrade workers
in female ghettoes? Should it see the obligation to train more men,
especially unemployed men, for white-collar work?
And what about risk? Note that risk – this is an important variable,
because the work-related accident is a major cause of death for men – is
seldom if ever a criterion in pay-equity programs. “Work place accidents
are … a major killer of men. 98% of all the employees in the ten most
dangerous professions are men and 94% of all those who die in the
workplace are men.”102
If we are going to level the playing field, truly, we will have to end the
current domination of pay equity discussions by women’s advocacy groups
both within and beyond the government. In one research paper, Morley
Gunderson and Paul Lanoie begin by supporting (or seeming to support)
pay equity programs but conclude by rejecting them.103 They point out, for
example, that many aspects of these programs seem innocuous enough but
hide severe problems. They present three “typical” case studies: a
manufacturing company staffed mainly by blue-collar men, a public
hospital staffed mainly by women, and a newly established
telecommunication company staffed by both men and women.104 At this
point, the authors present an important definition. “Target efficiency refers
to the extent to which a program assists as many persons in the target group
by as much as possible without having the benefits spillover [sic] into the
non-target groups. In the case of pay equity, the target group would be
persons in female-dominated jobs whose pay is ‘undervalued,’ although the
real target is likely to be women in such female-dominated jobs.”105
Gunderson and Lanoie admit that the procedures are complex, so
complex that they can easily be manipulated in favour of women – the
target group – especially in the private and nonunionized sectors (although
the very same procedure could be managed or manipulated in the public
and unionized sectors to the detriment of men.) They discuss the benefits of
pay equity for a few men in female-dominated jobs but point out that these
benefits undermine the ultimate goal of closing the wage gap between men
and women, because men can take advantage of “leakage” from the female
target group. In other words, any improvement in the pay of a few men
detracts from the improvement of all women in relation to men. Clearly,
advocates of pay equity do not want to help men in female-dominated work.
Although advocates of pay equity sometimes use this possibility in
propaganda directed at men, they view it as a negative factor in the larger
picture.
The authors note that some employers hire experts even before receiving
complaints of discrimination, because the complicated procedures required
by law would probably be misunderstood without them. And
misunderstanding them would waste time and cost money. This is work for
the experts! And thousands are ready to become experts in this growth
industry.
Some economists, they point out, argue that wage fixing in the case of
pay equity amounts to price fixing. It ignores market forces that would
naturally correct some problems, including the problem of employees who
stay in undervalued jobs, say, or employers who “downsize.” Advocates of
pay equity reject that argument by claiming that the market created
discrimination in the first place. Other economists support employers who
complain about the high cost of pay-equity programs, noting that money is
merely transferred from employers to employees. Consumers or taxpayers
(or possibly other workers) absorb the cost, they say, adding that there are
hidden costs to pay equity at every stage of a complex and technical
procedure. Design, implementation, and administration involve committees,
job evaluators, consultants, and lawyers.
Gunderson and Lanoie describe the bureaucratic duplication involved in
pay-equity programs, which would involve separate plans for each
organization, for each bargaining unit within each organization, and for
nonunionized employees. And the resulting complexity, apart from
anything else, has given rise to legal wrangling. Organizations require
tribunals to adjudicate the almost inevitable conflicts. When one side
challenges a decision, the result can be costly for litigants and defendants.
“These real resource costs are ‘eaten up’ in the process; they represent
shrinkage in the pie that can otherwise be distributed to the parties. As aptly
stated by Fudge and McDermott … ‘[T]hat is the final beauty of pay equity:
it consumes so many resources there is little left for anything else.’”106 The
only people who make money are the professionals, in other words, not
those who were actually supposed to earn more money.
Given all this complexity and the need for experts, say Gunderson and
Lanoie, the system can hardly be transparent. Worse, the experts are by no
means impartial. Because pay-equity programs are designed to improve
women’s wages, these experts have vested interests in furthering the cause
of women by promoting their own obscurantism, complex methods, and
bloated bureaucracies. The end result is that these programs develop lives
of their own. Therefore, Gunderson and Lanoie recommend reversion to the
“complaints-based approach” and add that “there is no evidence that the
original needs for the [complaints-based] program have dissipated over time
in that the discriminatory pay gap that could be reduced by pay equity has
now been closed.”107
Feminist calls for equality, or even equity, sound at first like nothing
other than calls for justice. Lurking just below the surface, though, is often
the call for gynocentrism. Whatever its underlying motivation,
gynocentrism has already been institutionalized, either directly or indirectly,
in laws or interpretations of them, constitutional amendments or
interpretations of them, and bureaucracies at every level of government.
The rhetoric has functioned like that of motherhood. Who (except for some
feminists) would ever oppose that in public? Equality is not only the
legitimate expression of egalitarian feminism, therefore, but also the ideal
front for ideological feminism. Not only are students exposed to
gynocentric indoctrination, but so are legislators, judges, bureaucrats,
corporate managers, and employees.
Here is one example. The National Judicial Institute, established by the
Canadian Judicial Council in 1988 “to provide continuing education courses
for federally appointed superior court judges,” has since 1992 provided
“gender sensitivity” seminars.108 The institute’s program on gender equality
consists of “a 30-minute video, printed materials and an afternoon panel
discussion.” Both the video (which is used in connection with admission to
the bar) and the printed materials (which are taken from a book edited by
feminist professors Sheilah Martin and Kathleen Mahoney)109 preclude any
real discussion of gender, because they present only feminist interpretations
of the Charter and therefore only feminist takes on problems such as
domestic violence, custody and support, sexual assault, and systemic
discrimination.
Systemic gynocentric bias has led to more than a demand for quotas,
usually known as “targets.” It has led also to a demand for social and
cultural (though not political) revolution. Ideological feminists measure
progress according to a “female standard” and in view of “female
knowledge.” Ideological feminists denounce equality of opportunity,
insisting on equality of result. Ignoring the fact that the former has been
greatly modified over the past thirty years to suit women, they claim that
modifying it has prevented a critique of what they believe is the
“phallocentricity” of knowledge. Women have nothing to learn or gain, in
other words, from the experience of men.

There is no reason not to suppose that women, as they earn seniority, will
rise to the top. But consider the current debate over pay equity in Canada,
which erupted anew in 1998 when the Human Rights Tribunal ruled that the
federal government had underpaid two hundred thousand federal employees
in female-dominated jobs. It was not only the high cost of corrective
measures that caused an outcry, by the way, but also the fact that federal
employees were already overpaid. In 1997 the Canadian Labour Congress
found that the employment of women in the public sector had risen by 47%
between 1976 and 1996, whereas that of men had actually fallen by 14%. In
fact, female employees had become the majority, and their average earnings
were almost double those in the private sector. Canadian women earned a
better hourly wage two years after graduation, moreover, than did men.110
And more women were hired more quickly than they would have been
without affirmative action.
No policy is going to eliminate the wage gap between men and women,
because women (or men) who stay home with their children will lose
financially. Even when governments provide special measures – family
bonuses, tax breaks, and so forth – they do not make up for lost income and
therefore lower pensions.111 Not unless we resort to some form of
totalitarianism and eliminate the freedom to make choices. Nevertheless, we
can mitigate the problem in two ways: by providing people with a variety of
incentives and thus of choices, and by providing them with parental leave.
At the heart of this controversy is the fact that women, historically, have
been more closely involved than men with rearing young children. Until
recently, most were not part of the paid labour force. One result was
economic vulnerability in the event of widowhood and divorce. Special
protections have been introduced to prevent their vulnerability, and many
women have been able to choose between working at home and working in
the larger world. But many women who stay home to rear children will
eventually want to rejoin the labour force, especially in view of extended
life spans. To make that possible without penalizing those who choose to
stay at home with children, we would have to do at least two things very
effectively: offer a wide variety of educational and retraining programs and
eliminate age discrimination. For some reason, that form of discrimination
is seldom mentioned by anyone advocating either affirmative-action
programs or pay-equity programs. And yet it is rampant.112
We do take seriously the fact that women as a group – though not
necessarily as individuals and seldom, nowadays, as young individuals –
earn less than men. And we do take seriously the fact that some jobs should
be reclassified, if not because of malicious discrimination (which is
probably very rare) then because they have changed with the advent of new
technologies (which is probably very common). But there is surely no need
to evaluate society in exclusively economic and political terms. Ultimately,
every society must be evaluated in moral terms as well. Advocates of pay
equity, like the advocates of affirmative action already discussed, invite
moral evaluation, in fact, because their schemes are all premised on
“fairness.” Even if they could bring about a fairer distribution of wealth,
their schemes would still be morally flawed. They are based firmly,
inherently, and irrevocably on the dubious principle that ends can justify
means, which involves sacrificing the interests of some people to serve the
interests of other people. And for those who do not care about moral
principles, there is this to think about: the cynicism that flows directly from
any practice based on systemic discrimination and political or economic
manipulation. For evidence of that, look at the moral collapse of societies in
eastern Europe after decades of communism.
So where does all this leave men in the age of social engineering? In
theory, Canadian men should be included in sections 15 and 28 of the
Charter under “sex.” In fact, that claim has been resisted by interpreting the
Charter in connection only with “historically disadvantaged” groups. Men,
it is assumed wrongly, have not been historically disadvantaged. But men in
our time really have become disadvantaged as the official victims of
institutionalized double standards. Men have become the sacrificial victims
of society, to put it bluntly, because the economic interests of women have
taken precedence over the economic and sometimes other interests of men.
Here is one example. In Weatherall v. Canada,10 the Supreme Court
ruled that the frisk-searching of male prisoners by female guards was
acceptable but maintained that the frisk-searching of female prisoners by
male guards remained unacceptable.113 One reason for the double standard
was to ensure the job security of female guards. This trumped the right to
privacy of male prisoners. But the reason actually cited in one authoritative
source involved “historical, biological and sociological differences between
men and women.”114 It is most unlikely that any judge would condone
inequality for women on the grounds of their biological characteristics,
which would be explained away as the social constructions of a patriarchal
society (except, of course, when biological characteristics could be cited as
grounds for inequality in a positive sense and thus for entitlement). As for
historical (or sociological) differences, which are of immediate interest to
us here, the ruling clearly suggests that male prisoners, unlike female ones,
deserve no privacy. Why not? Partly because this case involved the
conflicting interests of guilty prisoners and innocent guards, to be sure, but
mainly because our society has historically ignored the notion that men
value privacy as an essential feature of human dignity but has nonetheless
insisted on the notion that women do. Men have not been conditioned to
feel inhibited by modesty, but women have been. Exposing men to the
prying eyes of women does not constitute a violation of their human
dignity, supposedly, but exposing women to the prying eyes of men does.
At issue here is whether privacy should be considered an essential
feature of human dignity, not whether Canadian notions of masculinity or
femininity have fostered it. Either way, the judgment in this case is very
disturbing. It reveals an underlying double standard: recognizing the
historical conditioning of women but not that of men. If privacy is an
essential feature of human dignity, the judge might have considered the
possibility that Canadian culture has historically disadvantaged men by
denying it to them but not to women. If privacy is not an essential feature of
human dignity, on the other hand, why allow it for female prisoners?
Most men are not in prison. Most have jobs. And almost all need jobs.
Older male employees, those who are preparing to retire, are unlikely to be
affected by affirmative action or pay equity (unless men, but not women,
are actually fired on principle in the event of downsizing). Slightly younger
men might be disappointed if their promotions go to women. But young
men, those planning or beginning their careers, are paying the full price for
affirmative-action programs or pay-equity programs. Even those who get
jobs realize that their chances of getting better ones, or even ones at the
same level, have been diminished. And these mechanisms are not only for
women but also for minorities, which means that young men will always be
at the bottom of the hiring pool. Even minority young men will have to wait
until minority women are hired. They realize, at some level of
consciousness, not only that their prospects are dimmer than those of young
women but also that society does not care about the prospects of young
men.
When the system is expanded to include other groups, this problem is
magnified, despite the rhetoric about diversity. Writing about what might be
“the greatest policy achievement in recent history,” Katherine Boo observes
that “over the past decade significant numbers of formerly welfare-
dependent black women have successfully entered the work force. But what
about black men?”115 The fact is that black men are in bad shape. Welfare
reform has opened a “chasm between the status and prospects of black
women and those of the men they might marry. A grim home economics: In
the 1990s the employment of young black females dramatically increased,
despite the fact that many of those working women were single mothers.
Meanwhile, the employment of their less-encumbered male counterparts
stagnated, even in a period of unprecedented economic expansion.”116
A higher proportion of black women than white women are employed.
And not only at menial jobs. They earn, on average, 96% of what white
women earn. That is a major achievement. A much lower proportion of
black men than white men, however, are employed: 30% lower. And that
figure excludes men in jail. “Set aside the profound emotional implications
of this gender gap [and think about] the loneliness of newly working
women struggling to raise children by themselves; the resentment of men
watching female contemporaries succeed, with considerable government
assistance, in jobs at which they themselves have failed or from which
they’ve been displaced by women.”117
The underlying cause, according to Boo, is feminism (in our
terminology, gynocentrism). Men in general and black men in particular,
she argues, have been ignored. The “grave predicament of the contemporary
black male, and its fundamental connection with the fate of black children,
has managed to slip quietly through two distinct cracks: the one between
competing special-interest blocks of the poverty industry, and the one
between the hardened ideological categories of right and left.”118
Paul Offner has commented on the funding patterns of what he calls the
welfare-industrial complex and the resulting neglect of black men: “The
emotional testimony at congressional hearings on welfare reform is
inevitably going to be about day care, or welfare time limits, or definitions
of activities that qualify as work … because women and children are the
social-services constituency – the individuals with whom the government
and the nonprofits interact. Men are barely on the screen, except as dead-
beat dads.”119 Consider also the depressing effects of political expediency
on both sides of the political spectrum.

If there is less rigorous discussion about how, now, to create opportunity for
black males, it may be because the political utility to such a debate is
uncertain. Drawing acute distinctions between the deserving and the
undeserving poor, the political right resists heavy investment in a child-
abandoning, work-resistant, lawbreaking population. Buttressing the right’s
position is the fact that previous federally funded efforts to put young black
males to work have produced few appreciable results. The left, meanwhile,
is reluctant to advocate for men in the face of the considerable needs of
women.120

What does Boo suggest? How can we create hope for struggling black
men and, by implication, for struggling men in general? “What if
unemployed fathers who owed child support were mandated to participate
in work-related activities or community service? What if they then received
stipends while learning skills or searching for jobs with the assistance of
community-based programs that have established a track record in helping
women?”121
Social engineering is a very blunt instrument. It affects not only those
immediately involved in this or that scheme but also society as a whole.
Affirmative-action programs and pay-equity programs are only two
symptoms – we will discuss several others in the following chapters – of a
much more pervasive phenomenon: the apparently paradoxical trend toward
both extreme collectivism and extreme individualism at the same time. We
say “apparently,” because the paradox is more apparent than real.
First, consider the trend toward extreme collectivism, which is revealed
not only in the rise of political ideologies based on group identity, including
feminism, but also in the rise of state control that has emerged as a direct
result of their utopian programs. These utopian programs must be imposed
on society. Or, to put it another way, the state must control people more and
more rigorously – economically, legally, and politically – in order to attain
not merely equality of opportunity but equality of result. Second, consider
the trend toward extreme individualism. At one time, men and women
pooled their resources as family units within larger units, or classes, defined
by economic status, religion, ethnicity, and many other things. In our time,
women (and, by default, men as well) are seen as autonomous individuals
within rival classes. When income statistics are compared, they are often
understood (falsely) in connection with the earning capacity of individual
women versus individual men. Few think about the interdependence of men
and women in family units as a significant factor. This is hardly surprising,
since the goal of many feminists – the ones we classify as ideological – is
not merely sexual equality or even “equity” but autonomy and even
separation from men (about which we will say much more in chapter 8). So
far, this autonomy has been realized most fully by individual women
(although some feminists would like to attain collective autonomy as well).
The result is a rapidly fragmenting society of more or less autonomous
individuals controlled directly by the state in ways not mediated, as they
once were, by family or community.

This debate over entitlements shows that human rights are threatened on an
international level. Human rights once referred to the rights of men,
women, children, and religious communities. They are now being redrafted
in the name of “gender balance” to focus exclusively on women’s rights
(which we discuss in appendix 6). Because this is a controversial departure,
officials use the term “human rights” anyway as a front. Occasionally, they
give a nod to the old worldview by throwing in references to “men and
women” or “girls and boys.” But they do so mainly to counter any charge of
overt discrimination.
We are by no means the only ones to think about these problems. Jean
Bethke Elshtain, for instance, suggests that there are three models for
understanding rights in connection with men and women. One is “sex
polarity,” which assumes that men and women are categorically different
and might as well belong to different species. This sex polarity has both
ontological and hierarchical implications. In the past, women were
devalued. Now, men are devalued. This rhetoric, which is always about
power, often resorts to analogies such as slavery and war. As we have
pointed out elsewhere, this is the rhetoric of conspiracy.

The difference between earlier generations of male disparagers of women


and current disparagers of men by women is that the language of rights was
not available as a central category in the rhetorical struggle. Rights, then,
traffics as a variant on power-talk, as the emblematic relationship between
male and female as separate categories is that of oppressor and oppressed.
Sex polarists cannot, by definition, think their way out of, or through, this
static formulation. Or, perhaps better put, they can get out of the
oppressor/oppressed and master/slave pairing only through the obliteration
of one category: thus men must be “feminized,” and the more virtuous and
saintly sex must triumph for the scenario to play itself out to a desired
end.122

Elshtain’s second model, “sex unity,” ignores the difference between


male and female bodies as “a source of identity … the object of
epistemological wonder and understanding.”123 From this point of view,
men and women are interchangeable, especially since the advent of
reproductive technologies such as surrogacy or ex utero gestation, which
get around the most obvious difference.
Elshtain’s third model is “sex complementarity.” This “begins from a
stance of ontological equality and equal dignity that is nonetheless
compatible with different roles and offices … [It] affords a sense of
partnership, of what it means to be in community and in communion.
Framed with this understanding in mind, rights become signs of human
dignity, marks of ‘the same’ and ‘the distinct’ simultaneously. This latter
position is philosophically richer but it complicates matters politically and
requires a more nuanced understanding of the way rights structure our
identities both with and against multiple bodies – family, church,
neighborhood, and state.”124
Human rights developed within the Western tradition of formal rights,
which were based in turn, observes Elshtain, on both the classical idea of
universal law and the Christian one of natural law. Rights were immunities,
inhering in people as such, from interference by the state. With the
development of market economies, however, rights as immunities became
rights as entitlements.

Entitlements place me in a different position towards both the state and my


neighbor. Rather than serving an interpositional role – the state is not
permitted to do certain things because so to do would violate human dignity
– rights now affords us a way to couch a particular claim – I am entitled to
certain things, because I belong to one of a proliferating number of possible
human categories (male, female, young, old, handicapped, minority, etc.) …
Tethered to an adamantly individualistic understanding of the human
person, rights as entitlements denies any weight to principles of belonging,
obligation, and community or communal identity. In this adversarial version
of rights, the tethering of self to community is severed – at least in theory –
and the transitive nature of rights is lost. Rights as immunities, as inherent
markers of human ontological dignity is the understanding of rights in
general to which Christians are most indebted and toward which they can
make the strongest contribution.125

When rights as immunities turned into rights as entitlements and when


group identities – determined by sex, for instance, or race – were
presupposed, rights became adversarial. “Not only that. A world defined by
rights as adversarial possessions, increasingly lodged in a presupposition of
pre-given group identities’ (by gender or race, for example), promotes or
requires a flattening out of human identity. We are all bundles of needs and
claims … What separates us one from the other is not our human
distinctiveness but the fact that some are oppressors, others oppressed;
some hegemonic, others object.”126 Elshtain concludes that the sex-polarity
position has aligned with the adversarial approach to human rights and to
human rights themselves “as a way to get and to hold power.”127 For those
who disagree, too bad. They, presumably, are the products of false
consciousness.
Elshtain’s position on human rights is very close to our own. Like her,
we believe that ideological feminism not only polarizes the world into “us”
versus “them,” women versus men, but also places these ontologically
different groups into a hierarchy. Men were above women in the past, but
the reverse is true today. It should be needless to say – but clearly is not –
that two wrongs do not make a right. We would prefer to get beyond the
androcentric view that “human” means “man” but also the gynocentric one
that “human” means “woman.” We would prefer to see human beings, in
short, with stereoscopic vision. In the context of human rights, this would
mean seeing the bodies (and histories) of men and women as both different
and similar. The latter would surely make sense in view of the fact that men
and women are members of the same species.

The word “equality” is almost universally accepted in the United States and
Canada as the highest political goal of society, but how many people – how
many voters – are actually aware that it can be defined in two radically
different and opposing ways? Among those who do, how many realize that
advocates of one definition want not merely to modify the other definition
but to replace it? Or that each definition represents not merely a political
position but a worldview?
Equality of opportunity, even in its current modified form, emerged from
the worldview that created both countries (though not, of course, the recent
Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms). It encourages society to reduce
the gulf between rich and poor and currently tries, with varying degrees of
success, to prevent anyone from falling below a minimal level of economic
security, but does not replace personal responsibility with state regulation.
Equality of result has emerged much more recently from a worldview that
promotes very different notions of (among other things) the state, the
community, the citizen (or individual), and the law. It insists that society
must distribute wealth evenly according to a mathematically calculated
paradigm. And to achieve that goal, it does replace personal responsibility
with state regulation.
The older worldview accommodates both liberalism (which encourages
the active pursuit of amelioration) and conservatism (which places that
within a larger moral context). It therefore requires negotiation and
compromise in connection with reform. The newer worldview
accommodates neither liberalism nor conservatism. It therefore tolerates
negotiation, or compromise, only in connection with immediate political
expediency. Fundamentally utopian, it strives for revolution – if not
political revolution in the narrow sense, then cultural revolution in the
broad sense – rather than reform. To succeed, its advocates must wipe the
slate clean and start over again. MacKinnon certainly understands this and,
taking her feminist theory of the state to its logical conclusion, says so
unequivocally. And lots of people, including legislators, like what they see
of it.
The “contested” definition of “equality,” then, is by no means a trivial
matter, of importance only to hairsplitting academics or nitpicking lawyers.
At stake is a worldview and its vision of society.
6
Maternal Rights v. Paternal Rights: The Case of
Children
In family law disputes, women are often fighting for the safety of
themselves and their children, while some men are fighting to maintain
power and control. Making custody and access decisions less formal will
not cause violence to disappear; it will simply remove the few existing
protections for women and children.1

Today, simply being a divorced father instantly subjects you to being treated
with contempt by your state government. State agencies universally regard
mothers as their customer to serve and protect, and fathers as forced
supplier, not gender-neutral parents of the same children.2

Consider the following case, that of a well-to-do household. “Michael” goes


to court in the hope of having the judge reduce his family-support
payments. On the surface, his case seems preposterous. After all, he earns
$158,000. The judge rejects his plea, perhaps not surprisingly, and orders
him to continue paying his former wife $7,153 every month. But that
amount represents 96% of his take-home pay; after deductions, he takes
home $7,455 every month. And after making his family-support payments,
he has only $302 on which to live. The fact is that even single men on
welfare in his city actually receive more money: $520. His son and former
wife, on the other hand, are hardly living at the poverty line. Was Michael
evil enough to have deserved this situation? Neither infidelity nor physical
violence caused his divorce. Nor, for that matter, did “psychological
violence.” It was caused, according to his wife, by the fact that he spent too
much time at work. When the local newspaper ran a story on deadbeat dads,
nevertheless, his sixteen-year-old son had this to say: “Dad, did you read
that article in The Star? Well that’s what I think of you.”3
Controversies over the rights of children often involve controversies
over the rights of women and men, and the former usually take precedence
over the latter – even if children are deprived as a result. Discussion has
been heavily dominated by a galaxy of interconnecting “interests”: feminist
advocacy groups lobbying for the economic betterment of divorced
mothers, specialized government bureaucracies that rely almost exclusively
on feminist analysis, collection agencies with vested interests in getting
more money from noncustodial parents (that is, by and large, from fathers),
and assorted academic experts, clinicians, lawyers, and journalists.
Collectively, they have been called the child-support industry. Because
some participants are government or social-service bureaucrats not engaged
in commerce as such, this phenomenon is industrial in a derived but
interesting sense. Many thousands of these people now earn their livings,
after all, by catering to needs created within their own bureaucracies. (More
about industrialization of that kind in chapter 7.) Despite the differences
between American and Canadian law, the situation in one country is
basically the same as that in the other.
After an introduction on the history of custody arrangements, we will
review the legislation governing divorce, custody, and child support, some
prevalent misconceptions about fathers, some of the resulting legal
problems, the current debate over law reform, and the link that this debate
reveals between gynocentrism and misandry.

Most people in our society now expect that the custody of children in cases
of divorce or separation will be awarded to mothers. It was not always so.
Roman law automatically awarded custody to fathers, a practice that
continued in Western countries long after the fall of Rome. Only in the
nineteenth century were questions raised about it. After a landmark case in
Britain, judges awarded custody of children under the age of seven to their
mothers and children over seven to their fathers. This practice produced the
“tender years doctrine.” But even that doctrine, which recognized the
importance of both mothers and fathers, was doomed by the Industrial
Revolution. For one thing, more and more fathers worked in factories. By
default, women became the primary caregivers at home. Moreover, fewer
and fewer fathers taught trades to their sons. The importance of fathers for
children, in short, was no longer so obvious.
By the 1920s, both society and the courts presumed (barring unusual
circumstances) that custody of children should be given to their mothers.
Even though legislators introduced gender-neutral laws in the 1960s, judges
still presumed that maternal custody was in “the best interest of the child.”4
And few fathers, on the advice of their lawyers, were prepared to argue with
them in court. Even fathers who did argue seldom won custody.5 At the
moment, things are beginning to change. Not, of course, to the presumption
of paternal custody. The trend is toward joint, or shared, custody. But even
that has been attacked by many feminists.
Child support is closely related to divorce and custody. Everyone agrees
that parents, both custodial (usually mothers) and noncustodial (usually
fathers), should provide economic support for their children. But child-
support arrangements, which might otherwise be settled according to the
child’s best interest, are now usually settled according to the wife’s best
interest, with child support often elided through legalistic legerdemain into
wife support. Even when they suspect that something is wrong, few men
know precisely what it is. Nonetheless, many have had to think carefully
about the concrete problems caused by separation from their children after
divorce. Fathers have begun to mobilize for law reform, in fact. Because at
least some women can see the need for even divorced fathers to remain
actively involved with their children – something that current laws often
discourage – this wing of the men’s movement is likely to find grudging
acceptance from them.
The controversy over divorce, custody, and child support is complex –
partly because of the byzantine legal principles that now govern family life
but mainly because of the ideological rhetoric that governs discussions of
it.6 Two arguments in particular function as trump cards; merely alluding to
them, which is done over and over again in every possible context, drives
every other consideration out the window. One argument is that men
demanding rights as fathers are dishonest and actually have no interest in
their children. What they really want, allegedly, is to control their former
wives. The other argument is that many of these men are actually violent or
perverted. Giving them a legal right to joint custody, therefore, would mean
exposing women and children to danger. These arguments and similar ones
(which we document in appendix 9) are flawed on close examination, but
constant repetition has by now made them seem like conventional wisdom.
Repeat a lie often enough, someone once said, and it becomes the truth.
In the United States, child support has been regulated at the federal level by
resorting to the Constitution’s Commerce Clause. Section 8 describes the
power of Congress to collect taxes, provide for common defense, and
promote general welfare; article 1 gives Congress the authority to “regulate
Commerce with foreign Nations, and among the several States, and with the
Indian Tribes.” What can commerce possibly have to do with child support?
The convoluted reasoning is that people who owe support might try to
avoid payment by moving across state lines. This can be prevented by
federal authorities, advocates argue, because “interstate commerce” is
regulated by the federal government. But child support is surely not
commerce. Never mind. Even though the intention of the Commerce Clause
was originally to facilitate free trade across state lines, according to Wendy
McElroy, it was gradually given broader interpretations.7 Feminists saw in
those interpretations ideal opportunities to further their own interests, using
the Commerce Clause to argue for federal, or “interstate,” regulation of
child support. Federal jurisdiction not only solved the immediate problem
of men crossing state lines to avoid child support but also gave the problem
a higher profile and provided efforts to solve it with better funding. How
did we get to this point?
The story began in 1975. Feminist groups were delighted when President
Ford established the Office of Child Support Enforcement (OCSE). He
warned them, even so, that this office would amount to a federal intrusion
into the powers of both states and families. No matter. There were more
important things to worry about. Stephen Baskerville shows how interest
groups, including some feminist ones, “demonized divorced fathers into
‘deadbeat dads’ and then criminalized them.”8 Men who refused to pay up
were the topic of a journalistic feeding frenzy. The problem, it was said, had
become a national scandal (even though the Government Accounting Office
noted that “95% of fathers having no employment problems for the past
five years pay regularly; 81% in full and on time”).9 Taking its marching
orders from public opinion as mediated by journalists and talk show hosts,
as usual, legislatures across the country raced to come up with corrective
measures.
The federal program increased in size ten times between 1978 and
1998.10 Bill O’Reilly, the host of one talk show, declared a national
“epidemic of child abandonment in America, mainly by fathers.”11 Senator
Evan Bayh attacked “irresponsible” fathers in several speeches. Liberal
Democrat Al Gore promised voters harsher measures against “deadbeat
dads” if he was elected and promised to imprison more of them. Even
earlier, President Clinton had urged his administration to plan a “crack
down” on irresponsible fathers. To track them down, officials were given
two new resources: the Directory of New Hires (which lists all new
employees in the country) and the Federal Case Registry (a massive
surveillance system that monitors between sixteen and nineteen million
citizens). And Republicans, never soft on maintaining the traditional family
or afraid to call for law and order, soon followed suit. President George W.
Bush announced a $320-million program to “promote responsible
fatherhood,” and Congress considered a bill to “reconnect fathers with their
families.” Sounds okay. But the underlying plan was that of the Democrats,
according to Baskerville. Both parties wanted to extract more money from
fathers.
Here, though, is the background story. Society experienced a “divorce
revolution” and the rise of a “divorce culture.”12 Divorces are usually
initiated by women, as it happens, at least partly because feminism has
convinced them of the need for greater autonomy – which is to say,
liberation from men and marriage. Trouble is, divorce involves a financial
strain on women (and men). Experts produced exaggerated statistics on the
sorry economic plight of women following divorce, which led to anxiety for
women but also to guilt for society as a whole. And that, in turn, led to
successful political action by and for women as victims of men. In practical
terms, the result was to reinforce the claim that wives should get enough
money from their former husbands to maintain their standard of living
before divorce. Those who could not get it directly as alimony found ways
of getting it indirectly as a by-product of child support. Third, many women
claimed sole custody. Some believed that children belonged, in effect, to
their mothers. Others were genuinely worried about violence or molestation
by the fathers.
Congress passed welfare legislation in 1984 that required states to adopt
not only guidelines for the payment of child support but also formulae to
increase amounts. Baskerville notes that these guidelines and formulae had
been promoted by the OCSE, which argued that making noncustodial parents
(usually fathers) pay more would get custodial parents (usually single
mothers) off welfare.13 In other words, an important but hidden goal was to
solve a larger problem than the poverty of children: the “feminization of
poverty.” The trouble was that many of these fathers were themselves on
welfare; few were economically stable enough to pay higher amounts or
even the current amounts. As a result, the government could not collect
enough to take many mothers off welfare. No one cared that men on welfare
or with low incomes were impoverished due to new demands. The Bradley
Amendment (or Omnibus Budget Reconciliation Act) of 1986 altered the
Social Security Act to prevent “retroactive modification of child support
awards or arrearage for any reason, ever.”14 That was just the beginning.
In 1988, the net was expanded to catch more middle-class fathers, even
though there was no evidence of need, and the amount of money expected
from them was increased. The new guidelines targeted not only those on
welfare, in other words, but also those not on welfare. Being employed,
they could presumably pay at higher rates than those who were
unemployed. As a result, federal collection agencies could show evidence
that they were collecting more money for women and tightening the screws
on “deadbeat dads.”15 The Family Support Act required state agencies to
administer all cases (not only welfare cases), garnish the wages of all
noncustodial parents automatically (including those with spouses who did
not require the money), introduce paternity-testing programs, and deny
passports to noncustodial parents who owed more than five thousand
dollars. In addition, it required written explanations for not following state
guidelines from judges who adapted them to particular circumstances and
therefore seldom went against the guidelines.16
The Child Support Recovery Act of 1996 made “the willful failure to
pay a past due support obligation [of more than $5,000] with respect to a
child residing in another state a federal offense … A first violation … is
punishable by two years imprisonment and/or a fine. The F.B.I. has primary
investigatory jurisdiction. Additionally, Special Agents of the Office of the
Inspector General of the United States Department of Health and Human
Services have been given authority to investigate violations …”17 The aim
was to prevent noncustodial parents from changing jobs, concealing assets,
using false names and social security numbers, moving to other states in
order to avoid paying (or moving after being served notice of contempt of
court for not paying), and so on. Some situations, according to this act,
require immediate intervention by the federal government: when custodial
parents or their children need expensive medical care, have problems due to
handicaps, or are threatened with eviction. Other situations involve federal
charges: bankruptcy fraud (concealing assets), bank fraud, tax evasion
(false statements), or other crimes.18 Offenders may be fined, in addition to
being charged for the amount in arrears, or imprisoned.
The Welfare Reform Act of 1996 allowed the federal government to
improve its methods of surveillance with potential seizures in mind. By
1998, for instance, all companies would have to report new employees and
their wages to a new central data base. By 1999, all financial institutions
would have to comply with government requests for information on
accounts; non custodial parents in arrears would lose their driver’s or other
licences. Child support orders would have to include health coverage (in
addition to basic child support). And states would have to identify 90% of
unmarried fathers or lose their federal reimbursements and incentive
payments.
Also in 1998 the Child Support Recovery Act was amended by the
Dead-beat Parents Punishment Act. This measure increased both the status
of violations and the penalties. Here was a formal act of Congress that used
the very informal word “deadbeat” in its title. That alone should have made
citizens suspicious. Although the gender-neutral word “parents” followed it,
everyone knew that “dads” were targeted. Mothers were almost always
given custody of children, after all, and fathers given instructions to pay for
their support.
The Hyde-Woolsey Act,19 introduced in 1999 but never passed, involved
the Internal Revenue Service. This act would have required “all employers
to withhold child support payments and send them to the I.R.S. The I.R.S.
would then distribute the withheld amount to custodial parents owed child
support. The bill would also [have treated] child support obligations as
taxes for purposes of penalties and interest related to failure to have them
withheld by employers.”20 Amounts were already being withheld by
employers, of course, but bringing in the Internal Revenue Service would
have introduced an even more aggressive collection agency with more
extreme penalties for infractions. This bill, however, died in committee.
More recently, in 2000, the Department of Health and Human Services
ruled that noncustodial parents owing more than $2,500 in child support
would no longer be eligible for food stamps.
In Canada, child support is defined by the federal Divorce Act of 1985
and the Federal Child Support Guidelines of 1997.21 Underlying these
guidelines is the Formula for the Tables of Amounts Contained in the
Guidelines. Child support is collected, on the other hand, by provincial
agencies. In Ontario, for instance, the Family Responsibility Office is in
change of collections under the Family Responsibility and Support Arrears
Enforcement Act of 1996. This office receives all support orders and
enforces them. It operates by garnishing wages, bank accounts (up to 50%),
and funds from federal sources such as income tax refunds or employment
insurance benefits. If necessary, it reports noncustodial parents to the credit
bureau, seizes their bank accounts or other assets (including registered
retirement saving plans), suspends their passports, suspends their driver’s
licenses, and takes them to court.22 Canadian legislation serves the same
purpose, in short, as American legislation.

Many observers have pointed out that our culture fosters a whole lot of
misconceptions – no pun intended – about fathers. In the first part of
Divorced Dads, Sanford Braver challenges those who have collectively had
a profound and pervasive influence on the American legal system
governing divorced fathers.23 A psychologist who led the largest federally
funded research project on divorced fathers,24 he isolated six primary
“myths” about divorced fathers: that they are usually the ones who either
initiate divorce or trigger it by abandoning their families,25 that they usually
have most of the legal advantages in negotiating divorce and custody
arrangements,26 that they experience a climb in their standard of living and
their ex-wives a decline,27 that they are in better emotional health than their
ex-wives,28 that they seldom bother to continue supporting their
children,29and that they seldom bother even to stay in contact with them.30
Do husbands abandon their marriages more often than wives? Some
people argue that men have more to gain economically from divorce than
women and that they are therefore more likely than women to initiate
proceedings. Other people argue that men are more irresponsible than
women and thus more likely to cause the problems that lead to divorce. Still
others argue that there are too many women looking for husbands;31 men
are in a better bargaining position than women and therefore in a better
position to find new partners or at least to initiate divorce proceedings when
things go wrong.
But the fact is that approximately two-thirds of divorces in the United
States are initiated by women,32 and the rate is even higher in
Canada.33From the ideological perspective of some feminists, the reason is
very simple. Marriage, they believe, is an inherently patriarchal institution
and thus inherently oppressive for women even without violence. No
wonder they want out. But studies have shown that other explanations are
more likely. “If women can anticipate a clear gender bias in the courts
regarding custody,” writes Candis McLean, “they can expect to be the
primary residential parent for the children. If they can anticipate
enforcement of financial child support by the courts, they can expect a high
probability of support monies without the need to account for their
expenditures. Clearly they can also anticipate maintaining the marital
residence, receiving half of all marital property and gaining total freedom to
establish new social relationships.”34 If they stand to gain so much from
divorce, in other words, why put more effort into making the marriage
work? This is an interesting, but cynical, explanation. According to
Baskerville’s more charitable one, divorcing women no longer feel loved or
appreciated.35 But there are other explanations.
In order to find out why men and women initiate divorce proceedings,
economists Margaret Brinig and Douglas Allen conducted a massive study
of divorce, analyzing all forty-six thousand divorce suits filed during 1995
in four states: Connecticut, Virginia, Montana, and Oregon.36 Although one
reason for women is to get away from violent or adulterous husbands, “in
the state with the best records of grievances, Virginia, only 6 percent of
divorces were granted on grounds of violence, and husbands were cited for
adultery only slightly more often than wives.” Another reason is “the belief
that your partner is no longer good enough for you. The classic example is
the guy who takes a trophy wife after dumping the high-school sweetheart
who sacrificed her own potential to put him through medical school, but a
woman can be similarly tempted to leave a husband who is less successful
than she is.”37 What then?
The solution to the mystery, the factor that determined most cases, turned
out to be the question of child custody. Women are much more willing to
split up because – unlike men – they typically do not fear losing custody of
the children. Instead a divorce often enables them to gain control over the
children.

“The question of custody absolutely swamps all the other variables,” Dr.
Brinig said. “Children are the most important asset in a marriage, and the
partner who expects to get sole custody is by far the most likely to file for
divorce.”
The correlation with custody is so strong, Dr. Brinig said, that she has
changed her view about the best way to preserve marriages and protect
children. She previously advocated an end to quick no-fault divorces, but
she now believes that the key is to rewrite custody laws.38
Robert Seidenberg discusses yet another explanation, one that should be
taken seriously by researchers at least as a possibility.

Abandoning one’s children is not a “normal” thing to do. It is natural for a


father to love his children. For most fathers only extreme circumstances
could force the breaking of this bond. Consider too, how difficult it must be
to pick up and leave, not only one’s children, but one’s home town, family,
friends, and job, and how difficult it is to enter an underground cash
economy – all to avoid supporting one’s own children! Someone would
literally have to be crazy to do this, unless there were extraordinary
pressures to uproot.

For fathers who have gone many rounds with the courts, lost their
children, had their property seized, had their wages garnisheed [sic], and
spent time in jail, flight becomes a rational alternative. Deadbeat Dads are
men who have “voted with their feet.” They would more appropriately be
called “Refugee Dads” or “Fathers in Exile.”39
The second misconception is that divorced fathers are better equipped
than mothers to negotiate separation,40 divorce, and custody. Although both
men and women complain about their problems, many people are prepared
to believe that women – members of an official or unofficial victim class –
are at a relative disadvantage. Feminists have argued, and not only in this
context, that laws were made by and presumably for men.41 Or that the
judges are usually men. Or that men are richer than women and can afford
better lawyers. Or that men are more aggressive and thus better equipped
for legal battles. Braver points out that not one of these arguments is
legitimate, certainly not now. And he is not the only one. “In terms of
commanding federal dollars, electing politicians, enacting legislation,
controlling academic discourse, and influencing media to promote their
cause,” writes Seidenberg, “the feminist movement is one of the most
powerful political forces in the United States today. Unfortunately, the
public, including the middle-class professional men most affected by
custody litigation, still tends to perceive feminists as the near-powerless
victims they portray themselves to be. Judges, however, are astute political
creatures; they understand the extent of feminist political power and act
accordingly.”42
The third misconception is that divorce brings men a higher standard of
living and women a lower one. It would be hard to exaggerate the
importance of this claim. Yet several investigators have shown that this
assumption is false. Here is what happened. Lenore Weitzman published
The Divorce Revolution in 1985, reporting that while the average mother
lost 73% of her income after divorce, the average father gained 42%.43 This
“fact,” supposedly discovered by the Harvard researcher, has been cited as
grounds for divorce and custody legislation ever since. As Geoffrey
Christopher Rapp and others have pointed out, however, Weitzman got the
math wrong. Other researchers were unable to duplicate her findings, and
she was unwilling to provide them with access to her files. No matter. Since
1985 her startling but false figures have been quoted repeatedly by
politicians, academics, social workers, lawyers, judges, and journalists.44
Rapp, who works for CNN, pointed out that Weitzman’s claim “has become
one of the philosophical bases for deciding child custody and property
division in divorce cases. It has also altered public perceptions of men,
women and divorce. It was cited hundreds of times … and was regarded so
clearly as holy writ that President Clinton cited it too in his budget proposal
… as part of his attack on deadbeat dads.”45 Eventually, of course, the full
story came out. It was a hoax, just like the one about violence against
women peaking on Super Bowl Sunday, the one about 150,000 women
dying every year from anorexia, and so on (which we discuss in appendix
3). But the damage had been done, and not everyone really cared about why
or how.
The fourth misconception is that divorced fathers are more satisfied than
mothers, emotionally, with the results of divorce and loss of custody. As for
divorce itself, Braver writes that ex-husbands find it harder to let go of their
wives than for ex-wives to let go of their ex-husbands.46 (On the other
hand, he adds, ex-husbands find it easier than their ex-wives to let go of
their anger.)47 Ex-husbands often find it harder to adjust to divorce than
their ex-wives. “The one who leaves the marriage holds all the power.
Consequently, the one being left – most often the man – feels utterly
powerless because he can do nothing to prevent the breakup of the
marriage.48 This is a matter not so much of losing power but of losing self-
esteem. Women, by contrast – even if we judge only from what they so
often tell Oprah Winfrey on television – often feel “empowered” by
divorce.
Loss of custody presents a much more severe emotional problem.
Custodial parents, almost always mothers, gain valued roles. As they
become breadwinners and heads of their households, their self-esteem
grows. But noncustodial parents, almost always fathers, lose these valued
roles. As a result, their self-esteem withers.49 Besides, divorced mothers
usually have more extensive support networks than divorced fathers. At the
very least, they usually have their children to provide them with emotional
support.
Gender expectations make the problem even worse for divorced fathers.
Men are expected to suffer in silence no matter what happens to them.
“Whereas a mother who has lost custody of her children elicits …
immediate sympathy for the hurt the loss must cause her, fathers are
somehow expected not to suffer equally when the same happens to them.”50
Indeed, they are usually suspected of having caused their divorces in the
first place.
But what about “visitation rights”? Braver agrees with David Blanken-
horn, a pioneer on this topic, who says that divorce and fatherhood, by
definition, are irreconcilable. The challenge for many is almost
insurmountable. A father with permission to receive his children as visitors
must

devise, essentially unassisted, an entirely new household for those


occasions when his children come to visit. He must start over, reinvent
everything, construct an alternative family life with his children – complete
with new rules, new routines, new expectations, and new father-child
relationships. Most crucially, he must accomplish this feat in a home in
which his children do not live … [and in which] virtually all parental
control resides with the custodial parent. Compared to the mother, the father
is largely without power or even knowledge … Visiting father-hood almost
always becomes disempowered fatherhood, a simulacrum of paternal
capacity.51

The result, as everyone knows, is that fathers in this position focus on


merely entertaining their children and supplying them with presents. In
other words, they try to become big friends rather than real fathers. And
children can tell the difference. They know that love and respect cannot be
bought.
A system that can take away most of a seriously involved father’s
income has driven many to destitution and some to suicide.52 According to
sociologist Augustine Kposowa, longitudinal studies show that divorced
men are nine times as likely as divorced women to commit suicide.53 Given
the draconian measures taken by countless bureaucrats and sixty thousand
plainclothes agents – garnishing the wages of delinquent fathers, using
computers to trace their whereabouts, revoking their licenses (even if their
jobs depend on driving), confiscating their assets, and throwing them in jail
but not necessarily allowing them any contact with their children – how
many of us would not, placed in that position, become desperate?54
The fifth misconception is that divorced fathers seldom bother to support
their children. According to the study by Brinig and Allen, couples are
statistically less likely to divorce in states that presume joint custody. And
when they do, fathers are less likely to lag behind in their child support
payments. In fact, the compliance rate is 87% to 90%.55 “‘Custody is now a
way – in some marriages the only way – for women to achieve a real show
of force over men,’ Dr. Brinig said. ‘If you remove that distortion, it’s apt to
change the way men and women relate to each other and to their kids.
Fathers are likely to spend more time with kids if they can expect to still see
them if the marriage doesn’t work out. Women will be more likely to see
men as parenting partners, and less likely to use divorce as a power
play.’”56
For all the feminist rhetoric against deadbeat dads, Ronald Henry notes,
“when mothers are ordered to pay child support, their compliance rate is
lower than that of fathers.”57 Braver, too, discusses this problem.

Virtually all the researchers who arrived at the conclusion that fathers are
overwhelmingly not paying child support used only one source of data in
arriving at their findings: the custodial mothers … The same bias, of course,
would likely apply to any answers given by the non-custodial parent … For
the Census officials and other researchers to come to their conclusions by
asking only mothers and not allowing fathers to be heard, is equivalent to a
judge making a decision in a case after denying one party to a disagreement
the opportunity to take the stand. No judge would think of doing this, and
our system of justice specifically precludes it, because we intuitively realize
that people tend to tell their story in a way that makes themselves look good
and their adversary look bad … mothers furnish the information about
whether they are receiving child support, and divorced mothers can hardly
be considered unbiased sources … Not a single one of the previous
researchers or census officials indicated that questioning only mothers may
have been a problem. Nowhere in any published reference to the figures
was the appropriate qualifying phrase “according to the custodial parent”
included.58

The sixth misconception is that divorced fathers spend little or no time


with their children. They are known as “runaway dads.” Has there been an
epidemic of fathers abandoning their children? Braver found that very few
fathers did so. Those who did, moreover, almost always did so because of
unemployment. Actually, he argues, mothers are implicated in the problem.

According to the evidence we examined, vastly fewer fathers than


conventional wisdom recognizes appear to have stopped seeing their
children and become the runaway dads the bad divorce-dad image portrays.
And what about the ones who have disconnected from their children? The
answer … suggests that non-visitation, which is undeniably harmful to most
children (as well as the father), is caused substantially by mothers’
recalcitrance. Clearly, in the view of fathers, more contact is prevented by
the choices of the custodial parent, not by their own choice. And most
disturbing, many fathers whose visitation rights have been trampled on have
little legal recourse to become what society loudly proclaims it wants of
them: to be a father to their child.59

Some fathers do become “runaway dads,” true, but that is no reason for the
system to encourage this phenomenon.

At least six problems are inherent in our legal systems: systemic bias
against fathers, gross inefficiency, Kafkaesque bureaucracies, scams that
serve the interests of everyone but fathers and children, the criminalization
of fathers, and vested interests.
Systemic bias against fathers prevails in the methods used to calculate
child support payments. Some of these methods were created for welfare
families but extended to middle-class families, for instance, which distorts
calculations for the latter.60 Here is a partial list of the flawed assumptions
on which they are based:
• authorities use various mathematical models to calculate support
payments, but each is of dubious value for one reason or another;61
• they ignore the income of custodial parents, which leaves all costs to
non-custodial parents;62
• they assume that children should have the same standard of living as
they had before, even though this is usually a very unrealistic goal for
non-custodial parents, who must support two or more households
instead of one;63
• they assume that the amount collected from non-custodial parents
should rise as their income rises, even though income has nothing to
do with the actual cost of maintaining children;64
• they assume that non-custodial parents will have little or no contact
with their children,65 even though they might live together almost
half of the time, and they therefore ignore the fact that noncustodial
parents must pay not only for all expenses while the children are
living with them but also for all expenses while the children are
living with their custodial parents;66
• they assume that only custodial parents deserve tax breaks such as
credits and deductions;67 and
• they assume that the amount should be fixed and therefore unrelated
to specific or changing circumstances such as the ages of children
(costs varying considerably according to age), the existence of
previous or later children, and even the fact that some “children”
have become adults.68

We would add here that these schemes are flawed for political reasons, too.
According to Roger Gay, the amounts awarded are often increased
arbitrarily because of pressure from feminist lobby groups.69 Fathers pay
heavily in lawyer and court costs to fight these arbitrarily increased
amounts.
One result of systemic bias against divorced fathers is to support the
assumption that they become “deadbeat dads” due to lack of interest in their
children, since the law penalizes those who actually do try to take an active
interest in their children. Why be surprised or even shocked, therefore,
when many fathers act accordingly? This is a self-fulfilling prophecy.
Another result is to support the glorification of single mothers. If single
mothers can do everything necessary for their children, helped only by child
support payments or welfare payments, then why expect fathers to take an
active interest in family life at all? (Did we say “glorification”? Yes, we did.
More about that in due course.) Yet other results include destitution and
occasionally even suicide.70 Consider the case of a Canadian man. He had
been married to his employer, a physician who had paid him a handsome
salary and wrote off the expenses for tax purposes. When they divorced, he
had to take an eight-dollar-an-hour job. Nonetheless, he was required to pay
child support based on the much higher salary earned previously. He lost
more money by trying to get the payment adjusted to his new
circumstances. (Noncustodial parents are forced to spend a lot of money, by
the way, if they decide to challenge court rulings.) Once, when he was two
days late, his ex-wife tried to have him jailed. Forced to live in his car, he
committed suicide in 1999 by inhaling the exhaust fumes.71
The second problem inherent in our legal systems is inefficiency.
Nicholas Riccardi and Greg Krikorion present some telling examples of
injustice in the United States due to sheer inefficiency – inefficiency that,
we strongly suspect, would never be tolerated if women suffered from it.
Officials of Los Angeles County have admitted, for instance, to going after
the wrong men for child support payments approximately 350 times a
month.72 Many men are never even informed of their child custody hearings
and are then charged huge amounts in arrears, although required payments
are sometimes impossibly high in any case. They must pay up, moreover,
even if access to their children is legally denied or illegally prevented. And
when their wages decline, their required payments do not. According to
K.C. Wilson, the evidence of compliance with American child support
legislation is less than edifying after two decades of reform. “Billions of
dollars a year, hundreds of thousands of fathers in jail, seized assets,
suspended licences, terminated business, and government taking on the
management of all child support has not [increased] compliance.”73 And
what does all that mean for women? “Single mothers are no better off.
Indeed, [the system] may be counter-productive.”74 Wilson suggests several
reasons. The system is impersonal. Many of these men are in jail, too,
which hardly helps them pay up. The amounts required, in short, push too
many men beyond their ability to pay.75
The third problem involves Kafkaesque bureaucracies. Some cases are
truly ludicrous. One American father had to support an adult. Why?
Because child support ends only when children leave school, under federal
law, which can occur many years after they come of age. A minor was
forced to support a child of the adult woman who had been convicted of
statutorily raping him. An octogenarian invalid was forced to support a
child of the housekeeper who had assaulted him. A man shackled with an
electronic ankle bracelet was forced to support his twenty-one-year-old
“child” at college even though his twelve-year-old child lacked medical
care.76 In Canada, too, fathers have been forced to support adult children.
These cases are anomalous, it is true, but enough of them occur to indicate
the need for correction in the name of, if nothing else, common sense.
The fourth problem involves scams. Fostered directly or indirectly by
systemic bias against fathers, scams often indicate collusion between public
and private interests. Robert Williams, a paid consultant with the United
States Department of Health and Human Services, created a scheme to
increase the amount of child support significantly: two and a half times as
much as the earlier system. When Congress produced a deadline for states
to adopt his scheme if they wanted to continue receiving federal funds,
many did so. Meanwhile, Williams was developing his own child support
consulting business and collection agency: Policy Studies Inc. By 1996, he
had more contracts than anyone else in the private sector. Moreover, the
number of his employees had grown from three to five hundred, and his
company received between 10% and 32% of all the money collected.77
When child support payments were high, there were many delinquents.
When collection was left to the private sector, therefore, he made a lot of
money. As for the states, they made between 6% and 10% on each dollar
collected. In addition, they received two-thirds of the operating costs of the
scheme and 90% of the computer costs. The federal government spent over
$2 billion in 1996, according to Baskerville, which meant that California
was able to collect $144 million and New York $49.1 million.78
Officials and scholars often rely on questionable or even false statistics,
as Lenore Weitzman and the bureaucrats who were influenced by her did, to
legitimate the bias. In Canada, however, the government itself actually
resorted to covering up its bias. Remember the formula that was appended
to the Guidelines? This was appended only in theory. It was very hard for
anyone to find either the formula or information about it. Even members of
Parliament had not seen it when they passed the guidelines into law! After
almost two years, an eight-page report on the formula was published.79 And
its circulation list was very restricted.80 The Family Law Committee of the
Canadian Bar Association was excluded, for instance, as were justices of
the Supreme Court. Member of Parliament Roger Gall-away had to invoke
the Freedom of Information Act to get his copy. “Documents recently
released by the Department of Justice under a Freedom of Information
request,” writes Alar Soever, “indicate that a conscious decision was made
by the Department of Justice to limit circulation of this report.”81 We find it
astonishing that someone had to use the Freedom of Information Act to find
basic information on the economic condition of so many citizens. But that is
how ideological interest groups operate: behind the scenes rather than in
full view, very often, or through bureaucracies rather than legislatures.
According to evidence presented by Soever, at any rate, the Child
Support Team of Justice Canada, which created the formula, feared that
releasing it would raise awkward questions. And with good reason. They
must have known that it would inevitably result in serious disadvantages for
noncustodial parents, including those who make their payments. Knowing
that publication would be delayed, the Child Support Team noted in a
summary for the minister of justice that its focus had been on
implementation rather than theory and that, in any case, the document was
too technical for anyone who was not a mathematician or an economist!
Why, then, tax the intelligence of ordinary citizens?82 Glenn Cheriton
points out, moreover, that officials removed two male economists from the
child support team and left only female lawyers.83 This arrogance would
have caused an uproar if word had leaked out in time.
The most common kind of scam involves paternity fraud: when a woman
cheats on her partner and gives birth to another man’s baby but her partner
nevertheless has to pay child support.84 The problem faced by Carnell
Smith, for instance, is not only ludicrous but also disturbing. Here is his
story. American law presumes that children born within wedlock are those
of the husband. So why does Smith, who is not the biological father of his
former girlfriend’s child, still have to pay child support? He took his case
through the lower courts. Unsuccessful, he took it to the Supreme Court. On
12 June 2002, the Supreme Court refused to hear it.85 But many paternity
tests, 28% of them in 1999, reveal that the presumed fathers are not in fact
the biological ones.86 Smith’s case rested on the grounds of “fraud
deception,” because the “victim is persecuted for the actions of the guilty
party” (that is, the biological father).87 This is unheard of in any other
circumstances. We will return to one important implication of this case.
Meanwhile, here is another case.
Damon Adams had a DNA test which showed that he was not the father
of a ten-year-old girl born during his former marriage. But the Michigan
court rejected this evidence and ordered him to continue paying $23,000 a
year in child support. Adams, like many other men across the country,
lobbied the state legislature to prohibit paternity fraud. Approximately a
dozen states have done so.88 But others, including Michigan, cite what they
consider more important interests. “Most states design their family laws,”
writes Martin Kanisdorf, “to protect what they call ‘the interests of the
child.’ That means siding with the child’s financial and emotional needs and
against supposed fathers who want to avoid paying for tricycles and braces.
Taxpayers also have a big stake in child support collections, which have
grown to $18 billion annually and cover 20 million children. If men who
are paying child support no longer have to and authorities can’t find the real
fathers, welfare agencies will get the bill for family assistance.”89 In other
words, the laudable goal of protecting children gives the state license to
disregard the rights of adult citizens and even to reward those who violate
the law. Kanisdorf’s overtly cynical mentality is evident from his
assumption that the only fathers affected are rich men who cannot be
bothered to pay for the necessities of children, even, in some cases, the
children of wives who are having affairs with other men. If biological
fathers cannot be found (which might not be a problem in the first place if
everyone was given a DNA test at birth just as everyone is now fingerprinted
at birth), then it is surely more fitting for a community to bear the cost out
of compassion than for innocent citizens to be punished out of sheer
political expediency. That turns them into scapegoats for public fear and
outrage over social breakdown.
Moreover, Kanisdorf ignores one important need of children: the need to
know who their biological fathers are and thus who they themselves are.
Has that become irrelevant to legislators? As one father, paying $1,400 a
month for a child whom he has never met and who was the result of his
wife’s adultery, put it, “I can get out of jail for murder based on DNA
evidence, but I can’t [use DNA evidence to] get out of child support
payments.”90 Meanwhile, financially strapped, he and his new wife and
their three children live with his in-laws, and he has lost his driver’s license
for missing support payments.
There are women who deliberately become pregnant by refusing to take
the pill, not telling their partners, and then refusing to have abortions.
Nonetheless, some of them claim child support. This situation prompted
Peter Wallis to sue his former girlfriend. “Some say that it is his
responsibility to ensure that such an ‘accident’ does not happen,” says Mary
Ann Sieghart. “He could have worn a condom. That is true, but a
relationship in which people are living together, as these two were,
presupposes a certain level of trust.”91 Moreover, says Sieghart, this case
brings up an analogy that should disturb women. They are allowed either to
abort or not to abort, after all, and with or without the knowledge of fathers.
But what about an analogous right to choose for men? Wallis did not choose
to have a child (which makes him analogous to a woman who fails to use
contraception), but he could not insist on an abortion (even though a
pregnant woman would be allowed to end her pregnancy) and therefore
ended up by being ordered to pay child support for years to come. Women
who make mistakes are allowed an escape clause, in short, but men who
make mistakes are told to shut up and pay up.
In view of all these scams concocted by both private individuals and
public institutions, Baskerville comments on how hard it would be for
Americans not to believe “that a lucrative racket now is cynically using our
children as weapons and tools to enrich lawyers and provide employment
for judges and bureaucrats. Rather than pursuing ever greater numbers of
fathers with ever more draconian punishments, the Justice Department
should be investigating the kind of crimes it was created to pursue – such as
kidnapping, extortion and racketeering – in the nation’s family courts.”92
The statistics on fathers who abandon their families are insignificant, he
adds, when compared with those that indicate “the scale on which families
are being taken over by a destructive and dangerous machine consisting of
judges, lawyers, psychotherapists, social workers, bureaucrats and women’s
groups.”93
Paternity fraud is a problem in Canada, too.94 A man in Ontario was
forced to pay the full amount for a son, even though the boy had been kept
away from him since birth and even though the boy’s adoptive father, too,
was paying the full amount. Listen to the morally dubious reasoning
proclaimed by the Court of Appeal in that case: “While it is true that neither
[the child] nor Mr. Zaver has had the opportunity of a personal relationship
with the other, Mr. Zaver has had a holiday from support for many years.
There is no indication that it will be an undue financial burden for him to
pay support in accordance with the Ontario guidelines.”95 This is why
fathers are now lobbying to make DNA testing mandatory at or before birth
and also to abolish the obligation of paying child support in cases of fraud.
The “experts” have said very little about the biological connection
between fathers and their children. That silence has been challenged by
fathers who demand DNA tests to establish paternity and thus eliminate the
possibility of being forced to pay for children who could and should be
supported by their biological fathers. Some women resist that change. For
one thing, it might reveal that they have had liaisons with men other than
their current husbands or partners. If the latter turn out not to be the
biological fathers, moreover, these women might be left with all the
expenses. At any rate, the current system is one of several factors that
combine to blur the biological facts and trivialize the biological importance
of father-hood. (More about single mothers and reproductive autonomy for
women in due course.)96
This desire to blur biological facts helps explain another ruling of the
Ontario Court of Appeal, letting mothers have sole authority for providing
their children with surnames. It said that “a mother can acknowledge a
father for custody or child support reasons but does not have to
acknowledge him on a birth registry for naming purposes.”97 Here is the
reason cited by Justice Kathryn Feldman: “[T]here will be circumstances
where a mother will have the ongoing responsibility for the child, and
should not be forced to have the child linked by name with the biological
father.”98 How to explain the discrepancy between acknowledging him
when it comes to paying for child support but refusing to do so when it
comes to naming his child? This explanation was offered: “Because
acknowledgement involves a volitional act of admitting knowledge of a
fact, it is possible for a person to acknowledge something to be true in one
context, but to decline to do so in another context.”99 This double talk
amounts to sheer moral expediency. According to earlier rules, if “the
mother acknowledges the father in the birth registry and both parents certify
the child’s birth but do not agree on a surname, the child shall be given a
surname consisting of both parents’ surnames hyphenated in alphabetical
order.”100 The same controversy arose in British Columbia. That province’s
Court of Appeal had made a similar ruling the year before. But when it was
appealed to Canada’s Supreme Court, the judge ruled that fathers should, in
fact, have their names on birth certificates.101
The fifth problem inherent in our legal systems is that divorced fathers
are criminalized in both the United States and Canada, directly in the
former and indirectly in the latter. In the United States, all noncustodial
parents – and they include those who do comply with child support
regulations – are now being monitored by the criminal-justice system and
thus being treated as criminals or potential criminals. “Under the guise of
pursuing deadbeat dads,” writes Baskerville, “we now are seeing mass
incarcerations without trial, without charge and without counsel, while the
media and civil libertarians look the other way. We also have government
officials freely entering the homes and raiding the bank accounts of citizens
who are accused of nothing and simply helping themselves to whatever they
find – including their children, their life savings and their private papers and
effects, all with hardly a word of protest noted.”102 Not only are problem
cases filtered through criminal enforcement agencies, moreover, but so are
all cases of child support. Otherwise, states would not be eligible for federal
funds. “This both further criminalizes the fathers and enables the
government to inflate the amount of collections it makes,” says Baskerville,
“which helps divert attention from the fact that the program operates at a
consistent loss.”103
This creates a situation that would endanger any free society. “Never
before,” said the Washington Post, ”have federal officials had the legal
authority and technological ability … to keep tabs on Americans accused of
nothing.”104 Fathers are under surveillance merely because they pay child
support. The situation is ominous, according to Steve Dasbach, in view of
the precedents in totalitarian societies. “[G]overnment bureaucrats will soon
have the power to deny you a job, and the ability to monitor your income,
assets, and debts … This law turns the presumption of innocence on its
head and forces every American to prove their innocence to politicians,
bureaucrats, and computers.”105 And surveillance is by no means the only
problem. As Baskerville points out, guilt and innocence are fatally blurred
“since officials are monitoring citizens who owe [money for child support],
those whose obligations are paid up, and those who are not under any order
at all. The presumption of guilt against those who are obeying the law was
revealed by one official who boasted to the [Washington] Post that ‘we
don’t give them an opportunity to become deadbeats.’” When a
noncustodial father is charged with civil contempt, he “must prove his
innocence without a formal charge, without counsel, and without facing a
jury of his peers.”106 The burden of proof is often on defendants. And
fathers are put in jail without trial. “Those who face trumped-up accusations
of child abuse also must prove their innocence before they can hope to see
their children. Yet now it is well established that most child abuse takes
place in the homes of single mothers. A recent study from the Department
of Health and Human Services, or HHS, found that “almost two-thirds [of
child abusers] were females.” Given that male perpetrators are not
necessarily fathers but much more likely to be boyfriends and stepfathers,
fathers emerge as the least likely child abusers.”107
Canadian laws governing child support are civil, not criminal. Even so,
courts have the authority to put offenders in jail. In some ways, civil law
creates even more problems for the accused than criminal law. In criminal
cases, after all, defendants are entitled to lawyers and legal aid. Not so in
civil cases. The courts need not provide either in default hearings, for
instance, if defendants lack proof of insufficient income.
The sixth problem involves vested interests, which people at all levels of
the legal system want to protect. Think of the political factors involved.
American judges are appointed at the higher levels and elected in some
states at lower levels. Either way, the process is a political one. Elected
judges are politically influenced by public opinion, after all, and appointed
judges are selected according to the recommendations of committees made
up of lawyers belonging to the political party in power and appointed by the
elected governor or legislators. Court judges are “elected or appointed by
commissions dominated by lawyers who have an interest in maximizing
litigation. Family court judges wield extensive powers of patronage, thanks
to their power to appoint attorneys and expert witnesses.”108 Worse, they
are in league with enforcement agencies. No wonder family court judges
are often honoured by enforcement groups. Seidenberg puts it this way:

There are intrinsic and extrinsic political influences that come to bear on the
judge’s decision-making habits. By intrinsic politics I mean the judge’s
immediate constituents – those people and organizations the judge comes in
contact with on a regular basis – the people who might have some say about
his reappointment. Essentially this means the lawyers who appear before
him, the local bar association, and the representatives of two large
bureaucracies – the Child Support Enforcement Agency and Child
Protective Services. Frequently, Child Support Enforcement and Child
Protective Services are housed in the same building as the court … The
extrinsic politics involves the larger political picture: such as the electoral
influences on the state legislators (some of whom may also be lawyers who
appear before the judge) and the popular mood.109

Moreover, notes Baskerville, we should consider another form of vested


interest in the United States. The National Child Support Enforcement
Association, according to its own website, consists of “state and local
agencies, judges, court masters, hearing officers, district attorneys,
government and private attorneys, social workers, caseworkers, advocates,
and other child support professions,” as well as “corporations that partner
with government to enforce child support.”110 He sees the American family
court system itself as a major problem, calling it a “secretive” institution
that operates behind closed doors, seldom records proceedings, and keeps
no statistics on decisions.”111

In other words, it is made up entirely of people who have a financial interest


in having children separated from their fathers. Setting child support levels
is a political process conducted largely by groups that benefit from divorce.
Parents are largely excluded. In about half the states, the guidelines used to
set child-support levels are devised not by the legislature but by courts and
enforcement agencies, and in all states the courts and enforcement agencies
play a dominant role in setting the guidelines. Under the separation of
powers we do not normally permit police and courts to make the laws they
enforce and interpret, since this would create an obvious conflict of
interest.112

Feminists, too, have vested interests in these courts. Women are the ones
who most often seek divorce, after all, and want to win custody. Not
surprisingly, they often end up on the commissions reviewing guidelines by
representing “custodial parent advocacy groups.” Men are the ones who
most often have to pay child support. Until very recently, however, they had
no advocacy groups to represent them.
In the Canadian system, too, vested interests can be found at every level.
F.L. Morton and Rainer Knopff have written about the “Court Party,”113 for
instance, referring to a coalition of groups from academics to legal
departments in government, law reform commissions, human rights
commissions, administrative tribunals, and the courts themselves. (We
discuss these topics in chapter 10.)
With all this in mind, consider this discussion of vested interests with the
words of Seidenberg:

The most overt discrimination in the United States is not against women, or
blacks, or hispanics, but against men in a specific situation – divorce-
custody proceedings. Other groups may suffer broader and deeper
discrimination. The discrimination against blacks, to take an obvious
example, affects more people in numerous areas of life. But the largest part
of this discrimination is subtle or hidden because no one today would want
to be labelled a racist. The discrimination against men in divorce-custody
proceedings, on the other hand, is blatant and shameless. Protective orders,
which evict men from their homes at a moment’s notice, are issued without
evidence; restraining orders are issued without testimony; at times custody
is awarded without testimony; and false child abuse allegations against
fathers are rampant.114

It is hard to avoid the conclusion that the whole system, whether in the
United States or Canada, is corrupt. And that is a dangerous situation in any
society, because it fosters rampant cynicism. At a public meeting in
Toronto, family-law lawyer Gene Colman noted that “gender bias is indeed
a reality in Canada’s courts.”115 Because most Canadian laws are written in
gender-neutral terms, “the problem lies not with the wording of the laws,
but with the judicial interpretation of the statutes as applied to the facts of
individual cases.”116 Apart from anything else, he added, this encourages
disrespect for the judicial system. Colman referred to family-law lawyer
Carey Linde, who had observed that these interpretations result from
“judicially assumed presumptions” that “have never been put to the test of
evidence, but spring from and are maintained out of gender biases still
ingrained in the system.”117 He referred also to criminal-law lawyer Edward
Greenspan, who had observed that “feminist influence has amounted to
intimidation, posing a potential danger to the independence of the judiciary”
and that “feminists have entrenched their ideology in the Supreme Court of
Canada and have put all contrary views beyond the pale.”118 These are very
serious charges, especially because they come from lawyers: insiders with
professional experience of the system. Because justice must not only be
done but also be seen to be done, Canadians would do well to take these
charges seriously.

What about reform? We have reached a turning point. Until recently, we


heard heated rhetoric from only one side: mothers and their advocates.
Now, though, we hear it from the other side as well: fathers and their
advocates. Reform, therefore, is at least possible.
The American child-support industry now affects enough men to have
generated dozens of books that are critical of the system, and most of these
books are read by both Americans and Canadians. We have already
mentioned Braver’s Divorced Dads and Seidenberg’s Father’s Emergency
Guide, but there are many others.119 Divorced fathers have organized
support groups, too, some of which can be found within local communities
and on the Internet. They function in two basic ways. First, they offer
therapy; hapless fathers write in to tell their stories. Second, they offer
ideas. Some are directed toward individual fathers in need, others toward
society as a whole. Among the latter are proposals for law reform that are
often accompanied by advice for those willing to take action as lobbyists.
One website provides visitors with an eighty-five page manual on how
fathers can beat the system.120 The rhetoric is overtly confrontational.
“Powerful tips and information,” according to the first page, that “those in
the system don’t want you to know about [t]hat will help you get the most
out of the family court system and help make the system more accountable
to you, your family and to all families who may be taken advantage of by
the system after you.”121 It is very similar in both purpose and tone to the
kind of manual that has been addressed to women for many years – and can
still be found at many feminist websites (which we illustrate in appendix 9).
Among the many practical tips given at this site are the following: have
witnesses present whenever possible when dealing with the courts and with
the social workers or psychologists assigned to your case; tape or videotape
interactions with them whenever possible; do background checks on
everyone assigned to your case – judges, lawyers, and clinicians – to learn
about flawed methods, examples of unaccountability, dissatisfied clients,
political or ideological affiliations; hire your own experts so that opposing
reports can be challenged; insist on seeing written reports by all those
involved so that you can check their interpretations and statistics; file
complaints against anyone involved who exhibits (or tries to hide) any sign
of bias; and go public if these complaints are ignored.
The mobilization of fathers has already led to some minor legal reforms
in the United States. The Deadbeat Parents Punishment Act of 1998, for
instance, streamlined the process for deciding which cases require federal
investigation and prosecution. These cases must be referred from a United
States attorney’s office, now, not from individual lawyers or advocacy
groups. This change offers some protection to fathers in these more serious
cases (although it hardly compensates for increasing the status of violations
and penalties in the first place, which, as we have already mentioned, the
act also does). Some states have introduced joint-parenting legislation.
Others have now adjusted or even forgiven arrears.122 Still others have
fixed an even worse problem, which gives men in Carnell Smith’s position
some basis for hope. Ohio and Georgia, at least, have passed legislation that
exonerates men after DNA tests prove that they are not the biological fathers
of children in question.
Moreover, the authority of Congress to interpret the Commerce Clause
broadly – that is, to use the official lingo, overbroadly – is being challenged.
Under the Child Support Recovery Act, as we have observed, failing to
comply with an interstate court order for child support has been a criminal
offense. According to the Supreme Court, however, this act goes beyond the
authority of Congress under the Commerce Clause.123
In Canada, the Ontario Court of Appeal agreed in 2003 that the Federal
Child Support Guidelines should be used with caution. The story is worth
telling here. Joseph Contino had applied to reduce the amount of child
support for his son, because he now had physical custody of the boy for
50% of the time. The judge agreed and changed the amount from $550 to
$100 a month, citing the shared-custody rules in section 9 of the guidelines.
The mother appealed this decision, and it was overturned by another judge
who actually increased the amount to $688, citing the best interest of the
child. Once again, Contino challenged the status quo. He brought his case to
the Ontario Court of Appeal, which ruled that it should indeed be assessed
according to the rules for shared custody. This time, the judges calculated
that Contino owed only $399 a month.124 The guidelines were still useful in
providing some level of predictability (for the child) and objectivity (for the
judge), they ruled, but they should not be used mechanically – which is to
say, without considering the particular circumstances of specific people.125
Finally, remember the Ontario case in which a judge ruled that a father’s
surname need not appear on a birth certificate? That ruling might turn out to
have been a legal landmark, because the Supreme Court overturned it on the
ground that sexual discrimination against men by the lower courts had
violated section 15(1) of the Charter, which stipulates sexual equality.

Advocates of equal rights for divorced fathers and mothers want more
reforms. For one thing, they want a presumption of joint custody. American
fathers, as we say, have already won that reform in two states, and Canadian
fathers are lobbying for it at the federal level. McLean points to evidence
from the United States. According to one study,

states which obtained high levels of joint physical custody awards in 1989
and 1990 showed significantly greater declines in divorce rates in the
following five years, compared with other states. Divorce rates declined
nearly four times faster in states with high joint physical custody (known in
Canada as shared custody), compared with states where shared custody is
rare. As a result, the states with high levels of shared custody now have
significantly lower divorce rates on average than other states. States that
favoured sole custody, on the other hand, also had more divorces involving
children.126

In addition, fathers want better models for calculating child support


payments. In the United States, R. Mark Rogers and Donald Bieniewicz
argue that “each parent has an equal duty to bear the financial costs of
rearing children. It only follows that both parents have an equal right to
share the cost offsets of tax benefits attributable to the same children.”127
To achieve this, they developed the Cost Shares model, which is based on
actual expenditures in single-parent households in various categories, the
average gross income of both parents, and a fair distribution of tax
benefits.128
In Canada, fathers propose legal recognition of at least three underlying
principles to improve the guidelines. They argue that “child support is for
the care and maintenance of children; [that] … both parents have an equal
duty to support their children; [and that] … all relevant circumstantial
information may effect the amount of the award.”129 The information might
include ability to pay, for instance, or ability to take care of yourself after
paying. In addition, they want several other modifications. Any legitimate
child support scheme should be not only logically and legally coherent but
also based on a clear definition with “criteria to determine whether the
presumptive award is just and appropriate … It is also apparent that the law
must … make a relational statement about the obligations of the parents and
provide the courts with the proper authority to consider all relevant factors
before making a final judgment.”130 The court should calculate a separate
payment for each child, which would prevent noncustodial parents from
being forced to support adults. (As it is now, once again, some fathers must
pay until the youngest child reaches maturity.)131 And calculations should
be based on the real cost of rearing children, which should be shared by
both parents according to the income of each. These measures would
require a new formula. It all boils down to acknowledging the actual time
spent by the children in each household and the actual cost of each stay.132
One possible bulwark against the unfair existing formula that underlies
the guidelines, says Soever, is the Divorce Act. The purpose of child
support payments, according to the Supreme Court’s interpretation, is
“maintenance of the children, rather than household equalization or spousal
support.”133 This interpretation could be used to reverse the formula, which
states that its purpose is to equalize “the financial circumstances of the two
households,” to make the households “equally well off” through the transfer
of payments. The formula transforms child support into “household
support,” says Soever, which contradicts the Divorce Act.134 Because the
term “household support” is more nebulous than either “child support” or
“spousal support,” instead of being used for children at all, it might be used
for almost anything receiving parents want. That arrangement does little for
children, but it clearly does a great deal for custodial parents. “Child
support” or “spousal support” turns into “household support” or “domestic
support” and “equality” into “equity.”
Another possible bulwark against injustice to divorced fathers might be
Canada’s Charter of Rights and Freedoms. For Soever, this legislation
should be used to support the claim that economic hardship for men created
by the formula constitutes discrimination under section 15 (which
presumably guarantees sexual equality).
A parliamentary committee listened to Canadian fathers and studied the
merits of joint parenting. In a report called “For the Sake of the Children,”
it proposed an interpretation of the Divorce Act that would presume
(barring unusual circumstances) that arrangement. This should have solved
at least some problems, right? Not so fast. Ideological feminists refused to
stand idly by. In fact, their rhetoric heated up. They used a primary feminist
strategy that we have already mentioned and will mention again: creating
social and economic change through linguistic legerdemain – ideally, by
establishing new terms and, alternatively, by creating new definitions or
new interpretations of existing ones. Using the Internet, they mobilized
their constituencies to isolate any potential legal changes that might benefit
fathers. In both the United States and Canada, then, officials have used
language to suggest change in the direction of joint parenting but
nonetheless have actually prevented real change. (For a detailed discussion,
see appendix 9.)

Because only adults are involved in public debate and because our book is
about men in relation to women, much of this chapter has revolved around
the conflicting rights of fathers and mothers. In this section, we will pay
particular attention to the link between gynocentrism (laws that attend to the
needs of women alone) and misandry (rhetoric that turns fathers into
“deadbeats” or worse, even if most of them obey the laws). Directly or
indirectly, however, the needs of children are always involved as well. And
in spite of all the rhetoric on both sides about divorce being better for
children than the alternative, in spite of all the jive talk about “quality
time,” the fact is that – from the perspective of children – a divorce can be
disastrous (unless, of course, the marriage has involved violence or extreme
psychological damage).

In the United States, 75 percent of juvenile delinquents, 71 percent of


pregnant teenagers, and 90 percent of teenage runaways, are children from
fatherless homes. Such statistics are endless. Whether the subject is gang
involvement, drug abuse, alcoholism, scholastic failure, or teen suicide, the
incidence among children from fatherless homes far exceeds the incidence
among children from homes where the father is present. Our culture’s
hostility toward men has reached a dimension where it no longer affects
only individual families, but is tearing apart the social fabric.135

Beyond the needs of adults and even of children are those of society as a
whole. Without major reforms to the legal systems discussed in this chapter,
society will become even more fragmented and polarized than it already is.
We are already moving toward a society in which women have colonized
reproduction, along with childrearing, and men will have less and less
incentive to participate fully in family life and more and more penalties if
any problems arise. Think of all this as a series of symbolic messages.136
Some are sent to boys and men, others to girls and women. Some are about
society, others about identity.
One message to girls and women is that they should strive for complete
autonomy. That means liberation, freedom, or even separation from men.
And that reveals a profoundly gynocentric worldview. But it reveals a
profoundly misandric one, too, because it implies that all men should be
kept under permanent suspicion of being violent, selfish, and controlling.
This much is clear not only from the laws under discussion but also from
the ideological rhetoric about those laws.
At one time – in this respect, the world of only forty years ago now
seems as remote as that of four hundred years ago – single mothers (and
their “illegitimate” children) were stigmatized. They were the objects of
either scorn or pity. In our time, they are not merely exempt from any
stigma but seen as role models. To get this far, we had to go through several
transitions.
The first was from single mothers as immoral women to single mothers
as victims. And from the ranks of victims, as we have been told for decades
by talk show hosts and political activists, come heroes. There is nothing
heroic in being a victim at the individual level, to be sure, but there is a
reward that translates directly into political power on a collective level:
uncritical public sympathy. Designated victim classes, not only women in
general but single mothers in particular, are lauded merely for enduring and
triumphing over obstacles. Underlying this glorification at the emotional
level is manipulation at the political level. Here is one example, the
response of a journalist to a Swedish study on the many problems faced by
children of single parents. “If we accept,” writes Janet Bagnall, “that
parents are doing the work of bringing up children on behalf of all society –
and I think we should – then single parents clearly need more help.”137 And
by “single parents,” she means single women: “It is not fair to expect a
single person to keep it together for herself and her children.”138 She does
not consider that reducing the number of single mothers in the first place
would be an even better solution than spending more tax dollars on them
and thus encouraging the phenomenon. That would involve a radical
rethinking of conventional wisdom on divorce, let alone of feminist
ideology. Not surprisingly, single mothers organize politically, with massive
support from feminist organizations, for economic support from
governments.
The next transition was from seeing single mothers as victims to seeing
them as heroines or role models, which coincided with the transition from
single motherhood as a phenomenon primarily of the lower class to single
motherhood as a phenonemon of the middle and upper classes as well.
Many of these women were not undereducated and underemployed victims
of irresponsible men. They were sophisticated and upwardly mobile
executives, entrepreneurs, professionals, and academics in their thirties.
Rather than wait for the right man to come along and, if they waited too
long, face the prospect of having to “marry down” or not at all, they
preferred to have children right away. Rather than put their careers on hold
while caring for young children, in other words, they chose to have their
cake and eat it too by combining motherhood and career. Caring for
children took time away from work, true, but looking for husbands took up
even more time. Besides, these women had the financial resources to pay
not only for daycare but also for part-time or full-time nannies. In short,
these women decided to have it all. Whether this was a blessing for their
children or not, of course, that was another matter. Researchers are still
troubled by the problem of fatherless children – this is now emerging as a
major topic of academic and political debate – but there are still feminists
who advise women not to worry as long as they can provide their children
with “quality time” and, perhaps, supply them with “father figures.”
One result of this second transition has been the evolution of what is best
described as a “single-mothers industry.” Like every other industry, this one
relies on a growing number of customers and a growing cadre of
professionals and experts to service them. It was featured by Susanne Hiller
in Canada’s National Post.139 The rate of increase for single mothers since
1991, according to Jane Mattes, was four times as high as the rate for
married mothers.140 At least four factors explain the new mentality. First,
social acceptance. Single mothers can now expect massive support from
their families and friends. Second, the development and industrialization of
reproductive technologies. Women who lack husbands or “relationships”
with men need no longer wait around as their biological clocks run down.
At ReproMed, according to Cathy Ruberto, about 30% of the clients from
2000 to 2001 were “single women in a hurry to become mothers.”141 Third,
the “rights revolution.” This boils down to the belief that what you want is
what society owes you: a right. And fourth, the glorification of heroic single
mothers in popular culture (due partly to the glorification of female
autonomy by feminists). This factor closes the circle, because it forms the
basis for public support.
Women at all levels of society are affected. Consider the iconic status of
single mothers such as Calista Flockhart and Angelina Jolie. But not all the
women who choose to become single mothers are television or movie stars.
Many are just highly educated and upwardly mobile career women. Some
of them would like to marry some day, and others would not. What they all
really want, with or without husbands, are babies. And organizations such
as Single Mothers by Choice, headed by Mattes, are happy to help them
out. Not that they need much help in this age of day care and sperm banks
or in vitro clinics. Even single women who do not choose motherhood, the
ones who have “accidents,” are often portrayed as victims (garnering
sympathy) who become heroes (garnering admiration) for rearing children
alone. No wonder that one single mother interviewed by Hiller said that she
had “never received a negative comment.”142 Do these women consider the
possibility that their children need fathers? Some do, but they are content
with “father figures.” Another woman told Hiller that her son “has a
grandfather and a stepgrandfather. He has male influences and is a real
boy.”143
The Library of Congress lists no fewer than sixty books on single
mothering and single parenting.144 And, as usual, television shows reflect
social trends. Consider Miranda on Sex and the City, Rachel on Friends,
Ellenor on The Practice, Viveca on Family Law. Odd exceptions? Hardly.
Referring to the new single mothers, in general, Jane Bock observes that
they “have altered the way we look at this issue because they’ve been
successful as single mothers. They are legitimizing single parenthood as an
appropriate life choice.”145 Legitimate? Appropriate? In which ways? By
whose standards? The number of American single mothers between thirty-
five and thirty-nine, which reached a new high in 2000 – 64,523, according
to the National Center for Health Statistics – is still low in absolute terms
but very high in relative terms: six times as high, in fact, as the figure for
1965. This, even as single motherhood among teenagers is declining!146
Complete reproductive autonomy for women has for years been a major
plank in the political platform of ideological feminism. It has been
exemplified best by the Feminist International Network of Resistance to
Reproductive and Genetic Engineering (FINRRAGE), an organization that is
preoccupied mainly with new reproductive technologies such as in vitro
fertilization, although it is equally opposed to “older” technologies such as
surrogacy.147 Members meet regularly, publish a journal, hold conferences,
and lobby governments for bans on the use of reproductive technologies. In
1989, Canadian members got the government to set up the Royal
Commission on New Reproductive Technologies, which produced a report
urging the government to take a “cautious” approach – albeit not quite as
cautious as the original instigators had wanted.
Among the more prominent members of FINRRAGE was Gena Corea. In
The Mother Machine, she claims that the new reproductive technologies
amount to new ways for men to control women.148 In other words, the
participation of men in matters that affect reproduction is just another way
of maintaining patriarchal control over women’s bodies. Given this point of
view, it is hardly surprising that Corea refers to the “subversive sperm” and
accuses some countries of “gynocide.” By the latter, she refers to sex-
selection techniques that would result in the mass killing of female fetuses.
But Corea refrains from accusing countries that conscript young men for
combat of “androcide.”
At the heart of Corea’s work is the symbolism of reproduction, what she
sees as the continuing problem of society turning women into “breeding
machines.” Never mind that the same society could be accused of turning
men into economic or war machines. Corea would agree, if pressed, but
what she fears most is that the “patriarchal urge to self-generate” will lead
to artificial wombs or cloning and thus make even these “breeding
machines” obsolete and turn reproduction over entirely to men. Never mind
that the same technology could be used for parthenogenesis, or asexual
reproduction, which would make the male contribution obsolete and even
lead, by another route, to “androcide.” For Corea and her ideological
colleagues, new reproductive technologies require a political response, not
only for the sake of a few infertile women who have been culturally
pressured into thinking of themselves as inadequate on that account but for
all women. At stake, ultimately, is their identity as women. That is partly
why ideological feminists argue for female autonomy. Taken to its logical
conclusion, that means placing reproduction itself in the exclusive control
of women. From this it follows that new or old technologies promising
female autonomy – contraception, abortion, and artificial insemination by
donor – are highly desirable; only those that might lead to male autonomy
or at least require negotiation between men and women – sex selection,
surrogacy, and in vitro – should be banned.
Another message to girls and women is that they may feel free to extract
as much money from men as they can. As we said in chapter 5, “equity” is a
key code word for feminists. Ideological lobby groups have found both
direct and indirect ways of embedding it in the fabric of law. What would
either the American or the Canadian Supreme Court say about a case
challenging the legality of child support systems? Feminists would almost
certainly argue that the principle of equity should take precedence over any
other consideration. In short, financial equity for women would trump
financial support exclusively for children (not to mention equity for men).
They would never say so, of course. They would have to do some serious
window dressing. But politicians of all stripes are good at window dressing.
One message given to boys and men is discouraging, to say the least:
fatherhood can be a nightmare – legal, financial, and emotional – due to the
laws governing divorce, custody, and access. These laws are not going to
prevent all men from investing in family life, certainly not those who
consider marriage a religious covenant, but they have already made many
other men think twice before becoming involved in what could easily
become a no-win situation. Why invest so heavily in family life, after all, if
your children can be taken away from you or even turned against you so
easily? At the very moment when men have begun to think about being
fathers in ways that their own fathers never considered, being more
physically and emotionally available than ever before, they hear that fathers
are disposable – except as a financial resource, of course, and ultimately not
even as a financial resource, given their replacement by the state and the
glorification of single mothers.
Closely related to that message is another: that the bond between mother
and child is both emotionally and erotically so powerful, in any case, that
not even the bond between mother and father can compete. One overtly
political implication is the ultimate autonomy of mothers in family life. One
covertly political implication, though, is the ultimate irrelevance of fathers
in family life. This message is so prevalent that it surfaces in discussions
not only of popular culture in general but also of pornography and even
romance novels in particular (which is why we discuss this point of view,
based on the psychoanalytical theories of feminists such as Mary O’Brien
and Nancy Chodorow, in appendix 5.)
The same laws send an additional and even more disturbing message to
boys and men. This one is specifically about women: avoid strong
relationships with those who could easily use the law to exploit you or
manipulate you into poverty. Men who try cohabitation either as a prelude
to marriage or as an arrangement preferred to marriage, for instance, find
more and more often that their legal and financial obligations – thanks
partly to “palimony” but mainly to the laws we have been discussing here –
are almost the same as those of marriage. And the success rates of both
arrangements are not exactly encouraging. If things continue moving in the
same direction, more and more men will come to believe that the risks of
long-term relationships with women outweigh the potential benefits. This is
already a problem in Canada, and it could become much worse.
The legal changes brought about directly or indirectly by ideological
feminism are just as misandric (though couched in the rhetoric of self-
defense) as the artifacts of popular culture that we examined in Spreading
Misandry.
To conclude, here is a suggestion that no one else has (yet) made:
mandatory courses outlining the legal consequences of separation or
divorce, especially when children are involved, for every couple preparing
to marry (and, on prudential grounds, for every couple planning to cohabit).
It is safe to say that very few potential husbands or fathers have even the
faintest idea of what these legal consequences would be. They might think
twice before entering any marital or quasi-marital relationships at all, true,
but even that might be better than waking up too late to the painful reality
of being taken to the cleaners by their ex-wives and – worst of all – losing
their children. The only alternative to cynicism would be to reform the
system so that fathers would have a significant legal investment in family
life and would thus be more likely than some now are to make an emotional
investment in it as well.
PART THREE
Sex on Trial: From Liberation to
Separation

So far, we have concentrated on economic battles between women and men


as they have been waged in courts of law due to legislative changes. We
turn now to political battles, also waged in courts of law due to legislative
changes, over the meaning of sexual acts. At issue is not whether violence
against women (or men) should be taken seriously. Clearly, it should. At
issue are the ways in which that has been done.
Everyone agrees that violence is a bad thing and that legal measures are
necessary to curb it. But violence against women has become an ideological
trump card. Every political demand of feminists is backed up, ultimately, by
the assertion that failure to comply is tantamount to endorsing violence
against women. Everyone agrees that harassment is a bad thing, moreover,
and that legal measures are sometimes necessary to curb it. But what
happens when many other forms of behaviour, though lamentable, are
elided with the ones that cause serious physical or economic harm? Two
things.
First, the serious nature of these problems is trivialized. Second, and
more important, the polarization between men and women is widened.
Although more and more women look with suspicion on the legal measures
proposed – and often attained – by ideological feminists, the fact remains
that few are either willing or able to reverse the process.
For one thing, many women have been convinced that they ought to fear
even the most trivial attentions from men. Also, many women are
convinced that every measure taken to protect women from men is at least a
symbolic step in the right direction. A few women, however, believe that
these measures are necessary for a quite different reason: to discourage
contact of any kind between the sexes. These are the ideological feminists,
those who believe that heterosexual relations – including those wanted or
even initiated by women – are inherently corrupted by a “power imbalance”
that renders women utterly incapable of giving their consent. In that case,
every heterosexual act involves the rape of a woman. Very few women
would agree with that conclusion, but very few are prepared to argue
against the inherent logic of an ideology that begins with the isolation of
patriarchy – that is, men – as the ultimate source of all problems for women
throughout history.
The result is what could be called the victimization industry, a congeries
of professional networks, political associations, and lobby groups
advocating ever more inclusive definitions of victimization, ever more laws
to punish violence, ever more dubious ways of overriding the principle of
due process, and ever more serious penalties for those found guilty.
We turn now to several disturbing problems. All of them involve either
violence or the threat of violence. And all of them are explained by
ideological feminists as evidence of an inherently violent worldview that
must be destroyed, root and branch. Even though we discuss these problems
in separate chapters, bear in mind that many feminists do not see them as
separate topics.
In chapter 7, we discuss the legal implications of pornography. In
chapter 8, we discuss what has been called the sexual harassment industry,
along with its legal implications. Women have indeed come a long way
over the past forty years. What began as liberation during the sexual
revolution – the adoption of a single standard for women and men – has
turned into a legal system that directly or indirectly, explicitly or implicitly,
fosters the separation of women from men. In chapter 9, we discuss the
most serious problem of all, the touchstone and ultimate trump card of
ideological feminists: their legal interpretation of sexual assault, which has
come to include everything from touching a woman to raping her. All three
have important political implications, of course, as well as other cultural
ones.
7
Power v. Pleasure: The Case of
Pornography/Prostitution
Rapists and pimps, representing the interests of normal men, some of whom
rape, some of whom buy, seem to have the law of gravity on their side …
No matter what lie they tell, it passes for truth, because the hatred of
women underlying the lie is an accepted hatred, a shared and unchallenged
set of prejudiced assumptions.1

In our sample, men tended to show more activity than women in brain
regions associated with visual processing … [which could] shed light on
why men so avidly support the worldwide trade in visual pornography.2

For many nonideological women and even for many “sensitive” men, the
very act of enjoying the sight of pretty women – even fully clothed women
– is now equated with sexism. Ken Tucker speaks for them in his review of
The Apprentice, a reality show in which contestants vie for a job with
tycoon Donald Trump. Tucker refers to “Kristi Frank, the camera crew’s
go-to girl for shots summarizing the action because (and yes, I’m indulging
in the sexism Apprentice thrives on) she’s great looking – but contributes
little to most competitions.”3 The fact that a (presumably male) camera
crew pays more attention to a woman’s looks than to her knowledge might
well be sexist. (The functional equivalent would be women who pay more
attention to a man’s wealth and power than to anything else about him,
Trump himself being an excellent example of men in this category.) But
Tucker is troubled merely by noticing the fact that Kristi is “great looking.”
And he assumes correctly that the readers of a mainstream magazine will
agree with him. What troubles Tucker has been given a name by feminists:
the “objectification of women.” It lies at the heart of current controversies
over pornography and prostitution (but also at the heart of controversies
over sexual harassment and violence against women, which we discuss in
the next two chapters).
After a brief introduction on the relation between pornography and
prostitution, we will review the legislation governing both and continue
with discussions of the various feminist positions on them: the belief that
both are based on the subordination and objectification of women, which
makes these industries inherently misogynistic; the belief that both should
be tolerated in order to avoid abrogating freedom in one form or another;
and the belief that both should be valued as venues for the liberation of
women from outdated notions of female sexuality. Before concluding, we
will provide a larger context for this debate, present some reasons for
tolerating pornography and prostitution, and discuss the double standard
that has characterized most discussions of this topic.

Feminists have produced a voluminous literature on both pornography and


prostitution. Actually, they comprise one topic rather than two. Although
they are enacted in different ways and controlled by different laws,
ideological feminists claim that the underlying phenomenon is identical.
Every basic reason that they cite for opposing one, in fact, they cite for
opposing the other as well. And this book is organized with their point of
view in mind. According to even moderately ideological feminists, both
pornography and prostitution “objectify” women and therefore, they say,
lead directly or indirectly to violence against women. According to more
radical ones, such as Andrea Dworkin and Catharine MacKinnon,
pornography

is a systematic practice of exploitation and subordination based on sex that


differentially harms women. The harm of pornography includes
dehumanization, sexual exploitation, forced sex, forced prostitution,
physical injury, and social and sexual terrorism and inferiority presented as
entertainment. The bigotry and contempt pornography promotes, with the
acts of aggression it fosters, diminish opportunities for equality of rights in
employment, education, property, public accommodations, and public
services; create public and private harassment, persecution, and denigration;
expose individuals who appear in pornography against their will to …
hatred … and embarrassment and target such women in particular for abuse
and physical aggression … promote injury and degradation such as rape,
battery, child sexual abuse, and prostitution and inhibit just enforcement of
laws against these acts; contribute significantly to restricting women in
particular from full exercise of citizenship and participation in public life,
including in neighborhoods; damage relations between the sexes; and
undermine women’s equal exercise of rights to speech and action
guaranteed to all citizens.4

Even when a discussion is explicitly about pornography alone, therefore,


readers should bear in mind that it is implicitly about prostitution as well. In
all respects except for the specific laws that regulate each, the two topics
are most effectively discussed together rather than separately. (They are
very closely related also to sexual harassment and even to violence against
women, which we discuss in chapters 8 and 9).
Pornography and prostitution can be discussed as industries in two
senses, neither of which is what usually comes to mind at the mention of the
word “industry.” They are industries in the commercial sense, albeit
disreputable and sometimes illegal ones, because they are defined by the
transactions of small businesses. In fact, pornography and prostitution are
two venues of the same industry. In the former, customers buy visual or
verbal images of sexual objects. In the latter, they hire sexual objects
themselves. Both venues are associated with other ones, in turn, and these
are part of an underground economy. They involve criminal and often
violent activities, in other words, such as drug dealing, pimping, and even
what amounts to slavery. Yet not all prostitutes are uneducated minors who
have run away from abusive fathers or uneducated women who have run
away from abusive husbands. In fact, not all are even female. The ones
known as call girls work in a very different social, cultural, and economic
environment. In some societies, the prostitutes known as courtesans enjoy
no small degree of status. Consider the geisha of Japan. Our point here is
that criminal activities are often entailed by pornography and prostitution as
these are currently organized but not inherent in them.
Pornography and prostitution have also generated new industries of a
different kind. As we said in the previous chapter, the word “industry” can
be applied usefully to jobs that involve the fallout from social and legal
problems. Like the children of divorce, the “victims” of pornography and
prostitution have become the focus of intense interest by a vast array of
specialized agencies, municipal offices, academic departments, federal
offices, and so on. These industries are defined not by commercial
transactions but by the public policies created by networks of closely
related private and public bureaucracies.
Porn is a little more complicated, in some ways, than prostitution. Some
feminists acknowledge a distinction between porn that directly or indirectly
threatens the safety of women and porn that merely titillates men (but also,
according to feminists as different as Helen Gurley Brown and Camille
Paglia, women as well). This porn is sometimes called erotica. Other
feminists acknowledge no such distinction, although some of them find it
politically expedient to do so for legal purposes. They believe that even the
most innocuous pictures of naked women should be seen as one end of a
misogynistic continuum that ends in rape. Following that pattern of thought,
they believe that even the most innocuous act of heterosexual intercourse
should be seen as one end of precisely the same misogynistic continuum.
For these ideological feminists, in other words, the very act of intercourse
between a man and a woman is tantamount to sexism in general and rape in
particular. They are in the minority, but their influence can hardly be
exaggerated.
As for prostitution, it includes a wide range of phenomena. One of them
could be classified as industrial; people pay prostitutes for their services.
But this is often accompanied by contextually related – though not
inherently related – phenomena that include pimps, violence, the trade in
drugs, and abuse of one kind or another.

In the United States, pornography is defined along a constitutional


continuum. At one end are images of real children who are engaged in
sexually explicit activities. These images are not protected by the
Constitution. The involvement of children is carefully monitored by federal
laws. The authority for this comes from sections of the federal Criminal
Code on porn, sexual abuse, sexual exploitation of children, selling or
buying of children, sexual exploitation of minors, activities relating to
material constituting or containing child porn, coercion for prostitution, and
so forth.5
At the other end are images of real adults who are engaged in sexually
explicit activities. These images are protected. Between these two extremes
are ambiguous images: “explicit material created without the benefit of a
live child model but which appears to depict an actual minor, or produced
by having an adult pose as a minor and later presented or sold as if it
depicted … an actual minor, arguably falls somewhere in between.”6 The
Child Pornography Prevention Act of 1996 (CPPA) was supposed to
modernize existing legislation by bringing it into the computer age.
Sometimes, computer manipulation of images makes it possible for children
(like adults) to be involved even when they know nothing at all about what
is going on. Included among illegal images of children, for instance, are
those that have been manipulated, enhanced, or wholly generated by
computer technology. In 2002, after several years of legal wrangling over
constitutionality, the Supreme Court ruled in Ashcroft, Attorney General, et
al. v. Free Speech Coalition et al.7 that the Child Pornography Prevention
Act

prohibits speech that records no crime and creates no victims by its


production. Virtual child pornography is not “intrinsically related” to the
sexual abuse of children. While the Government asserts that the images can
lead to actual instances of child abuse, the causal link is contingent and
indirect. The harm does not necessarily follow from the speech, but depends
upon some unquantified potential for subsequent criminal acts … The
contention that the CPPA is necessary because pedophiles may use virtual
child pornography to seduce children runs afoul of the principle that speech
within the rights of adults to hear may not be silenced completely in an
attempt to shield children from it … That the evil in question depends upon
the actor’s unlawful conduct, defined as criminal quite apart from any link
to the speech in question, establishes that the speech ban is not narrowly
drawn. The argument that virtual child pornography whets pedophiles’
appetites and encourages them to engage in illegal conduct is unavailing
because the mere tendency of speech to encourage unlawful acts is not a
sufficient reason for banning it … The overbreadth doctrine prohibits the
Government from banning unprotected speech if a substantial amount of
protected speech is prohibited or chilled in the process … that the CPPA
should be read not as a prohibition on speech but as a measure shifting the
burden to the accused to prove the speech is lawful raises serious
constitutional difficulties.8
Prostitution is governed by the Victims of Trafficking and Violence
Prevention Act of 2000. It prohibits activities connected with prostitution
across state lines. This approach is based on the Constitution’s Commerce
Clause. Division A is the Trafficking Victims Protection Act: “trafficking”
refers to the use of fraud or coercion to rape, abuse, torture, starve,
imprison, or psychologically abuse girls or women.9 Citing what had been
found by Congress, division A held that trafficking in the national and
international sex trade is a modern form of slavery and the fastest-growing
source of profit for organized crime.10 When it comes to local prostitution,
whether on the street or in brothels, state law governs, rather than federal
law. Prostitution is illegal everywhere except in some parts of Nevada.11
In Canada, the legal situation is somewhat different. Part V, section 163
of the Criminal Code covers several activities, including making, printing,
publishing, distributing, circulating, selling, or keeping “in his possession”
– the legislators did not bother to use gender-neutral language – “any
obscene written matter, picture, model … which publicly exhibits a
disgusting object or an indecent show.” This material has as its “dominant
characteristic … the undue exploitation of sex, or of sex and any one or
more of the following subjects: crime, horror, cruelty and violence.” The
only exception is for material that serves the “public good,” presumably
something artistic or educational.12 Section 163(1) prohibits not only using
minors – that is, anyone under eighteen, even though the legal age of
consent is fourteen – in the production of porn but also providing them with
access to it. In 2002 it became illegal to post child porn on the Internet.13 In
the same year, Bill C-20 was proposed to clamp down even more heavily on
child porn. Although this bill died, a similar one was proposed in 2004.
Measures included eliminating the defense of artistic merit,14 even though a
case in 2001 maintained the loophole.15
Canadian prostitution is mainly under federal jurisdiction, although
municipalities have been allowed to “regulate or license indoor activity.”16
Federal laws against various aspects of prostitution date back to Canada’s
first criminal code. These laws were updated by the Soliciting Law of 1972.
In 1983, the Special Committee on Pornography and Prostitution (also
known as the Fraser Committee) recommended that prostitution be
legalized but also that its venues and circumstances be restricted. In 1985
the Communicating Law – this name is unfortunate, to say the least, since
many Christian churches use precisely the same word for participation in
holy communion – prohibited “communicating in a public place for the
purpose of buying or selling sexual services.”17 Legislators allowed a limit
on freedom of expression according to the “reasonable” test, which must
balance “the salutary and deleterious effects of the law.”18 The
Communicating Law was challenged in several court cases. They argued
that it violated both freedom of expression and freedom of association as
guaranteed by sections 2b and 2d of the Charter of Rights and Freedoms.19
Nonetheless, the Supreme Court upheld this law.
Prostitution is regulated also by sections 210 to 213 of the Criminal
Code.20 Section 210 makes it a criminal offense, punishable by
imprisonment for not more than two years, to own and manage a bawdy
house, work in one, be found in one (without a lawful excuse), or rent space
to one. Section 211, directed at pimps, is about transporting people to
bawdy houses and getting them involved with prostitution. Both 210 and
211 involve summary charges (once known as misdemeanors).21
Section 212 is about manipulating and controlling prostitutes, which is to
say, about pimps. It prohibits procuring and soliciting. Offenders may be
imprisoned for up to ten years. And if they procure prostitutes under the age
of eighteen, up to fourteen years. Even if they procure someone under
eighteen for “consideration,” they are guilty of an indictable offence and
liable to imprisonment for up to five years.
But section 213, about communicating in public for prostitution, is really
the main one. According to subsection 1 of section 213, “every person who
in a public place or in any place open to public view (a) stops or attempts to
stop any motor vehicle, (b) impedes the free flow of pedestrian or vehicular
traffic of ingress or egress from premises adjacent to that place, or (c) stops
or attempts to stop any person or in any manner communicates or attempts
to communicate with any person for the purpose of engaging in prostitution
or of obtaining the sexual services of a prostitute is guilty of an offence
punishable on summary conviction.” According to subsection 2, “public
place” includes motor vehicles that can be seen by the public. In short, this
law tries to prevent communicating in public, because it creates a
“nuisance” for the community that many people want most to eliminate.
Out of sight, out of mind.
In 1998, Justice Canada produced its “Report and Recommendations in
Respect of Legislation, Policy and Practices Concerning Prostitution-
Related Activities,” which revisited the legislation to see if anything should
be changed or added.22 The report revealed many differences of opinion.
Some arose during consultations with advocacy groups for women and
prostitutes. Others arose from conflicts within the working group. After
discussing the pros and cons of each proposal, the latter made several
recommendations but also admitted that “there was a great deal of
confusion about the current legal status of prostitution in Canada.”23 Those
testifying did not always know precisely what was legal, for instance, or
illegal. “Although prostitution in Canada is not illegal, most prostitution-
related activities are. This creates confusion among the public and does not
tell prostitutes or customers where and under what circumstances they can
meet.”24
Street prostitutes, defined in section 213, were the main focus of these
discussions. They had always been the main target of police, for two
reasons.25 First, they were associated with an unwholesome atmosphere in
neighbourhoods. Second, they were associated with violence at the hands of
both pimps and customers. These two problems are closely related, because
eliminating street prostitutes from communities means merely moving them
to less visible places such as dark streets and parks, industrial districts, or
remote country roads. And doing so makes it easier for criminals to hide
their drugs and their assaults and murders.26 The working group
acknowledged this but pointed out that not much could be done legally at
the local level, because Canadian laws governing prostitution are federal.
Some members of the working group worried that the current legislation
penalized the poor (prostitutes) and favoured the rich (residents and
landowners or business owners). More expensive prostitutes, who plied
their trade discretely, were not bothered by the police; others, who did so on
the streets, were routinely arrested by the police.27
Feminists influenced the report, even though they could not always agree
on precisely what would be best for women. One solution was to create
harsher penalties for prostitutes.28 Some feminists disagreed because that
would make life even harder for them. A second solution was to create
separate offences for prostitutes and customers.29 A third was for the police
to leave prostitutes alone and arrest only their customers.30 Some feminists
considered it a good way of bringing more customers to court than ever
before. Appearing in court involves mandatory fingerprinting and
photographing, after all, which make it easier to track repeat offenders from
one place to another and from one offence to another. This measure, some
believed, would actually deter customers, because most would be ashamed
to appear in court in these circumstances.31 Because this solution would
eliminate specific offenses for prostitutes, however, some feminists worried
that the police would charge them instead merely for loitering. Other
feminists worried that this, in turn, would merely give prostitutes longer
criminal records than they already had, because fingerprinted prostitutes,
too, would be easier to track.32
Therefore, although some members wanted harsher sentences or
sentences only against customers, the working group did not recommend
these measures. They believed that section 213 referred merely to a
“nuisance offence,” that the rate of recidivism was low, and that legislation
was unlikely to solve the problem of street prostitution in any case. Instead,
the working group recommended that federal, provincial, and territorial
governments provide better resources for prostitutes, including “safe
accommodation, crisis intervention and counseling for those who desire
assistance in leaving the sex trade … [and] treatment and counseling
particularly with respect to sexually-transmitted diseases and alcohol and
drug abuse.”33
Some members wanted to help prostitutes leave the business by
providing them with job training and job placement. They pointed to a
program for prostitutes in Toronto called Streetlight, which includes a day-
long class about choices and an eight-week “life skills program.” Funds
generated by a “john school” pay for the latter. Similar programs exist in
Ottawa and Edmonton.34 The working group “urged [communities] to
recognize the importance of specialized exit programs.”35 Some members
of the working group argued that fear of violent reprisals makes it hard for
prostitutes to present evidence against customers and pimps. Therefore,
officials should come up with strategies to “help equalize this power
differential.”36 They could use screens in courtrooms, closed-circuit TV or
videotapes, out-of-court testimony, or phone tapping. The working group
recommended these measures.
As for customers, the working group was even more divided. There was
a hot debate over measures to punish them – revoking or suspending their
driving licenses, impounding their cars, and shaming them. Some American
communities broadcast the names of customers. Other communities send
letters to the homes of clients, a measure that has been known to cause
divorces. The working group failed to reach a consensus but recommended
continued study of these measures.
In John Lowman’s estimation, the mixed messages of Canadian law on
prostitution have made the “john” into a folk devil.37 The “john schools” set
up by some Canadian communities are designed to “reeducate” customers
at their own expense, either on a pre-charge basis (which eliminates the
necessity of appearing in court) or a post-charge basis (when attendance at
these schools functions as the sentence or part of it). The day’s curriculum
typically includes lectures by experts on how street prostitution damages
neighbourhoods, by ex-prostitutes on how much suffering the “trade”
caused them (which, we are told, helps these ex-prostitutes “heal”),38 and
by medics on sexually transmitted diseases. The working group
recommended that communities be allowed to decide for themselves about
the usefulness of john schools but also “urged [them] to recognize the
importance of specialized exit programs for female, male and transgender
prostitutes who wish to leave the sex trade as an integral component of the
community’s attack on street prostitution.”39 Yet other strategies involved
prostitutes and members of communities meeting together to resolve
differences, through mediation if necessary.

The most extreme position on pornography and prostitution is surely that of


Catharine MacKinnon and her pal Andrea Dworkin, so a brief introduction
to their work is in order here. The former is a very prominent lawyer,
academic, and activist,40 the latter a very well-known writer and activist.41
Dworkin is often dismissed by liberal feminists, expediently, as a member
of the lunatic fringe. In other words, they either say or imply, she need not
be taken seriously. Yet we do take her seriously. After all, MacKinnon
does.42 And MacKinnon has had a major impact on legislation not only in
the United States, her own country, but also in Canada.
As a lawyer, MacKinnon is probably more directly influential than
Dworkin. Her legal strategies are evident in Toward a Feminist Theory of
the State, where she discusses “feminist jurisprudence” in the context of a
radically transformed society. Elsewhere, she discusses the need to focus
attention on civil cases rather than criminal ones.43 Because criminal cases
require a very stringent standard of evidence, jurors must be convinced
“beyond a reasonable doubt,” which makes it hard to convict men. In civil
suits, on the other hand, jurors are convinced merely by a “preponderance
of evidence.” That makes it easier than it would otherwise be to sue men
and win.
MacKinnon uses her background in political science to analyze the
politics that keeps women subservient. She opposes both the political right
(with its morality talk) and the political left (with its freedom talk). Both,
she believes, keep violence against women invisible and irrelevant.44 She is
openly hostile toward those, including women, who disagree with her and
routinely accuses them of insensitivity to women’s pain (since they reject
the politics of victimization) and selling out to men (by playing the political
game of “divide and conquer”).45 She is much more hostile to men, of
course. Even the best of them, she taunts, are cowed by the mass media.
Others are, well, men. MacKinnon’s entire worldview is based on power –
that is, the power that men have over women (and, by implication, the
power that women should have over men).
As MacKinnon sees it, the problems faced by women are all due,
directly or indirectly, to a titanic conspiracy of men against women. The
conspirators come from both sides of the political spectrum, are driven by
sex and money, and bring together a wide range of pursuits such as
journalism, entertainment, publishing, crime, teaching, research, and law.
Their power is seldom obvious. When challenged, she says, they resort to
the First Amendment as an opportunistic way of protecting their interests.
Politicians, lawyers, and academicians, she claims, have all cowered before
this political bloc.46
Even though MacKinnon relied heavily on Marxism, at first, feminism
led her to the belief that a new and independent analysis was necessary for
women.47 Dworkin agrees. When it comes to women, she says, the political
left sold out and thus directly or indirectly joined the right. Only women
now remain on the left: “Far to the left, off the mainstream continuum – at
least as currently articulated in popular discourse – are women whose
politics are animated by a commitment to listening to those who have been
hurt and finding remedies that are fair.”48 All men belong, moreover, to the
culture of “dead white males.” Listen to her:

In addition to romanticizing forced sex and celebrating sexual exploitation,


the Left has joined the Right in defending the culture of dead white men:
protecting it from criticism or change; keeping it inviolate, immune from
contamination by creative persons not dead or white or male. The culture of
dead white men, built on the bodies of silenced women and colonialized
people of color, has become a weapon to keep living women of all races
silent. Like a private club that keeps out all but an elite few, art and books
especially are used to tell the emerging women – emerging not only from
silence but often enough from hell – that they are not good enough or
important enough or worthy enough to be listened to. The proof of their
insignificance is in their suffering: having been raped or beaten or
prostituted. Was Aristotle? Was Descartes? Why listen to women who are
more pleasing laid out flat, legs spread, than standing up, talking back,
talking real? Why should the men of liberation interrupt the liberatory act
itself to listen to the person whose hole he was sticking it in? And if I were
to say that hole is not empty space waiting to be filled by anyone or
anything, what would my authority be? How do I know? But he knows –
every “he” knows.49

As we say, many feminists argue that Dworkin is nothing more than a


vocal member of the radical fringe. Why take Dworkin or any other
extremist seriously? And why pay the price, in any case, for doing so? Men
who take ideological feminism seriously and speak out against it are
routinely attacked as misogynists (even though the same accusation is flung
at men who fail to take it seriously). But remember that MacKinnon is
Dworkin’s chief collaborator. And no one can accuse her of living on the
fringes of legal or political circles. Au contraire. Professionally, MacKinnon
is a member of the academic and legal elite.50 In other words, her ideas
almost inevitably influence the feminist mainstream. These two, but
especially MacKinnon, have had an enormous impact on legislation to
protect women from men.
Martha Nussbaum understands Dworkin’s approach as retributive, being
based on revenge. She takes a close look at Dworkin’s novel Mercy, which
tells the story of a woman named Andrea (surely no coincidence, especially
when many of the details of this woman’s life match those of her own
biography of abuse by men).

This novel does not read like a novel because its form expresses the
retributive idea that its message preaches. That is, it refuses to perceive any
of the male offenders – or any other male – as a particular individual, and it
refuses to invite the reader into the story of their lives. Like Andrea, it can’t
tell him from him from him. The reader hears only the solitary voice of the
narrator; others exist for her only as sources of her pain. Like the women in
the male pornography that Dworkin decries, her males have no history, no
psychology, no concrete reasons for action. They are just knives that cut,
arms that beat, penises that maim by the very act of penetration. Dworkin’s
refusal of the traditional novelist’s attention to the stories of particular lives
seems closely connected with her heroine’s refusal to be merciful to any of
those lives, with her doctrine that justice is cruel and hard.51

By now it should be clear that we are dealing not only with culturally
promoted gynocentrism but also with legally promoted misandry, which is
the point we are trying to make throughout this book. Dworkin’s men are
generic objects, not human characters. It is easy, therefore, to treat them –
and punish them – as a class. Whether any man is guilty or not of any
specific crime, he must pay along with others of his class. “The inclination
to mercy is present in the text only as a fool’s inclination toward
collaboration and slavery. When the narrator, entering her new profession as
a karate-killer of homeless men, enunciates the ‘politic principle which
went as follows: It is very important for women to kill men,’ a voice within
the text suggests the explanations that might lead to mercy. As the return of
the narrator quickly makes clear, this is meant to be a parody voice, a fool’s
voice, the voice of a collaborator with the enemy.”52
MacKinnon’s basic argument against porn is that women are doubly
“violated” by it: first by its production and then by its consumption. Even if
it does not lead to the physical violation of women, she opines, the mere
sight of porn, the very existence of it, constitutes a violation of women.
From this point of view, one finding of researchers seems particularly
interesting. The keywords describing oral sex in clinical terms get a
lukewarm response from users of the net, but those describing it in more
imaginative terms (such as “choking”) get an enthusiastic response. “Such
findings,” writes one journalist, “may cheer antipornography activists; as
Dworkin puts it, ‘the whole purpose of pornography is to hurt women.’”53
But is it? This would certainly be news to the gay men who enjoy porn –
unless, of course, you argue that they secretly hate men and want to hurt
them. Because almost every feminist assumes that the appeal of porn is not
merely vulgar but sinister, this claim is worth discussing here in more
detail.
Dworkin believes that pornography and prostitution are based on a
“commerce in women,” a free market where women are bought and sold. A
woman, she argues, “is meat in [a man’s] marketplace; he is the butcher
who wields the knife to get the right cut; and he communicates through the
cutting, then the display of the body parts. She is worth more in pieces than
she ever was whole.”54 Elsewhere, she refers to the “colonialization of
women’s bodies for male pleasure.”55 This process, she says, is based on
male sexual force (which supposedly brings men pleasure) and male sexual
exploitation (which brings a few of them fortunes). And all this depends on
“dominance and submission as a dynamic and the ‘objectification’ of
women as a fundamental element of pleasure.”56 Commerce itself is okay,
says Dworkin, unless it involves the exploitation of labour. (She must be
using that word in its popular sense of excessive exploitation, because its
technical sense can refer merely to anyone who works for others.) But
commerce in human beings is not. That amounts to buying and selling
people, to slavery.57
Many feminists are troubled by the existence of pornography and
prostitution because they believe that these not only “objectify” women (a
word that we discuss below) but also place women in a subordinate position
and therefore both condone and encourage violence against them.
MacKinnon and Dworkin pointed out that efforts to curb or reform it have
been notoriously unsuccessful. With that in mind, they promoted a series of
amendments to the ordinances of several cities. The idea was to ban porn
for violating women’s civil rights, preventing them from participating freely
and fully in public life due to either violence or fear of violence. Their best-
known campaigns focused directly on porn, but their opposition to
prostitution was based on the same reasoning. In Indianapolis, the city
council found that

Pornography is a systematic practice of exploitation and subordination


based on sex, which differentially harms women. The bigotry and contempt
it promotes, with the acts of aggression it fosters, harms women’s
opportunities for equality of rights in employment, education, access to and
use of public accommodations, and acquisition of real property; promotes
rape, battery, child abuse, kidnapping and prostitution … and contributes
significantly to restricting women in particular from full exercise of
citizenship and participation in public life.58

In its amended ordinance, write James Jacobs and Kimberly Potter, the city
“prohibited the production, distribution, exhibition, or sale of pornography
and the display of pornography in any place of employment, school, public
place, or private home … created a civil cause of action for persons
coerced, intimidated, or tricked into appearing in a pornographic work; and
… provided victims of sexual violence a cause of action against sellers of
the pornography.”59 In Hudnut v. American Booksellers Association, a case
of 1986, this ordinance was challenged by the Seventh Circuit Court of
Appeals (a challenge that was later upheld by the Supreme Court).60 At
issue were the First Amendment (which protects freedom of speech) and the
definition of porn (which was too broad or vague).
MacKinnon and Dworkin proposed an even stronger ordinance for
Minneapolis, but it was challenged and struck down for similar reasons.
Porn, according to the Minneapolis proposal, is

a concrete description of the materials the pornography industry makes and


sells: graphic sexually explicit materials that subordinate women and
others. It is not a description of any ideas … By contrast with the
Indianapolis version of the ordinance, this definition is not restricted to
violent material. This is because the violence of pornography is not limited
to materials that show violence. Women are coerced into materials that
show no violence. Rapists use materials showing what appears to be
consenting sex to stimulate their rapes and to select their targets. Children
are abused to make pornography that shows no violence. Pornography
showing no violence is violently forced on women and children.61

The Minneapolis ordinance would have prevented coerced performances


to be used for porn, although their definition of “coerced” was debatable.
Among the facts not allowed by the defense, according to the Minneapolis
ordinance, would have been that

the person is a woman or … [that] the person is or has been a prostitute …


[that] the person has attained the age of majority … [that] the person is
connected by blood or marriage to anyone involved in or related to the
making of the pornography … [that] the person has previously had, or been
thought to have had, sexual relations with anyone, including anyone
involved in or related to the making of the pornography … [that] the person
has previously posed for sexually explicit pictures with or for anyone,
including anyone involved in or related to the pornography at issue … [that]
anyone else, including a spouse or other relative, has given or purported to
give permission on the person’s behalf … [that] the person actually
consented to a use of a performance that is later changed into pornography
… [that] the person knew that the purpose of the acts or events in question
was to make pornography … [that] the person showed no resistance or
appeared to cooperate actively in the photographic sessions or in the events
that produce the pornography … [that] the person signed a contract, or
made statements affirming a willingness to cooperate in the production of
pornography … [that] no physical force, threats, or weapons were used in
the making of the pornography … or [that] the person was paid or otherwise
compensated.62

Most of these stipulations make sense, but the last five are highly
problematic indeed. MacKinnon and Dworkin defended them by arguing
that most of the women who appear in porn are poor and powerless.
Therefore, they are incapable of giving informed consent to the publishers.
And therefore, their participation is “coerced.” This is the same argument
used elsewhere against any sexual relations between men and women,
according to which women are “powerless” almost by definition. Therefore,
they are incapable of giving men informed consent. And therefore, all
sexual relations between them and men are “coerced” – which is to say,
they are rapes. Apart from any other problems – and we can think of several
very important moral ones – one is of particular importance in a specifically
legal context: the assumption that grown women must not be treated as
adults and held responsible for their own behaviour.
MacKinnon and Dworkin argued that no one would use the First
Amendment to challenge this ordinance, because that document does not
protect people from coercion. Moreover, the ordinance would have banned
only the “graphic, sexually explicit subordination of women, whether in
pictures or words …”63 Clever wording would have excluded not only
highbrow literature but also middlebrow movies and even some lowbrow
erotica. (This was a concession to political expediency; both MacKinnon
and Dworkin believe that all sexually suggestive representations of women
are, in fact, degrading forms of “objectification” and really ought to be
banned.) In short, the ordinance was designed to avoid challenges.
Nevertheless, this ordinance and many similar ones were defeated.
According to MacKinnon, these defeats were due to a conspiracy of liberals
and pornographers, a “cabal” that included some misguided women who
chose either foolishly or deceptively to support an abstraction – freedom of
expression – over the civil right of women to freedom from real fear.64
McKinnon’s role in this matter began during the 1980s.65 She won some
cases and lost others. Her most important victory came in 1988. As a
consultant to the Legal Defense and Action Fund (operated by the National
Organization for Women) in Louis Robinson v. Jacksonville Shipyards,66
she argued that porn constitutes a “hostile environment” for women;
displaying it in the workplace, therefore, qualified as sexual harassment
under Title VII of the Civil Rights Act of 1964. MacKinnon’s efforts to
make porn illegal in the United States were ineffective in all cases except
for that one, which linked porn with a “hostile working environment” and
therefore with sexual harassment. What did her in most often was the First
Amendment, a cornerstone of the legal system and even of national identity.
For various reasons, MacKinnon has been more successful at banning
porn in Canada than in the United States. She has worked closely with the
Legal Education and Action Fund (LEAF) for many years. In R. v.
Keegstra,67 she provided an important affidavit and a factum for LEAF’s
intervention before the Supreme Court.68 Here is MacKinnon’s own
summary of the case: “leaf had successfully argued before the Canadian
Supreme Court that racist and anti-Semitic hate propaganda violates
equality and multiculturalism rights under the new Charter, so criminalizing
such expression is constitutional.”69 In other words, the government may
limit freedom of expression in order to promote the equality of traditionally
disadvantaged groups.70 Even though this particular case was not
specifically about porn, it provided a basis for an extremely important one
that was: R. v. Butler.71 Donald Butler defended his right to own and
distribute porn against criminal prosecution under Canada’s obscenity law.
To do so, he cited Canada’s Charter of Rights and Freedoms. In other
words, he challenged “the constitutionality of section 163 of the Criminal
Code, which prohibits the sale of ‘obscene’ materials … any publication a
dominant characteristic of which is the undue exploitation of sex, or of sex
and any one or more of the following subjects, namely, crime, horror,
cruelty and violence.”72 Dworkin sent LEAF a letter in which she argued
against using criminal law because it requires a higher standard of proof
than civil law and thus results in fewer convictions. MacKinnon agreed, but
she decided nonetheless to work with leaf. The Court ruled that the
government may limit freedom of expression in order

to prevent harm to society rather than to impose any particular standard of


public or sexual morality. According to the Court, obscenity is harmful
because it communicates a degrading and dehumanizing message that is
“analogous to that of hate propaganda.” Consistent with LEAF’s position, the
Court declared that the particular harm avoided by regulating pornography
is “the degradation which many women feel as ‘victims’ of the message of
obscenity, and of the negative impact exposure to such material has on
perceptions and attitudes towards women.”73

Please note, however, that this ruling involved a double standard. Material
that degrades women (even if produced by and for gay women) is now
illegal in Canada, but material that degrades men (even if produced by and
for gay men) might remain legal.
Every case is about the specific behaviours of specific people and their
effects on other people, of course. Butler was specifically about several
films that allegedly depict women in ways that are harmful to all women.
Every case sets a legal precedent, moreover, being directly or indirectly
about similar behaviours by similar people. That is why judges not only cite
legal precedents but also discuss legal and social consequences. Not
surprisingly, the court focused very heavily on pornography as a
phenomenon that can harm women (and therefore society as a whole).
Unfortunately, the court barely paid lip service to pornography as a
phenomenon that can harm men.
Now and then, to be sure, the court describes material that “could be said
to dehumanize men or women.”74 But these statements are extraneous to
the main arguments and do not form any consistent pattern. They give the
impression, therefore, of being inserted to make the discussion politically
correct. After all, the Charter does guarantee sexual equality. It is hard,
therefore, to take these statements seriously. Moreover, some statements
actually cast doubt on the very possibility that pornography can have
harmful effects on men. Consider the following: “Harm in this context
means that it predisposes persons to act in an anti-social manner as, for
example, the physical or mental mistreatment of women by men, or, what is
perhaps debatable, the reverse.”75 Nowhere does anyone acknowledge that
popular culture – mainstream popular culture – routinely portrays men in
negative ways and that some women act accordingly, whether in connection
with mental mistreatment of men or (as we show in chapter 9) physical
mistreatment. Nowhere, moreover, does anyone acknowledge that gay porn
routinely presents men as “willing victims” of other men. To acknowledge
that, of course, would be to provoke a political conflict with gay people.
Even though the Charter does require equal treatment under the law for
women and men, therefore, that requirement remains an empty abstraction
when the needs of men are at stake. Public rhetoric about equality
notwithstanding, the legal system remains mired in notions that generate
inequality. This is an example of what we call “systemic discrimination”
against men. It seems most unlikely that any Canadian official would try to
clamp down on pornography produced by and for gay men on the grounds
that it degrades men. Anyone inclined to do so, at any rate, could hardly use
Butler as a precedent.
In addition, the Supreme Court agreed with LEAF that it was unnecessary
to prove the existence of a causal link between porn and violence. It was
necessary only to show the existence of a “reasoned apprehension of
harm.”76 Moreover, it was easier to solve the problem by banning obscene
materials than by restricting them. This was indeed a major victory for
MacKinnon in her – and LEAF’s – campaign to outlaw porn. She and
Dworkin concluded that

in the United States, our Anti-Pornography Civil Rights Ordinance –


together with related legislative initiatives against the harms of racist hate
speech – has helped to trigger an escalating constitutional conflict between
“speech” rights guaranteed by the First Amendment and “equality” rights in
the principles underlying the Fourteenth Amendment. In our neighbor
nation to the north, Canada’s Supreme Court has determined that racist hate
expression is unconstitutional (Keegstra) and that society’s interest in sex
equality outweighs pornographers’ speech rights (Butler). Taken together,
these two rulings are a breakthrough in equality jurisprudence, representing
major victories for women and all people targeted for race hate. We wish
that U.S. constitutional consciousness were so far along.77

Calling Butler “a stunning victory for women,”78 MacKinnon praised


Canada for being “the first place in the world that says what is obscene is
what harms women, not what offends our values.”79 Several years later,
though, she was back-peddling real fast. In a press release of 1994, she and
Dworkin responded to criticisms that Butler was being used by Canada
Customs to stop feminist, gay, and lesbian materials – including some
books by Dworkin herself! – from entering the country.
They began their defense by arguing that “Canada has not adopted our
civil rights law against pornography. It has not adopted our statutory
definition of pornography; it has not adopted our civil (as opposed to
criminal) approach to pornography; nor has Canada adopted any of the five
civil causes of action we proposed (coercion, assault, force, trafficking,
defamation).”80 After describing the history of their involvement in the
case, they argued that there had been a long-standing practice by Canada
Customs to stop gay and lesbian materials. Therefore, the current situation
had had nothing to do with Butler. Besides, they argued, Butler had actually
improved the situation for gays, because restrictions could no longer be
based on the ground that some works are immoral but only on the ground
that they would harm women (which gay porn, at least the kind addressed
to gay men as distinct from gay women, would not do). Even so, they had
to acknowledge one anomaly. Lesbian porn would be caught in the net,
after all, if it were suspected of harming women.81 Obviously, neither
MacKinnon nor Dworkin believed that men, with their godlike power,
could be harmed by anything. Or cared one way or the other in any case.
Clearly, the war on porn has been waged on different battlefronts in the
two countries. Americans have resisted the idea of making it illegal
(although they have done so in connection with the involvement of
children) mainly because of the importance they attach to freedom of
expression. Canadians, on the other hand, have resisted the idea that
freedom of expression is more important than the equality of “historically
disadvantaged groups.” And those groups, they say, include women. The
Canadian definition of (illegal) porn ostensibly excludes erotica, but it
includes not only the link between sex and crime, horror, cruelty, or
violence but also the “degradation” of women for the pleasure of men.82 Yet
the latter is a very vague notion. As MacKinnon and Dworkin themselves
have argued, after all, it can be identified with any sexual contact at all
between men and women.
Before concluding our discussion of this extreme position, it is worth
pointing out that not everyone who agrees with it can be identified with
radical feminists. Who could be more mainstream that Gloria Steinem? It
was she who led a crusade against a controversial movie, The People vs
Larry Flynt, with an essay in the New York Times.83 Her main point was
that this movie about the publisher of Hustler magazine had cleaned up the
image of an evil man. Instead of protesting, critics had glorified the movie
along with the man himself as a tribute to his crusade for freedom of
speech. There is something deeply disturbing, to be sure, about both Flynt
and his magazine. Month after month, it reproduces images that are
neurotically grotesque, not erotically beautiful or innocently playful. Should
they be banned? If not as obscenity, which is notoriously hard to define,
then as hate literature?
These questions were surely worth asking. But Steinem’s own bias
added nothing to the debate. “My question is: Would men be portrayed as
inviting, deserving and even enjoying their own pain and degradation, as
women are in Mr. Flynt’s life work?”84 Actually, they are. For decades, in
fact, men have been portrayed in precisely that way. Not usually in
connection with sex, it is true, although there have been some notable cases
of that. One example would be Somerset Maugham’s Of Human Bondage,
either in print or on film. Philip, the protagonist, is nothing if not
masochistic in his love for a cruel waitress. Far more common, though, is
the masochism expected of men in connection with war and other kinds of
violence. If you are going to argue against violent porn for dehumanizing
women, you should at least be prepared to argue against other material for
dehumanizing men.

Not all feminists have joined the crusade against porn. Some liberal
feminists, for instance, want to safeguard freedom of expression. In
Defending Pornography, Nadine Strossen argues that censorship does more
harm than good to women. To oppose porn, she says, is to undermine the
argument for women’s equality and autonomy. If men are allowed to enjoy
porn, after all, then why not women? This is a technical argument for legal
equality. Maybe Strossen believes that most women, unlike men, would
choose not to act on this form of equality. But how many feminist or other
critics of her book have challenged the idea that porn is a necessary evil,
which implies that sex itself is no more than a necessary evil? In his article
on this topic for Time, at any rate, Philip Elmer-Dewitt mentions not one.
Because he makes it clear that porn is “a guy thing,” statistically, the
implication is that there is something necessarily evil about men
themselves. Strossen’s attitude to porn, and therefore to sex, is by no means
unusual, although it is unusual for a feminist.85
The notion that sex is a necessary evil at best has had a long history,
unfortunately, in the West. During the Hellenistic period, gnosticism – a
profoundly dualistic worldview that was characterized by extreme
polarization between matter or “flesh” (which had negative connotations)
and spirit or mind (which had positive ones) – entered both Greco-Roman
and Jewish writings. It entered early Christianity, therefore, from not one
but both of its primary sources.86 The result, which can be seen in writings
as early as those of St Paul, was an aversion to the material world in general
and to sex in particular. Given their belief that the world was about to end,
the earliest Christians reacted appropriately. It became clear to them very
quickly, however, that the Second Coming and establishment of God’s
Kingdom would be postponed. In that case, they would have to plan for the
future of a Christian social order. And they did find ways of affirming sex
within marriage for practical purposes, partly by drawing on the mainly pre-
Hellenistic Old Testament tradition, which had a relatively “high” view of
sex and marriage.
Catholics are ambivalent about sex to this day, because they
acknowledge the authority of two quite different (though not contradictory)
traditions. According to Augustinian theology, sex transmits Original Sin,
along with life, from one generation to another. According to natural law,
sex within marriage has the legitimate function of procreation. The result is
a reasonable compromise. Procreative marriage is a legitimate ideal for
most people, but asceticism is an even higher ideal for the few.
Most Protestant communities have rejected monastic asceticism, along
with many other features of the Catholic worldview, but have nonetheless
fostered more subtle forms of the ascetic ideal. This is true especially of
Calvinists, who created the founding cultures of both the United States and
English Canada. Some Protestants have looked with greater suspicion on
sensual or even aesthetic pleasure of any kind, in fact, than Catholics have.
But all Christians are tied to founding documents – including, at least, the
New Testament itself – that are ambivalent about material existence in
general and about sexual behaviour in particular.
No matter what its historical origin, the fact remains that profound
anxiety about sex is very common in our culture. And this is true of
feminists no less than of other people. Some feminists argue that
(heterosexual) sex is an unnecessary evil. Others argue that it is a necessary
evil. Still others that it is liberating.

Some feminists question the primacy of “objectification” in connection with


pornography and prostitution. In Sex and Social Justice, Nussbaum argues
that MacKinnon and Dworkin have “totalized” it.87 (We would add that
they have endorsed a totalitarian mentality.) As evidence, she points to
MacKinnon’s statement that “[a]ll women live in sexual objectification the
way fish live in water.”88 Nussbaum identifies at least seven ways of
understanding objectification: instrumentality, denial of autonomy,
inertness, fungibility (that is, interchangeability with other objects of the
same type), violability, ownership, and denial of subjectivity. Some are
morally problematic, she suggests, but others are problematic only in this or
that context. Still others are necessary or even desirable. Nonetheless,
Nussbaum applauds MacKinnon and Dworkin for two things.
First, she applauds them for describing the socialization of women into
subservience and the resulting deformation of their desire – that is, the
alleged “eroticization of male power” and female passivity.89 According to
MacKinnon and Dworkin, women are culturally conditioned to be sexually
aroused by male power and men by female powerlessness. As for the
former, this has probably always been true about men as providers, if only
because a mate with access to material resources – economic power – has
always been in the interest of any woman and her children or potential
children. Moreover, the wives and children of men with high prestige –
social power – often enjoy additional advantages. But MacKinnon,
Dworkin, and Nussbaum are referring to something else entirely, something
far more sinister: sexual aggression – physical power – as the ultimate
source of erotic appeal. Women, they say, have been conditioned to find
male brutality sexually attractive. This comes dangerously close to the
notion that women are masochists and want to be raped (which would, in
any case, be a contradiction in terms). When rapists say so, the implication
is that women are biologically programmed to enjoy rape and culturally
programmed to deny it. In that case, there can be no such thing as rape. In
other words, “no” really must mean “yes.” When some feminists say the
same thing, however, the implication is that women have been culturally
programmed to enjoy what amounts to rape. And all acts of heterosexual
intercourse really are rapes, from this point of view, because women, dupes
of “the patriarchy” one and all, have been rendered incapable of truly giving
their consent. Yes, women want to be raped, they argue, but only because
men have made them that way! This point clearly lies at the very heart of
what MacKinnon and Dworkin, along with Nussbaum, are saying.
Moreover, Nussbaum applauds MacKinnon and Dworkin for extending
the “Kantian” tradition of demanding that people – in this case, women – be
treated as ends and not merely as means to other ends. But she adds that
objectification actually can occur within relationships characterized by
equality and mutuality. Nussbaum argues, pace MacKinnon and Dworkin,
that it is indeed morally permissible or even desirable to treat the other
(temporarily) as passive or inert, see the other’s genital organs as wonderful
objects, or surrender autonomy to the other. Porn might even be useful in
the effort to overcome puritanism, she says, and delegitimate the repression
(by men, presumably) of female eroticism. (Judging from the productions
of both popular and elite culture, we suggest that it would be hard to
imagine a society less puritanical or less sexually repressed than our own is
at the moment – with the notable exception of feminists who insist on
“sexual correctness.”)90 Nussbaum is less certain than MacKinnon and
Dworkin, in this context, that “bad objectification” is rooted in “deformed
desire,” in the “eroticization of male power.” It might be rooted, she admits
here, merely in a culture of commodification.
In any case, Nussbaum opposes even civil ordinances against porn.
These, she says, would probably be administered inadequately. Worse, they
would jeopardize “expressive interests” (such as elite literature, say, or
photography) and even prevent us from learning about sexism. Besides, it
might be very hard to establish a causal relation between porn and any
particular harm (although that would present no problem in Canada, where
lawyers need only show a “reasoned apprehension of harm.”) Although
Nussbaum does not believe that porn should be illegal, she does believe that
it is immoral. And she wants impressionable young men, at least straight
ones, to know why. She has no use for those who excuse porn by saying
that “boys will be boys” or even canonize pornographers in the name of free
speech.
Because Nussbaum sees herself as a liberal, she protects freedom of
speech from legal controls and subjects it instead to moral controls. The
idea is still to eliminate porn, of course, but not by abridging freedom of
speech. We believe that her moral argument against porn is somewhat
facile. Only in an ideal world would we treat all people in all circumstances
as ends in themselves rather than as means to other ends.
But this is not an ideal world. To act on this moral premise, to treat
everyone as a “thou” instead of an “it,”91 would make daily life impossible.
The fact is that we must make distinctions between the few people we love
intimately and the many other people we live and work with. We must
“use” or “objectify” the latter, even though we should do so respectfully. In
some situations, especially within families or communities, that might
involve reciprocity based on mutual obligation or common cause. In others,
it might involve simple (but generous or at least adequate) payment for
services rendered. No one should seriously believe in any moral obligation
to set every commercial transaction, say, within the context of a
“meaningful relationship” or one based on “mutuality and equality.” In
short, treating people as the means to some other end is not necessarily
immoral.92
Two arguments, easily confused, refer to means and ends. One of them,
which we do not make here, is about the end justifying the means – that is,
about a noble end justifying an evil means. For two reasons, we are not
suggesting that porn be justified as the evil means (tolerating the
objectification of people) that is necessary to attain a noble end
(maintaining freedom of speech). First, we do not believe that any evil
means (except killing in self-defence) can be justified by any noble end.
That is why we oppose all ideologies, which rest on precisely that belief.
Second, we do not believe that either sex or (nonviolent) porn is inherently
evil in the first place.
The other argument, which we do make, is about people as either means
or ends. We argue here that all people are ultimately ends in themselves, but
we have just acknowledged that some legitimate or even necessary
interactions with other people in daily life would be impossible on that
basis. We see no harm in treating other people as the means to other ends in
some circumstances as long as doing so does not involve harm. And there is
nothing harmful, at least not on secular grounds, about sex between
consenting adults.
Another problem with antiporn rhetoric is that “objectification” and
“domination” are very nebulous words and have therefore easily been
turned into ideological jargon. Given the interest of ideological feminists in
litigating their way to power, that should come as no surprise. How many
people actually think about what “objectification” means or ask whether it
is always evil, or, for that matter, if women alone are objectified? How
many people actually think about the various ways in which people can
“dominate” each other, moreover, or realize that women can be no less
adept at it than men?
Wendy McElroy, too, argues against the censorship of porn (and, by
implication, the banning of prostitution). But she has a different reason.
Instead of classifying erotica as a necessary evil, she classifies that kind of
porn as a good thing for women no less than for men. Having interviewed
women who work in the industry, in connection with her book XXX: A
Woman’s Right to Pornography, she notes that, far from being victims,
these women are liberators.93 In fact, they are members of the “sexual
elite.” They make their own choices, for one thing, including the choice of
discarding outmoded sexual mores. They enjoy what they do, moreover,
because they could not put on convincing performances otherwise. But
McElroy goes further. She rejects the notion that their (male) employers are
wicked exploiters. Even they, she says, have moral standards. Violence,
being fantasy, is always simulated. And not all violent fantasies are
permitted. McElroy conludes that the main problems for these women
(assuming that only women are involved) are relatively low pay from their
employers and even less respect from the public.
McElroy’s main point is simply that erotic porn is good for women. It
gives them a safe place to be sexually playful in an otherwise dangerous
world. It stimulates their imagination, encouraging women to explore their
own sexuality beyond conventional boundaries. But some readers will draw
the conclusion that these boundaries were established by men and thus
constitute the real exploitation: tying sex to marriage and reproduction, for
example, and demeaning women who actually enjoy sex. So women can
turn feminist theory on its head but still come out attacking men! Men are
evil both for encouraging women to participate in pornographic behaviour
and for failing to do so. Either way, it would seem, men are wrong.

In both the United States and Canada, there has been plenty of conflict over
freedom of expression. Should we limit free speech to prevent
discrimination? Or should we limit discrimination by preventing free
speech? This brings us to the topic of hate literature. According to Jacobs
and Potter, the modern nation has had a long history of trying to suppress
dangerous forms of free expression. Why allow anyone to promote
prejudice based on race, nationality, or ethnicity? Jacobs and Potter
conclude that “unlike most other countries in the world, in the United States
these laws have not withstood judicial scrutiny or political judgment.
Tolerance for vile expression is the price we pay for the right to free
speech.”94 The Indianapolis ordinance promoted by Mackinnon and
Dworkin inspired Harvard Law School professor Laurence Tribe to point
out that “the First Amendment similarly protects advocacy … of the
opinion that women are meant to be dominated by men, or blacks to be
dominated by whites, or Jews by Christians, and that those so subordinated
not only deserve but subconsciously enjoy their humiliating treatment … It
is an inadequate response to argue, as do some scholars, that ordinances like
that enacted by Indianapolis take aim at harms, not at expression. All
viewpoint-based regulations are targeted at some supposed harm.”95
The Canadian Civil Liberties Association has gone to court over freedom
of expression and succeeded in 63% of its cases. It has failed, however, in
challenging the censorship of pornograpy and hate speech.96 Former
executive director Alan Borovoy argues that liberalism is now deeply
threatened by Charter litigants on the political left (even though his own
organization had had close ties with the Canadian trade unions).97 And,
according to F.L. Morton and Rainer Knopff, Butler involved an activist
and innovative approach to the interpretation of existing laws – in this case,
those that censor obscenity – to square with feminism: “No longer would
the law be interpreted as a bulwark of public morality against sexual
depravity; it would now be seen primarily as a way of protecting women
and children against male oppression. Consensual erotica would thus be
distinguished from the objectification of women for the pleasure of men.”98

At the heart of this debate is how we understand sexuality. We need to place


it in a larger context. This will involve a brief discussion of male biology
and cultural evolution.
Magnetic resonance imaging (MRI) records blood flow in the brain.
Bright yellow and deep orange on the computer screen reveal which parts
are being stimulated, and that, in turn, reveals the chemicals involved and
their functions. Men and women who claimed to be deeply and happily in
love were studied, using MRI, as they looked at pictures of each other and
pictures of other people. The finding showed differences between most men
and women. “In our sample, men tended to show more activity than women
in brain regions associated with visual processing whereas women showed
more activity in regions associated with motivation and attention,” writes
Helen Fisher, and “this male brain response may shed light on why men so
avidly support the worldwide trade in visual pornography.”99 Fisher
speculates that the connection between visualization and penile arousal is
due to the evolutionary importance of recognizing a suitable reproductive
partner. Women find reproductive partners not so much by looking at men
but by remembering which ones are most likely to provide for them and
their infants (which ones are not only strong but also smart, fearless,
generous, and so forth).
Suzanne Frayser, an anthropologist, points out that the instinctive aspects
of sexuality in human beings are always set within a context of cultural
meaning,100 that is, nature and culture are correlatives; culture guides nature
– our physical urges – to meet the reproductive needs on which we rely for
survival as families, as religious or ethnic communities, and even as a
species. We rely much less on instinct than other animals and much more on
adaptability. Culture must be flexible enough for adjustments to new
situations or environments but also conservative enough for protections to
ensure the intergeneration cycle – to ensure that most men and women are
brought together, produce children, and care for them until they reach
maturity and renew the cycle. Marriage – this institution is characteristic of
all societies, at all times, and in all places – is the cultural mechanism that
does these things.101
Even though marriage as a norm is universal, not all its features are;
some are nearly universal and others variable. In some societies, marriage is
mandatory, although exceptions are sometimes tolerated. In others,
exceptions are either officially or unofficially allowed. These might include
monastics, prostitutes, single people, and gay people. Given this general
mandate to ensure collective continuity, societies have handled sexuality in
various ways. Some overtly or covertly allow premarital sex. Others overtly
or covertly allow extramarital sex after marriage for men. Still others do so
for men but also for groups of women such as courtesans. That arrangement
has been common throughout history but is now attacked by feminists as
“male chauvinism,” “patriarchy,” “phallocentrism,” or whatever.
Nonetheless, its underlying rationale should not be understood so
reductively. Faithful wives make it possible for husbands to know who their
own children are and thus encourage fathers to invest resources in their
children accordingly. And at least before the welfare state, this was
important to women, who would otherwise have been on their own. They
intuited that this was a trade-off: of their own desire for sexual variety for
protection and resources.
Officially monogamous systems such as our own have placed
prohibitions on sex outside marriage, the goal being to foster exclusive
bonds between men and women. These prohibitions have led in some cases,
unofficially, to extramarital sex – usually, at least in the past, on the part of
men. And that, in turn, has led to feminist attacks on the double standard.
But most people in our society have inherited an even worse problem in the
early Christian belief that sex itself is a sign of “carnality” and thus of sin.
This attitude toward the material world, including that of the human body,
has had profound effects by now even on secular people. When Nussbaum
claims that any sexual activity is inherently contaminating unless it can be
cleansed by or subordinated to some “higher” purpose, she consciously or
unconsciously continues a long Western (but by no means a universal)
tradition.102
Sorry for that digression. Back now to the point. In the past, people
linked sex outside marriage mainly with prostitutes or with courtesans, their
elite counterparts. In a symbolic sense, though, they linked sex outside
marriage also with pornography. The latter is much more prevalent now,
after the advent of technologies that make mass production and distribution
possible, than it ever was. It not only competes with prostitution but also
displaces it to some extent. After all, porn eliminates some of the problems
that prostitution presents: unwanted pregnancy, say, and sexually
transmitted diseases. Because prostitution involves people (no matter how
objectified) rather than merely pictures, on the other hand, it still has one
obvious advantage over pornography: a greater illusion of intimacy. From a
comparative perspective, at any rate, it is clear that prostitution and
pornography have been banned mainly in monogamous traditions. And
even in these traditions, they have often gained unofficial acceptance. The
only question is why. We do not believe that feminists have provided an
adequate answer. We do believe that they, like the Christians that some of
them despise, are products of cultural and religious history.
Every society must promote the intergenerational cycle through some
form of marriage. With continuity thus ensured, it can afford to tolerate
exceptions to the norm. In our time, the main exception, at least in secular
circles, is consensual sex between adults who are neither married nor “in
committed relationships.” These people, especially those who intend to
marry, do not threaten the norm of marriage. Nor do they threaten the
stability of any particular marriage. As long as contraception prevents
unwanted pregnancies, we see no harm to anyone (except to the extent that
they deny themselves, even temporarily, the psychological or spiritual
richness associated with marriage).
By extension, we see nothing inherently wrong with porn. It need not
threaten the institution of marriage. First, consider the least problematic
context: porn as fantasy for unmarried adults, whether straight or gay,
couples or individuals. Through fantasies, people explore sensations. And
eroticism is about sensations, in this context, not emotions or ideas. Both
men and women enjoy physical sensations. Sexual pleasure is derived not
only from seeing and touching, by the way, but also from hearing, smelling,
tasting, and so on. It is surely unnecessary to assume that male or female
lovers who enjoy licking and even nibbling each other are engaging in
murderous fantasies. The pleasure here is in the act itself, not what it might
lead to in some other context.
Porn as fantasy is closely linked with the desire for play. Whatever else
porn might be, after all, it is surely play. Like many other species, human
beings like and perhaps even need to play. Sometimes play involves
physical activity, sometimes mental activity, and often both. The word
“play” refers to activity that has no obvious or immediate usefulness. It has
a function, true, but an indirect one. Play helps people, adults no less than
children, move beyond the here and now that would otherwise monopolize
their attention and prevent them from thinking about new or different
possibilities. In this sense, the content of play is less relevant than the
activity. Play is an end in itself but also the means to some other end. Play
creates new ways of perceiving and experiencing the world. Or, putting it in
slightly different terms, it fosters our ability to adapt and thus to reduce the
threat of change.103

There are some good reasons for tolerating pornography and prostitution,
which is not to say that there are good reasons for celebrating either.
Human existence would surely be easier if people had no need for sex
apart from procreation. Maybe it would be easier if only we could control
that need more effectively than we have. But would we be happier? To
answer that question, think about the quality of life in societies that make
the most intense efforts to control or deny human nature: totalitarian ones.
Even if these societies could make people happier, which they do not, they
would still be likely to fail in the long run. Tightly controlled societies
endure only as long as conditions remain stable, as they do in relatively
isolated societies (although even these, according to the current generation
of anthropologists, are never either completely isolated or completely static)
but not in modern ones.104 Because they discourage innovation, the basic
requirement for which is freedom of thought and the basic training for
which is freedom to play, societies that depend very heavily on orthodoxy
and conformity discourage the kind of adaptability required to face change
effectively. The most obvious example of inflexibility in recent times, of
course, is that of Eastern Europe under communism.105 But another
example, the one that is most prevalent here and now, is surely the
mentality inherent in ideological feminism.
Like communism, ideological feminism is utopian. Ignoring the
ambiguity and ambivalence that have always characterized human
existence, it directly or indirectly proclaims that society would be happy if
only it was more thoroughly controlled by the state. In other words, it
focuses attention heavily on power, believing that women have less power
than men (which is true in some ways though not others) but also believing
that power itself should be the primary factor in creating a new and
presumably better society. For women to prosper, in other words, they must
control men by wielding more power over them (even though Marilyn
French and some other ideological feminists assert that “power over” is a
distinctively “male” preoccupation). We have argued here and elsewhere in
this book that every society must use culture to create order by controlling
nature but also that no society worth living in can be based entirely or even
primarily on doing so.
At the very least, we should acknowledge the need for a single moral
standard and a single legal one. If porn is bad because it dehumanizes
women, it is surely just as bad because it dehumanizes men (either those
men who are depicted in porn or those who use it). And if it is bad for men
to create or buy porn, then it is surely bad for women to do the same thing.
But how many women actually use porn? Very few, if you confine your
inquiry to the most obvious equivalents. (At least some readers of Playgirl,
in fact, are probably gay men.) Very many, on the other hand, if you
consider various functional equivalents.
In Spreading Misandry, we discussed the dehumanization of men in
popular culture, especially in movies and on television shows. Think now
about romance novels, which are written by and for women. In these books
– sold at every supermarket, this formulaic genre is probably more lucrative
than any other – men are reduced to the wealthy fantasy objects of female
protagonists (a topic that we discuss in appendix 5).106 Consider also
“women’s magazines” and “teen ‘zines.” In these publications, women or
girls learn how to “catch” and “hold” men or boys. They do not present
readers with coarse or vulgar pictures, to be sure, but they do encourage
readers to objectify and even manipulate the opposite sex. And what about
soap operas? These shows manage to objectify both sexes, actually, because
both are presented as sexually and financially predatory.
By far the most disturbing venue for objectifying and even
dehumanizing men, though, would be the books and articles written by
feminist ideologues. These publications encourage readers – either overtly
or covertly, directly or indirectly – to feel contempt for men as inferior
beings or even to hate men as the source of all suffering and evil throughout
history. The usual justification is based on the assumption that men have
such godlike power that nothing can damage them. This, we believe, is a
false and dangerous assumption. It implies that women are justified in using
any means short of violence (although Valerie Solanas advocated even
violence)107 to promote a social, economic, and legal revolution. Classic
(but by no means rare) examples would include the following feminists:
Robin Morgan, author of Demon Lover;108 Marilyn French, author of
Beyond Power (a massive compendium purporting to show not only that
men are both evil and inferior to women but that so is maleness itself in just
about every species)109 and The War against Women;110 Andrea Dworkin,
author of Intercourse; and Catharine MacKinnon, author of Toward a
Feminist Theory of the State. The list could go on and on. These authors
implicitly deny the full humanity of male people.
The fact that some of these authors – not all but some – stop short of
basing their claims on maleness itself does not make the sinister creatures
that they describe recognizable as real human beings. They are not the
complex, ambivalent, and confused people who actually co-exist in daily
life with equally complex, ambivalent, and confused women (much less
those who actually live with women in imperfect but mutually sustaining
relationships). From what these authors say, it would seem that (straight)
men have only “one thing” on their minds: not merely having sex with
women but having sex with unwilling women – or, failing that, using some
other, closely related way of subjugating women. Even though feminists of
this school seldom claim that evil is genetically produced by the distinctive
chromosome carried by men, they do claim that evil is culturally produced
by the genetically defined class of men. The difference between these two
claims, the latter ensuring that men are found morally guilty for deliberately
choosing evil, is nothing if not subtle. At best, these feminists either say or
imply, men are the creations of dark cultural forces that are so ancient, so
titanic, so pervasive, so malevolent, and so implacable that they might just
as well be genetically encoded. If men were to stop being evil, they would
have to stop being men at some profound level. Only those who see the
light and convert to feminism of one kind or another, as it were, are
redeemable. And even then … If this message does not qualify as hate
literature, the obvious parallel being anti-Semitic literature, it is hard to
imagine anything that would. So far, though, no one has suggested that we
use hate legislation to ban this stuff.
Every society should acknowledge, and most do, that not everyone is
going to marry and that trying to impose life-long asceticism on people who
do not is unfair. In any case, if pornography and prostitution are made
illegal, many people will meet their needs illegally and often in ways that
are dangerous for society. Since some people will disobey the law no matter
what, that argument does not in itself provide a good enough reason to
legalize their behaviour, but it does provide a good enough reason to weigh
the pros and cons very carefully.
Now, what about pornography or prostitution within marriage? Most
people would reject them, because our marital tradition is monogamous
(although it is becoming serially monogamous). The trouble with both
pornography and prostitution, they might say if they get beyond the
vulgarity or their own prudishness, is that they introduce a third party, or at
least an image of one, to the marriage. The analogy is to adultery. There is
some truth to that in theory. But there is ambiguity, too, in reality. Most
societies and religious communities, especially monogamous ones, make
massive efforts to encourage fidelity within marriage. And to some extent,
pornography – along with masturbation – detracts from the centrality of a
spouse. Fear of pornography and prostitution can easily become excessive,
true, as it has in Western religious traditions. But the underlying problem
should not be dismissed as trivial.111
On the other hand, these same things could actually be useful – more
useful, at any rate, than in clandestine forms. Think of what can happen
when one spouse is sexually withdrawn. One solution would be to dissolve
the marriage, but doing so would have a negative effect on any children
(apart from anyone else). Another solution would be for the sexier spouse to
make use of a legal safety valve: an erotic picture, say, or a prostitute.
Religious people will baulk at that suggestion, and for good theological
reasons, but this book is not addressed exclusively (or even primarily) to
religious people. It is about law, and that must apply to all people.
It is safe to say that both pornography and prostitution within marriage
are morally and psychologically ambiguous. The threat to marriage and
society, at any rate, is far from certain. No one would argue that looking at
erotic pictures and masturbating, consorting with prostitutes, or even casual
coupling with friends would be an effective way of satisfying the deepest
human needs that are represented by marriage. These needs include not
merely amusement, not only companionship (or even holiness, for religious
people), but also enduring relationships that promote the continuity of
families in particular and society in general. But human nature is complex,
and we do not live in an ideal world. Not everyone can find a way to link
sex with love. Even while promoting the ideal of marriage, many societies
have recognized the need for compromise by implicitly tolerating other
sexual outlets. In short, society should presume that erotica is legally
acceptable, even if religious communities find it morally unacceptable, and
that adult citizens should use their freedom to see or read whatever they
want to see or read. We would not be justified in banning pornography and
prostitution, therefore, although we would be justified in regulating them
very carefully.
We have argued that there are some good reasons for tolerating both
pornography and prostitution. But not in all contexts. We refer specifically
to contexts involving violence and minors. Some have seen them at one
time or another, pictures of people choking partners during oral sex or of
torturing them for erotic pleasure. Others have even experienced acts of this
kind with prostitutes. Maybe these are not just innocent fantasies; maybe
they reveal at least the secret desire to inflict pain. Maybe, though not
necessarily. They might in fact be merely fantasies, daydreams that explore
the forbidden.112 As a form of play, porn can be linked with both anarchy or
violence and artistic or intellectual creativity. The link is inconvenient, to be
sure, but not necessarily evil. The case against “rough sex” or sado-
masochism can be made effectively, but it is more complicated than meets
the eye.
Here is an analogous situation: the imaginative exploration of murder in
mainstream movies. Everyone recognizes that these movies are fictional.
Moreover, they are placed within a moral framework. Until the day before
yesterday, as it were, moviegoers were always expected to believe that
murder is indeed evil and that those who do evil will be brought to justice.
But critics of violent porn might say that because it is more or less hidden
from view, it lacks that moral framework. Its defenders might reply that it
allows people to explore fantasies that have nothing to do with the real
world, ones that they would never act out in real life. And they might add
that the moral framework is sometimes very ambiguous in mainstream
movies, particularly in some recent ones, but also even in earlier ones. You
have only to think of one famous scene in Gone with the Wind (which we
discuss in appendix 5). Rhett carries Scarlett, against her will, up to the
bedroom and has “his way” with her. Next morning, however, a delighted
Scarlett wants more of the same from Rhett. Well, was she raped or not?
And if so, are viewers – female viewers – justified in enjoying the fantasy?
Should this movie be banned or the scene excised by censors?
A similar question arises with respect to violence on television. It is true
that a few viewers go out and copy the violence they see on television, and
there is some evidence that children and adolescents who watch a lot of
violent shows are more likely than others to become violent in the future.113
But most viewers, by far, do nothing of the kind. Clearly, then, some
additional factor or factors must be involved in cases of antisocial
behaviour. If additional factors were not involved, one might ask feminists
who want to ban porn why they do not want to ban television as well? And
if not all forms of television, why not at least some forms? Possibly because
feminists present porn as a threat to women alone (despite gay porn), which
makes it easy for them to conceptualize porn as a “women’s issue.” They
can hardly say the same of violence on television, which presents at least as
many male victims of violence as female ones. But if violence against
women is intolerable, why not violence against men as well? Is the latter
acceptable merely because in many cases both the culprits and the victims
are men, as if the victims somehow deserve their fate by virtue of their
common maleness?
The problem of ambiguity aside, would women actually be safer if men
were denied outlets such as porn or prostitution? Who knows? In the papers
collected for In Harm’s Way, McKinnon and Dworkin, along with many
others, present evidence of porn leading directly to violence against women,
although they say little or nothing about gay porn leading to violence
against men or even about lesbian porn leading to violence against women.
Can pornography and prostitution lead to violence? Of course they can.
Must they do so? Are they inherently evil? Not unless human nature itself –
and, in this context, most people would think of male human nature – is
evil. Here is the implicit deductive argument that underlies this entire
discussion: All men like porn; porn is evil; all those who like something
that is evil are themselves evil; ergo, all men are evil. There are those who
believe precisely this. When people discuss porn in the public square (and
even within religious communities, which often agree with radical
feminism on that particular topic), they should at least acknowledge one of
the several things at stake: the condemnation of an entire group of people
on biological grounds.114
But something must still be done about pornography and prostitution
(although minors are already protected). Like so many other unregulated or
deregulated industries, they can cause serious harm. Apart from any ways in
which they endanger women in particular, after all, they are currently
operating in ways that endanger society as a whole. Partly because of their
marginal status as underground operations, for instance, both are heavily
associated with drugs and violence. The solution most commonly proposed
by ideological feminists in the United States and Canada is to ban them, or
at least try to do so. At stake in that solution, especially in connection with
porn, is freedom of expression, which raises several questions. Is society
more in danger from the absence of freedom or the misuse of freedom? Is
society more in danger from conformity or nonconformity? We suggest that
no solution will work unless it accepts ambiguity and therefore
compromise. From this point of view, it would make sense for the law to
presume that people are free to conduct their lives as they see fit but also to
limit that freedom – and freedom is always limited to activities that do not
endanger others – when either violence or minors are involved.
What, then, would we actually suggest in the way of law reform? As for
pornography, we see no reason to oppose the production of erotic imagery.
On the other hand, we support the current prohibition of material that either
depicts or involves minors in its production. In addition, we would
encourage legislation against violent porn but not against vague ideas of the
“subordination of women.” And as for prostitution, we see no reason to
oppose payment for sexual services. To put it bluntly, we would stop the
prosecution, even persecution, not only of adult prostitutes but also of their
adult customers.
Although some erotic pornography is classified as art and although high-
end prostitutes live and work in very comfortable conditions, pornography
and prostitution are heavily associated with the lurid and the sordid. Why
tolerate these industries? Because, whether some people want to admit it or
not, both pornography and prostitution serve a very widespread need. And
not only for men. As Frederick Mathews points out in connection with a
study by the National Juvenile Prostitution Survey, half the juvenile
prostitutes reported that they had been approached by female customers or
female pimps, or “procuresses.” Of these prostitutes, 62% were male and
43.4% females.115 Women do enjoy watching the Chippendales “dance,”
watching steamy soap operas, and reading romance novels. And all those
things are forms of porn, albeit ones that most people consider respectable.
Many who turn to either pornographic images or prostitutes are unable to
find sexual gratification in more satisfying ways – that is, in the context of
marriage or some other durable relationship, rather than in the context of a
business transaction. These people lack the money, good looks, personality
skills, or whatever, to attract spouses. And far from being an inherent threat
to marriage, as we say, pornographic images and prostitutes might actually
prevent at least a few marriages from disintegrating due to affairs; people
pay for them, after all, without loving them. Those involved in these
industries – male or female, gay or straight – would become providers of a
service like any other. Not love, which cannot be hired, but sex. This is
particularly important in the case of prostitutes. In a regulated industry –
and prostitution is regulated in some European countries – they could
participate in the economy: paying taxes but also collecting sickness or
unemployment insurance, old-age pensions, and so on. Government
inspection or supervision, moreover, could provide them with healthier
working conditions and eliminate pimps.
Lowman’s approach might be helpful. “We should repeal all the
prostitution laws,” he says, “and start over.”116 He continues by suggesting
that four principles should guide legislators: considering the procurement of
minors for prostitution “as an abuse of power, not a prostitution contract”
(by which he must mean an abuse of prostitution); using ordinary criminal
laws to protect prostitutes from violent customers and pimps; using
ordinary civil laws to control street life in the interest of bystanders and
residents; and helping prostitutes establish businesses for themselves in
“appropriate locations.” To these, we would add the following: replacing
the double standard for prostitutes and their customers with a single one. If
we refrain from treating prostitutes as criminals, then we should refrain
from treating their customers as criminals – unless, of course, the latter
indulge in violence or other criminal activities.
If we ban violent pornography for leading to violence against women in
real life, for instance, then we should ban violent popular culture as well –
that would include movies, songs, and even some segments of news shows
– for leading to violence against everyone. If we ban it for expressing
hatred against women, then we should ban feminist books and other
productions that express hatred against men. If we ban merely erotic porn
for objectifying women, then we should ban romance novels, along with
ideological diatribes for “objectifying” men.
If we ban porn intended for straight people, moreover, then we should
ban porn intended for gay people. Little is said in public about gay porn,
because gay men and women are considered oppressed groups, or “equity
seeking groups,” and therefore immune to criticism. The fact is, however,
that many gay people like porn and some resort to prostitutes. Feminist
lesbians try hard, nevertheless, to dissociate themselves from gay men on
this topic. Their porn is said to be superior, somehow, to gay male porn.
One lesbian, for example, argues that she and her friends prefer “art porn”
to the vulgar and raunchy stuff gay men prefer. “Its more sophisticated
strategies of hiding, showing and implying sexuality are far more
interesting than two-hour videos of badly shot humping. Perhaps, just
perhaps, we dykes are more sexually complex beasts than our gay brothers,
needing more than dicks in holes to get us off. And, as we’ve suspected all
along, women turn to other, more fulfilling, sources to arouse and satisfy
their fantasy selves unlike those straight boys who still haven’t figured out
that ‘Here clitty, clitty’ won’t get girls the least bit wet or wild.”117 Well, la-
di-da.

MacKinnon and Dworkin are clearly at one end of the feminist continuum,
even of the ideological feminist continuum. They are radicals, or, as we
would say, ideologues. But they are neither loony nor stupid. On the
contrary, they are rational and brilliant. And their arguments are
sophisticated. Given the initial ideological premises, these arguments
proceed clearly, logically, and consistently to articulate a coherent
worldview. This worldview is in profound and irreconcilable conflict with
other worldviews, however, including the one that we support. And the
evidence indicates that their worldview is rapidly becoming the dominant
one in our society, the one that sets the tone for legislation. Anyone who
thinks that our society is moving away from polarization between men and
women, therefore, should think again.
At the heart of our dispute with MacKinnon and Dworkin is not merely
what they say about men but what they do not say about hatred. They would
never admit to hating men. After all, “hating” is not a word that most
people apply to themselves. But that is partly because of how they define
the word “hatred.” If it refers to emotional antipathy, then it would be easy
to deny any accusation of hatred. Even MacKinnon and Dworkin like some
men. On that basis, they could say honestly that they do not hate all men.
But as we have pointed out elsewhere, hatred should not be used as a
synonym for emotional antipathy, or anger, toward this or that individual. It
should be used instead to describe a distinctive phenomenon: the deliberate
cultural propagation of contempt for a whole segment of the population – a
race, a class, a sex, or whatever – per se. In this respect, it would be hard to
read anything by MacKinnon or Dworkin that could not be classified as
hate literature. They present male people – all of them, even the few likable
individuals who try to mitigate the inherent malevolence of their own
maleness – as thoroughly contaminated by malice toward women, by evil
that they have chosen collectively. Feminists under their influence would
find it very hard not to have contempt for men as a class and foster
legislation that puts men in their place as those who would harass, batter,
rape, and kill women if only they were allowed to do so. At the very least,
converts would find it hard not to discourage any fraternization whatever
between women and their inferiors. If this reminds you of racism, it is no
accident. Even though they eschew the crude notion of biological
determinism, they foster the slightly more sophisticated notion of cultural
determinism (applied, however, to a group that is biologically defined).
Hence the need to destroy the current culture, root and branch, and replace
it with another.
8
Separatists v. Integrationists: The Case of Sexual
Harassment
Men who sexually harass say [that] women sexually harass them. They
mean they are aroused by women who turn them down. This elaborate
projective system … is surely a delusional structure deserving of serious
psychological study. Instead, it is women who resist it who are studied …
The assumption that in matters sexual women really want what men want
from women, makes male force against women in sex invisible. It makes
rape sex.1

What we may have thought of, with self-hatred and guilt, as a dirty
childhood game is reinterpreted as child sexual abuse. The flattering wolf-
whistle becomes sexual harassment. The pile of dirty dishes in the sink no
longer occasions self-rebuke and a sense of personal failure, but rather
anger at an unreconstructed husband. It is not simply that the interpretation
of the experience changes: the very experience and the emotions associated
with it are different too.2

Early in 2004 a controversy erupted over a claim by Naomi Wolf, famous


until then for two feminist tomes: The Beauty Myth3 and Fire with Fire.4In
a major article for New York Magazine, she accused literary scholar Harold
Bloom of having placed his hand on her thigh twenty years earlier.5She had
been a senior at Yale, he her much older prof, and the two had been
enjoying dinner and wine in her apartment at her invitation – presumably,
on a purely scholarly basis. “The next thing I knew, his heavy, boneless
hand was hot on my thigh.”6 Bloom left after the alleged act, and Wolf
threw up. (How would she have reacted, one cannot help wondering, if her
assailant had been a handsome young man with a slender, sinewy hand?)
But her ordeal did not end. In fact, the trauma has continued to torment her
ever since. According to Wolf, “the transgression … devastated my sense of
being valuable to Yale as a student.”7 First, she claims, her grades went
down due to rage and depression. Then she failed to get a Rhodes
scholarship on the basis of Bloom’s recommendation (although she later
clarified early reports by saying that his letter had been written before the
incident in question took place).
But now, after months of getting nowhere with officials at Yale and no
doubt empowered by her own journey into feminism, Wolf went public,
although she had already alluded to this event in college talks. Why then?
To save other women, at Yale and elsewhere, from the same horror, not so
much from an inappropriate romantic overture, because Yale and other
universities have long since brought in new codes of professional etiquette,
but from an indifferent academic bureaucracy. At the very least, she must
believe, both Bloom and Yale should be suitably punished in the court of
public opinion for her suffering. Why not sue either Bloom or Yale?
Because the university’s policy on sexual harassment is clear. It gives
alleged victims two years, not two decades, to report events of this kind.
And besides, Bloom had indeed taken no for an answer; even Wolf does not
allege that he had continued his advance toward her.
Some people have argued that Wolf was justified in protesting not only
the way that she was abused by a professor twenty years earlier but also the
way that she had been abused much more recently by academic bureaucrats.
Others have argued that Wolf ignored the gains of women. Wolf, writes
Anne Applebaum, has “reduced herself to a victim, nothing more. The
implication here is women are psychologically weak: One hand on the
thigh, and they never get over it. The implication is also women are naive,
and powerless as well: Even Yale undergraduates are not savvy enough to
avoid late-night encounters with male professors whose romantic intentions
don’t interest them.”8 Still others have argued that Wolf applied the
standard of our time to the ways of an earlier time; she sought not justice
but notoriety and succumbed to the victim mentality that permeates our
politically and sexually correct society by almost equating a man’s hand on
a woman’s thigh with rape.9 And if you think that this controversy emerged
out of nowhere, read on.
After a brief introduction on the historical context, we review the
legislation governing sexual harassment and continue by discussing the
ideological assumptions that have influenced recent legislation, several
strategies that are used to institutionalize the position of ideological
feminists, the ways in which formal legislation has influenced the less
formal policies of institutions such as the university, “heterophobia” (which,
though never acknowledged by feminist ideologues and seldom even
noticed by other feminists, is both an assumption and a strategy), and the
effects of this debate.

By the 1960s, women, including highly educated women, had become a


major part of the labour force. The men who worked in their offices and
factories, unfortunately, did not always welcome them for purely
professional reasons. Some men bartered jobs or promotions for sexual
favours, an arrangement that is usually known as quid pro quo. Other men
did not welcome women at all. Seeing the workplace as a symbol of
masculine identity, they tried to discourage women and thus get rid of them.
Still other men made them uncomfortable, often unwittingly, by displaying
pictures of nude women here and there or making risqué jokes now and
then. All of these things, which came to be called “sexual harassment,” led
women to mobilize for legal and quasi-legal measures to protect
themselves. These measures have been nothing if not controversial, and we
will discuss them in the following pages.
But first we must acknowledge our particular indebtedness to Daphne
Patai. She has commented extensively on sexual harassment. Because her
analysis of ideological assumptions and strategies amounts to a brilliant
exposé of feminism’s dark side, we have drawn heavily on her work. She
argues that misandry is indeed pervasive in contemporary feminism, and
not merely on the fringes.10 She argues also that it is revealed most
strikingly among those feminists who have deliberately generated what she
calls the “sexual harassment industry.” At any rate, Patai is important here
for three reasons. First, she identifies the strategies that ideological
feminists use to move from the fringe to the mainstream. Second, she
highlights the link that they make between sexual harassment in the
workplace and sexual harassment in other forms: pornography, prostitution,
rape, domestic violence, and so on – all of which, for ideologues, are
variants of the same phenomenon. Third, she intuits that ideologues see the
source of all these problems not merely in male sexuality but in
heterosexuality. This last insight was the missing link in our own theory of
misandry.
American legislation on sexual harassment has proliferated. Title VII of the
Civil Rights Act of 1964 does not refer explicitly to sexual harassment, but
it does refer to discrimination by “race, color, religion, sex, or national
origin.” The same title established the Equal Employment Opportunity
Commission, its job being to implement and enforce the act. In 1972, title
IX of the Education Amendments extended the scope of the Civil Rights
Act to include institutions that receive federal funding.11 In addition, it
established formal grievance procedures. In 1976 the federal case of
Williams v. Saxbe12 and in 1980 that of Alexander v. Yale University13
extended the idea of discrimination based on sex to quid pro quo sexual
harassment.
American feminists found it very hard to find legal grounds for charging
men with “subtle crimes” such as “offensive behaviour.” Apart from
anything else, charges of this kind led to countercharges of obstructing free
speech. But the Equal Employment Opportunity Commission provided a
loophole. Its 1980 guidelines extended the concept of sexual harassment to
include “unreasonably interfering with a person’s work performance or
creating an intimidating, hostile, or offensive work environment.” The
guidelines were used in Moire v. Temple University School of Medicine14
and a few years later in Meritor Savings Bank v. Vinson15 (a case we discuss
below).
According to the Civil Rights Act of 1964 illegal discrimination had to
be intentional. The Civil Rights Act of 1991, however, removed that
requirement. The emphasis was now on “disparate impact,” or effect, not
intention. In 1992 the Campus Sexual Assault Victims’ Bill of Rights16 –
this is binding on all universities that receive federal funds – required
authorities to revise their policies in ways that protected those making
charges of sexual harassment. By 1993 it was no longer necessary for
plaintiffs to show even that they had been harmed by the allegedly offensive
behaviour. According to guidelines established by the Equal Employment
Opportunity Commission, sexual harassment included conduct that merely
created “an intimidating, hostile or offensive working environment.”
Canada took similar measures. The Canada Labour Code, according to a
reader-friendly pamphlet, “establishes an employee’s right to employment
free of sexual harassment and requires employers to take positive action to
prevent sexual harassment in the work place.”17 And sexual harassment
includes “any conduct, comment, gesture, or contact of a sexual nature that
is likely to cause offence or humiliation to any employee or that might, on
reasonable grounds, be perceived by that employee as placing a condition
of a sexual nature on employment or on any opportunity for training or
promotion.”18 Sexual harassment includes, among other things, the
“displaying of sexually explicit, racist or other offensive or derogatory
pictures.”19 Employers must have a policy in place and make “every
reasonable effort” to make sure their employees do not experience
harassment. Employees who do, though, have a right to complain without
revealing their identities “unless disclosure is necessary for the purposes of
investigating … or taking disciplinary measures.”20 When alleged harassers
are found guilty, employers must take disciplinary action. Unsatisfied
victims have a “right to take a complaint under the Canadian Human Rights
Act.”21

One assumption of those who advocate legislative change in both Canada


and the United States is that only women encounter sexual harassment.
Catharine MacKinnon claims precisely that.22 According to her statistics,
moreover, as many as seven out of ten American women experience sexual
harassment at least once in their lives. But these statistics are highly
questionable (as we show in appendix 3).
Another assumption, articulated most effectively by MacKinnon (usually
with Andrea Dworkin) is that sexual harassment constitutes merely the tip
of a patriarchal iceberg. She believes that men find women sexually
attractive precisely because women lack power and are oppressed. To
satisfy their sexual inclinations, therefore, they must continue to
subordinate or oppress women. It works the other way, too. She believes
that women find men sexually attractive – which is to say, that women have
been culturally conditioned to find men sexually attractive – precisely
because men have power and are oppressive. The upshot of her argument is
this: to eliminate one factor (the power of men over women) requires us to
eliminate the other (heterosexual attraction) as well. The more difficult we
make it for men to act out their sexual impulses, no matter how trivial or
even welcome these might seem to patriarchally programmed women, the
better off women will be. Clearly, MacKinnon wants to marginalize or even
demonize ordinary men – all men, not only deviant men. For her, in fact,
the only deviant men would be those who agree with her theory.
This last point is worth discussing in more detail. For MacKinnon, the
mystifying power of men is not merely pervasive in this particular society
at this particular time but inherent in the way things always have been and
always will be whenever men and women interact – even here and now,
when women wield power in everyday life. Hence her dictum that sexual
harassment “is done by men to women regardless of relative position on the
formal hierarchy.”23 Obviously, the ultimate solution would be to prevent
women from coming into any contact at all with men.
Both MacKinnon and Dworkin recognize the possibility of consensual
arrangements between women but not between women and men. Because
they believe that all women in our society are subordinate to all men, even
if they actually earn more money than men or outrank them, it follows for
them that no woman in any circumstance is actually capable of freely
giving consent to sexual relations with any man, much less of actually
wanting sexual relations with any man. Every heterosexual act, therefore, is
defined in terms of violence. That is merely one point on a continuum, one
that begins at the seemingly innocent end with friendly heterosexual
relations, continues with sexual harassment, and ends with rape.
Before the Messianic Age, though, women will have to live with men.
What ideological feminists want, Patai points out, is to “alter the terms of
the negotiation so that women hold all the cards.”24 When the words
“unwanted” or “unwelcome” become “routinized, it will be difficult to
challenge such a privileging of one sex’s ‘wants’ over the other’s, for
merely to raise a question about it invites the retort that one is promoting
oppressive behavior toward women (or is selling out to the patriarchy).”25
Never discussed, says Patai, is women’s own allure created by gesture,
dress, and so forth. This, too, is a kind of power. “The message is clear:
Women are never at fault. They need not examine their own ways. They
need only to learn when and how to file complaints, although, interestingly,
even this recourse is never construed as a ‘power’ in their possession. Only
men have power, and it is men, not women, who need to change.”26
Those two fundamental assumptions – that only women encounter
sexual harassment and that sexual harassment (like rape) is based on the
eroticization of male power over women – have led ideological feminists to
adopt several strategies in their quest for a feminist utopia. We have already
referred, both in this chapter and in the previous one, to two extremely
effective strategies of ideological feminism: expanding the definition of one
crime to include forms of behaviour that were once not classified as crimes,
or reinforcing old claims with new ones, and eventually generating
something that approaches hysteria. This strategy requires them to keep
upping the ante. Just as pornography and prostitution can be forms of rape,
so can sexual harassment. We call this strategy “linguistic inflation,”
because words or ideas can be debased and thus made trivial
(unintentionally or not) just as currencies can be debased and thus made
worthless. Here is Patai on the topic.

As I have repeatedly stressed, the shi [Sexual Harassment Industry] does


not attempt to differentiate between instances of indisputable abuse and
mere expressions of sexual interest. Each is taken to be as egregious as the
other. The key concept by which male-female interactions are being
redefined is “power differential,” the presence of which contaminates any
sexually tinged word, gesture, or look and turns it, potentially, into “sexual
harassment.” This persistent inability or refusal to draw distinctions cannot
be taken as accidental. Male sexual interest is not simply being construed,
or interpreted, as “power.” It has actually been redefined as such. The slow
and continuous expansion of efforts to regulate personal relations, now
extending even to consensual relationships between adults, is a particularly
clear example of the stigmatizing of male sexuality in and of itself. True,
women and homosexuals are occasionally caught in the trap, but this seems
an unintended consequence; they are not the main targets – as the sexual
harassment literature has made clear from its very inception. Sexual
harassment is first and foremost an act committed by powerful males
against powerless females. The infantilization of adult women implicit in
this view does not seem to trouble many of those who profess feminism.27

The original problem, quid pro quo harassment in this case, is now
understood as the mere tip of a colossal patriarchal iceberg – that is, a vast
and eternal conspiracy of men to objectify, subjugate, subordinate, and
otherwise oppress women. According to MacKinnon, “economic power is
to sexual harassment as physical force is to rape.”28
The new definition of sexual harassment became dinner-table
conversation in connection with Anita Hill’s allegation against Clarence
Thomas, but it was established as law in Vinson. MacKinnon represented
Mechelle Vinson in this case, which provoked a landmark decision,
according to an article in US News and World Report, because it redefined
sexual harassment by expanding it to include the experience of a hostile
work environment.29 But this article neglects to mention what really
changed after this case. According to Newsweek, it involved far more than a
hostile work-place: it involved rape. Vinson “claimed that her supervisor
fondled her in front of other employees, followed her into the lady’s room,
exposed himself and, on several occasions, raped her.”30
Now consider a chart that appeared in the same article. A survey in 1987
(before the Hill-Thomas affair) found that 35% of the sample included
“sexual remarks” as a defining feature of sexual harassment; 28% included
“suggestive looks,” 26% included “deliberate touching,” 15% included
“pressure for dates,” 12% included “letters and calls,” 9% included
“pressure for sexual favours,” and 8% included “actual or attempted rape or
assault.”31 Two conclusions can be drawn from these figures. First, the
definition of sexual harassment now includes rape itself. Second, the
definition of rape now includes sexual harassment. Since 1986, it is worth
repeating, rape and “sexual remarks” have been merely two ends of a single
continuum, two manifestations of a single phenomenon. If someone who
rapes can be charged with sexual harassment, therefore, why should
someone who merely makes “sexual remarks” not be charged with rape?
Clearly, a major change took place between 1980, when the Equal
Employment Opportunity Commission based its guidelines on civil rights
legislation, and 1986, when the Supreme Court based its definition in
Vinson – a case that could have been argued on the grounds of rape or
indecent exposure – on feminist ideology.
Patai, too, comments on the recent tendency of “experts” to conflate
mere words or gestures that make women uncomfortable with serious
offenses.32 Linguistic inflation works in two ways because the process,
once set in motion, is self-perpetuating. The goal is to protect women from
men by making interaction between the sexes increasingly hard. But the
increasingly ugly consequences for men who do interact with women
require increasingly grandiose justifications. This problem is solved,
observes Patai, by expanding and magnifying – we would say almost
“sacralizing” – the notion of sexual harassment as a counterpart of rape.
Ideological feminists transform accusers first into victims and then into
“survivors,” as if they had been brutally assaulted, tortured, or persecuted.33
Until the late 1980s, in fact, the word survivor was used most often in
connection with two horrors: the Nazi death camps and cancer. Only then
did feminists expand on “survivor” by applying it to molestation, domestic
violence, and sexual harassment. “By means of semantic contamination,”
says Patai, “a seamless continuum exists between passing comments,
criticism in the classroom (which ‘silences’ women students), and criminal
sexual assault.”34
As Patai points out in connection with MacKinnon’s belief that verbal
hostility is tantamount to rape (a controversy that we discuss in chapter 9),
MacKinnon “could not seriously maintain that ‘I hate you, dumb cunt’ is
the same thing as killing a woman in a misogynistic rage.”35 If words are
made to seem like deeds, they become as damaging as deeds. But Patai
notices that MacKinnon is nothing if not clever. She justifies linguistic
inflation on the basis of speech-act theory, which tries to show that words
are deeds. When hearing a word becomes an experience of violation, then
sexual harassment becomes a self-fulfilling prophecy. Ideological feminists
want something more than mere equality with men, whether in the
university or in the workplace. The whole point of inflating the harms of
sexual harassment is to inflate the severity and pervasiveness of evil that
can be attributed to men and therefore to justify the separation of women
from men – that is, to undermine the movement toward the integration of
men and women. (Some ideological feminists imply the desirability of
sexual separatism on psychological or psychoanalytical grounds, as we
point out in appendix 5, without actually demanding it on political
grounds.)
Here is an example of linguistic inflation, albeit a hypothetical one, from
Katie Roiphe. A new female student considers it sexual harassment when a
guy flirts with her at a college party – even though he refrains from actually
touching her. As college life goes on, she experiences more incidents of this
kind. Now a feminist, she believes in the “zookeeper” approach: training
the “beast” to behave in acceptable ways. Here is a real account:

Susan Teres … said, at the 1992 Take Back the Night march, that 88 percent
of Princeton’s female students had experienced some form of sexual
harassment on campus. Catharine MacKinnon, a professor of law and the
chief architect of American legal harassment policies, writes that “Only 7.8
percent of women in the United States are not sexually assaulted or
harassed in their lifetimes.” No wonder. Once you cast the net so wide as to
include everyone’s everyday experience, identifying sexual harassment
becomes a way of interpreting the sexual texture of daily life, instead of
isolating individual events. Sensitivity to sexual harassment becomes a way
of seeing the world, rather than a way of targeting specific contemptible
behaviors. In an essay attempting to profile the quintessential harasser, two
feminists warn in conclusion (and in all seriousness) that “the harasser is
similar, perhaps disturbingly so, to the “average man.”

As one peruses guidelines on sexual harassment, it’s clear where the


average man comes in. Like most common definitions, Princeton’s
definition of sexual harassment includes “leering and ogling, whistling,
sexual innuendo, and other suggestive or offensive or derogatory
comments, humor and jokes about sex.” MacKinnon’s statistic includes
obscene phone calls. These definitions of sexual harassment sterilize the
environment. They propose classrooms that are cleaner than Sesame Street
and Mr. Rogers’s Neighborhood. Like the rhetoric about date rape, this
extreme inclusiveness forces women into old roles. What message are we
sending if we say We can’t work if you tell dirty jokes, it upsets us, it
offends us? With this severe conception of sexual harassment, sex itself gets
pushed into a dark, seamy, male domain …
If someone bothers us, we should be able to put him in his place without
crying into our pillow or screaming for help or counseling. If someone
stares at us, or talks dirty, or charges neutral conversation with sexual
innuendo, we should not be pushed to the verge of a nervous breakdown. In
an American College Health Association pamphlet, “Unwanted sexual
comments, jokes or gestures” are characterized as “a form of sexual
assault.” Feminists drafting sexual harassment guidelines seem to have
forgotten childhood’s words of wisdom: sticks and stones may break my
bones, but names will never harm me.”36

It could be argued that Roiphe has gone to the other extreme, claiming that
all problems can be solved by wielding a sharp tongue. But many of them,
surely, can be.
Linguistic inflation would never have been an effective strategy had it
not been for another ideological strategy. Every law is supposed to be
reasonable. But reasonable according to which standard? Or, to be more
precise, in connection with the dominance of postmodernism, whose
standard? Surely not that of a reasonable person, ideological feminists
argued, because male and female persons have totally different ways of
thinking about or experiencing the world. Men do so from a position of
power, supposedly, and women from one of subordination. Their
gynocentric approach “encouraged feminists to pursue new theories that
would better reflect the women’s view of office flirtations.”37 They began
to argue that harassment charges should be judged from the viewpoint of a
reasonable woman, not a reasonable person. And they emphasized
“woman,” not “reasonable.”38 What they meant by a “reasonable woman”
was by no means self-evident.
In Louis Robinson v. Jacksonville Shipyards,39 a federal judge in Florida
declared in 1991 that pictures of nude women displayed on the wall of a dry
dock were legitimate evidence of what a reasonable woman could consider
sexual harassment.40 This case institutionalized an aspect of MacKinnon’s
position on porn. And in San Francisco, a federal appeals panel ruled that a
female agent of the Internal Revenue Service could sue a fellow agent “for
pestering her with sexual innuendoes in conversation and love letters.”41
The court declared that “a reasonable woman” could consider this conduct
“sufficiently severe and pervasive to … create an abusive working
environment.”42 These two cases and an increasing number of other court
cases opened up the possibility that almost any aspect of men’s conduct –
the guidelines of the Equal Employment Opportunities Commission
consume no fewer than thirty-one pages – could be grounds for “reasonable
women” to accuse them of sexual harassment. “Thus, a woman’s subjective
judgment of men’s actions, regardless of their intent, became the standard
by which complaints could be judged.”43 Merely feeling uncomfortable is
now cause for litigation. The “reasonable woman” is not some-one whose
goal is to rely on reason and cultivate objectivity, after all, but someone
whose goal is to rely on emotion and cultivate subjectivity.
Feminists argued not merely that the collectivity of women alone should
define sexual harassment but also that the individual woman alone should
be able to establish when it has taken place. And the courts have accepted
this. The law’s point of view, legal experts say, is that of the victim. “As one
attorney for employers put it, ‘If one woman’s interpretation sets the legal
standard, then it is virtually up to every woman in the workplace to define if
she’s been sexually harassed.’ This puts sexual harassment in the same
category as violations of college speech and behaviour codes, which often
turn on the feelings of the aggrieved rather than on any objective and
definable offense. But if feelings are trumps, how do we know when sexism
and harassment end and hypersensitivity or even ideology begins?”44
According to the guidelines of the Equal Employment Opportunity
Commission, claimants must show that the “purpose or effect” of some
behaviour interferes with their ability to work and thus creates an
“intimidating, hostile, or offensive work environment.”45 As in a famous
theological dispute of the Middle Ages,46 one tiny word has sparked a
conflagration: the word “or,” as in “purpose or effect.” Women no longer
need to prove that men actually intended to be offensive. They need only
allege that a “reasonable woman” could have interpreted his behaviour in
that way. “This set the stage,” writes Patai, “for the elevation of women’s
word to the level of law – which was precisely the goal of feminist
activists.”47
To be universally acceptable and therefore effective, law must be based
on objective criteria. Something is either legal or illegal. It either did or did
not take place. But this standard no longer applies to laws that affect
women. Instead, radical subjectivity applies.48 Ultimately at issue here and
elsewhere in this book is the privileged position of subjectivity in feminist
(and postmodernist) thought. Privileging subjectivity has had important
consequences not only for jurisprudence but also for scholarship. (We
discuss the link between epistemological subjectivism and ideological
feminism in chapter 10). At issue here is the ultimate authority that
feminists – and not only ideological ones – attribute to experience (the
celebrated subjectivity that they associate with women) instead of to reason
(the supposedly arid or even destructive objectivity that they associate with
men, even though they undermine the position of female scholars by doing
so). Apart from anything else, they hope to obviate the need for rational
argument and rely instead on emotional ranting. Appealing to what women
“know” (and what men either do not or cannot know) has been popular
among feminists for decades. Ideological feminists believe that women
have an innate advantage when it comes to feeling. (Misogynists agree,
ironically, but consider their reliance on feeling an innate disadvantage.)
The glorification of feeling, often accompanied by the denigration of
thinking or logic, is characteristic of the pervasive therapeutic emotionalism
that is best illustrated by the daytime talk shows on television and the
rampant popularity of pop psychology. Witness the public response to
Princess Diana’s death.49
In another sense, though, the “reasonable woman” is someone whose
goal is to rely on neither the objectivity of reason nor the subjectivity of
emotion but on a hybrid that could be called “subjective reason.” We refer
by that oxymoron to objectivity in the service of subjectivity, or reason in
the service of ideology (which is by definition about “us” versus “them”
and therefore subjective). In other words, the “reasonable woman” is really
an ideological woman, one who has been trained to think in “ideologically
reasonable” ways.
At first, the trouble was that not many women had been suitably trained
to recognize signs of their own oppression. They needed expert advice,
training manuals, support groups, counselling sessions, and so on. Which
they got. The results have been serious. Feelings of discomfort were trans-
muted into feelings of a hostile environment. And due process disappeared
for the accused. No matter. Except, of course, to men. Given everything that
Patai has said about the background of this “reasonable woman” standard, it
would be tempting to call it the “reasonable ideologue” standard. There
would be no point in doing so, however, because reason is not a significant
feature of ideology. The appeal of all ideologies, whether on the political
left or the political right, is primarily emotional. In order to exploit
collective identity for political purposes, after all, every ideology must first
establish and support it.
Ideological feminists make a direct link between experience and
interpretation. Celia Kitzinger, for instance, observes in the second epigraph
to this chapter that what we now call “sexual harassment” is a “social
construction” (just as sexuality is).50 “It is not simply that the interpretation
of the experience changes: the very experience and the emotions associated
with it are different too.”51 Kitzinger could have added that women are
being taught precisely how to reinterpret things. Patai puts it this way:
“Unlike battery and sexual assault, where the hurt resides in the action
itself, the injury in much of what is today labeled sexual harassment arises
in the interpretation women are being taught to adopt as a guide to
understanding others’ words and gestures.”52 Everyone wants to legislate
safety for women, but ideological feminists want to legislate comfort for
women.
Another strategy could be called “victimology.” To Patai’s point, we add
the following. The preoccupation with victimology has a complex history. It
involves not only ideological feminism but also pop psychologism and neo-
Romanticism, both of which glorify emotion at the expense of reason and
both of which are strongly supported by various branches of feminism.
Victims are people. They are citizens. But so are the accused and even the
condemned. Our legal systems do bend over backward, as it were, to ensure
that the accused are given every opportunity to defend themselves. They are
mere individuals, after all, confronted by the massive power of the state.
Victims of sexual harassment share one set of characteristics:
vulnerability and (often) femaleness. Victimizers share another set: power
and (often) maleness. Forget the real world; rhetoric is what really counts
here. Completely ignored is women’s own harassment of male professors
and students, because “in such a perspective, an individual woman’s
‘professional power’ is always trumped by a male’s (including a male
student’s) ‘social power.’”53 This attitude is not an abstraction, of interest
only to ideological theoreticians and their opponents. It is a fact of everyday
life in the classroom and the workplace.

Having already discussed the strategies of law reformers in our review of


the legislation on sexual harassment, we turn now to the less formal
counterparts of this legislation: quasi-legal measures that include the codes
or policies established by institutions such as universities and corporations.
Better to err on the side of caution – that is, on the side of those who would
throw all caution to the winds in their zeal to convict sexual harassers
(especially government officials responsible for either withholding grant
money or taking punitive legal action that would lead to financial damages)
– than on the side of justice. The major impact of recent legislation is not to
be seen in the few cases that make it into court, surely, but in the fact that
all private companies and public institutions now protect themselves with
quasi-legal sexual-harassment codes.
Aside from instituting definitions that are too broad and too ambiguous,
these codes often ignore due process, which contributes to the chilling, and
even polarizing, effect on relations between men and women. Of greatest
importance here, however, is that one sex has gained the upper hand.
Women alone have been allowed to decide what is or is not permissible.
And men – most of those accused so far have been men – have been
saddled with the burden of proof. In short, they are guilty unless proven
innocent. This perception, fostered by both law and policy, fosters the more
general perception that men are evil. This is no longer a matter of
gynocentrism, which might, at least in theory, be justified as a corrective to
androcentrism. It is a matter of institutionalized, legalized misandry.
Many universities have come up with codes of “sexual correctness” to
match their codes of political correctness. In some cases, the authorities
adopt them formally. In other cases, the students adopt them informally. At
Antioch College in Yellow Springs, Ohio,54 students require verbal
permission not only for every stage in the process of seduction – including
kissing, touching, and even looking – but also on every occasion of
seduction. This new norm is called “communicative sex.” Patai refers to the
message that this sends to men, who are assumed to be the seducers, but not
only to men. “Looks, gestures, sighs, hints, the back-and-forth of sexual
play – all would be delegitimized if explicit verbal consent were to become
the sine qua non of ‘legal sex.’”55 Given the constant threat of litigation,
moreover, sensible men would have to insist on written permission. Just try
to make a romantic movie out of that.
In a contribution to “Hers,” in the New York Times Magazine, Francine
Prose provides a case study of what sexual harassment can mean in an
American university.56 Prose introduces herself as a feminist. “I write about
‘women’s issues.’ I teach in writing programs and am painfully aware of the
pressures facing young (and older) female writers. I find myself more often
than not taking the woman’s side. I believed Anita Hill.”57 But in the case
of her friend, Stephen Dobyns, she takes the other side.
Dobyns, a writer and teacher of creative writing, was brought before an
academic tribunal. At a party, he had splashed a drink in the face of a
student who had overheard him talking about her breasts – that is, she had
overheard him asking a colleague to stop looking at them – and she had
filed a formal complaint. Two other students came forward to say that
Dobyns had destroyed their ability to function both in class and as writers.
Although Prose acknowledges that her friend acted inappropriately, she
does wonder if his guilt pertained to any sensible definition of sexual
harassment. As she points out, no one accused Dobyns of trying to
exchange good grades for sexual favours. He did not sleep with students or
even proposition them. Nor did he engage in the kind of hectoring that used
to define the word “harassment.” He was accused of using “salty language”
– not even in the classroom, but at a party.
The point made by Prose is not that throwing drinks at people should be
considered acceptable behaviour but that some female students have
returned to a view of womanhood (and manhood) that bears an eerie
likeness to that of much earlier generations.

Victorian damsels in distress, they used 19th-century language: they had


been “shattered” by his rude, “brutish” behavior. After testifying, they
seemed radiant, exalted, a state of being that, like so much else, recalled
“The Crucible,” which used the Salem witch trials as a metaphor for the
Army-McCarthy hearings.

Are these the modern women feminists had in mind? Victorian girls,
Puritan girls, crusading against dirty thoughts and loose speech? I thought
of all the salty words I have used in class – words that could apparently cost
me my job – and of my own experience with sexual harassment: the
colleague who told me that his department only hired me because I was a
woman; if they could have found a black woman, they would have hired
her. Such words were more damaging than anything he could have said
about my breasts. But no one could have accused him of harassment: he
didn’t make a pass at me or refer to a sexual act.58

In the end, Dobyns was found guilty of verbal sexual harassment. The
tribunal recommended that he be suspended, without pay, for two years,
expelled from the campus (except the library), required to put in two
hundred hours of community service, and ordered to pay one of his accusers
$600 for wages she had lost in connection with “mental suffering.”
Here is another case, this one from Canada. Early in 1994, the
government of Ontario issued its “Framework Regarding Prevention of
Harassment and Discrimination in Ontario Universities.”59 This document
opens with a proclamation: “The government of Ontario has adopted a
policy,” it reads, “of zero tolerance of harassment and discrimination in
Ontario’s universities.”60 The government quickly went into reverse after
the text was leaked to a newspaper in Ottawa only two weeks before the
deadline for action, leaving academics outraged by what they considered a
real threat to freedom of speech.61 Critics worried about the whole idea of
“zero tolerance.” Listen to William Leggett, the principal of Queen’s
University in 1994.

In a most unfortunate omission, the [policy] made no mention of the


importance of approaching discrimination and harassment prevention in
ways that uphold the traditions of academic freedom and free speech which
are central to our educational mission, our research functions and the proper
carrying out of our social responsibilities. Promoted in an inappropriate
manner, the demand for a harassment-free environment may inhibit the free
exchange of ideas and the debate that are essential to the intellectual vitality
of a university. A distinction needs to be made between, on the one hand,
affirming the right to voice in an academic setting unpopular ideas that may
be perceived as wounding or hurtful and, on the other, the gratuitous abuse
of that right for purposes that are not academic but merely offensive.62

Tom Darby of Carleton University argued that the document was an attempt
to impose political correctness on the university. He and others believed
that it represented “an ill-considered stab at social engineering that attempts
to impose a climate of complete civility on university life at the cost of free
intellectual inquiry.”63 Bill Graham, president of the University of Toronto
Faculty Association, noted that civility does not, in fact, lie at the heart of
university life. “What you have to do while protecting human rights,” he
wrote, “is recognize that universities are the very places where you should
be offending people sometimes. Part of the purpose of university is to
examine, question, and criticize the basic beliefs of our society and the
various groups in it. You have to challenge people.”64
Some academics might have noticed an additional problem but refrained
from mentioning it (partly because it had already been embedded in law).
The policy’s definition of “sexual harassment” is exceedingly broad.
Examples cited include not only “gestures, remarks, jokes, slurs, taunting,
innuendo, threats” and so on, but also “physical, verbal, or sexual
assault.”65 According to Canadian law, “sexual assault” is the term for what
was once called “rape.” What troubles us is not the inclusion of rape as an
offense (although that would surely be prosecuted by the state as a criminal
offense and not merely by the university as an infraction against its
harassment policy) but the implication that rape is merely one end of a
continuum that includes what most people would consider trivial and
unrelated phenomena. We must assume that the government of Ontario has
established ideological feminism as its official philosophy.
Allegedly “stunned” by the hostile response to its policy, Ontario
officials tried to mollify critics by claiming that it was intended merely as a
guideline to support policies already in place at universities, not as a new
policy to be backed by coercion. But if policies were already in place, why
the alleged need for further guidelines? Other officials, both bureaucrats
and academics, tried to trivialize the controversy by arguing that everyone
had been overreacting. “People can come forward with complaints,” said
Dale Fogle, a sexual-harassment officer at Wilfrid Laurier University, “but
that doesn’t mean complaints will rule the day. It has to be weighed and
find its way through procedural channels. It’s just not going to result in
some big chill on freedom of speech.”66 But how many people would risk
the harrowing experience of going through these procedural channels? It is
so much easier and safer to remain silent on controversial topics. According
to the policy’s defenders, common sense will prevail. Yes, but whose
common sense? (In this case, the characteristic question of postmodernists
is addressed to postmodernists themselves.) Besides, we should have laws
that cannot be so easily misused.
Graham pointed out that this government policy would allow officials to
censor remarks in class about the rights of gay people, because those
remarks would infringe on the rights of religious fundamentalists. The same
policy would prohibit a course on feminism or one taught from a feminist
perspective, moreover, because it would inevitably produce a negative
atmosphere for male students. But if this highly politicized document was
written by “ideologues and fundamentalists,” as critics claimed, then it was
clearly written with no intention whatsoever of allowing the inherent logic
of “zero tolerance” for harassment and discrimination to prevail (a problem
that we discuss in appendix 4). On the contrary, only politically correct
groups would be given protection.
Ideological feminists involved in policy reform euphemistically call one
strategy for dealing with harassment “reeducation.” Those found guilty of
sexual harassment – and sometimes even those found innocent – are
required to participate. Patai discusses what this really means in the context
of a university. It often involves more than threats, lectures, readings, and
discussion groups. In fact, it often involves what could be called a
“conversion experience,” followed by “repentance” and “atonement.” The
latter is expressed as an act of public contrition or at least a letter of apology
– reviewed first by the “trainer,” of course, and then submitted to an official
of the department, as well as one from the Equal Employment Opportunity
Commission.
Due process at institutions such as universities would include the
following: a presumption of innocence until or unless the accused is proven
guilty; precisely stated accusations; separation of investigators from judges
to avoid conflicts of interest; access of the accused to legal counsel from the
start; and hearings in which the accused can face their accusers and call
witnesses in their own defense. The current lack of due process is endorsed
by many feminists, according to Roiphe, who believe that

academic freedom and due process are simply more platitudes generated by
the old boy network. They dismiss any concern about fairness with their
image of the ranks of male professionals united against the slim victim.
Sexual harassment has assumed such grand proportions in the minds of
these feminists that they are not concerned with the machinations of the
disciplinary system, however Kafkaesque. To many feminists … who are
interested in cleansing the university of harassers, a few casualties of justice
along the way seem like a small price to pay.67

In any case, “reeducation” should remind everyone of brainwashing, which


is more intense, to be sure, but which has the same goal.
Finally, consider another strategy. Of great interest here, explains Patai,
is the urge not merely to punish men for stepping out of line but to shame
them publicly for doing so, which might remind some readers of the stocks
used in seventeenth-century New England and elsewhere or of the self-
criticism rituals once required in many Marxist or neo-Marxist
communities. Roiphe has documented the horrors of antiharassment wish
lists, which often include plans to publish or publicize the names of alleged
harassers – the “walls of shame,” for example, that are advocated by many
on college campuses. Those who advocate institutional policies of this kind
seldom pay any attention to the need for due process, not surprisingly,
which would be assumed in a court of law.
Even if no conclusive result is reached by the investigators, observes
Patai, those accused of sexual harassment remain under suspicion. Sexual
harassment experts appear before tribunals with a “harasser profile,” which
provides a script by which to interpret all testimony.68 Even when the
accused are actually found not guilty, they are still often punished by being
required to attend “workshops.” The idea is for a company or university
department to demonstrate zeal in attacking sexual harassment. “One can
think of few other areas,” adds Patai, “in which even the failure to find any
evidence of wrongdoing is always accompanied by protestations of total
commitment to ferreting it out nonetheless.”69 Actually, we can think of
several. We have already discussed this very thing in connection with child
abuse, say, and child support. But Patai is correct in a way, because
ideological feminists see all of these as aspects of one problem and
therefore adopt the same strategies to deal with all of them.
Worst of all, says Patai, some people will be accused unjustly. Their
names will never be cleared, because secrecy surrounds the whole
process.70 Yes, yes, some say, a few people will be treated unjustly
according to these new rules. A few people will be accused falsely. But so
what? Most harassers are punished, they say, and that discourages other
potential harassers. The end, presumably, justifies the means. Shaming
accused harassers is, not surprisingly, just like shaming the customers of
prostitutes.

Because the expanded definition of sexual harassment reflects the world-


view of those consciously or unconsciously opposed to heterosexuality,
lesbians have clearly won a major victory. This conclusion takes us to what
Patai calls “heterophobia” and also back to what MacKinnon calls the
“eroticization of male power.” Both are examples of what we call misandry.
Among the many forms taken by misandry in popular culture have been the
notions of ridiculing, bypassing, dehumanizing, and even demonizing men.
Translated from the reel world to the real world, and the other way around,
these tactics encourage sexual segregation – in Canadian parlance, sexual
separatism – instead of sexual integration.
Some comentators refuse to believe that most people are heterosexual by
nature (though reinforced by culture). In other words, they believe that
heterosexuality is nothing more – nothing less, to be more precise – than an
invention, a “social construction” perpetuated, or perpetrated, by men,
precisely in order to oppress women. If so, then the cultural conditioning of
so-called heterosexual women can be overcome with suitable ideological
training. Failing that, women must escape from the tyranny of
heterosexuality by separating themselves as much as possible from men.71
How else can we explain the lengths to which feminists have gone in trying
to eliminate what many other people, including many women, regard as
trivial complaints? Why else make the effort to convince women that they
are “uncomfortable” with men in almost any circumstances? For that
matter, why else bend over backward to make the law enforce “comfort” in
the first place? This situation is the result of an ideology that insists on
conflating the trivial with the serious.
As Patai points out, this debate presupposes confusion over the
difference between social constructionism and essentialism. Many
feminists, including the most radical, deny that they are essentialists. They
do so for at least two reasons. First, essentialism would mean that
heterosexual men have no choice when it comes to their attitudes toward
women. And that would mean freeing them from moral responsibility for
subordinating or even attacking women. Second, even ideological feminists
usually insist on paying lip service to pluralism, the lingua franca of
politics. As Alice Echols has pointed out,72 the difference between
essentialism and pluralism might not matter. If heterosexuality is so deeply
engrained through culture, after all, it might just as well be imposed by
nature.
Deconstruction is the method of choice for all purposes among post-
modernists. The aim is to “subvert,” or “problematize” disapproved ideas,
institutions, behaviours, cultural productions, and so on. Before
consciousness raising can take place, after all, false consciousness must first
be exposed, challenged, undermined, subverted, or transgressed – that is,
deconstructed. In this case, the target is heterosexuality: that which brings
men and women together.
Sheila Jeffreys, a British feminist and separatist, believes that
heterosexuality as a social construction is based on the “ideology of
difference.”73 By this, she means an ideology that sees women as powerless
creatures (which is precisely what MacKinnon and her ideological
colleagues believe about women). Like MacKinnon, she believes that men
eroticize this powerlessness of women and are then attracted to it.
“Jeffreys’s views,” writes Patai, “bring together the two strands I am calling
‘heterophobia’: the fear of and antagonism toward the Other – that is, male
sexuality, especially as manifest in heterosexuality; and the turn toward
Sameness, understood as the only kind of authentic relationship possible.”74
The ideas of Jeffreys would seem to suggest that men cannot be blamed
for their evil ways. If you cannot blame people for accepting a biological
pattern that was imposed on them as embryos by nature, how can you
blame them for accepting a symbolic pattern that was imposed on them as
infants and children by culture? Neither Jeffreys nor any other feminist, at
least of this school, has raised that question. In any case, we suggest, the
facile “insight” of Jeffreys can be expressed concisely as a syllogism. The
power differential between men and women is evil. The power differential
between men and women is inherent in heterosexuality. Ergo,
heterosexuality is inherently evil. There is an irony in all this. Most
feminists take pride not only in the “connectedness” they presume to be
inherent in femaleness (even though they cast suspicion, to say the least, on
the connectedness of women to half of the human race) but also in the
diversity or pluralism they presume to be inherent in feminism (even though
many are willing to exclude from feminism, depending on circumstances,
the “voices” of women who oppose them in one way or another). They
often argue that only men are dualistic: troubled by the exotic, the foreign,
the alien, the dangerous Other (even though, in doing so, they clearly
embrace their own form of dualism). Patai calls this replication of power
language the promotion of a “radical feminist agenda,” because the utopian
project of eliminating all power would involve the elimination of all
relationships except those of clones reared exactly alike. There will always
be some differences that can translate into hierarchies of power: if not
wealth or privilege, then intelligence, artistic sensibility, health, and age. “It
is, of course, true that quid pro quo harassment – sexual shakedown –
presupposes some imbalance of power. All blackmail does.”75 But, she
continues, differences of power need not damage relations.
The logical conclusion of this belief that only men wield power, or that
only women are incapable of doing so, is an attack on the notion that
women are capable of giving consent to sexual relations with men. And
ideological feminists have indeed drawn this conclusion – even though they
argue that women are indeed capable of withholding consent: “no,” they
maintain, really does mean “no.”
The most common response to this theory of heterophobia is to trivialize
it. How many feminists, after all, really want to destroy heterosexuality?
Not many. Therefore, why bother with these loonies? And why bring
feminism into disrepute just because of a few radicals? But before
answering that question, think more carefully about those radicals. Do we
really want to declare that straight men are sexist for feeling physically
attracted to female bodies or even for merely thinking about them? This
question was certainly taken very seriously by feminists in the 1980s and
1990s. Listen to a letter to the editor from one lesbian reader of Ms: “We
may be your worst nightmare,” she states in connection with an article on
current trends in feminism, “but we are also your future.”76 Taken to its
logical conclusion, ideological feminism really does lead to lesbianism,
because only lesbians are ready, willing, and able to do without men
altogether and therefore to end “patriarchy.” (Because our “patriarchal
society” nevertheless permits artificial insemination by donor, they can
produce children without having to form even the most fleeting liaisons
with men.) But not all women are lesbians. Those women who do want
intimate and sexual relationships with men, therefore, will have to rethink
some of their assumptions about both sexual orientation and sexual
harassment.
It will not do to dismiss Patai’s notion of heterophobia just because few
women are prepared to go all the way and become lesbians. “The problem
is not the ‘fringe’ feminist that … is rejected by most women. The problem
is the general antagonism toward men that has been part of feminism from
its very beginning … Linked to the very successful movement against
sexual harassment, it has brought us to the present heavy-handed and ever-
expanding definitions of what even [Jane] Gallop refers to as a ‘loathsome
crime.’”77
At the heart of Patai’s theory is not the conspiracy of a few lesbians, who
represent neither most feminists nor even most lesbians, but the collusion –
direct or indirect, witting or unwitting – of many straight women. Why else
would they try to explain away, or even apologize for, their own sexual
orientation? And that is precisely what they do in Heterosexuality: A
Feminism and Psychology Reader.78 This anthology was edited by two gay
women, Sue Wilkinson and Celia Kitzinger, but many of the essays were
written by straight women. The authors are clearly troubled by conflict
between their sexual orientation and their feminist identity. Listen to Mary
Crawford: “I use heterosexual privilege to subvert heterosexism.”79 And
Sandra Bartky: “The felt impossibility of changing one’s sexual orientation
is not an argument for the desirability of this orientation.”80 Sandra Bem
explains, in a way that might remind some readers of defendants at the
McCarthy hearings, that she has lived and loved a man for twenty-six years
but is not and has “never been a ‘heterosexual.’”81 Why not? Because her
sexuality is “organized around dimensions other than sex,”82 whatever that
means.
The relation between fringe and mainstream feminists can be seen very
easily in connection with mainstream feminists’ evaluation of one
designated lunatic. Valerie Solanas, as we have already mentioned, was the
founder of SCUM (Society for Cutting Up Men) and the author of its
manifesto. To be blunt, she hated men. In fact, she advised women to kill
men and even tried to kill one – Andy Warhol – by herself. She saw no
reason to apologize for anything. Solanas was indeed a radical extremist.
She was clearly part of the “lunatic fringe” (and was even committed to a
mental institution). But, as Patai observes,

Solanas did not lack feminist champions for her exorbitant gesture, as
evidenced by the two representatives of NOW, Ti-Grace Atkinson and
attorney Florynce Kennedy, who accompanied her to court. Atkinson said
on that occasion that Solanas would go down in history as “the first
outstanding champion of women’s rights,” while Flo Kennedy called her
“one of the most important spokeswomen for the feminist movement … In
her long introduction to the 1970 edition of the SCUM Manifesto, [Vivian]
Gornick called Solanas a “visionary” who “understood the true nature of the
struggle” for women’s liberation. [Years later, Mary Harron made a movie
based on this event: I Shot Andy Warhol. Once again, the critics glorified
Solanas.] It is revealing that far from expressing alarm at the manifest unity
of theory and praxis in Solanas’s violence against men, some reviewers of
this film have treated Solanas as a free spirit and see this celebrated in the
movie.83

Sally Miller Gearhart, on the other hand, is not a lunatic. She is a


professor of communication, at any rate, and participates fully in
mainstream society and mainstream feminism. Nevertheless, she openly
advocates the decimation of men. Literally. She would allow no more than
10% of the population to be male. Why? Because she believes that women
are innately peaceful and kind and caring and sharing and loving, and so on
(explaining away unacceptable female leaders as the dupes, or puppets, of
men), and that men are innately violent and evil and horrible. Precisely how
would she decimate the male population? Partly by giving women total
autonomy in reproduction and allowing men no say in it whatsoever, partly
by encouraging “men to participate in their own demise by willingly
assisting in a program of reducing their numbers (reassuringly, she makes
clear that mass murder is not contemplated, but rather, slow attrition
through new reproductive technologies and support from men for feminist
goals). And from what I see on some feminist e-mail lists and in the
published work of some men … there are indeed accommodating males
who would gladly embrace even this policy for the sake of maintaining
their cherished, but never entirely secure, status as ‘feminist men.’”84
Not all women are enthusiastic about Gearhart’s plans. She explains
these scoffers away as “male-identified” women who need to be reeducated
(along with recalcitrant men, no doubt). It is worth noting here that
proposals of this kind are not as farfetched as they might sound. Women
have already mobilized for complete control over the use of new
reproductive technologies. We have already mentioned the Feminist
International Network of Resistance to Reproductive and Genetic
Engineering, a very sophisticated and influential organization that draws on
the skills and resources of academics in many countries. Although members
oppose some technologies, they do not oppose all of them. They want those
that would give reproductive autonomy to women, at least theoretically or
partially, but not to men.
Marilyn Frye, who teaches women’s studies at Michigan State
University, is another feminist who buys the separatist line. And she, too, is
not exactly beyond the mainstream. “For females to be subordinated and
subjugated to males on a global scale, and for males to organize themselves
and each other as they do, billions of female individuals, virtually all who
see life on the planet, must be reduced to a more-or-less willing toleration
of subordination and servitude to men. The primary sites of this reduction
are the sites of heterosexual relation and encounter – courtship and
marriage-arrangement, romance, sexual liaisons, fucking, marriage,
prostitution, the normative family, incest and child sexual abuse.”85
We have indirect evidence, too, in support of Patai’s theory. Even in the
1990s, it was obvious to everyone, including disappointed feminists, that
young women were having trouble with the word “feminism.” They liked
the economic gains made by feminists, to be sure, but disliked something in
the mentality of feminists whom they knew or had read about. Few of these
young women could articulate precisely how the problem had come about –
some might have declined to do so for fear of being attacked as politically
incorrect – but they often referred to intolerance in general and occasionally
to “man hating” in particular. Outraged feminists denied these charges, of
course, just as they deny Patai’s charge of heterophobia.
Just as misandry is the sexist counterpart of misogyny, presumably,
heterophobia is the sexist counterpart of homophobia. Yet Patai’s new word,
though clever, is not necessarily helpful, because the word “homophobia,”
applied as a blanket condemnation of all who oppose homosexuality,
denotes irrational fear (which is a psychological problem) even though it
almost always connotes implacable hatred (a moral problem). Patai
disregards this linguistic duplicity. She makes it clear that heterophobia,
like homophobia, really is about hatred (in addition, perhaps, to fear). By
referring to heterophobia, in any case, she focuses attention beyond
misandry itself to its logical conclusion: the ideological goal of “protecting”
women from all contact with men: economic, social, physical, and sexual.
In other words, Patai shows that those ultimately (but not solely)
responsible for misandry are the lesbian separatists (the word, as we
understand it, refers by no means to all lesbians). Only they, as we have
already pointed out, can take ideological feminism to this logical conclusion
(unless they make exceptions for their own sons or a few “male feminists,”
the men we have called “honorary women”). They attack not only men,
therefore, but also women who consort with men. In short, they attack
heterosexuality. This is not about lesbians per se. It is about an idea that
only lesbians, presumably those without sons, are capable of adopting if
they want to do so. These women are a tiny minority. But to those who
might conclude that they are of no importance in the larger context of
feminism, we say, read on. Here is Patai.

At the present moment, “sexual harassment” seems often to be little more


than a label for excoriating men. It has become the synecdoche for general
male awfulness. Its real function at this moment, in addition to keeping
feminist passions at a fever pitch, is to serve as the conduit by which some
extreme feminist tenets about the relations between the sexes enter
everyday life with minimum challenge. No longer a well-intended effort to
gain justice for women, it has been turned into a tool (powered by a legal
apparatus and manipulated by a professional cadre of trainers and
enforcers) for implementing, and indeed normalizing, what was once
merely a marginal and bizarre feminist worldview.86

Elsewhere, she adds an important connection between what might be the


active or direct misandry of some and the passive or indirect misandry of
many others:
Let me therefore be clear that what I am mainly criticizing here is an
important – and to me profoundly disturbing – aspect of feminism: its
predilection for turning complex human relations into occasions for
mobilizing the feminist troops against men. There is within much feminist
writing today (as there has been for the past few decades) a pretense that the
charge of male bashing is a slanderous mischaracterization motivated by
political impulses that are conservative (and thus assumed to be
reprehensible). But it is plain and irrefutable that much contemporary
feminism is indeed marred by hostility toward men. The virulence of it
varies from group to group. But the antagonism is pervasive, and through
the attack on “sexual harassment,” it has entered society at large.87

Taking what some would consider an extreme position, Patai argues that in
our time, the whole notion of “women” has been fragmented according to
race, sexual orientation, region, class, and so on. Hatred of men is therefore
probably the one thing that unifies women today. The result is what she
calls the “oppression sweepstakes.”88
The belief that men as a group are bent on attacking and oppressing
women as a group is an idée fixe, a central or even primal obsession seldom
questioned even in ideological circles. This became obvious to Patai at a
conference held in 1998 to celebrate the twentieth anniversary of
MacKinnon’s Sexual Harassment of Working Women. The conference
began with Dworkin emotively calling the audience’s attention to the
backlash that began when white middle-class men saw that sexual
harassment laws were going to affect them.

This reaction, Dworkin thoughtfully suggested, showed us that “millions of


men wanted to have a young woman at work to suck their cock.” Did
anyone rise to contest such outrageous slander directed at all or most men?
On the contrary … MacKinnonite terms were universally accepted as the
key to social problems: Battery is “about” male power, control, and
domination. So is rape. So is stalking. A tone of urgency was sounded by
speaker after speaker, many of them seemingly alarmed that issues of
“privacy” were resurfacing, as in the Monica Lewinsky matter, and were
fueling a “backlash.”89
The women present were all supporters of MacKinnon’s movement. Patai
recalls no mention of any problem such as false accusations, but does recall
hearing numerous testimonials by those who had “survived” harassment.
One common way of defending hatred is to “justify” it as the result of
fear. Hatred often is the result of fear, true, but even that hardly justifies
hatred. It could be argued, after all, that anti-Semites are genuinely afraid of
Jews. What makes hatred different from fear, although the two are very
closely linked, is the factor of motivation. Fear does not necessarily have a
moral dimension. We can be afraid of people without believing that they are
motivated by malice. Hatred always has a moral dimension. We hate
people, because we believe that they are not only powerful but also evil.
Another common way of defending hatred is to “justify” it as a response
to the hatred of others. Once again, it often is. But even that hardly justifies
hatred. Not unless it justifies revenge as well. Listen, now, to Patai:

It is astonishing that decades of progress for women, decades of


denunciation of misogynist ideas, should have brought us to the point where
a mere reversal – misandry instead of misogyny – should count as serious
feminist thought and should be taught and promoted in the name of
feminism. Although it is not difficult to match crazed feminist
pronouncements of our time with crazed masculinist assertions from the
past, there are two important differences. The first is that – apart from
collections of misogynistic rants across the centuries (the same sorts of
material professors like to hand out to their students to shock them into
sudden awareness of the long history of male disdain for women) – few of
us today, least of all in the academy, are exposed to persistent hysterical
denunciations of women. For the writings of feminist extremism, on the
other hand, there does seem to be a large and apparently insatiable market,
and their authors are without question among the best-known names in
contemporary feminism. The second difference is that no one ever believed
or claimed that the old misogynistic ravings could pave the way to a better
life for humankind, whereas somehow heterophobes have gained
acceptance for many of their prejudices precisely because they are being
proclaimed in the name of an ideal female future.90
Actually, Patai’s second point of difference is debatable. Some of the
passages often cited were written by theologians, for instance, and their
misogynistic points of view did indeed work their way into mainstream
theology as ways of producing a “better life for humankind.” On the other
hand, Patai ignores a third point of difference. The old misogyny was
created and disseminated without the knowledge available to us through
hindsight. Our ancestors did not know precisely what could happen when
hatred was ignored, tolerated, or justified in the name of some theology or
ideology. We do. Hatred is never justifiable, not even when it is the result of
ignorance or fear. It is even less justifiable, however, when propagated by
those who have the benefit not only of historical hindsight and even
personal or collective experience as victims of hatred but also of
sophisticated thinking about the nature of hatred – racial, religious,
linguistic, or whatever – and its relation to ideology. This point is very
important, because it challenges the common belief that “radical” feminists
can be distinguished neatly from mainstream feminists and therefore
prevented from discrediting the larger movement. They can be
distinguished in some ways, true, but not always neatly.
Feminists like to point out, especially when some aspect of feminism is
challenged, that the movement is anything but monolithic; there are many
feminist “voices.” Most of them feel free enough to raise questions about
this or that effect of feminism on women. Others do not. So far, however,
very few have felt free enough to raise questions about the effect of its
doctrines on men, at least not in connection with any compassion for men.
What makes Patai very unusual, even among those who are open to
criticism of feminism, is her recognition that feminist extremism is
problematic because of its effect on men. Yes, feminist extremism creates
problems for women (bringing feminism into disrepute, causing squabbles
among feminists, or leading to charges of sexual harassment against a few
female professors).91 Yes, it reduces university classes to group therapy
sessions (turning college students into fearful and neurotic infants). Yes, it
prevents any mature perspective on sexuality (misunderstanding the nature
of power). In addition, though, it propagates hatred toward men. Hers is a
specifically moral position, not merely a practical one. According to Patai,
“the writings of the most notorious and least responsible among
heterophobes have enormously contributed to the creation of a ‘gotcha’
atmosphere in which individual autonomy and its sexual manifestations in
particular are under attack.”92 Whether feminists will take this particular
critique seriously enough to do anything about misandry remains to be seen.
Patai’s reviewers, by and large, have not.
Ideological feminists do hold out some hope for men, but only to the
extent that men are willing to stop being men. From this it follows that
feminists may blame those men who are unwilling to do the right thing.
This has become clear in their response to recent developments in medicine.
Given the relentless hostility of ideological feminists toward
heterosexuality in general and male sexuality in particular, it is not
surprising to find that some of them have ridiculed medical treatments for
impotence. Whether feminists want to admit it or not, men are as central to
their ideology as Jews are to anti-Semitic ideology. It could be argued, in
fact, that ideological feminism is itself “phallocentric” because of its
preoccupation with male power.
The wonder is not so much that some otherwise sensible women have
come to believe this nonsense but that even a few men – the ones that we
call “honorary women” and that Patai calls “groveling men” – have come to
agree with them. These converts to ideological feminism and thus zealots
for the true faith, do whatever they can, short of surgery in most cases, to
reject their own maleness. The sort of thing that gives the Uncle Tom, or the
“self-hating” Jew a bad name. Patai discusses a few of these guys, the ones
with high profiles as friends of famous heterophobes. One is Dworkin’s
long-term roommate (and eventual husband) John Stoltenberg, who argues
that he has eliminated dualism by “refusing to be a man,”93 one of those
“penised humans.”94 Like Dworkin, who is clearly his mentor, Stoltenberg
equates maleness with evil. Hence his demand for the “End of Manhood.”95
Another example is Robert Jensen, whose stated goal is to refuse all sexual
gratification, including that provided by other men and even by erotic
pornography, on the grounds that he could not imagine any sexual act that
was not contaminated by “patriarchy” (defined, as usual, in terms of control
or power) and thus by evil.
Stoltenberg and Jensen are obviously extremists. But that is not a good
enough reason for dismissing their cultural significance, for failing to take
them seriously, because they are indeed taken very seriously by ideological
feminists, including those who have influenced public opinion and public
policy. These men are feminist trophies, or advertisements. They
supposedly provide living proof that ideological feminism, if taken to its
logical conclusion, is transparently correct. After all, even “they” admit it.
However, not many men, feminists surely realize, will go to such lengths in
the effort to win medals from feminists.
There is something very pathetic about many of the men who call
themselves “male feminists” and who are usually exempted by feminists
from the general attack on men. Their response to misandry, at any rate,
does sound more than a little neurotic. Although they have not (so far)
advocated castration or sex-change operations, and although asceticism,
including sexual abstinence, is common both historically and cross-
culturally, this particular form of asceticism is disturbing because of its
double standard. What makes it unprecedented, however, is its social
function (or lack of one). Historically and cross-culturally, asceticism has
always been associated with prestige – possibly too much prestige in some
cases96 – not with shame or self-loathing. Ascetics give up worldly
pleasures, to be sure, but they see no reason to refuse both spiritual and
worldly rewards in return for doing so. The former might include spiritual
powers of one kind or another: access to the divine through visions or
theophanies, spirit possession, esoteric knowledge, prophetic revelations,
telepathy or out-of-body travel, and so on. The latter might include
membership in publicly honoured and sometimes politically powerful
orders. Stoltenberg and Jensen ask men to embrace asceticism in return
neither for spiritual rewards (unless self-righteousness masquerading as
altruism counts as a spiritual reward) nor for worldly rewards (unless
ideological feminists are willing to offer any, which seems very unlikely).

Quite apart from any decline in the incidence of sexual harassment itself,
the debate over sexual harassment has affected society in at least four ways.
It has spawned an industry,97 for one thing, just as it has spawned similar
ones in connection with single parents, domestic violence, and rape. This
industry might be good for the economy, but it might not be so good for
society. To cope with rapidly multiplying cases of sexual harassment, there
must be cadres of trained specialists ready for action: theoreticians,
therapists, publicists, lobbyists, lawyers, fundraisers, and so forth. With a
whole new field of legal expertise opening up, the opportunities for both
legal scholars and legal advocates are virtually infinite. The courts will be
clogged with cases for decades to come. As a result, there will be more
lawyers, and richer ones, than ever before. Entrepreneurs have already
found ways of cashing in on new opportunities for lawyers. Spytech, for
instance, produces miniature tape recorders. Its advertisement goes like this:
“Sexually harassed? Prove it. Stop it. Sue.”98 A two-page ad in Harper’s
Magazine, beginning on the cover’s inside page, addresses employers as
follows: “ Domestic violence affects 1 in every 4 women. It costs American
businesses over $3 billion each year. And your company can be part of the
solution. Domestic violence is the leading cause of injury to women in our
country, and its impact extends from the home to the work-place. The
result? Shattered lives and billions of dollars in business losses annually due
to absenteeism, turnover, medical expenses and lower productivity … If
your most valuable assets were at risk, wouldn’t you protect them?”99 The
assets at risk are female employees at home, however, not at work; the risk
is not sexual harassment but domestic violence. The ad implies that these
are two forms of the same problem.
Here is a Canadian example of this industry. A company called The
Edge uses its website to advertise “training services.” It offers “problem
solving techniques,” “awareness programs introducing employees to the
issues of harassment, discrimination and workplace conflict,” “detailed,
intensive training for management, including introduction and application
of step-by-step management procedures – detailed manuals provided during
training; practical workshops,” and so forth. All are designed to meet
“your” particular needs. One bulleted item reveals a close link with the
government. Contact us, it advises readers, “[w]hen you need a human
rights practitioner with twenty years experience, including six years as
Director of Communications and Education at the Ontario Human Rights
Commission.”100 It must be comforting to know that there is always a
career in private industry after a prestigious government appointment ends.
Second, the debate over sexual harassment has endangered freedom of
speech. Long before the advent of political correctness in its current form,
legislators knew that freedom of speech always is and always must be
limited. We have libel laws to make people think twice before using their
own freedom of speech to attack others. We have laws to protect people
from those who consider it fun to scream “fire” in crowded theatres. We
have laws prohibiting the use of speech to advocate criminal activities. And
we have laws to punish those who indulge in blackmail or intimidation –
which is exactly what sexual harassment can amount to. Using freedom of
speech to intimidate employees is one thing. Using it in ways that merely
seem offensive to some people is another thing entirely. American laws to
protect people from what is offensive eviscerate the First Amendment and,
in doing so, destroy the foundation of a democratic society. Similar
comments would apply to Canadian laws.
As many pointed out during the American debate over flag desecration,
freedom of speech means nothing at all if it includes the freedom to say
only those things considered inoffensive. We might dislike vulgar talk. We
might dislike erotica. But the mentality endorsed by MacKinnon and other
ideological feminists, the one that is now institutionalized in law, could be
infinitely more dangerous to a free society. Should it really be a duty to look
for anything in the work environment that might be offensive to women in
general? If so, then some serious questions must be asked. Do we really
want to live in a society that, if this mentality were held up as a model,
would inevitably encourage intolerance? (The term “zero tolerance” has an
ironic twist; those who insist on it are usually the same people who insist on
unlimited tolerance for their own contributions to “diversity,” including
overtly ideological ones.) Do we really want to work in an atmosphere that,
under these circumstances, would inevitably encourage snoopers, spies, and
informants? It is true that finding evidence of harassment is hard. But to
repeat the old adage once again, some cures can be worse than the diseases.
One aspect of free speech, seldom discussed or even acknowledged, has
something to do with fashion. In our society, people are free to express
themselves by dressing as they see fit. Well, more or less free. Those who
wear jackets or t-shirts with racist slogans, for instance, might have some
explaining to do. More to the point here, though, is the power exerted by
mainstream fashions. People are legally free to dress up in hoop skirts or
togas, but most people would be much too inhibited by the current sartorial
standards, informal but nonetheless powerful, to do so in public.101 Many
cultural observers have commented on the current trend for girls and young
women to emulate, or at least look like, rock stars or supermodels. These
icons – Madonna, say, or Britney Spears – have carefully cultivated the
look usually associated with street prostitutes, one that features bare
midriffs and tattoos. (Boys and young men, too, follow fashions that glorify
life on the “street.” Their idols – rockers, rappers, and punkers – set the tone
by trying to look and act like pimps or thugs.) And yet not many cultural
observers have commented on the specific significance of hairstyles for
girls, young women, and middle-aged women. When Jennifer Aniston
changes her hairstyle, the event is not exactly ignored by journalists and
paparazzi. Commercials for shampoos and related products indicate a
definitely sexual subtext to all this. The most obvious, perhaps, are the ones
produced by and for Herbal Essences hair products. Like all hair
commercials, they feature a woman tossing her head and letting her hair fly
freely. But unlike most others, they feature, in addition, the sound of an
orgasm. The implication is clear, and it has been for centuries. Hair
fetishism has a long history, after all, the only new development being a
reversal of interpretation.102 Until the 1960s, loose hair symbolized sexually
loose women. From the 1960s on, loose hair – the longer and wispier the
better – has symbolized sexually free women. This brings us to the matter at
hand: the relation between current fashions for women and sexual
harassment. We are not suggesting that women who dress provocatively
deserve to be harassed or that those who harass them may be excused for
doing so. We are indeed suggesting, however, that women who present
themselves in provocative ways should realize what they are saying to men
and decide on whether that is actually what they want to say. If so, then they
should welcome, or at least expect, the advances of men. If not, then they
should take responsibility for making wiser choices every morning.
Some women have the courage to acknowledge this. Ellen Frankel Paul,
deputy director of the Social Philosophy and Policy Center at Bowling
Green State University in Ohio, warns of the danger inherent in using the
courts as a way of policing behaviour. “Do we really want legislatures and
judges delving into our most intimate, private lives,” she asks, “deciding
when a look is a leer and when a leer is a civil rights offence? Should
people have a legally enforceable right not to be offended by others? At
some point, the price for this protection is the loss of both liberty and
privacy rights.”103 To which we would add another price: the rejection of
personal and collective maturity as a goal worth seeking.
Third, the debate over sexual harassment has endangered democracy.
Perhaps because of the long utopian tradition in America, many ideological
feminists (and others) now argue for the use of legal coercion, rather than
moral persuasion, to eliminate speech that they find offensive. As readers of
both American and European history know, however, attempting to build
utopias often leads to nightmarish dystopias. After all, utopias are based
primarily on the urge to escape from human finitude (enforcing conformity
to some ideal of perfection) and on the urge to control (forcing others to
accept your own ideal). But there is no perfect society or even a perfect
workplace. People are flawed. Choices are unavoidable. Risk is
everywhere. Part of being an adult, therefore, is the ability to accept these
fundamental facts of the human condition. Some forms of pain should be
prevented by law, including intimidation and blackmail or quid pro quo
cases of sexual harassment. But we should confront other forms of pain on
our own (if need be with the help of an ombudsman). These forms of pain
would include the use of offensive language. Why? Because people are not
like the robots; eventually, they rebel against repression. In short, we can
either respect the limits on the urge to control – and freedom of speech
surely requires us to limit that urge – or pay the price for refusing to do so.
We have not yet heard from Camille Paglia. As usual, she has a lot to say
about feminism (or at least ideological feminism, in our parlance) and its
effect on society. For her, the hostile-environment policy, is

grotesquely totalitarian. It offends free-speech rights and is predicated on a


reactionary female archetype: the prudish Victorian lady who faints at a
sexual innuendo. This isn’t feminism; it’s Puritanism. The Anita Hill case,
far from expanding women’s rights, was a disaster for civil liberties. That
Hill, an articulate graduate of the Yale Law School, could find no job-
preserving way to communicate to her employer her discomfort with mild
off-color banter strained credulity. That Thomas could be publicly grilled
about trivial lunchtime conversations that occurred 10 years earlier was an
outrage worthy of Stalinist Russia … Feminist excesses have paralyzed and
neutered white, upper-middle-class young men as should be obvious to any
visitor to the campuses of élite schools … While men must behave
honorably (governors and presidents should not be dropping their pants in
front of female employees or secretly preying on buxom young interns),
women must also watch how they dress and behave. For every gross male
harasser, there are 10 female sycophants who shamelessly use their sexual
attractions to get ahead. We don’t want a society of surveillance by old
maids and snitches. The proper mission of feminism is to encourage women
to take personal responsibility without running to parental authority figures
for help.104

Finally, these developments have legalized misandry. Even if most men


could be coerced into outward conformity, that would do nothing to reverse
this trend. On the contrary, it would more likely have the opposite effect.
Because the new definition of sexual harassment makes it easier to convict
people who are guilty of no such thing, we have merely replaced old
problems in the workplace with new problems. At one time, women had to
worry about sexual or physical intimidation by men. In our time, men have
to worry about legal or political intimidation by women. Given the size of
many financial settlements, we would have to be either incredibly naive or
profoundly ideological to ignore the possibility that some women are
motivated to frame men. Life in the workplace is already pervaded by
suspicion, resentment, self-righteousness, and hypocrisy.

At issue in the continuing struggle between women and men, no less than
that between blacks and whites, is whether to promote separatism or
integration. Separatism has been fashionable for the past thirty years of
cynicism, but not everyone has abandoned integration.
9
Female Victims v. Male Victims: The Case of
Violence against Women
Rape violates women physically and mentally, humiliates them, devastates
their sense of self-respect, undermines their dignity, and often leaves them
with a sense of inferior status in the community which may never be
undone. Threat of rape makes threat of such violation a permanent feature
of the landscape of women’s lives.1

[P]artner abuse is routinely portrayed and acted upon as though it were


almost exclusively about men abusing and victimizing innocent women
and, by extention [sic], their children – despite the overwhelming
sociological evidence that a significant amount of abuse is also suffered by
male partners.2

On Super Bowl Sunday, 2004, Janet Jackson and Justin Timberlake caused
a national furore during their performance for the half-time show.
According to their plan, Timberlake tore off part of Jackson’s costume and
left her breast partially exposed (the rest of it was covered with a “nipple
shield”). There was a lot of angry talk about exposing children to sexually
explicit behaviour. But some people saw an even deeper problem.
According to Don Macpherson, the real problem was not sex but misogyny.
Timberlake, presumably a role model for boys, had symbolically committed
a sexual assault on Jackson. “It was not Jackson who bared her breast,”
wrote Macpherson, “but rather her male fellow performer … And while it
was part of a stage act scripted in advance, in the act itself there was no
indication Timberlake had Jackson’s consent to do so.”3 Yes, but this was
indeed a scripted performance. Jackson was at least as responsible for what
happened as Timberlake. If we blame him and other male pop stars for
legitimating this symbolic act, then surely we should blame Jackson and
other female pop stars as well. It can hardly be said, after all, that the latter
have presented themselves as modest and innocent or even as naive. On the
contrary, as we noted in chapter 8, they have done everything to push the
boundaries of female nudity and provocation. And with what purpose in
mind? What is the message that they want to give men? Look but don’t
touch? Of greater importance is the message that some feminists want to
give men: that even symbolic acts of sexual violence against women
constitute actual violence against women.
After an introduction on the term “violence against women,” we will
review the legislation governing it. We will then discuss the debate over
domestic violence, the debate over rape, and the misandric fallout from
these debates.

Closely related to pornography, prostitution, and sexual harassment,


according to ideological feminists, is something known generically as
“violence against women” or “male violence” (the latter never refers, for
some reason, to the violence of men against other men). These terms
include, at the very least, both domestic violence and rape. They have
become feminist trump cards, because everyone agrees that acts of physical
aggression are intolerable. Trouble is, that agreement does not go very far in
the controversy that has been generated.
Not everyone agrees on precisely what constitutes violence in the first
place, for instance, let alone violence against women. Should there be any
significant distinction between physical violence and “emotional violence”?
What is more important, not everyone agrees that violence against women
should be singled out from other forms of violence for special attention.
Some ideological feminists do not care about violence against men, whether
by women or by other men. Others believe that there is no fundamental
difference between violence in general (including violence against men)
and violence against women in particular. They believe instead that all
forms of violence, like everything else in a patriarchal society, are
ultimately derived from the paradigm of violence against women. The only
way to end violence of any kind, therefore, is to end the subordination of
women. From their point of view, referring to violence in general is
therefore tantamount to ignoring or even trivializing the underlying problem
of violence against women.
Not everyone agrees, moreover, with another fundamental premise of
ideological feminists: that violence against women is merely one end of a
continuum that begins with risqué jokes, erotic publications, or
heterosexuality itself. In other words, they believe, all men are implicated in
all crimes – including everything from kissing to raping – against all
women. From this point of view, men are the archetypal oppressors of
women, no matter what form the oppression might take. Case closed.

In 1978, Congress passed the Privacy Protection for Rape Victims Act. This
legislation included Federal Rule of Evidence (FRE) 412, which was
popularly dubbed the “rape shield” law. Rule 412 consists of both
evidentiary rules and procedural requirements.4 It stipulates that evidence of
the past sexual behaviour of an alleged victim of rape or assault is not
admissible except in three circumstances: first, if the defendant claims that
the plaintiff has invented the story of sexual assault to explain awkward
facts – a pregnancy, an injury, or an absence – to her husband or boyfriend;
second, if the defendant claims that he had a sexual relationship with the
alleged victim and therefore understood that she had given her consent on
the most recent occasion (although courts usually reject this claim if the
reference is to a much earlier phase of the relationship); third, if excluding
evidence would violate the constitutional rights of a defendant – such as the
right to know the nature and cause of the accusation, the right to a speedy
and public trial by an impartial jury, the right to be confronted with the
witnesses against him, and so forth (all under the Sixth Amendment) and
the right to due process (under the Fifth Amendment). Note the gendered
lingo; those who wrote these laws made no attempt to use gender-neutral
terminology, even though men can be and sometimes are raped.
Since it is the defendant’s burden to show why any of these three
exceptions should be allowed, 412 favours the plaintiff, who would prefer
to exclude evidence. “Assume that the government’s case consists entirely
of v’s testimony that a raped her. The government’s case would be far from
overwhelming and v’s credibility would be a critical issue in the case. The
proffered evidence is directly related to v’s motive to lie, and therefore, to
her credibility. Furthermore, a’s friend will testify about the affair he had
with v on the night of the alleged incident. By doing so, this witness will
also partially corroborate a’s version of the facts. Accordingly, a court is
likely to find that the evidence is favorable to the defense.”5
In the Violent Crime Control and Law Enforcement Act of 1994 (also
called the Violence against Women Act), the ante was upped to favour the
plaintiff even more strongly in rape cases. Three new federal rules of
evidence were introduced. Rule 413, “Evidence of Similar Crimes in Sexual
Assault Cases,” states that “[i]n a criminal case in which a defendant is
accused of an offense of sexual assault, evidence of the defendant’s
commission of another offense or offenses of sexual assault is admissible.”6
Rule 414, “Evidence of Similar Crimes in Child Molestation Cases,” and
Rule 415, the “Evidence of Similar Crimes in Civil Cases Concerning
Sexual Assault or Child Molestation,” provide further definitions of
evidence.7
According to 413 and 415, the offense of sexual assault includes any
conduct proscribed by chapter 109a of Title 18, United States Code, which
includes “the intentional touching, either directly or through the clothing, of
the genitalia, anus, groin, breast, inner thigh, or buttocks of any person with
an intent to abuse, humiliate, harass, degrade, or arouse or gratify the sexual
desire of any person.”8 This definition allows a wide range of evidence –
for instance, evidence of a pinch on the butt – that had not previously been
used in a criminal case against a defendant.
These new rules were by no means unopposed when they were being
drafted. The Advisory Committee on Evidence Rules considered responses
from judges, lawyers, law professors, and legal organizations. The
overwhelming majority opposed 413, 414, and 415, mainly because they
would allow biased evidence.9 They noted also that the problems at issue
could be solved by means of existing federal rules of evidence.
Furthermore, the committee pointed out, “the new rules, which are not
supported by empirical evidence, could diminish significantly the
protections that have safeguarded persons accused in criminal cases and
parties in civil cases against undue prejudice. These protections form a
fundamental part of American jurisprudence and have evolved under long-
standing rules and case law. A significant concern identified by the
committee was the danger of convicting a criminal defendant for past, as
opposed to charged, behavior or for being a bad person.”10 Moreover, the
new rules overrode protections such as the hearsay rule or rule 403’s
balancing test.11
The upshot of the committee’s review was an almost unanimous vote
(except for representatives from the Department of Justice) to oppose the
new rules. In view of all this, the committee urged Congress either to
dismiss the rules or to make them amendments to rules of evidence 404 and
405.12 When these recommendations went back to Congress,
Representative Susan Molinari, who had sponsored the new rules, reminded
Congress of the enormous support that they had within President Bush’s
violent-crime bill.13 She then announced that the new rules would take
effect within the year and could be repealed or modified only by additional
legislation.14 In defense of her position, she argued that the “enactment of
this reform is first and foremost a triumph for the public – for the women
who will not be raped and the children who will not be molested because
we have strengthened the legal system’s tools for bringing the perpetrators
of these atrocious crimes to justice.”15 Moreover, she argued, the “proposed
reform is critical to the protection of the public from rapists and child
molesters, and is justified by the distinctive characteristics of the cases it
will affect.”16
Congress passed several other acts to curb other forms of violence
against women and children in the early 1990s: the Victims of Child Abuse
Act of 1990, the Equal Justice for Women in the Courts Act of 1994, the
Safe Homes for Women Act of 1994, the Violence against Women Act
(VAWA) of 1994, and the Family Violence Prevention and Services Act of
1996.17
Of particular interest here is the Violence against Women Act, which
originated with feminist interest in hate-crime legislation. James Jacobs and
Kimberly Potter observe that the Hate Crime Statistics Act of 1990 named
eight hate crimes and defined prejudice as “a preformed negative opinion or
attitude toward a group of persons based on their race, religion, ethnicity,
national origin, or sexual orientation.”18 The political scenario that
accompanied the passage of this act is intriguing. It was demanded by a
coalition that included B’nai Brith’s Anti-Defamation League, the Anti-
Klan Network, the International Network for Jewish Holocaust Survivors,
the American Arab Anti-Discrimination Committee, the Japanese American
Citizens League, and the Organization of Chinese Americans.19 All
declared that hate crimes had reached epidemic proportions. Somehow, they
managed to exclude women’s groups, although the latter had lobbied very
hard for inclusion. Why? Because, said the coalition, statistics on rape and
domestic violence were already being collected by the government.
However, Jacobs and Potter suggest that the real reason was to avoid being
overwhelmed by such a massive lobby group. In any case, feminist
advocacy groups replied by calling the exclusion “gender bias” and
lobbying Congress either to amend the act or create a separate one for
violent crimes against women. And the politicians complied, ever mindful
of the fact that most voters are women.20 The Violence against Women Act
was the result. Victims of rape and domestic violence could now use the
civil courts, with their low standards of proof and no presumption of
innocence, to sue for damages.21
In 2000, Congress passed the Victims of Trafficking and Violence
Prevention Act. Division a is the Trafficking Victims Protection Act.22 The
word “trafficking” in this document means using fraud or coercion to rape,
abuse, torture, starve, imprison, or psychologically abuse girls or women.
Citing the findings of Congress, it held that trafficking in the national and
international sex trade is a modern form of slavery and the fastest-growing
source of profit for organized crime.23
Trafficking is very broadly defined here to include psychological abuse,
a vague notion that can be exploited easily for political purposes. And
despite the claim that there were no laws that acknowledged the gravity of
trafficking offenses, except when children were involved, many laws
against sexual assault were in place at the state level. Feminists were
motivated at least partly by the sheer prestige of federal law, no doubt,
along with the gravity of violating it.
Division B is a revision of the Violence against Women Act.24 Mandating
a vast bureaucracy, it requires legal assistance and “advocacy” services;
grants to coordinate services and activities at federal, state, and local levels;
shelters for battered women and their children; grants to study arrest and
antistalking policies; ways to enhance school and campus security;
transitional-housing assistance for victims of domestic violence; grants for
“training” and “educating” judges, court personnel, and forensic examiners;
a national domestic-violence hotline; federal counsellors for victims; a
study of state laws regarding insurance discrimination against victims of
violence against women; a study of violence against women in the work-
place; unemployment compensation for victims of violence against women;
a report on the effects of parental-kidnapping laws in domestic violence
cases; the development of ways to prevent battered immigrant women and
children from remaining locked in abusive relationships; protections for
older and disabled women; pilot programs on safe havens for children;
“supervised visitation and safe visitation exchange of children by and
between parents in situations involving domestic violence, child abuse,
sexual assault, or stalking”;25 notice requirements for sexually violent
offenders; and a research program, along with its own task force, to oversee
implementation and coordination of the recommendations. This revision
replaced the words “racial, cultural, ethnic, and language minorities” with
“under-served populations.”26 Also, a new category of violence was
introduced: “dating violence” by one “who is or has been in a social
relationship of a romantic or intimate nature with the victim.”27
Due to the original VAWA, the federal government has maintained a
Violence against Women Office (VAWO). Its publications encourage “victim
service agencies and legal service providers to enhance delivery of quality
comprehensive legal services to victims of domestic violence, sexual
assault, and stalking.”28 Here are some titles: Understanding DNA
Evidence; The Sexual Victimization of College Women; The Nature, and
Consequences of Intimate Partner Violence; and The Criminalization of
Domestic Violence. The office provides the Toolkit to End Violence against
Women, moreover. This was developed by the National Advisory Council
on Violence against Women, which was co-chaired by the Departments of
Justice and Health and Human Services.
The Federal Bureau of Investigation makes use of several statutes
covering crimes against children. We have already discussed the ones on
porn and child support. Others protect minors from aggravated sexual
abuse, sexual abuse, and prostitution.29 In 1996, the Pam Lychner Sexual
Offender Tracking and Identification Act declared that sex offenders who
had two or more convictions or were convicted of aggravated sexual abuse
must register as sex offenders, the length of time they spend on this registry
depending on the type of offence.30 The Crimes against Children Unit of the
Federal Bureau of Investigation has a National Sex Offender Registry, as
does the National Crime Information Center.31
Canada has taken similar steps to protect plaintiffs (who are almost
always women) in rape cases and make it easier to prosecute defendants
(almost always men). In 1982, Parliament amended two sections of its
Criminal Code. Section 276 limits cross-examination about sexual history.32
Section 277 prohibits evidence about sexual reputation.33 These changes
became known as Canadian “rape shield” laws. “Sexual history” now refers
to sexual acts known to have been performed, and “sexual reputation” only
to alleged proclivities.
Section 276 is very much like its American equivalent, rule 412.
“[E]vidence that the complainant has engaged in sexual activity, whether
with the accused or with any other person, is not admissible to support an
inference that, by reason of the sexual nature of that activity the
complainant … is more likely to have consented to the sexual activity … or
… is less worthy of belief.”34 Like the American counterpart, it makes an
exception if the evidence “is of specific instances of sexual activity … is
relevant to an issue at trial … [and] has significant probative value that is
not substantially outweighed by the danger of prejudice to the proper
administration of justice.”35 To make a decision, the judge, provincial court
judge, or justice must take into account

the interests of justice, including the right of the accused to make a full
answer and defend … society’s interest in encouraging the reporting of
sexual assault offences … whether there is a reasonable prospect that the
evidence will assist in arriving at a just determination in the case … the
need to remove from the fact-finding process any discriminatory belief or
bias … the risk that the evidence may unduly arouse sentiments of
prejudice, sympathy or hostility in the jury … the potential prejudice to the
complainant’s personal dignity and right of privacy … the right of the
complainant and of every individual to personal security and to the full
protection and benefit of the law … and any other factor that the judge,
provincial court judge or justice considers relevant.36
Section 277 states that “evidence of sexual reputation, whether general
or specific, is not admissible for the purpose of challenging or supporting
the credibility of the complainant.”37 Moreover, section 666 says that
“where, at trial, the accused adduces evidence of his good character, the
prosecutor may, in answer thereto, before a verdict is returned, adduce
evidence of the previous conviction of the accused for any offences,
including any previous conviction by reason of which a greater punishment
may be imposed.”38
The rape-shield laws were challenged in R. v. Seaboyer; R. v. Gayme.39
The two defendants argued that their right to a fair trial under the Charter
was infringed by the Criminal Code, which does not allow a defendant
(apart from the three exceptions that we have mentioned) to cite the plain-
tiff’s previous sexual history.
According to one of the men, he sincerely believed that the woman had
given him consent and also that his credibility would be reinforced by
evidence of her sexual history. LEAF argued against him, because his defense
would have been “according to the accused’s beliefs and not according to
the victim’s experience.”40 In addition, LEAF argued that men make the
following wrong assumptions about women: that they either secretly want
to be raped – ironically, MacKinnon herself actually agrees with that
because of her own assumption about the “eroticization” of male violence –
or are congenitally promiscuous, that women argue coercion to cover their
promiscuity, that women cannot be violated if they are no longer virgins,
that women consent to sexual activities unless they fight back vigorously,
that women are not unduly troubled if they know the men involved, and that
women might say yes for fear of being killed after saying no.
The Supreme Court upheld section 277 but struck down section 276,
arguing that its legitimacy should be decided in each case by the judge
alone. For Christopher Manfredi, nonetheless, “one should not exaggerate
the extent to which LEAF lost in Seaboyer. Indeed, the government invited
representatives of the Canadian feminist movement to participate actively in
the drafting of a new sexual assault law that redefines both the nature of
consent and the defenses available to defendants in sexual assault
proceedings. In this sense, LEAF was able to convert a legal defeat into a
political victory.”41
To encourage the reporting of rape and litigation, LEAF argued in
Canadian Newspapers Co. v. Canada that it was necessary to prevent
newspapers from publishing the names of alleged victims.42 But in the case
of a false complaint, argued the opposition, publishing these names might
bring forth witnesses to support the defendant. The opposition argued also
that not publishing these names would violate freedom of expression, which
is protected by the Charter. A unanimous decision by the Supreme Court
supported the ban on publishing names, however, arguing that it did not
violate freedom of expression and protected the equality of “women and
children.”
To deal with the problem of violence against women, Health Canada
established several Family Violence Initiatives between 1986 and 1997.
These brought federal, provincial, and territorial governments together with
Crown corporations, nongovernmental organizations, professional agencies,
universities, aboriginal community organizations, and so forth. Beginning
in 1995, moreover, Canadian law gave strong support to women in cases of
domestic violence. Saskatchewan passed the Victims of Domestic Violence
Act that year and other provinces followed suit. The Saskatchewan
legislation includes several parts. According to the Emergency Intervention
Orders, only alleged victims may occupy their homes; alleged abusers may
not live or communicate with either their alleged victims or the families of
their alleged victims. According to the Victims’ Assistance Orders,
convicted abusers must provide financial compensation to their victims.
And according to the Warrants of Entry, police officers may enter any home
in which domestic violence is suspected.43 This powerful legislation was
challenged in several court cases.44 As a result, claimants had to show that
serious violence had indeed occurred.
In 1995, Bill C-42 amended the Criminal Code as follows: it made
protective court orders both easier to get and more effective, increased the
maximum penalty for violation of a peace bond (a form of restraining
order) from six months to two years, and reclassified “hybrid offenses”
(which allowed prosecutors to proceed directly, without requiring victims to
testify twice).45 More amendments were added that year by Bill C-72,
which excluded intoxication as a defense in cases of assault and sexual
assault. Still more amendments had been added the following year by Bill
C-41, which had allowed judges to include offences against spouses and
children as aggravating factors for purposes of sentencing and also allowed
victims to seek restitution for expenses incurred by moving out to avoid
physical harm.
The Firearms Control Act of 1996 introduced several changes: it
required Canadians to get licenses for all weapons, established a national
registry of these weapons, and raised the mandatory sentence for sexual
assault or other violent crimes to at least four years.
In 1997, Bill C-27 introduced several more changes. These made it easier
for young victims and victims of sexual exploitation to testify in court,
allowed for the prosecution of Canadians who sexually exploit children
abroad, increased penalties for those who hire juvenile prostitutes and those
who stalk and kill, and made it clear that female circumcision is an offence.
That same year, Bill C-46 protected victims of sexual offences by restricting
the use of personal records such as those compiled by psychiatrists or
counsellors. The federal budget for one year, 1997–98, included not only
$30.7 million to deal with domestic violence in particular but also federal
subsidies to deal with violence against women in general. In the late 1990s,
some provinces set up domestic-violence courts to ensure a specialized
response to women, which might involve emotional and financial support
for witnesses, cultural interpreters, tapes of emergency calls, photographs of
injuries, or speedy trials.
A government report of 1998 addressed to the United Nations
Commission on Human Rights reviewed what the Canadian government
had done for women since 1994.46 Measures taken had included
inaugurating public-awareness campaigns, developing “gender evaluation
tools” for “gender-based analysis,” funding shelters, and establishing
research centres.47 In addition, the report covered topics such as federal
initiatives, provincial and territorial initiatives, criminal-justice measures,
statistics, “training” programs for the criminal-justice system, prevention
awareness programs, and support services such as safe houses and crisis
interventions. The report is worth a read for anyone who can endure its
bureaucratic jargon. Here are the highlights.
The federal government had discussed “training” or “educational”
programs for judges. Plans had involved the promotion of feminist legal
theories and provided statistical support based on feminist analyses. The
discussion had referred to similar programs for the Royal Canadian
Mounted Police and the National Parole Board; both programs had been
intended to increase “awareness of equality issues affecting various groups
who feel disadvantaged or inadequately understood by the Canadian justice
system.”48 Both had included tools that would be useful in coping with
violence against women. One example is the Investigative Guide for Sexual
Offences, which describes appropriate ways of investigating sexual assaults
and effective ways of creating workshops to “educate” communities.49
The report went on about how “to do gender equality analysis in the
prosecution of family violence cases.”50 In addition, the federal government
had set up “awareness” programs that had been intended for use in schools,
to raise consciousness among children, counsel those who had experienced
abuse, and “guide” professionals in medical and social work. Canadians had
now been granted programs for (male) “abusers,” moreover, from short
interventions to intensive therapeutic ones for those in prisons or on
probation. These programs had received a great deal of publicity in the
mass media.
The report linked sexual assault and the economic status of women.
Canadians had now been given the benefit of workshops on how to improve
women’s participation in the economy. One of these, held in 1998, had been
called “Women and the Knowledge-Based Economy and Society.” Its
mandate had been to ensure that “gender-based” (read: feminist) analyses
for all “future policies and legislation to determine their implications for
women and men.”51 The underlying logic had been distinctly
MacKinnonesque: that violence against women occurs primarily because
women have a lower economic status than men. In Seaboyer the feminist
Legal and Education Action Fund (LEAF) used the same argument:

It is submitted that sexual assault is an equality issue … Women are singled


out for sexual assault and their accusations of sexual assault are
systematically disbelieved because of their gender, that is, because they are
relegated to an inferior social status as female, including being socially
defined as appropriate targets for forced sex … It is submitted that in an
equal society, sexual assault on women and children would be exceptional,
rather than as common as it is under current conditions of inequality.52
In its discussion of violence against women, the report cited fallacious
statistics contained in the Violence against Women Survey of 1993 (which
we discuss in appendix 3) and called them “a national base of information
on the extent of violence against Canadian women in Canadian society.”53
The debate over domestic violence is very acrimonious and has been for
decades. In terms of legislation, though, women have clearly won the
debate. They have had enormous success in establishing public awareness
and prevention programs, which include “gender-based” evaluation tools
and special services for women. The latter, in turn, include hotlines,
shelters, counsellors, specialized courts, new police policies (entering
homes where violence is suspected), new court policies (preventing contact
between violent men and their children or mandating supervised visits or
awarding houses to female victims), and so forth. Women needed many of
these reforms. Trouble is, ideological feminists have exploited them to
empower women in ways that not only foster misandry but also create
systemic discrimination against men. The results go beyond reform. Most
people, both women and men, still assume that only women need to fear
domestic violence.
Before proceeding, please note that this section is about violence within
the home (although, as Warren Farrell points out, violence is not the only
weapon used by men and women against their spouses or partners).54
Violence outside the home is another matter. Many more men than women
resort to violence outside the home, usually against other men. Our point
here is only that the story of domestic violence, sometimes known
specifically as “abused women,” is much more complicated than anyone
would guess after a steady diet of ideological rhetoric from feminists.
There is clearly a legitimate link between statistics and laws; the latter
should be made in view of the former. But what if the statistics are
methodologically flawed or prejudicially interpreted? To place that
discussion in its proper context, we turn now from domestic violence
against women to domestic violence by women. The former is a serious
problem, to be sure, but so is the latter. And neither journalists nor feminists
have said much about the latter, except in attempts to explain it away as an
aberration, one that is usually caused either directly or indirectly by men in
any case. Scholars, on the other hand, have been researching this topic for
decades. And not only male scholars.
Contrary to conventional wisdom, which is based on the suppression of
evidence and even biased statistics, research that began in the 1980s has
repeatedly shown that women commit or even initiate domestic violence at
least as often as men do. In the research of Murray Straus and Richard
Gelles, 53% of the women questioned admitted that they had struck first.55
Other studies indicate that women are more likely than men to become
violent without expecting reprisals.56 According to Coramae Mann, only
around 10% of the self-defense claims are legitimate.57 Why? For one
thing, some women kill men who are incapacitated in wheelchairs, asleep in
bed, or not then engaged in violent or threatening behaviour. By making
preemptive strikes, albeit strikes based on reasonable fear of future
violence, these women take the law into their own hands. Since men are
often victims of domestic abuse, moreover, some scholars refer now to the
Battered Man Syndrome, which is the counterpart of the Battered Woman
Syndrome (although not all of the reasons that men stay in abusive
relationships are the same as those of women who do so).
Warren Farrell still had to rebut denials that men were often victims of
domestic violence. In Women Can’t Hear What Men Don’t Say, he
summarized all this evidence:

To their credit, despite their assumption that men were the abusers, every
domestic violence survey done of both sexes over the … [last] quarter
century in the United States, Canada, England, New Zealand, and Australia
… found one of two things: Women and men batter each other about
equally, or women batter men more. In addition, almost all studies found
women were more likely to initiate violence and much more likely to inflict
the severe violence. Women themselves acknowledged they are more likely
to be violent and to be initiators of violence. Finally, women were more
likely to engage in severe violence that was not reciprocated.58

According to both women’s support groups and to police reports, men


are responsible for approximately 90% of domestic violence. According to
men’s support groups, on the other hand, women are responsible for 81% of
domestic violence.59 Which to believe? For feminists, the answer is
obvious. For researchers, the answer is not so obvious, or should not be.
The whole point of research, after all, is to examine the evidence and
possibly find something new, not merely to confirm what is already
assumed. Some research eventually does confirm earlier assumptions or
hypotheses, but not because of any hopes on the part of scholars.
Farrell consulted the National Organization for Women. Were there any
two-sex studies of domestic violence, he asked, showing that most batterers
were men? He was referred to the National Crime Victimization Survey, but
this presented him with a problem. The survey asked men and women if
they had ever been “hit” or “kicked” in the context of a crime. Men were
found to be much more likely than women to answer in terms of violence
outside the home. Women were found to be much more likely than men to
answer in terms of violence within the home, which was and is legally
defined as a crime. As a result, more women than men claimed to have been
the victims of domestic violence. “We have educated women to think of
being punched or kicked by a man as a crime, so a crime survey can get
women to report that as a crime; we have not yet educated men to think of
being bitten, punched, kicked, or hit with a frying pan as a crime, so a crime
survey fails to get men to report these behaviors as a crime. A crime survey
cannot hear what men do not say.”60
Besides, Farrell points out, men are more likely than women to be
specific in responding to questions. Asked if he has ever been battered, he
might say no. Even after being hit repeatedly with a frying pan. Asked if he
has ever been hit with a frying pan by his wife, on the other hand, he might
say yes. How to explain this difference in perception between the sexes?
There might be some biological or evolutionary reason for men to favour
specificity, but the most obvious reason in this case is surely that both
women and men have been carefully trained over the past twenty-five years
to identify even slapping a woman as domestic violence. Neither men nor
women, on the other hand, have been trained to identify even stabbing a
man specifically as domestic violence.61
Moreover, Farrell found evidence that both sexes trivialize injuries done
to men. According to a survey by the Department of Justice, 41% of
Americans find it “less severe when a wife stabs her husband to death as
they do when a husband stabs his wife to death.”62 The same double
standard is applied to nonlethal forms of violence. Both sexes consider it
more serious when a man hits, bites, or throws something at a woman than
when a woman does precisely the same thing to a man.63 Nonetheless, most
people would say, surely the effect of violence is more severe when women
are the victims (which would be a matter of practical, but not moral,
importance).
It is true that more women than men, 2.9% versus 1.9%, seek medical
help as a result of domestic violence.64 “Is this because a frying pan hurts a
man less,” asks Farrell, “than a fist hurts a woman … Or is there something
wrong with the way we are measuring who is injured? To measure which
sex is injured more by measuring which sex reports to the doctor more is to
make the same mistake we made by assuming women were battered more
because they reported domestic violence to the police more.”65 The
lamentable fact is that men are much less likely than women to seek
medical help in any circumstances, even for routine checkups. They would
have to be much more severely injured than female victims, therefore, to
end up in emergency rooms.
Even those who do are not necessarily identified as refugees from
troubled homes. Physicians are not trained to ask male patients, unlike
female ones, either leading or specific questions about domestic violence.
Nor has any government published information to help physicians identify
the subtle signs of domestic violence in male patients, unlike female ones.
“It is exactly the feeling that men are stronger – usually true – that
[ostensibly] gives women permission for hitting them harder and using
weapons. This is even true in mothers’ attitudes toward their sons vs. their
daughters. Sons are more than twice as likely as daughters to be injured
when their mothers hit them.”66 As a result, says Farrell, even the statistics
on men who do show up in emergency rooms might not adequately reflect
the number of victims of domestic violence. According to him, women are
more likely than men to use weapons. “The weapons women use are more
varied and creative than men’s, doubtless in compensation for less muscle
strength.”67
And the women of some other societies are not much different in this
respect from those of our own. Farrell examined statistics not only from the
United States and Canada but also from the United Kingdom, New Zealand,
British Honduras, Puerto Rico, Israel, and Finland. Except in Puerto Rico,
he found, women are either just as likely as men to indulge in domestic
violence or more so.68 In addition, Farrell examined the statistics on various
subcultures in the United States. He found, for example, that in the case of
Quakers, who are pacifists by creed, both men and women indulged in
minor forms of violence and at approximately the same rate: 12% for
women versus 11% for men, slightly higher in both cases than among the
general population. When it came to severe forms of violence, however, the
Quakers were much more peaceable: 2.5% for women (versus 4.4% for
other women) and 0.8% for men (versus 3% for other men). Culture, in
short, can make a difference.69
According to one American study conducted by the Department of
Justice, observes Jerry Adler, about 2.5 million crimes of all kinds are
committed against American women every year.70 This study was based on
interviews rather than police reports, which tend to underestimate the
number of domestic assaults. According to the National Clearinghouse for
the Defense of Battered Women, nevertheless, 800,000 women are battered
every year in Pennsylvania alone!71 Not even the staid American Medical
Association, apparently, can be trusted. On one occasion, it reported that
family violence killed as many women in five years as the total number of
Americans killed in the Vietnam War.72 This would mean 10,000 women
murdered every year, though, which is more than twice the number
recorded by the FBI.73 “Yes, it would be better if journalists were more
skeptical of statistics,” writes Adler. “But they’re not the ones who have
turned public-policy debate in America into a tug of war over data. What’s
important to know about spouse abuse is that it’s wrong, whether it kills
1,400 women a year or some other number. Data on sexual molestation
even if it were accurate ought to have no bearing on anyone’s civil rights.
Someday we’ll remember that facts are only the shadow cast by truth.”74
Similarly, Philip Cook observes that there is a “higher or nearly equal
rate of domestic violence against men.”75 He devotes the first chapter of
Abused Men to a critical analysis of statistical sources: police reports and
surveys. He asks questions about the many variables. Is the violence trivial
(slapping, grabbing, shoving, pushing)? Is it serious (injuries requiring
medical attention)? Is it catastrophic (murder)? Is its category underreported
or adequately reported? On the question of whether women physically
assault their mates at a rate similar to men, he observes that “[t]he answer
often depends on who is asking the question, how it is asked, and how the
data are analyzed. Statistical results from surveys can vary greatly owing to
differences between the populations studied, so it is often best to directly
examine results obtained from different reporting groups first in order to
piece together an overall picture. It then becomes easier to judge these
results fairly as they compare to more generally representative surveys.”76
But precisely what kinds of violence are involved in these studies? If
women really do engage in domestic violence, maybe they are just throwing
burned toast around the kitchen or elbowing their husbands out of the way.
Maybe men, by contrast, are knocking their wives out cold or shooting
them. In that case, the numbers would be lying and should be dismissed.
But the studies reported by Farrell – and he reported a lot of them, carefully
documenting each – indicate nothing of the kind. One of them makes a
clear distinction between minor and severe types of violence. The former
includes throwing an object (4.1% by husbands versus 7.4% by wives);
pushing, shoving, or grabbing (10.4% versus 10.9%); and slapping (2.6%
versus 3.8%). The latter includes kicking, biting, or punching (1.3% versus
3.4%); hitting with an object (1.6% versus 2.8%); beating (0.8% versus
0.6%); choking (0.8% versus 0.6%); threatening with a knife or gun (0.4%
versus 0.7%); and using a knife or gun (0.2% versus 0.1%). In all but three
categories – beating, choking, and threatening with a knife or gun (though
not actually using a knife or gun) – wives out-ranked husbands.77
Following a study of police records by Maureen McLeod, Cook reports
that

72 percent of the attacks against women by men involved the use of bodily
force (hitting, punching, slapping, kicking, etc.), but for women assaulting
men, only 14 percent involved bodily force … Only 15 percent of the
women faced a gun or a knife in a domestic battle. A gun or a knife was
used or threatened against a male victim 63 percent of the time … Owing to
the greater use of cutting objects and other weapons, McLeod states,
“Offenses against men are significantly more serious in nature than are
offenses against women.” Her examination of police reports found,
“Whereas just over one-fourth of all spouse abuse incidents involving
female victims are categorized as aggravated assaults, the corresponding
statistic for male victims is demonstrably higher … 86% are aggravated;
over two-thirds of these aggravated events are serious assaults with a
weapon.” … The more frequent use of weapons by women (82 percent for
women versus 25 percent for men) in spousal assaults results in a greater
injury rate for men, according to McLeod: 77 percent of the assaulted men
report some injury. These statistics clearly exceed estimates of the extent of
victim injury among female victims, generally documented as between 52
and 57 percent.” In fact, McLeod says, 84 percent of the men who were
injured by domestic violence required medical attention, with 50 percent of
these being hospitalized overnight or longer.78

Cook concludes that “males may suffer serious injury more often
whereas females likely suffer a greater number of total injuries ranging
from minor to serious.”79 After examining a great deal of evidence – police
reports, hospital surveys, military surveys, shelter surveys, national surveys
– he questions the claim that domestic violence by women can always be
explained as self-defense. “Although the data do not indicate what
proportion of the violent acts we see in response to violent acts by men, the
fact that women had higher mean and median rates for severe violence
suggests that female aggression is not merely a response to male
aggression.”80
As for domestic murder, Cook reports that more women than men are
indeed killed by their spouses. The difference is 20%.81 According to
Farrell, though, many more wives would be implicated in murder if several
hidden factors were taken into account. For one thing, some women use
poison or some other method that might be listed in official records as an
accident. Other women either persuade their boyfriends (occasionally male
students) or hire experienced hit men to murder for them. These murders, if
solved, are listed as “multiple-offender killings.” They do not show up,
therefore, in the statistics on women who murder. “We only know,” says
Farrell, “that in multiple-offender killings there are four times as many
husbands as victims than wives, according to the FBI.”82
More men who kill their wives than women who kill their husbands, by
the way, also kill themselves. Their motivation is not to collect insurance
money, or to marry someone else. “In brief,” writes Farrell, “a wife’s style
of killing reflects her motivation, which requires the killing not be detected;
a husband’s style of killing reflects his motivation and, well, a husband who
kills himself is pretty likely to be caught – a dead husband is a dead
giveaway. Even if her killing does get detected, it is much more likely to
never be recorded as a spouse killing – but as a multiple-offender killing, or
an accident or a heart attack. When a woman is murdered, we are more
likely to track down the killer than when a man is murdered.”83
Who are these women who batter and sometimes even kill their
husbands? Mainly women who were battered as children: the same variable
accounts for many men who batter and sometimes kill their wives.
(According to one study, ironically, both boys and girls who were beaten by
their fathers grew up to become victims, but those beaten by their mothers
grew up to become victimizers.)84 Women are conditioned to think about
men, says Patricia Pearson, in precisely the same way as men themselves
do. As a result, many women are not even aware of the damage they can
inflict on men. And the shelters seldom teach women how to deal with their
own anger and violence. Even in the late 1990s, observes Pearson, 23% of
women in one study – a figure that had not changed over the previous
twenty years – believed that “slapping the cad” is justifiable.85 That lesson
is taught very effectively through popular culture. In fact, as we observed in
Spreading Misandry, what we call The Slap is a convention so deeply
embedded in popular movies and television shows that few people even
wonder about it. Each episode of the sitcom Men Behaving Badly, for
instance, began with a montage of old movies in which women slap or
punch men hard enough to knock them down or even out cold. What makes
that convention so interesting is that it does not presume any physical
provocation. Women who slap men do so because of something that has
been said to them or even implied about them, not something that has been
done to them.
Women have learned, moreover, to manipulate the cultural system very
effectively to their own advantage. “Donning the feminine mask, they can
manipulate the biases of family and community in order to set men up. If he
tries to leave, or fight back, a fateful moment comes when she reaches for
the phone, dials 911, and has him arrested on the strength of her word:
‘Officer, he hit me.’ With mounting pressure on North American police
forces to disavow misogynistic attitudes and take the word of a woman over
a man, female psychopaths and other hard-core female abusers have an
extremely effective means to up the ante and win the game.”86
If all of this is true, though, why do so few people know about male
victims of domestic violence? Who are these men? Farrell explains that
academics have suppressed evidence by intimidating their colleagues. Men
have been very reluctant to report their own victimization, moreover, and
journalists have been reluctant to write about it. Finally, the whole notion of
men being battered by women is so counterintuitive that few people even
think of the possibility. Having already discussed the first explanation,
suppressing evidence, we turn now to the others.
Men are indeed very reluctant to report abuse from their wives or female
partners. And Farrell is by no means the only one to say so (although he
was among the first). Drawing her information from a support group for
battered husbands, Pearson points out that blue-collar men have been
conditioned to think of themselves in macho terms as invulnerable. Others
refrain from hitting back or reporting damage for less obvious reasons.
First, they are conditioned by the notion that “real men” are not supposed to
fight women; doing so actually diminishes their status. Second, they are
afraid of losing their children in custody suits. Third, they realize that
attention would inevitably shift to them on the assumption that only men
are violent. Fourth, we would add, men are afraid of public ridicule for
being unable to defend themselves from their wives or female partners.
(Similarly, men are afraid not to risk their lives in battle; for men, as for
women, there has always been a “fate worse than death.”)
Men are much less likely than women to report their domestic
tribulations to police officers, journalists, researchers, or physicians in
emergency rooms. The most obvious explanation is simply that most men
are still ashamed to admit that they are sometimes victims and in need of
help. Actually, many men are ashamed to be in need no matter what the
circumstances. Even asking for directions to a gas station, as stand-up
comedians often point out, can be problematic. “A battered man knows
there are no shelters for battered men,” in any case, “because no one really
believes he exists.”87 Well, some people do believe them. But they are
likely, most men still believe, to respond with ridicule. That adds shame to
fear and anger.
Even men who do end up in emergency rooms, says Farrell (albeit on the
basis of anecdotal evidence from men who speak to him on radio shows),
often disguise their injuries as the results of athletic accidents. They are
usually successful, he adds, because it is much easier for physicians to
believe that healthy men have been tackled by quarterbacks than brained by
their own wives. The result of all this is “learned helplessness” au masculin.
“Both sexes feel helpless,” writes Farrell, “when the love of their life turns
into the nightmare of their life. But men … feel much more helpless about
asking for outside help. In brief, women’s strength is in knowing when they
feel helpless. Men’s weakness is not knowing. The fact that we have
identified women’s ‘learned helplessness’ but not men’s is … a sign that the
women’s problem is on its way to being solved, while the men’s is as yet
unrecognized.”88
Moreover, Farrell observes, “men learn to call pain ‘glory’; women learn
to call the police.”89 Men have been conditioned from childhood to accept
pain as the measure of their worth as men. This is not masochism. Men do
not understand the pain they endure, in general, as deserved punishment or
as an end in itself. They understand it as a necessary evil. “Why,” asks
Farrell, “did virtually every culture reward its men for enduring violence?
So it would have a cadre of people available to protect it in war. The people
considered the most in need of protection were women and children. The
sex considered most disposable was men – or males.”90 To be a man, in
short, has been to protect other members of the community even at the cost
of one’s own life. “Part of the pressure men put on each other to carry out
this mandate is ridiculing a man who complains when he is hurt. We often
think that when a man insults another man by calling him a ‘girl,’ the insult
reflects a contempt for women. No. It reflects a contempt for any man who
is unwilling to make himself strong enough to protect someone as precious
as a woman. It is an insult to any man unwilling to endure the pain it takes
to save a woman’s life – including the pain of losing his own life.”91 This is
definitely not to say that we should continue to see men, or any other group
of human beings, as an expendable class or race. It is merely to
acknowledge a historic reality of immense psychological importance for
both men and women.
Feminists have argued that all this talk about men protecting women
amounts to nothing more than a patriarchal smokescreen. Far from feeling
obliged to protect women and children, they say, men feel justified in
assaulting them. How else can you explain the men who do, in fact, assault
women? This is a fundamental premise of ideological feminism. It is the
fundamental assumption also of many treatment programs for abusive men.
But the assumption is false. “Battering a woman,” Farrell observes, “is the
male role broken down. A man who batters a woman is like a cross-dresser:
he’s out of role.”92
One obvious explanation in the context of this book is the general
breakdown of gender itself, which began (consciously) among men who
joined the “beat” and “hippie” movements but was far more effectively
institutionalized by women who joined feminist movements. Although
Farrell refrains from pointing it out, this is a very serious problem today
because of ideological or postmodernist attempts to “deconstruct” all
notions of gender, not merely as social constructs but as evil ones. The
importance of this knowledge when treating abusive men can hardly be
exaggerated. Assuming that they resort to violence because of their
patriarchal power is unlikely to produce effective treatment, after all, if the
underlying problem is precisely the opposite. This approach will not,
therefore, empower women. It will empower only ideological feminists.
But more than the breakdown of gender – a cultural system – is involved
here. The term “women and children” is still used routinely by journalists to
indicate those who should be off limits in connection with war and
violence. And women are still considered immune to conscription for
combat.93 This indicates that men are still considered the protectors, at least
in theory, of society. So why do some individual men turn against the very
people whom they have been taught to protect? “When a man feels the
woman he is supposed to protect is threatening him or verbally chopping
him apart, he begins to make a mental transfer from protecting her to
protecting himself from her. She begins to lose her status as a woman.”94
Being a protector, Farrell points out, means having the power to protect, but
not all men have enough to maintain even the illusion of offering
protection. Far from having too much power, he suggests, they have too
little. In anger and frustration over a discrepancy between the cultural ideal
for men and the economic reality for themselves, they turn against the ideal
(a topic that we will discuss much more fully in Transcending Misandry).
The relation between power and violence, says Farrell, presents us with
an ironic twist. The evidence indicates that “when women abuse, they are
sometimes in a position of power, sometimes without power, and sometimes
they are experiencing both simultaneously. When men abuse, they are much
more likely to be in a position of powerlessness – the act of abuse being a
momentary act of power designed to compensate for underlying
experiences of powerlessness.”95 As it happens, elderly women are more
than four times as likely to abuse their husbands as elderly men are to abuse
their wives.96 The husbands, usually older and in worse physical condition
than their wives, are in no position to do any damage. The wives feel
powerless in the way that elderly people always do, but they feel powerful,
too, in relation to their husbands. (Ditto for abusive mothers.)97
This strongly supports what common sense has always suggested: people
who victimize others pick on those least likely to fight back. “Why are
women more likely to abuse men who are powerless while men are more
likely to protect women who are powerless? Or, put another way, why, if he
feels powerless, is he more likely to be abusive and she is also more likely
to feel abusive? She perceives him as no longer being able to protect her, so
she acts on her instincts to get rid of a man who can’t protect her.
(Remember, she survived for millions of years by selecting protectors,
which means knowing how to weed out men who can’t protect her.) Put
another way, female abuse of men who can’t perform is instinctive. She
feels powerless when he feels powerless.”98
It is unnecessary to agree that this phenomenon is instinctive, and we do
not. It is enough to see its inner logic. Farrell adds that abused lesbians, too,
often suspect that their partners feel dependent rather than powerful. “So
among women, feelings of power or powerlessness – or some combination
of both – seem in various ways to catalyze abuse.”99 The situation is quite
different among men. Farrell points to a study of the American
Psychological Association, which found that abusive behaviour by men
correlated more closely with feelings of powerlessness – having no job or a
poorly paid one, being uneducated or poorly educated, receiving emotional
support from few friends or other social contacts, using drugs or alcohol,
suffering from psychological problems such as depression, and so on – than
abusive behaviour by women.100 “Men’s greater physical strength would
seem to indicate men’s violence toward women involves male power …
[But] this is tricky, because men learn to use that strength to protect women
and will beat up or even kill a man whose uses it against a woman. It is
when the power of his masculinity breaks down that he is most likely to be
violent toward a woman.”101
Closely linked with the relation between pain and “glory” is that
between pain and love. Farrell’s explanation of this phenomenon sounds
like masochism.

Men have learned to associate being abused with being loved. For example,
becoming the football or ice hockey player some woman will love (and men
will respect) requires his enduring physical abuse, name-calling, hazing, or
emotional humbling. News magazines such as Maclean’s help us reinforce
our propensity to call men who are physically beaten “heroes,” even as we
call women who are physically beaten “victims.” Taking abuse will get him
through boot camp so he can become the officer some woman will adore;
and it is part of the territory of “death professions” like firefighting or coal
mining, where he hopes to earn enough to afford a wife. By the time he is
eligible for love, he has been trained to be humbled, hazed, and abused.102

So men have a hard time admitting, first to themselves and then to


others, that they are in trouble. Suppose, however, that they do admit to
being in trouble. Why not leave? This is the very question asked of women
in similar circumstances. Feminists have always insisted that some female
victims of domestic violence stay not merely due to economic hardship
(even though the low-income women in at least one study were actually
more likely than high-income women to leave)103 but also due to Battered
Woman Syndrome. This combination of low self-esteem and fear of being
hunted down not only explains why they stay but also, allegedly, justifies
them in resorting to murder. As Farrell points out, though, some male
victims have either the same or equivalent problems.
Like many women, for instance, many men are economically unprepared
to leave. Not all men even have jobs, let alone well-paid jobs. Not even all
men with well-paid jobs can afford to maintain two homes (which,
according to the law, is what they would have to do). And not all men are
willing either to leave their children, often their only source of love, or to
leave them with violent mothers. “Many men, then, endure the physical hurt
of being beaten rather than endure the emotional torture of feeling they’ve
left their own children unprotected, lost love, and lost their home. When
these combine with the helplessness that emerges from the fear of asking
for help, they create the ‘Battered Man Syndrome.’”104
Just as men are reluctant to acknowledge their own victimization, argues
Farrell, journalists have been reluctant to report it. Both they and their
readers or viewers rely on notions that have become conventional wisdom,
notions that are actively fostered by some feminists. Men in general batter
women, but women in general do not batter men. Men do so out of
contempt, but women do so in self-defense. Men can always leave home,
but women cannot due to lack of money or fear of revenge. Women try to
solve domestic problems through talking, but men try to do so through
violence, due to the belief that women are their property and should
therefore submissively accept the superior status and privileged position of
men.105 No wonder, as Cook observes, journalists seldom use gender-
neutral language when the general topic is domestic violence. The generic
culprit is always “he,” the generic victim always “she.” And no woman ever
complains to the editor about this example of sexist language.
We have already noted that much of the evidence collected from surveys
indicates that women actually initiate domestic violence at least as often as
men do. In No Angels: Women Who Commit Violence, a collection of
essays, several authors question the assumption that women are innately
peaceful, that only exceptional women – that is, only women who could be
considered either mad or bad – are capable of violence.106 But in the end,
these authors excuse and even legitimate violent women by suggesting that
they merely react in a rational way to the violence of men. Maybe they have
not read the studies on domestic violence among lesbians. According to
one, rates of abuse were higher among lesbians in their prior relationships
with women than in their prior relationships with men: 56% had been
subjected to sexual aggression by their female lovers, 45% to physical
aggression, and 64.5% to emotional aggression.107 Another study found that
levels of violence were higher among lesbians than among gay men: 55%
of gay women reported physical violence but only 44% of gay men.108 Yet
another study found that 47.5% of gay women reported violence in their
relationships but only 22% of gay men. Moreover, 38% of the women
reported using violence against their partners but only 22% of the men.
“Lesbian violence shatters the myth,” writes Farrell, “that women abuse
only when men drive them to it. It dispels the myth that male power and
male privilege create violence against women. Lesbians do not have much
male power and privilege.”109 Of course, feminists often “explain” abusive
women by claiming that patriarchy causes or even forces women to behave
in these ways. (Never mind that this reduces women to the level of passive
morons.) But if patriarchy can be blamed for the bad things about women,
as Farrell points out, surely it must be lauded also for the good things about
men.
Whatever. In The Battered Woman, Lenore Walker threw down the
ideological gauntlet to lawyers and legislators.110 This book has become the
authoritative defense for killing husbands or male partners who are not
immediately engaged in violence. Walker claims that the Battered Woman
Syndrome has two defining characteristics. First, women somehow “know”
that they are about to be murdered. Second, they are psychologically unable
to leave. They are justified in striking first, taking the law into their own
hands. (Ideological feminists seldom allow that technicality to stop them
from blaming male victims.) By coining the term “Battered Woman
Syndrome,” Walker directly or indirectly legitimated what would otherwise
be called vigilante justice. According to current law in many places, the
action of the battered woman qualifies as self-defense. “The problem is,”
says Farrell, that “the husband is too dead to defend himself. And the court
can’t hear what men are too dead to say. In contrast, when men claim self-
defense, they are often not even believed by their counselors.”111
The Battered Woman Syndrome has been widely accepted as an
explanation for why women remain with violent men. It relies heavily on
the idea that women learn helplessness after failed attempts to escape from
the cycle of abuse (but also, say feminists, after millennia of cultural
conditioning to make women submissive or, as MacKinnon would say, to
“eroticize” male brutality). These women, so says the theory, feel trapped
and thus ironically refuse help from the outside world. They are especially
reluctant to press charges due to economic dependence or fear of physical
retaliation. But Grant Brown points out that the figures do not confirm this
theory. On the contrary. First, they show “that women are more willing to
testify against their partners … the more seriously they have been injured
by them. Second, women are more willing than men to testify against their
partners, regardless of the level of injury suffered … All of the evidence
indicates that abused men fit the theory of the ‘battered woman’ better than
abused women do!”112
One result of these misconceptions about domestic violence, is a
difference in the way that men and women are treated by the courts.

As a result of the invisibility of the female methods of killing, women who


do kill benefit from the stereotype of women as innocent and are treated
very differently by the law: thirteen percent of spousal murder cases with
women defendants result in an acquittal vs. 1 percent of murder cases with
men defendants. Similarly, the average prison sentence for spousal murder
(excluding life sentences and the death penalty) is almost three times longer
for men than for women – 17.5 years vs. 6.2 years.113 And, thus far, a
woman has never been executed for killing only a man. When we can only
see women as innocent, the law becomes equally blind.114

Brown, in an excellent Canadian study of this problem, finds


considerable evidence of systemic discrimination against men. His primary
goal is to show that prosecutors are the major players in cases of domestic
violence. His secondary goal is to examine other players – police officers
and judges – in connetion with data that are relatively inaccessible to the
public. Brown used two sources, both from Alberta, that had never been
studied: databases that track responses by the Edmonton police to domestic
violence from 1999 to 2000 and files on domestic violence compiled in
2001 by the crown prosecutor’s office in Edmonton.
Given the importance of these findings (and the need to respect every
nuance of highly technical language), we find it worthwhile to quote
extensively from Brown’s own summary.

The results of this investigation indicate that men who are involved in
disputes with their partners, whether as alleged victims or as alleged
offenders or both, are disadvantaged and treated less favourably than
women by the law-enforcement system at almost every step. Men are much
less likely to report their victimization to the authorities to begin with,
either because they consider it unmanly to do so or because they believe the
authorities will not take their complaints very seriously, anyway. When men
do report their victimization, or when it is reported for them by third parties,
the police are less likely to lay charges against their partners than they
would be to lay charges against comparable male suspects. In fact, the
police seem reluctant to lay charges against women in partner violence
cases unless a relatively serious offence has been committed or other
aggravating factors are present. The result is that, even though the charging
ratios by the Edmonton police in the period under scrutiny are higher
against women than in many other jurisdictions in Canada in the past, they
still diverge greatly from what the sociological data on partner violence
indicates would reflect reality. The categories of female-only assaults and
mutual aggression seem especially under-represented in the police charging
data.

After laying charges, police are significantly more likely to take a man
into custody than a woman, even when factors such as the level of injury
inflicted and prior criminal record are taken into account. Nor do
prosecutors tend to mitigate this disparately harsh treatment of men. On the
contrary, prosecutors appear to pursue cases involving male suspects more
vigorously than those involving female suspects. Thus men are more likely
to be found guilty and are less likely to benefit from withdrawn charges,
even though they are suspects in proportionately more of the no-injury
cases. Men are also less likely to benefit from favourable plea bargains,
despite the fact that they have committed, on average, less grievous
offences. And men are significantly more likely to receive harsher
sentences than women, even when all other relevant factors are taken into
account. Indeed, gender is often the most significant factor in predicting
how the law-enforcement system responds to incidents of partner violence.
This pattern of unfavourable outcomes bears all of the classic signs of a
self-reinforcing system of discrimination against men, a system that is
supported by ideological myths and stereotypes. Public-awareness
campaigns based on information from official sources typically promote the
awareness of and remedies for female victims only; so men who are
victimized often do not even realize that help (such as it is) is available to
them, and many of their cases do not come to the attention of the
authorities. Many men have had experience with the law-enforcement
system and refuse to engage it when they are themselves the victims of
abuse. They can be forgiven for wondering why they should subject
themselves to all of the embarrassment associated with pursuing charges
against a violent female partner when the justice system does not seem
inclined to take it seriously anyway. This reluctance on the part of male
victims, in turn, reinforces stereotypical attitudes of police and prosecutors,
who figure either that the man can look after himself or that he is not really
interested in pursuing his complaint anyway. Since relatively few cases
involving violence by women reach the courts, judges acquire the mistaken
impression that violence against men is not a serious social problem, and
excuse their leniency toward women with the sexist assumption that
children should not be punished for the crimes of their mothers.
Prosecutors, seeing how judges routinely slap women on the wrist for even
fairly major assaults, lose incentive to fight these cases aggressively in the
courts, and offer favourable plea-bargains to the women instead. And the
police, seeing that prosecutors do not appear to pursue cases against women
as vigorously as cases against men, in turn decide not to lay charges against
women except in the clearest of cases. Up and down the system, everyone
quickly adjusts to the political myth that family violence is only about
protecting “women and children” from abusive male partners. Breaking this
cycle of bias can only be achieved through system-wide concerted, and
conscious efforts.115
Brown discusses several other examples of systemic discrimination in
the courts against men. Consider the problem of no-contact orders, which
prevent suspects from having access to their own property, their own
homes. For reasons that Brown explains elsewhere, most of the suspects are
men. He sees no justification for their treatment, in view of the fact “that
mutual aggression is the most common form of partner violence.”
Moreover, he suggests that “if the police fear continued violence but do not
want to take both the man and the woman into custody, the least they could
do by way of mutual accommodation is to allow the man to stay in the
home and take the woman to a shelter.”116 Or, we suggest, the reverse. But
that would mean creating shelters for men.
Now think of plea bargaining. Brown shows that the most significant
factor in that system is the sex of suspects. This, in fact, “is the only
variable that is associated, at statistically significant levels, with receiving
‘any term’ as a penalty for partner violence. In other words, being male is
more likely to result in receiving a more severe penalty on a plea-bargain
than any other factor … including the level of injury to the victim … It
seems that prosecutors are driving a much harder bargain with the men who
are charged with partner violence than with the women, despite the
generally more violent profile of the women in this sample.”117
There is no reason to assume that similar findings would not be
discovered in cities other than Edmonton, whether in Canada or the United
States. Indeed, the province of Alberta is generally considered rather less
likely than many other places to be guided directly or indirectly by feminist
ideology. If even part of Brown’s thesis is correct, it would be prudent, let
alone conscientious, to call for a systematic and publicly funded study of
the problem that he has revealed. No society can function harmoniously if
one segment of the population is subjected to intentional or unintentional
discrimination by the state. And a quick glance at the Internet indicates that
many men, including those not involved personally with domestic violence,
believe that they are the targets of systemic discrimination.
Even though ideological feminists have politicized domestic violence,
they have turned rape into their ultimate trump card. Whenever they run out
of arguments about other matters, they point to the symbolic and political
nature of rape as the ultimate crime of men against women (although, as
they point out in other contexts, rape is only one end of a single continuum
that includes domestic violence, sexual harassment, pornography, and so
forth). Thirty years ago, Susan Brownmiller claimed, in effect, that rape is
also the universal crime of men against women. We live in a “rape culture,”
she claimed in Against Our Will.118 What she meant was that, the conscious
intentions of individual men notwithstanding, all men subjugate all women
by the universal female fear of being raped. This claim is still a
fundamental – no, the fundamental – doctrine of ideological feminism.
Feminists have urged an interpretation of equal protection under the law
that involves special legal protection for women against violence by
men.119 Failing to report and punish rape encourages rape. That increases
fear among women. And that, in turn, diminishes their freedom of
movement. Feminists have sought protection in constitutions (or their
amendments) and charters. They have sought them also, when stymied by
lack of precise wording or lack of opportunity, to add the necessary wording
in reinterpretations of existing legislation. Some Americans, for instance,
have tried to interpret the Fourteenth Amendment very broadly – it
guarantees equal rights to all citizens – in order to seek redress at the
federal level for crimes such as rape. They claim that state courts have been
indifferent to sexual offences against women. Others have tried to use the
Commerce Clause of the Constitution, arguing, according to Wendy
McElroy, for federal regulation of violence against women on the grounds
that violence, or even fear of it, interferes with women’s productivity and
mobility as workers. “The cost of gender violence to the national economy,”
they say, “was estimated at between $5 billion and $10 billion.”120 Never
mind that crimes of violence, including rape, actually declined in the late
1990s.121 Among the big players in the controversy over rape legislation
has been Catharine MacKinnon. As we say, she has been involved in both
American and Canadian court cases.122
The claim that women sometimes find it necessary to kill men surfaced
as the subtext of several critically acclaimed and successful movies: Thelma
and Louise, I Shot Andy Warhol, and Monster. In each of these movies, the
latter two being based on true stories, the female protagonist is portrayed
sympathetically for killing one or more men.123 Yes, yes, everyone involved
with these movies duly acknowledged that killing people – even these
gross, vulgar, and brutal men – is wrong. And yes, everyone acknowledged
that the protagonists are pathological and therefore unsuitable as role
models. But the fact is that these protagonists really do evoke sympathy
from viewers. Emotionally, viewers are encouraged to cheer them on. And
not only in scenes that actually involve self-defense. By now, it seems self-
evident to almost everyone that the male victims are not intended to be seen
as real people or at least as realistic characters but as symbolic
representatives of patriarchal tyranny.
In Monster, serial killer Aileen Wuornos is depicted as someone who
had suffered molestation as a child at the hands of her father and continued
to suffer as an adult prostitute from rapists. When she finally kills for the
first time, it is to defend herself against a john who tries to rape her. No
wonder viewers are encouraged to think that her rage eventually spills over
into murder. No wonder, she sees all men as rapists (even one who actually
offers to help her). Nonetheless, just in case, she weeps and expresses some
remorse to the young woman who befriends her (but later betrays her in
court). Not many movies explain the behaviour of male serial killers, by
contrast, in connection with childhood abuse or lack of love. Nothing in
American Psycho, for instance, prepares viewers to see Patrick Bateman as
someone who had been mentally deformed by an unhappy childhood. He is
simply a handsome and charming demon.
Partly as a result of all this ideological baggage, at any rate, discussions
of rape involve several serious conceptual problems: defining rape,
identifying rape victims, and prosecuting alleged rapists. The very word
“rape” is now problematic. Some feminists define it as a subcategory of
“sexual assault,” which covers a very broad range of offenses. The
implication is that all offenses, no matter how innocuous some might seem,
are manifestations of a single crime – all are tantamount to rape. The
linguistic inflation of MacKinnon and Dworkin is legendary. When
MacKinnon can seriously claim that she was raped by a negative book
review (a bizarre event that we will come back to in a moment), even
though the review merely used her own analogy between words and rape, it
is surely time to examine the matter more carefully. Maybe the impact of
language actually diminishes as a result of what could be called linguistic
inflation. What can the word “sacred” mean, for example, when it is used to
describe everything from rites to rights, from encounters with the divine to
citizenship in the state or even the security of a friendship? What can the
word “awesome” mean, similarly, when it is used in connection with such
trivial things as the size of a pizza or the colour of a shirt?
The word “rape” has already been inflated, partly by MacKinnon herself,
to include sexual harassment. And that, in turn, has been inflated to include
possession of an “offensive” magazine or poster. But MacKinnon has upped
the ante by resorting to hyperinflation. Her point in Only Words is that porn,
including nonviolent erotica, is literally a form of sexual assault.124 She
made the same point in connection with the review of her book by Carlin
Romano in The Nation.125 Romano, a former philosophy teacher, began his
review with two hypothetical scenarios designed to test MacKinnon’s
claim: one person thinks about raping MacKinnon; another person does
something about it. Is there a difference or not? The first scenario is
offensive, at least to MacKinnon, but does it constitute rape? Does it
constitute even a provocation to rape?
MacKinnon herself insists that she does make a distinction between what
actually happens and what is imagined or stated. For rhetorical (and
ideological) purposes, though, she conveniently ignores this distinction. In
this way, she herself can be accused of not taking language seriously
enough. Those who care about words, after all, care enough to use them
carefully and precisely. Actually, MacKinnon does not care about words at
all. She cares about the safety of women. This, in itself, is fine. But is she
really protecting women by debasing language? That remains to be seen. At
stake here is no longer an academic dispute but a legal and political dispute.
Although not all victims of rape are women and although not all rapists
are men (according to the very broad definition of rape that, ironically,
some feminists now advocate), we are interested here in the majority of
cases: women raped by men. The publication in 1994 of a massive study of
sexual behaviour in America, The Social Organization of Sexuality, was
greeted as a milestone, the most important event of its kind since Kinsey’s
study almost fifty years earlier.126 Among its findings were that many
women (and some, but not as many, men) reported that they had been
forced into sexual acts on at least one occasion. This study did not use the
word “rape” to describe this phenomenon. That word has been so inflated
semantically, so loaded politically, that it would be virtually useless in a
scholarly work. But the connection between “sexual act” and “rape” must
not be ignored, because it points at the very least to a problem of all
statistical studies: they can be used, and often are used, in tendentious ways.
Have all these women been raped? The answer depends on how rape is
defined, of course, and, unfortunately, on who defines it.
Even though the authors themselves carefully avoid that word, many of
their readers probably infer it. Everyone can agree that being forced into sex
without consent is rape. Not everyone can agree, though, on what
constitutes force. For some people, it refers to physical coercion. For others,
it can refer also to psychological intimidation or emotional manipulation.
For how many, one wonders, does it refer even to attitudes – a vague sense
of duty, say, or a desire to please – that exist only in the minds of women
who are “forced” into sexual acts? Nonetheless, for some feminists, men
would still be the guilty ones, collectively though not always individually.
After all, they explain, men have created a culture that directly or indirectly
encourages women to adopt this submissive attitude. Even women who
willingly submit to men, in other words, are still innocent victims; the
culture (of femininity) makes them do it.
This explanation might be more convincing if the same logic were
applied to men. Hundreds of thousands of men locked up in prison could
use the same defense for shooting neighbours, selling drugs, robbing
convenience stores, driving under the influence, and so on. Why not argue
that the culture of masculinity, poverty, and racism makes them behave in
these ways? In both cases, there is some truth. If men were nothing more
than the creations of a sinister culture, they could hardly be expected to take
responsibility for their own behaviour. And that defense would apply not
only to crime in general but also to rape in particular. But individual men
really are held responsible for their own behaviour, regardless of their youth
in dysfunctional families or their conditioning by dysfunctional subcultures.
Why, then, should women be exempt from the same standard? The problem
of rape is very serious, but so is the problem of using statistics, whether
explicitly or implicitly, to make political statements about rape. Statistical
studies are unlikely to clarify the problem of rape unless everyone can agree
on what rape is in the first place.
Central to any discussion of rape is its definition, as we have said in
chapter 8, which remains a topic of controversy, to say the least. Here we
must turn away from statistics and back to the law, because many legal
definitions of violence against women, including the definition of rape (and
the legal terms that have replaced that word in some jurisdictions) have
been directly or indirectly influenced by ideological ones. One obvious
example is the Violence against Women Act, in which the definitions of sex
crimes are explicitly elided with hate crimes.127 American legal definitions
vary from one state to another but usually include one or more of the
following features: sexual intercourse that involves physical coercion;
sexual intercourse that occurs without explicit consent, sexual intercourse
with someone who is mentally or physically handicapped, sexual
intercourse with someone who is under the age of consent.128
At the federal level, definitions of rape have been provided for the
purpose of collecting statistics. Lawrence Greenfeld, a statistician with the
Department of Justice, has compiled a glossary of “sex offenses” found in
over two dozen sets of statistical data maintained by the Bureau of Justice
Statistics and the Uniform Crime Reporting program of the FBI. Greenfield
points out that the use of terms and definitions is far from uniform. One
definition of rape involves “forced sexual intercourse in which the victim
may be either male or female and the offender may be of a different sex or
the same sex as the victim. Victims [of forcible rape] must be at least 12
years old …” Another definition involves “forcible intercourse, sodomy, or
penetration with a foreign object. Does not include statutory rape or non-
forcible acts with a minor or someone unable to give legal consent,
nonviolent sexual offenses, or commercialized sex offenses. Includes
attempts.” Yet another definition involves “forcible intercourse (vaginal,
anal, or oral) with a female or male. Includes forcible sodomy or
penetration with foreign object. Does not include statutory rape or any other
nonforcible sexual acts with a minor or with someone unable to give legal
consent. Includes attempts.”129
All these definitions make a primary distinction between “statutory rape”
and “forcible rape.” One definition of the former involves “carnal
knowledge of a person without force or the threat of force when that person
is below the statutory age of consent. The ability of the victim to give
consent is a determination by the law enforcement agency.” Another
definition involves “carnal knowledge of a child without force. Includes
attempts.”130 One definition of “forcible rape,” on the other hand, involves
“the carnal knowledge of a female forcibly and against her will. Assaults or
attempts to commit rape by force or threat of force are also included;
however, statutory rape (without force) and other sex offenses are
excluded.”131 Another definition involves “carnal knowledge of a person
forcibly and/or against the person’s will; or not forcibly or against the
person’s will where the victim is incapable of giving consent because of
his/her youth or because of his/her temporary or permanent mental or
physical capacity. This offense includes both male and female victims and
threats and attempts.” Yet another definition involves “forcible intercourse
with a male or female. Includes attempts and conspiracies to commit
rape.”132
Both types of rape, “forcible” and “statutory,” are considered sexual
assaults. Under “other sexual assaults,” however, are crimes that involve
“gross sexual imposition, sexual abuse, aggravated sexual abuse, and other
acts such as fondling, molestation, or indecent liberties where the victim is
not a child. Include attempts.”133
Unfortunately, it is impossible to compare American definitions of
“rape” with the Canadian one, because the word “rape” is no longer used as
an official classification in Canada. Instead, the Criminal Code refers to
three types of “sexual assault.” In a case of “(simple) sexual assault,”134
“someone forces any form of sexual activity on another person without that
person’s consent” and – this is important – the assault includes “kissing,
fondling, grabbing, sexual intercourse, etc.”135 In a case of “sexual assault
with a weapon,”136 “someone uses or threatens to use a real or imitation
weapon … [or] threatens to cause bodily harm to a 3rd person” or “more
than one person assaults someone in the same incident.”137 In a case of
“aggravated sexual assault,”138 the most serious of all, “someone is
wounded, maimed, disfigured, brutally beaten, or in danger of dying, while
being sexually assaulted.”139 These three types of sexual assault are listed
in order of seriousness and severity of punishment. As a whole, then,
“sexual assault” is defined in Canada as an assault of a sexual nature that
might or might not involve sexual penetration.140
The American system, on the other hand, “contains only one narrow
version of sexual assault. The offence of forcible rape is limited to forced
sexual intercourse by a male against a female. This crime differs from the
Canadian sexual assault offences, which are neither gender-specific nor
confined to sexual intercourse … Therefore, comparing the Canadian
sexual assault offence and American offence of forcible rape would not be
reliable.”141 Although rape is classified in the United States as one kind of
sexual assault, in short, it is not in Canada. There is no separate
classification for rape, which, along with other crimes, is classified as
sexual assault (under the three classifications listed above). Why is this
worth noting here? Because the Canadian system classifies rape in the same
category as kissing without consent; rape is just one end of a single
continuum. This system allows Canadians to inflate the seriousness of these
other sexual assaults. On the other hand, it does acknowledge that men can
be raped, not only women (although it probably assumes also, incorrectly,
that men can be raped only by other men).
Ideological feminists, both American and Canadian, often claim that
sexual assaults are unlike any other crimes. Sexual assault is unique, they
sometimes argue, because no other crime is about sex. But you could just as
easily say that no other crime but murder is about death (although even that
is debatable in view of the fact that several crimes, legally distingished
according to motivation, involve death). Even if it were true, then, this
statement would be tautological and therefore almost meaningless. But is it
true? The fact is that not one but several crimes are about sex, the most
obvious being sexual harassment. Significantly, those who make this claim
hide the ideological implication that sexual harassment is just another form
of rape. Moreover, they “forget” something that ideological feminists have
been insisting on for at least thirty years. Rape, they say, is about power and
not about sex.
We discuss claims of this kind by Susan Molinari, an American, below.
Her Canadian counterpart, Pamela Cross, argues that sexual assault – she
refers here specifically to what everyone understands as rape – is a “unique
crime.”142 And it surely is, because every form of crime – indeed, every
phenomenon – is unique. If it had no distinctive characteristics, how could
we describe it or identify it at all? But every phenomenon is also linked
with others in a larger, coherent pattern. Cross would never actually deny
that sexual assault is one form of assault or that assault is one form of
interaction, that interaction is one form of human behaviour, and so on.
What she does deny is that sexual assault has anything significant in
common with other forms of assault. What she means, of course, is that
sexual assault is uniquely unique. That is a very problematic claim, because
it raises the level of rhetoric from merely ideological to metaphysical. To
describe something as uniquely unique would be to describe it in terms that
are utterly beyond those used by either scientists or social scientists. Cross
believes that sexual assault is so heinous that it requires not only a separate
legal standard but also a separate moral standard. The result is to isolate
sexual assault from all other forms of assault and thus create a category that
is, in effect, sacrilegious. To commit a sexual assault (presumably on a
woman) is to commit an act that cannot be defined in purely secular terms
and is therefore beyond the scope of any rational discussion.
With this in mind, then, consider Cross’s explanations for her claim that
sexual assault is a unique crime. First, she claims that it “is the most
intimate of offences, in a way that even murder is not.”143 This implicit
downgrading of murder would come as a nasty shock to the families of
murder victims. But what precisely does Cross mean by “intimate”? We are
not nit-picking; precision really is necessary in any discussion of law. Does
she mean that sexual assaults occur privately? But so do many other crimes.
Suicide bombers kill or injure people on crowded buses or in public
buildings, to be sure, but most people – those who intend to get away – do
so as stealthily as possible.
Cross claims that “most other crimes do not require privacy in the same
way that is required for sexual assault.”144 But she presumes
anachronistically things about sex that many people no longer presume.
Consider what happens at movie theatres. Although the people ostensibly
having sex are actors (some but not all of whom use stunt doubles), the
people watching them in public auditoriums – men and women, often on
dates – are not. Are they embarrassed by what they see? If so, they certainly
do not make that clear to the Hollywood producers. On the contrary, as the
producers know very well, explicit sex on the screen is big at the box office
and is now making inroads even on television and the Internet. In fact, say
the moguls, the more of it the better. This attitude, one aspect of the sexual
revolution, marks a significant change for the middle and upper classes.145
This change is by no means confined to the phenomenon that takes place in
theatres. Making out in public, or at least in the crowded context of dorm
parties and raves, is not exactly unheard of nowadays. And it is precisely in
this context, fueled by booze and drugs, that sexual assaults are likely to
occur.
Or does Cross mean by “privacy” that sexual assaults take place in the
context of close emotional relationships? Probably, but so do many other
crimes: murders are often committed by people who have very close
emotional relationships with their victims. Or does Cross refer merely to
physical proximity? Surely not, because she denies the parallel of murder.
What could involve closer physical proximity than stabbing someone, say,
or strangling someone? Well, what then?
On the same topic, Cross claims that “[v]ictims of most other crimes feel
no sense of personal shame that makes them reluctant to inform the
authorities that a crime has taken place.”146 But male victims of domestic
violence, for instance, find themselves in precisely the same category. And
not much has been done to change either their attitudes or those of society
and its agents: police officers, lawyers, judges, physicians, and social
workers. How many men could convince a court, moreover, that a woman
had initiated unwanted sexual behaviour? According to the stereotype,
every man wants to engage in sex at all times and in all places. Even though
every man knows that this is false, how many male judges or jurors are
likely to say so in court? Fewer and fewer women, on the other hand, feel
ashamed of themselves or responsible in any way for the immoral and
illegal behaviour of those who attack them. On the contrary, more and more
of them feel indignant (and with good reason). This means that Cross’s
claim is, once again, anachronistic.
So is a closely related claim. “Seldom do victims of more ‘public’ kinds
of crimes fear,” writes Cross, “that they will be blamed for what has
happened to them. For example, a homeowner who has been robbed after
leaving a door or window unlocked is unlikely to feel the same sense of
responsibility for what has happened as do many sexual assault victims.”147
This almost incredibly facile analogy is based on a false assumption. Is it
true that only victims of sexual assault blame themselves for what others do
to them? What about the parents – including fathers – of children who are
kidnapped while they are busy talking to their friends or doing business on
their cell phones? They would almost certainly feel much more guilt.
People do often prefer to “blame the victim,” but not only the victims of
sexual assault. What about all those, not only in Canada and elsewhere but
even in the United States, who blamed Americans themselves for the
attacks of 11 September 2001? The lamentable fact is that most people use
blame for irrational purposes now and then. Blaming either themselves or
others provides an explanation for evil. Otherwise, they would have to
acknowledge that the world is governed by chance or chaos and is thus
meaningless.
Cross claims that sexual assault is unique in that it “often [leaves] no
physical injuries and little, if any, forensic evidence.”148 Actually, that has
been true until recently of most or even all crimes except physical assault.
Living victims of sexual assault have not always had much evidence, it is
true, and for a variety of reasons. But that situation is becoming less and
less common due to new forensic technologies. Cross’s chief aim is to help
living victims, moreover, not dead ones. But her claim is about sexual
assault in general and is relevant to legal proceedings against those accused
of both raping and killing their victims. The fact is, however, that police
departments routinely present forensic evidence in court of murder victims
who had been sexually assaulted.
According to Cross, moreover, “the perpetrator is often known, and even
known very well, to the victim” of sexual assault but not of other crimes.149
Once again, the same really could be said of many other crimes. To take
only one example, most members of rival gangs have known each other all
their lives, sometimes very well, but still see no reason not to kill each
other. On the other hand, many sexual assaults are perpetrated by strangers
on dark streets. If victim and victimizer know each other, Cross points out,
that could make alleged victims harder to believe; they could be considered
not objective enough.150 Okay, but the same would be true of alleged
victimizers; their testimony, too, could be considered not objective enough.
In connection with one thing, however, Cross does have a point worth
taking seriously. “It is not uncommon for women to be unsure themselves,”
she writes, “about whether or not they are the victims of a crime. This is not
necessarily because they have a lack of knowledge about the law, but rather
because the context in which the events took place is often complex.”151
But this raises a very serious question. If a crime is so subtle that not even
the victim is certain that it took place – or, to put it differently, that the
victim must be coached by an ideological cadre to explain it as a crime –
then what legitimates the use of law to punish it in the first place?
Unwittingly, Cross has actually trivialized sexual assault.
Also problematic is the identification of rape victims. In The Invisible
Boy, Frederick Mathews presents a great deal of statistical evidence to show
that violence against boys and men is indeed very pervasive.152 It is neither
a neurotic delusion brought on by our therapeutically oriented culture nor a
political plot to trivialize the victimization of girls and women. Of interest
here are not male victims of abuse in general but male victims of sexual
abuse in particular – which is to say, of rape.153 Mathews carefully
identifies those who sexually abuse boys and men: men and women,
strangers and acquaintances, family members and members of institutions.
It is true, he writes, that most of the culprits, including those who select
male victims and those who select female ones, are straight men. It is true
that serious physical injuries are more often caused by them, especially to
male victims, than by women.154 But he adds something that startled us.
“As recently as 10 years ago, it was a common assumption that females did
not or could not sexually abuse children or youth.”155 Nonetheless, after
reviewing the studies, he estimates that anywhere between 3% and 25% of
sexual abusers are women. Moreover, he adds, “there is an alarmingly high
rate of sexual abuse by females in the backgrounds of rapists, sex offenders
and sexually aggressive men …156 Male adolescent sex offenders abused by
‘females only’ chose female victims almost exclusively.”157
While male perpetrators are more likely to engage in anal intercourse and to
have the victim engage in oral-genital contact, females tend to use more
foreign objects as part of the abusive act. … This study also reported that
differences were not found in the frequency of vaginal intercourse, fondling
by the victim or abuser, genital body contact without penetration or oral
contact by the abuser.

Females may be more likely to use verbal coercion than physical force.
The most commonly reported types of abuse by female perpetrators include
vaginal intercourse, oral sex, fondling and group sex (Faller, 1987; Hunter
et al., 1993). However, women also engage in mutual masturbation, oral,
anal and genital sex acts, show children pornography and play sex games.
… The research suggests that, overall, female and male perpetrators commit
many of the same acts and follow many of the same patterns of abuse
against their victims. They also do not tend to differ significantly in terms
of their relationship to the victim (most are relatives) or the location of the
abuse (Allen, 1990; Kaufman et al., 1995).158
In a study by K.L. Wallace and others, adds Mathews, “8% of the female
perpetrators were teachers and 23% were babysitters, compared to male
perpetrators who were 0% and 8% respectively.”159 Elsewhere, Mathews
provides the following statistics: “Forty percent of juvenile homicide
victims were killed by family members, mostly parents. Fifty-three percent
of boys were killed by their fathers and slightly more than half (51%) of the
girls were murdered by their mothers.”160

Males do appear to be the majority of sexual abuse perpetrators, but women


are the primary physical abusers and neglecters of children. Mothers and
fathers appear to be equally likely to use corporal punishment. Mothers and
fathers can inflict serious and lethal harm on a child. Since more neglect
and physical types of violence are perpetrated against children than sexual
abuse, we need to take a serious look at how our terms and concepts are
blinding us to a large and neglected part of the abuse problem.161

Now consider what actually happens in both American and Canadian


courtrooms. Rape cases were once very hard to prosecute. For several
reasons, not all victims were willing to press charges. They did not want
others to know that they had lost their virginity; they were too modest to
speak about sexual matters publicly; they were hiding their infidelity; they
could seldom expect to win. To solve this problem, feminists adopted
several strategies that have been adopted, in turn, by courts and legislatures.
One strategy was to demand that the rules of evidence be rewritten.
Thirty years ago, the defense lawyer in a rape case was likely to use what
was considered evidence of the alleged victim’s promiscuity – her clothing,
speech, mannerisms, and so on – to prove that she had given her consent to
sexual activity and thus to cast doubt on her credibility as a plaintiff. The
assumption was that only a “bad” woman wanted sex and was therefore
unlikely to tell the truth – either because she really was bad or because she
was afraid to gain a bad reputation. Because her sexual history was
featured, she found herself on trial, in effect, and therefore subjected to
extensive cross-examination. This mentality was challenged in the 1970s as
a result of the sexual revolution and the women’s movement. A woman’s
character, feminists insisted, should not be judged by her sexual activities
outside marriage. But if women were sexually liberated and therefore
indifferent to what anyone thought about their sexual activities outside
marriage, why would they need or even want a law to protect them from
being embarrassed about these activities?
Never mind. By the end of that decade, American legislatures and courts
were prepared to avoid evidence of the alleged victim’s sexual history. That
evidence, it was argued, discouraged women from reporting rapes, had only
a tenuous connection with the rape being tried, embarrassed the plaintiff,
confused the investigation into facts of the case, and wasted time.
Susan Molinari’s defense of rape-shield laws, which we have already
mentioned in the review of legislation, is an American version of Pamela
Cross’s argument. For Molinari, rape cases are unique

and often turn on difficult credibility determinations. Alleged consent by


the victim is rarely an issue in prosecutions for other violent crimes – the
accused mugger does not claim that the victim freely handed over [his]
wallet as a gift – but the defendant in a rape case often contends that the
victim engaged in consensual sex and then falsely accused him. Knowledge
that the defendant has committed rapes on other occasions is frequently
critical in assessing the relative plausibility of these claims and accurately
deciding cases that would otherwise become unresolvable swearing
matches.162

Trouble is, Molinari fails to acknowledge the fact that sexual intercourse
really is very often – most often – the result of mutual consent, which is
why exceptions must be explained. And seduction really is – by definition –
clouded by ambivalence, which is why date rape is much harder to define
than the kind of rape that occurs in dark alleys. Besides, the two interactions
that Molinari compares, sexual intimacies and financial transactions, are
inherently dissimilar. Her analogy, no matter how clever it appears on the
surface, is therefore not merely facile but false. The former is as complex
and subtle and ambiguous as human nature itself, which is why it has been
explored by poets, philosophers, and even theologians for time out of mind.
The latter, on the other hand, is as simple as the entries in a ledger.163
Some feminists go further. Much further. Lawyers find it hard to get
male judges to take women’s accounts of rape seriously, says Sherene
Razack, because they find it hard to establish empirical proof. She suggests
replacing factual evidence, therefore, with personal stories “where the
social and historical context of the tale is critical to our understanding of
it.”164
Another strategy to avoid the problems faced by alleged victims of rape
is to demand victim-impact statements. Even though they are not used to
decide on guilt or innocence – they are read at sentencing – the theory
behind their use in court is closely related to the replacement of objective
evidence with subjective stories. Martha Nussbaum opposed the
introduction of these women’s stories, often called “empathy narratives,”
into the courtroom.165 Contrary to the feminist argument, she pointed out
that judges usually do empathize with women who accuse men of raping or
assaulting them. In fact, they find it much harder to empathize with men
who are accused. The defendants, therefore, not the plaintiffs, need rules
and structures. Nussbaum concluded with good reason “that we should
admit all evidence about the victim that is relevant to establishing what
happened and what the defendant did – and then no more. In the penalty
phase, the jury or judge should turn to the difficult task of understanding the
character of the criminal, because the penalty phase is about his fate.”166
But victim-impact statements, she added, “function primarily by giving vent
to the passion for revenge against such offenders.”167
Victim-impact statements feed into the ideological notion that all men
are rapists, which is the misandric face of gynocentrism.168 According to
Dworkin, every pimp and every rapist – but also every john, pornographer,
murderer of women – represents the interests of all men, normal men (a
mentality we have already discussed in connection with public response to
Marc Lépine). Or, to put it the other way around, all men – including those
considered normal – are really pimps and rapists (but also johns,
pornographers, and murderers): “Rapists and pimps, representing the
interests of normal men, some of whom rape, some of whom buy, seem to
have the law of gravity on their side: they reify the status quo, which is
what gives them credibility, legitimacy, and authority … No matter what lie
they tell, it passes for truth, because the hatred of women underlying the lie
is an accepted hatred, a shared and unchallenged set of prejudiced
assumptions.”169 Dworkin considers it perfectly legitimate and even
morally appropriate, therefore, for women to hate men: “It is fine for her to
hate those who ripped into her if hate keeps her willing to talk, unwilling to
let silence bury her again.”170
Dworkin uses the word “hate” in its popular sense: intense dislike or
intense anger. But this word has a deeper meaning, one that she might or
might not disavow. As we have said, it refers not to a transitory emotional
state but to a culturally propagated and institutionalized worldview in which
some people are held in contempt by virtue of their group identity. As a
result, that very mentality is both popularized and legalized or otherwise
institutionalized.
Underlying everything we have said about rape legislation and rape trials
is the prevalence of double standards. Instead of favouring defendants, laws
and courtroom procedures now favour plaintiffs; they betray systemic bias
by favouring women over men. The details of a man’s sexual history, unlike
those of a woman, are presumed relevant to the case against him and may
therefore be discussed in court. If a man committed sexual abuse before,
moreover, the law assumes that he probably did it again in the current case.
Where there’s smoke, in other words, there’s fire. Do we really want our
laws to be based on questionable proverbs?
Our legal systems are founded not on proverbs but on the moral and
philosophical conviction that every defendant must be considered innocent
unless proven guilty. But given both the rape-shield laws and the current
stereotypes of men as rapists and molesters, that way of thinking is being
turned on its legal head. In rape cases nowadays, the defendant is guilty
unless proven innocent. The burden of proof is on him rather than his
accuser. Sure, it is now easier to bring rape cases to court and easier to bring
in convictions. At what cost not only to men, however, but also to society as
a whole?
If a man’s sexual history may routinely be considered in court, why not
that of women? Given the difficulty of proceeding without evidence, let
alone witnesses, every source of information should be considered worthy
of consideration. It is true that sexual history, whether of the accuser or the
accused, is not actually evidence. Just because a woman gave consent on
earlier occasions does not mean that she probably did so on the occasion
being discussed in court. But just because a man assaulted a women on
earlier occasions, according to the new view, somehow does mean that he
probably did so on the occasion being discussed in court. Just because he
once pinched her on the butt does not, in fact, mean that he raped her on the
occasion being discussed in court. But in the absence of any other basis on
which to decide a case, the sexual histories of both might tip the balance.
We have solved some problems, in short, but only by replacing them
with new ones. American feminists themselves have noted a double
standard in the new rules of evidence used by courts in rape cases. And they
have done some fancy verbal footwork to justify it. Discussing the
challenges of her job, Jane Aiken, a professor of law at Washington
University in St Louis, notes that American students often acknowledge the
unfairness to men of this asymmetry. “Rule 415 says that prior sexual
misconduct is relevant and probative of behavior on the present occasion.
Rule 412’s rationale is that a woman’s sexual history is not a good predictor
of her present behavior.”171 She suggests that teachers can help students
overcome what they “perceive” to be unfairness by arguing that both 412
and 415 are needed to reduce the bias that jurors bring to the case in their
attempt to find facts. “Both of these rules assist the trier of fact in focusing
on the behavior of the alleged perpetrator, rather than indulging in
stereotypical beliefs that women cannot be believed when making claims of
sexual misconduct. The result is a powerful tool to combat long-held
stereotypes that have infected sexual misconduct cases: the victim either
invited the treatment, or deserved it, or is not to be believed without
sufficient corroboration.”172 She goes on to say that the problem of bias
against women is not merely that of jurors but also that of judges.
In earlier times courts were allowed to discuss the sexual history of an
alleged victim. In our time, they are allowed to discuss the sexual history
only of an alleged victimizer. Courts presume that a women’s sexual history
is irrelevant (although they make a few exceptions, which are defined very
narrowly and subjected to strict tests for relevance). But they presume that
introducing evidence of a man’s sexual history is relevant (unless doing so
happens to conflict with his constitutional rights under the Fifth or Sixth
Amendment). And the evidence need not be narrowly defined or subjected
to strict tests for relevance.
Ideological feminists insist on an additional double standard. When a
woman says “no,” she means “no,” even if she either said or implied “yes”
moments earlier. (This is why her sexual history is supposedly irrelevant,
although some feminists, including MacKinnon and Dworkin, go further by
claiming that women are incapable of giving consent to men in any
circumstances). No matter how a woman behaved until the very moment in
question, all that matters is whether she gave consent at this particular
moment. These feminists insist also, however, that a man’s sexual history
really is relevant.
At the heart of all sexual relationships is ambivalence. A woman might
want intercourse, for example, but also fear it. Even now, this is often true
of intercourse outside the context of marriage, although the use of
contraception can mitigate her fear of pregnancy, and condoms her fear of
disease. The sexual revolution has largely eliminated her fear of losing her
reputation, but it has not eliminated all anxiety. And even men are
sometimes unwilling or unable to have sex, although they are seldom
willing to admit it. The meaning of “yes” or “no” is not easily sorted out, in
short, despite the best efforts of those who campaign on campuses and
elsewhere for “sexual correctness.” Recognizing ambivalence, in fact, lies
at the very heart of sexual activity.
To underline the problems of both ambiguity and ambivalence, consider
the behaviour of Adrien Brody. After winning the Academy Award for best
actor in 2003, he grabbed Halle Berry and kissed her on the lips.173 He
embraced her so tightly, in fact, that her body swayed under his.174 Berry
looked stunned and uncomfortable (although she later denied that she
was).175 She certainly had not given him permission to kiss her, let alone to
embrace her. Did she have grounds for accusing him of sexual assault? The
only obvious difference between this event and many others now
considered both immoral and illegal is that Brody’s behaviour was
witnessed by thirty-three million people. The audience cheered. They might
have been cheering for his performance in The Pianist rather than on stage,
to be sure, and they might have refrained had they had time to think about
what they had seen. Even later, nonetheless, no one commented on this as a
potentially punishable act of sexual assault. No charges were ever laid
against Brody. Can all this be explained merely as a matter of people being
out of touch with the law? Or is the law out of touch with people? Two
things seem clear. Brody’s behaviour was ambiguous, to say the least, and
Berry’s response ambivalent.
Men accused of rape sometimes claim to have received implied
consent.176 The notion of “implied consent” can be problematic, but so can
the notion of what we call “implied nonconsent.” The problem is accepting
one but not the other, the latter but not the former. Defining “lack of
consent,” Cross writes that it “can be conveyed by words or actions. Even if
a victim does not say NO directly, she can communicate it through struggle
or body language.”177 In other words, she can struggle to imply lack of
consent. The court would recognize that but not her use of body language to
imply consent. Canada’s Criminal Code does allow for something known as
an “honest and mistaken belief in consent,” and in R. v. Ewanchuk,178 the
Canadian Supreme Court rejected implied consent but allowed the defence
of an “honest but mistaken belief in consent.”179 But how can that be
distinguished from implied consent? Without an explicit agreement, after
all, no one could hold the former without believing, honestly but
mistakenly, that the latter had been given. An honest and mistaken belief in
consent makes no sense, in fact, without the possibility of implied consent.
Ewanchuk exposed a problem of profound importance – one that goes
far beyond the rape cases that come up in court. If implied consent is so
difficult to argue in court, why would any man have sexual relations with
any woman in any circumstances without written proof of her consent?
Even that would be legally irrelevant. A woman could change her mind in
the few minutes or seconds between signing a consent form and engaging in
sexual activity. And “no,” of course, means “no.” Perhaps unintentionally,
this doctrine severely erodes the kind of trust that is necessary for healthy
sexual relations. We would have said “destroys” except for the fact that
most men and women, ignorant of the law, continue to copulate on the basis
of trust that has no legal standing whatsoever.
Legal experts often say, and with good reason, that extreme cases do not
generate good laws. And yet Canada’s Supreme Court has indeed used an
extreme case, rape, as the basis for legislation that will have a profound
impact on even healthy sexual encounters between men and women. But
some feminists, those at the extreme end of a political continuum, believe
that there can be no healthy sexual encounters between men and women. At
one time, they point out, women were at the mercy of men. They fail to add
that men, in our time, are at the mercy of women.
To remove the double standards that we have been discussing would
mean to challenge the idea that rape is always more serious than framing
someone for rape. It certainly is, when it causes death or deadly disease or
serious injury. Otherwise, both rape and falsely framing someone for rape,
which can lead to a lengthy prison sentence and the lifelong consequences
of being a convict, are comparable.

And consider the misandric fallout from all this. If our analysis of
contemporary trends in the United States and Canada is correct, then the
effects of negative stereotypes about men now rival and possibly surpass
those of negative stereotypes about women. For decades, ideological
feminists have described most or even all men as rapists and molesters just
below the surface. Dozens of laws and policies – those that govern equity,
porn, child support, sexual harassment, and so on – are now stacked against
men. The rape-shield law is only one example, perhaps the most important
one of all.
How can we restore parallelism and therefore justice? On the one hand,
it could be argued that the reputations of both men and women are seriously
harmed as a result of either adultery or promiscuity. Judging from popular
culture, it seems clear that married men, no less than married women, are
still attacked for even considering extramarital or extrarelational affairs. In
that case, we should prohibit the use of sexual history in the case of both
defendants and plaintiffs but then introduce exceptions for both in egregious
cases.
On the other hand, it could be argued that the reputations of neither men
nor women are seriously harmed today as a result of their sexual activities
either inside or outside marriage. Men were once given “permission,”
supposedly, to have extramarital affairs. How many women these days
really worry about their reputations as chaste or virginal beings? Judging
from popular culture – think of Sex and the City and talk shows – it seems
clear that not many women are embarrassed by the intimate details of their
sex lives. This, we have been led to believe during the past forty years, is
part of what sexual liberation is all about. In that case, we should allow the
use of sexual history for both defendants and plaintiffs, but with the few
exceptions that we have already discussed.
In an ideal world, sexual intercourse would be the venue for neither
sexual violence nor sexual politics. In the real world, lamentably, it is the
venue for both. What can we do while waiting for the messiah? Here are a
few suggestions. Because the second and third are unlikely to be adopted or
even taken seriously, we conclude this discussion on a dismal note.
In an ideal world, we would not need legislation to govern sexual
relations. In the real world, we obviously do. Therefore, everyone should be
carefully taught the legal implications of sex – including the precise legal
meaning of “sexual assault,” the specific kinds of evidence that may or may
not be used in court, the actual penalties for those convicted, and so on.
This could be a standard unit of sex education in high schools and repeated
in the student guide books distributed at every university.
In an ideal world, no one would rely on alcohol or drugs to overcome
social and sexual inhibitions. In the real world, more and more people do.
And the consequences can be brutal or even deadly. Just as we legally
prohibit drinking or shooting up before driving, we should socially
discourage drinking or shooting up before copulating. It would take a
colossal cultural effort to make this the norm in our intensely hedonistic
society, but it would be worth a try.
In an ideal world, finally, no one would try to justify double standards. In
the real world, many people do. We once had a double standard that
favoured men. Thanks to ideological feminists, we now have one that
favours women. Like the old one, it has both moral and legal implications.
No intelligent man, given these circumstances, would have sexual relations
with women at all. Any man whose need for sex trumps his need for legal
security should take at least one simple precaution: carrying written consent
forms along with his condoms. It takes only a moment to put on a condom
for physiological protection. Why not take an additional moment for legal
protection? Even that would not satisfy all women – as we say, ideological
feminists believe that women are incapable of giving their consent to sexual
relations with men and thus refuse to acknowledge that women should have
some moral or legal responsibility for their own behaviour – because a
woman might always change her mind after signing. Still, having written
consent from her, with date and time, might be of some use to a man in
court. It might be better, at any rate, than nothing at all.
Small measures of this kind might help a few men, but they would do
little to solve the problems created for men by the shift to a gynocentric
worldview.

Much of the current thinking and discourse, both public and professional,
about abuse and interpersonal violence is based on a woman-centred point
of view. This is neither right nor wrong, good nor bad, but rather the result
of who has been doing the advocacy. However, as a result of this history,
victims have a female face, perpetrators a male face. Because of this image
of perpetrators as having a male face, violence in our society has become
“masculinized” and is blamed exclusively on “men” and “male
socialization.” Although there is without question a male gender dimension
to many forms of violence, especially sexual violence, simple theories of
male socialization are inadequate to explain why the vast majority of males
are not violent.180

Not only are most men not violent, some of them are the victims of
violence. What about the effects on male victims of sexual abuse?
“Compared to non-abused men,” writes Mathews, “adult male survivors of
sexual abuse experience a greater degree of psychiatric problems, such as
depression, anxiety, dissociation, suicidality and sleep disturbance.”181 In
these ways, they are just like female victims. And why would anyone
expect it to be otherwise? The answer is obvious: “Most of the literature on
the impact of abuse has been written about female victims and thus tends to
reflect a female-centred perspective. There has been, in Fran Sepler’s
words, a ‘feminization of victimization.’”182 But the effects of ignoring
boys and men as victims of violence go beyond the academy.

Our minimization and denial of male victimization so permeates our culture


that it is in evidence everywhere from nursery rhymes, comic strips,
comedy films, television programs and newspaper stories to academic
research. We give male victims a message every day of their lives that they
risk much by complaining. Stated succinctly, if a male is victimized he
deserved it, asked for it, or is lying. If he is injured, it is his own fault. If he
cries or complains, we will not take him seriously or condone his “whining”
because he is supposed to “take it like a man.” We will laugh at him. We
will support him in the minimization or its impact. We will encourage him
to accept responsibility for being victimized and teach him to ignore any
feelings associated with his abuse. We will guilt and shame him to keep a
stiff upper lip so he can “get on with it.”183

We discussed the messages of popular culture in Spreading Misandry


and will do so again, from a slightly different perspective in Transcending
Misandry. Listen to Mathews:

When we give a message to boys and young men in any shape or form that
their experience of violence and victimization is less important than that of
girls and young women, we are teaching them a lesson about their value as
persons. We also teach them that the use of violence toward males is
legitimate. When we dismiss their pain, we do little to encourage boys and
young men to listen to, and take seriously, women’s concerns about
violence and victimization. When we diminish their experience or fail to
hold their male and female abusers fully accountable, we support their
continued victimization.184
Elsewhere, Mathews discusses the implications of all this not only for
research but also for the assessment of male victims and the development of
programs to help them. In addition, he discusses the direct and indirect
messages given to male victims and comes to an assessment similar to our
own: that Canada is ignoring the problems of boys and men. “Many
questions remain unanswered. Why is it that Canada, a country that prides
itself on being a compassionate and just society, lags behind other countries
in advocacy for male victims? Why has the media refused to give equal
coverage to male victimization issues? Why do we consistently fail to
support adult male victims? Why do we support a double standard when it
comes to the care and treatment of male victims?”185 Similarly, he opines
that “when trying to determine the prevalence of sexual harassment toward
males, we are faced with the same problem of Canada lagging behind other
western democracies … virtually no research has been undertaken in
Canada that documents the prevalence of sexual harassment of males.”186 If
our thesis is correct, then Canada’s lack of attention on this problem could
be related to Canada’s gynocentrism.

Clearly, we do not live in an ideal world and never will, but that is no
excuse for complacency or cynicism. Doing the best we can to reverse
polarization between men and women, however, surely means more than
merely replacing misogyny with misandry or confusing justice with
revenge.
PART FOUR
Society on Trial: From Classroom to
Legislature

Although feminist ideologues continue to talk about having a “long way to


go,” they have in fact been remarkably successful. In only a few decades,
they have generated a social, intellectual, and economic revolution. In this
part of the book, we examine the origins of that revolution, the ways in
which ideological feminists have “reinterpreted,” “renegotiated,”
“reinscribed,” “relocated,” “resituated,” or “repositioned” academic
standards of truth in research to suit themselves. Using postmodernism as
their front, they have colonized fields as diverse as the humanities, the law,
and the social sciences. It is primarily because of this revolution at the
upper levels of academia, propagated not only in countless classrooms but
also in countless chatrooms on the Internet, that our society is becoming
just as gynocentric as the androcentric one that feminists were supposed to
correct in the name of equality between the sexes. It is primarily because of
this “engaged scholarship,” in other words, that the “advocacy journalism”
we discussed in part 1 was possible in the first place.
The mentality discussed so far amounts to what we have described as a
quiet revolution. We have all but replaced the old androcentric worldview
with a gynocentric one. But the main topic of this trilogy is misandry, not
gynocentrism. The two are closely linked, of course, though not necessarily
identical. In the concluding chapter of this book, we discuss the ways in
which gynocentrism can lead to misandry and misandry to serious problems
for any democratic society.
Democracy can take at least two forms in the modern world: the liberal
democracy and the welfare state (although these overlap considerably).
Among the defining features of democracy in either of these forms, at least
in theory, are two of particular importance here. One of them is political
transparency: proposed laws are debated openly in legislative assemblies
that represent the voters and then either approved or not approved. The
other is the give and take between majority and minority interest groups
(albeit within the limits established to prevent any tyranny of the majority):
each group is expected to lobby for its own political interests. But the
introduction of ideology – we refer here not only to its content but also to
favoured strategies such as the use of fronts to avoid debate, infiltration to
achieve hegemony within institutions, deconstruction to eliminate rivals,
and political correctness to silence adversaries – perverts both features and
thus endangers the democratic polity.
In chapter 10, we discuss the function of women’s studies, a field in
which ideology often takes precedence over scholarship. In chapter 11, we
conclude with a discussion of the results.
10
Ideological Feminism v. Scholarship: Women’s
Studies as a Front
The Women’s Studies Program at McGill university provides students with
the opportunity to examine how the intersections of gender, race, ethnicity,
sexuality, religion, class and culture shape identity and inform power
relationships. The program emphasizes feminist theoretical and empirical
scholarship and fosters understanding of historical, multicultural and
contemporary social and intellectual issues.1

Women’s studies is quite explicitly feminism in action in an academic


setting. Many courses in women’s studies, especially the lower-level
introduction to women’s studies sorts of courses (which, by the way, fulfill
general-education requirements in many universities), are issues oriented.
They are far too often talking not about women’s contributions but about
women’s victimization. Thus, they typically have a roster of issues such as
violence against women, pornography, abortion, homophobia, white
privilege, and so on that the class goes through one by one. These issues
typically are not presented as problems to be studied from many points of
view but rather as problems to be exposed by feminist ideology. The bottom
line to me is that far too often women’s studies classrooms convey attitudes
to be endorsed by the students rather than substantive knowledge.2

Misandry has not unified all feminists, to be sure, but it has certainly
unified enough of them – explicitly or implicitly, directly or indirectly,
consciously or subconsciously – to create a powerful movement. Their
headquarters is the college classroom, and, thanks to the Internet, it now
includes countless electronic venues devoted to women’s studies. In
addition, it includes countless others that are either more overtly political or
less academically respectable (which we discuss in appendix 11).
In this chapter, we consider ideological feminism in the university by
examining three closely related topics: its version of epistemology, its
notion of “engaged scholarship,” and what links it with women’s studies but
also with women’s networks and the professions – especially law.

Even though many other ideologies have been discredited by history and
therefore abandoned, feminist ideology has been remarkably successful
because of its postmodern matrix. In Spreading Misandry and earlier in this
book we discussed the features of ideology in general and of feminist
ideology in particular, linking the latter with other ideologies on both sides
of the political spectrum. Although we discussed postmodernism, too, a few
additional comments are necessary here (and especially in appendix 1).
Post-modernism is not, per se, an ideology. In theory, it opposes all
ideologies. In practice, though, nothing could be further from the truth, not
only because of the intellectual dishonesty among postmodernists, who
“deconstruct” all ideologies except the ones that they like, but also because
of their epistemology. How do we know about the world? On what
intellectual authority can we discuss the world and act in it? Modernism
offers one model, which is usually identified as science, but the same basic
principles – they add up to the disciplined use of reason – apply also to
other forms of scholarship. Postmodernism offers another model. And
ideological feminism offers a variation on that.
The epistemology of modernism, its theory of knowledge, is hardly
esoteric, although some authors warn that current hostility toward science,
not only from the religious right but also – and especially – from the
political left, might change that.3 Scientists claim that they can describe the
world accurately enough for all practical purposes. To do this, they observe
the world, propose hypotheses to explain what they observe, collect
empirical evidence or conduct experiments to test their hypotheses, and
then draw conclusions that can be either verified or falsified by the
observations or experiments of other scientists. At the heart of all this is an
epistemological principle: that the human mind really can encounter reality,
mediated by the senses, and thus really know something about it. Scientists
do acknowledge that various factors can limit this ability. Both the senses
and the mind are notoriously subject to illusion,4 which is why scientists
insist on the cultivation of logic, skepticism (refusal to accept the ultimate
authority of casual observation, anecdotal evidence, conventional wisdom,
or even of what passes for common sense), and – above all – objectivity. By
that, they mean the ability to sift through evidence and draw conclusions
without regard to vested interests, whether collective or personal – that is,
without regard to financial support from institutions or emotional support
from colleagues and without regard to theological beliefs, ideological
doctrines, political goals, and so on.
At the beginning of this third millennium, most people in our society
have come to value science, especially in connection with medicine and
technology (even though many of them value religion, too, which often
takes the form of a worldview in conflict with that of science). But a
growing number of people, so far confined mainly to ideologues or
religious fundamentalists, have come to negate the value of science in
general and objectivity in particular – not merely the lamentable ways in
which science is sometimes used, by the way, but also the intellectual
foundations on which it is built. Among these critics of modernism, of
course, are postmodernists. Along for the ride are ideologues of one kind or
another, including feminist ideologues. And the consequences of their
“paradigm shift” can be felt not only in research labs and college
classrooms, where scientists seldom take them seriously, but also in courts
of law and even government bureaucracies, where legal authorities and
political leaders take them very seriously indeed.5 Although other
ideologies have used the umbrella of postmodernism to attack modernism,
we confine ourselves here to feminist ideology and its use of the
postmodernist umbrella.6
For postmodernists in general, the chief problem with science – or,
indeed, with modern scholarship of any kind – is its origin in one particular
culture at one particular time: the culture of Western Europe in the
seventeenth century. From this origin, they deduce that science is just one
cultural construction among many, one that is inextricably tied to the beliefs
of particular people and therefore worthy of no privileged position in
relation to the ways of thinking produced in other cultures at other times.
That is the theory. The fact is that postmodernists almost always do
privilege particular ways of thinking: marginal Western ones and non-
Western ones. This practice accounts for the growing status of both Western
folk medicine and non-Western medicine. Many postmodernists claim that
these forms are just as effective as scientific medicine. Many of them might
indeed turn out to be effective, but postmodernists make this claim on
political grounds, not scientific ones.
For ideological feminists, the problem is more specific. They believe that
Western culture in the seventeenth century was fatally contaminated by the
ultimate poison of patriarchy, which could be the result of either maleness
itself or a form of masculinity so deeply embedded that it might as well be
maleness. And if this claim fails to convince political adversaries, they
simply “re-situate” or “re-contextualize” their point of view in some other
“discourse” that will.
After decades of complacency, scientists have begun to respond. They
acknowledge that their way of thinking took shape in Western Europe
during the seventeenth century, due to an unrepeatable chain of ideas and
events but see no logical connection between that historical fact and the
intellectual value of science. What their critics see as something particular,
in other words, scientists see as something universal. That view might not
be politically correct, they say, but it is true nonetheless. Whatever its
cultural and historical origin, science now belongs to everyone (which is
why some non-Western feminists see it as their best hope).7 Adopting the
scientific method might not be easy for non-Western societies, although the
Japanese have shown that it can be done effectively enough, but it was not
easy for Western societies either. It took almost three hundred years of
conflict for science to become firmly embedded in the West, and it is under
attack even now for both theological and secular – which is to say,
ideological – reasons. Scientists acknowledge, moreover, that the full
implications of their findings have sometimes been missed or even
deliberately ignored. It is true, for instance, that women should have been
encouraged long ago to take up careers in science, but that seldom
happened, because of human fallibility and not because of anything
inherently wrong with science.
Most of those who attack science know little or nothing about it.
Nonetheless, postmodernists now question either the existence of objective
reality or the ability of anyone to see it. This presents a very attractive
opportunity for some advocates of women or other “subaltern” groups
being oppressed by the lingering academic shades of “dead white males.”
Why would feminists, in particular, want to undermine the search for
objective reality? Some of them do not, of course, because they rely on the
search for objective truth to prove their claims about the victimization of
women. Others do, though, in order to bypass messy disputes over those
claims. If they can show inherent bias against women in research under the
established rules, which are based on the possibility of knowing at least
something objective about the external world, then they can dismiss
politically or ideologically inconvenient complexity and ambiguity without
further ado. At the same time, they can fill the void with research based on
rules of their own. Not rules that openly foster objectivity, to be sure, but
ones that openly foster subjectivity. Once the subjective “voice” of women
(or minorities) has been established as a new standard, of course, no
dissonant “voices” need to be taken seriously; women can presumably
“know” things by virtue of being women and affirming their own
subjectivity, things that men cannot know by insisting on the ostensibly
universal standard of objectivity.
This point of view has put feminists (and other postmodernists) on a
collision course with science itself, the ultimate expression of the search for
objective knowledge. How to “deconstruct” science or at least to undermine
its credibility? Partly by colonizing one of its newest frontiers: chaos
theory. Chaos theory is a legitimate field within science, of course, so
feminists (and other postmodernists) revel in the spectacle of scientists
apparently deconstructing their own fields and thus, wittingly or otherwise,
contributing to the feminist project. Chaos theory reveals a profound
“paradigm shift,” they believe, which will destroy the “hegemony” or
“privilege” of objectivity and replace it with the “pluralism” or “diversity”
of “multiple subjectivities.”
Paul Gross and Norman Levitt have responded to this challenge in
Higher Superstition.8 Despite its name, they argue, chaos theory does not
support the notion that scientific laws are obsolete. It repeals neither
Newtonian physics (which scientists continue to use for many practical
purposes) nor rational thinking (which remains the basis not only of science
but also of logic). It has not, in fact, inaugurated a revolution. This field
developed in order to account for a neglected class of behaviour. “Chaos”
occurs because every form of measurement is inherently flawed; “chaos
theory” simply recognizes that the resulting errors grow exponentially in
some systems. Even chaotic behaviour, in other words, is a rule-governed
process. To put all this in a very simple form, think of playing roulette. The
wheel is simple and has a structure, but the outcome of any spin is virtually
impossible to predict. Or think of flipping a coin. We can calculate the
probability for either heads or tails, but we cannot predict the outcome for
any one flip.9
Given postmodernist distortions of scientific theory in connection with
chaos theory, why be surprised at the postmodernist distortions of scientific
theory in connection with rational thinking itself? Feminists who rely on
postmodernism – not all of them do – tend to equate rational thinking with
linear thinking, classifying both as patriarchal, without the faintest notion of
what scientists actually mean by linear thinking. Their aim is to promote
“lateral thinking” or other “alternative ways of knowing.” Edward de Bono
introduced the former term decades ago, in the nonscientific context of
education, merely to connote creativity and problem solving “outside the
box.”10
The problem is due, say Gross and Levitt, to distortions of what
scientists mean by both “chaos theory” and “linear thinking.” As a result,
postmodernists (and creationists) feel free to make extravagant claims that
are based not on science but on pseudo-scientific metaphors – a habit that
Gross and Levitt call “metaphor mongering.”
Because these critics work in fields such as literature and “cultural
studies,” their attacks focus on the linguistic or rhetorical imagery
associated correctly or incorrectly with science, not its content. Why did
scientists once talk about the human egg as “passive” and the sperm as
“active,” for instance? Was it really because men were either unwilling or
unable to see what women would presumably have seen immediately, even
before scientists – male scientists – discovered the egg’s active role in
selecting and absorbing the sperm? Why do scientists still talk about
“attacking” a problem? Is it really because they are just brutal “warriors”
dressed up in lab coats?
At issue here is not so much science per se (modernism versus
postmodernism, for instance, or “traditional science” versus “feminist
science”) but extending the epistemological rhetoric used against both
science and modernism to undermine the legal position of men. To explore
that problem, we must first discuss the epistemology of ideological
feminists in general and its impact on women’s studies – which is the
breeding ground of ideological lawyers and bureaucrats.
In one way or another, feminist epistemologies are radically subjective.
They refer to “women’s ways of knowing” as distinct from and opposed to
those of men. Why the difference? Why do men and women see the world
differently? One ideological answer is that women are victims and men
oppressors. Another is that women are innately different from (read:
superior to) men. Yet Janet Radcliffe Richards and Mary Beth Ruskai argue
that there can be no such thing as feminist epistemology.11 Richards begins
by illustrating the rhetoric and jargon characteristic of feminist appeals for a
new epistemology with the following passage from Elizabeth Grosz:

[Luce] Irigaray’s work thus remains indifferent to such traditional values as


“truth” and “falsity” (where these are conceived as correspondence between
propositions and reality), Aristotelian logic (the logic of the syllogism), and
accounts of reason based upon them. This does not mean her work could be
described as “irrational,” “illogical,” or “false.” On the contrary, her work is
quite logical, rational, and true in terms of quite different criteria,
perspectives, and values than those dominant now. She both combats and
constructs, strategically questioning phallocentric knowledges without
trying to replace them with more neutral or more inclusive truths. Instead,
she attempts to reveal a politics of truth, logic and reason.12

In other words, anything goes in the battle to discredit an adversary.


At the heart of this essay by Richards is her claim that a feminist
epistemology would be both self-contradictory and self-defeating. To make
her point, she uses a hypothetical scenario: convincing an intelligent and
educated woman, a nonideological feminist, to reject science in favour of
“feminist science.” To do so, this woman would have to be convinced that
there is something wrong with the way things are in the world. In that case,

she must obviously have a view about the way things are, or she could not
think there was anything wrong with it; and she must also have some ideas
about what possibilities there are for change, or she would not be able to
say that things should be otherwise. She must, in other words, have a range
of first-order beliefs about the world: the kind of belief that is supported by
empirical, often scientific, investigation. Beliefs of this kind also imply that
she has other beliefs about second-order questions of epistemology and
scientific method, since in reaching conclusions about what to believe about
what the world is like and how it works she has, however unconsciously,
depended on assumptions about how these things can be found out, and
how to distinguish knowledge from lesser things. These assumptions will
become more explicit if any part of her feminism involves (as it is pretty
well bound to) accusing the traditional opposition of prejudice, or of
perpetrating or perpetuating false beliefs about women. Similar points apply
to questions of value. In order to make any complaint whatever about the
way things are, a feminist must at least implicitly appeal to standards that
determine when one state of affairs or kind of conduct is better or worse
than another; and if her complaint takes a moral form rather than a simply
self-interested one – if, like virtually all feminists, she expresses her
complaints in terms of such things as injustice and oppression and
entitlements to equality – she must be appealing to moral standards of good
and bad or right and wrong, of which she thinks the present state of things
falls short. And if she has such normative, first-order standards, that in turn
will imply something about her attitudes to the higher-order questions of
meta-ethics, whether or not she thinks of them as such.13

The argument continues, at length, in this carefully reasoned vein. At


each point, Richards says something like this: “So the arguments through
which traditional feminism reached its first conclusions involved no
departure from familiar standards of evidence and argument in ethics,
epistemology, and science, but actually presupposed them. It was by appeal
to these very standards that the position of women was first claimed to be
wrong. And notice that all arguments of this kind depend on absolutely
ordinary logic. It is because the traditional beliefs are incompatible with
traditional standards of assessment, that the challenge to the received view
in its own terms is possible.”14
And even if some feminist claims were true, adds Richards, that would
be due to something other than feminism (or any other ideology). Given
their interests, it is hardly surprising that feminists have pointed out facts
that scientists have missed. But those facts would have been “there” no
matter who pointed them out or why.
Richards concludes that feminist attempts to establish their own
epistemology are likely to have the most negative effect on women
themselves:

It is hard to imagine anything better calculated to delight the soul of


patriarchal man than the sight of women’s most vociferous leaders taking an
approach to feminism that continues so much of his own work: luring
women off into a special area of their own where they will remain screened
from the detailed study of philosophy and science to which he always said
they were unsuited, teaching them indignation instead of argument, fantasy
and metaphor instead of science, and doing all this by continuing his very
own technique of persuading women that their true interests lie elsewhere
than in the areas colonized by men. And, furthermore, outdoing even his
own contrivances, in equipping them with a sophisticated, oppression-
loaded, all-purpose rhetoric that actually obstructs any serious attempt at
analysis.15

Daphne Patai and Noretta Koertge, too, describe what passes for feminist
epistemology and subject it to a withering critique.16 In an article of her
own, Koertge shows why feminist “paradisciplines” or feminist
“correctives” within established disciplines have been so successful in
universities and why feminist ideology is no longer confined to women’s
studies.17 “Paradisciplinary initiatives are even taking root within the
sciences. Psychology of women, black psychology and biology of women
have now been joined by feminist economics and feminist geography.
Opposition to the most central methods and tools of science is fostered in
the paradisciplines of ethnomathematics, Afrocentric science, and feminist
methodology. We thus are faced with a profusion of new academic
specialties that not only claim to complement traditional scholarship but
also to replace or “reinvent” it in radical ways.”18 There are two reasons,
she says: academic separatism and affirmative action.
By the former, Koertge refers to the “founder effect” explained by
evolutionary biologists. Once a small group of organisms is isolated,
inbreeding will cause the dominance of its idiosyncrasies and, given enough
time, a new species. And so it is, she says, with feminists in women’s
studies. From the beginning,
there was a deliberate attempt to isolate feminist scholarship from the rest
of the academy [at least partly to avoid subjecting feminists to the same
standards of criticism as other academics]. Some authors would cite only
women in their footnotes; since men were thought to be biased, only
women were considered competent to referee articles for publication; men
were sometimes even excluded from attending conferences and were rarely
invited to speak. The policy of restricting participation in allegedly
academic discussions to people of the appropriate “identity” was sometimes
also used to filter out people on the basis of race, ethnicity, and sexual
orientation [that is, whites and heterosexuals]. By severely limiting the
influence of outside commentary and by aggressively promoting each
others’ work, the seminal (ovular?) works within these various alternative
disciplines quickly gained the trappings of scholarly success. To be blunt,
how can one deny tenure to someone whose book receives rave reviews in
(feminist) journals and whose book jacket sports blurbs from (feminist)
professors at Berkeley, Columbia, or M.I.T.19

Affirmative action did the rest, because the influx of women tended to
favour fields in what became a “pink collar ghetto.” But how could it have
been otherwise? Those already established in academia explicitly and
vehemently denied the most fundamental principles of scholarship.

None of [Talcott] Parsons’s norms are acceptable: logic is a patriarchal


device for browbeating nonlinear thinking; since all knowledge is
contextual, the search for generality is a form of imperialism; empirical
validity must be tempered by moral and political appraisals.

Communality of a nonhierarchical sort is acceptable, but the rest of


[Robert] Merton’s norms must go: a humane community would be based on
trust, not skepticism; universalism should be replaced by standpoint theory,
which says that reports are always to be understood as a product of the
culture, gender, ethnicity, class of the observer who made them; no activity
can be or should be disinterested. Quite the contrary, a commitment to
correct political and social goals is to be encouraged.20
As for academic objectivity, Koertge adds, ideological feminists believe
that “observers should always remain emotionally connected to what they
are studying; the richness of subjective experience should not be stripped
away in the vain search for a lowest common denominator of objectivity;
intuition should not play second-fiddle to abstract, cold
rationality/objectivity; knowledge is always perspectival and tied to local
context, and the attempt to find an objective or ‘God’s eye’ point of view
always ends up privileging the powerful. Thus the playful curiosity so
characteristic of so-called pure science must be replaced by an attitude of
caring and commitment.”21
These strictures make no scientific sense. Nor, adds Koertge, do they
make political sense for women and their allies. “What a pity, if in the name
of liberating women, feminists should now encourage women and members
of various ethnic groups to stay comfortably within the habits of thought
that conform to traditional gender and cultural stereotypes. One of the joys
of liberal education in either the arts or sciences is the challenge to learn
how to think differently. How patronizing to tell young women that the
ways of logic, statistics, and mathematics are not women’s ways – that all
they need to do is stay connected.”22
Of great interest here is the foundation of feminist epistemology: the
authority of experience – the experience of women, that is, whether
understood in the personal sense or the collective. Knowledge is said to be
“located” or “situated” or “positioned” according to either biology (innate
faculties that allow women to “know” what men cannot) or history
(powerlessness, which somehow allows women to “know” what men
cannot). According to the biological notion, men and women are innately
different for more than reproductive reasons. Students learn about a
distinctive “female way of knowing,” “female logic,” “female voice,” and
so on. According to the historical notion, men and women are conditioned
to be different. This idea is considered easier to “prove,” and it is thus more
popular among ideological feminists. Either way, the word “difference” can
be morally problematic. Experts in women’s studies often use it politely and
indirectly in connection with some innate superiority of women over men
(even though almost every feminist claims to oppose both essentialism and
dualism).23 Patai and Koertge see this emphasis on difference as the
cornerstone of both pedagogical orthodoxy in women’s studies and
ideological separatism among feminists.
Donna Haraway, for example, describes the “dominant” epistemology –
presumably that of men alone – in terms of objectivity, value neutrality, and
pure inquiry.24 She describes feminist epistemology – that of women – as
subjective, value laden, and (in effect) purely political. Like good post-
modernists, she keeps asking questions that begin with “whose.” Whose
knowledge have we accepted so far? Whose evidence? Whose
interpretation? Whose interests are at stake? These, say many academics in
women’s studies, are the most important epistemological (and therefore
political) questions that feminists can ask. And the answer is always the
same cynical one: that of whatever group has the most power. For
ideological feminists, that answer is a euphemistic reference to men (or at
least white men).
Objectivity implies universality. If something is objectively true, after
all, it must be true for all people. Subjectivity, on the other hand, implies
particularity. Something might be true for some people but not for others,
say, or true in some circumstances but not others. But feminist ideologues,
despite their lip service to postmodernist relativism, identify universality
objectively with men and particularity objectively with women. Never mind
that this confirms the old misogynistic stereotype of women as irrational
beings or that it contradicts the ostensible disdain of women for objectivity.
Unlike women, who revel in “diversity” (except for those who step out of
line ideologically), men speak with one “dominant voice” (except for those,
if any, who can somehow be converted to feminism and adopt a female
“voice”). This “voice” of men is usually known as “the male model” or “the
male standard.” And the word “male” indicates something biological,
something innate, unlike the word “masculine.”
Although there are many “feminisms,” each one is a collectivist
movement; an “individualist movement,” in fact, would be a contradiction
in terms. And most feminists, no matter how marginal or how liberal, claim
to speak for women in general. When they refer to knowledge, not
surprisingly, they refer primarily to women’s knowledge. Like other
“knowledges,” it is “socially constructed” within the community of women
and its “webs of belief.”25 (The word “web,” presumably referring to the
web of a spider, is a ubiquitous but puzzling and even ironic metaphor.
Feminists use it to connote “connectedness” or “interconnectedness,”
something allegedly unique to women. Zoologists, on the other hand, tell us
only that spiders use webs to trap insects for food.)
Epistemology is not nearly as impersonal or dry as it sounds, at least not
in women’s studies. It has both therapeutic and political implications, which
are, in fact, closely interrelated. After all, “empowering” women is
supposed not only to improve their economic potential and political status
but also to transform their personal and collective identities.
Academics are not the only ones to have participated in the “social
construction” of women’s knowledge. Think of pop psychologists and their
role in creating a culture of therapy movements. Think in particular of their
ultimate creation: the daytime talk show. This genre is intended to
“empower” viewers – and most are women – by making them feel better
about themselves. Remember that the rise of therapism and feminism were
simultaneous. Coincidence? Hardly.26 The two are now interconnected, at
any rate, on many levels. In line with the therapeutic model now prevalent
in popular culture, say Patai and Koertge, students in women’s studies are
often asked to provide “testimonies” about their own experiences in order to
“get in touch with their feelings” – that is, with their anger toward men. To
facilitate this, teachers use small group discussions or, better still, role-
playing in which women “experience” their abuse by men.27 Students are
then required to record their emotional reactions in journals and analyze
them according to feminist criteria. They learn that knowledge is based on
experience, in other words, and that it is personal in nature. Growth is
measured by progress toward feminist analysis. By the time that they have
internalized feminist perspectives, students have become “empowered” by
“voicing” their feminist ideas and being “affirmed” by other women. They
have been transformed. Consciousness has been raised.
In the popular teach-yourself book called Women’s Studies, Joy Magezis
asks what prospective students can hope to get from this field.28 She
emphasizes the personal dimension of women’s studies: the field helps
students understand the ways in which society has shaped and limited them
in connection with race, ethnicity, class, sexuality, and so forth. This
understanding builds their self-confidence and gives them a sense of
control. In other words, once again, the field “empowers” them. Moreover,
it helps women to connect with each other through courses and networking.
Next, she discusses the history of feminism, indicating a clear link between
that history and women’s studies. Finally, she presents an exercise called
“your views.” Students are asked to examine their own views on what it
means to be women and on what they have in common with other women.
With this in mind, students begin writing journals or making videos or
creating other forms of self-expression. Exercises of this kind appear
everywhere, so students are always aware that the political is personal and
the personal political. In effect, teachers say the following: here is the
correct theory; document it with your own experiences. This exercise places
a premium on emotion rather than reason, and emotion, in turn, is closely
related to collectivism, although this relationship is often disguised by
appeals to “pluralism.” Magezis mentions feminists from various
perspectives: socialist, radical, psychoanalytic, black, and liberal. An
exercise called “Looking at different feminist views” asks readers to
describe which feels closest to the truth and why. She tells them that they
need not find one, though, because women come together when necessary –
even when they disagree (which would be news to Camille Paglia, Christina
Hoff Sommers, Katie Roiphe, Daphne Patai, and other dissident feminists).
But ideological feminists in women’s studies place most emphasis on
group therapy, not individual therapy, which is hardly surprising in view of
the fact that collectivism is a primary feature of every political ideology.
Teachers praise collaborative and “connected” learning. Because they
identify hierarchy with patriarchy, “the male model,” and because hierarchy
is latent in the very concept of the teacher-student relationship, they hope to
remove it to whatever degree is possible in a patriarchal institution. Profs
can always give an A to every student and thus foster “equality.” One
contributor to an e-mail list argued for the elimination of all traditional
academic notions: grading, deadlines, facts, specializations, disciplines,
objectivity, logic, rules of any kind, or whatever.29 In line with this
collectivist focus, many teachers encourage students to gain credits given
for internships done in women’s organizations and “mentored” by the
feminists they find there.
By now, it should be clear that the collectivist approach is not only
therapeutic, or personal, but also political. Patai and Koertge surveyed 150
women’s studies students at two universities with very different profiles.30
Students at both, presumably female, defined the goals of women’s studies
primarily in gynocentric and activist terms: to increase women’s self-
esteem, to empower women, to help women develop careers focused on
eliminating patriarchy and sexism, and so on. (These students were careful
to contrast their own goals with those of feminist “male-bashers” and
militants, or radicals).31
This result raises two important questions: Is there any significant
difference between women’s studies and ideological feminism? Or is the
former merely an academic arm of the latter? Based on both interviews and
their own extensive experience as professors of women’s studies, Patai and
Koertge say yes to both and go on to expose the political, or ideological,
dimensions of many women’s studies programs. Using the analogy of
religious studies or Chinese studies, it could be argued that women’s studies
is simply an interdisciplinary approach to the study of women. But this
field, say Patai and Koertge, almost always has a political orientation. It is
linked with the needs and problems of women, which are almost always
said to be caused by men, and with the goal of improving women’s status.
With all this in mind academics have made formal attempts to define
women’s studies. Teachers and researchers, they argue, should use feminist
principles.32 And courses should be about the evils of patriarchy such as
sexual harassment, molestation, domestic violence, rape, inadequate
reproductive rights, and attempts to prevent women’s “agency.”
Magezis begins her book with a telling observation: “Women’s studies is
putting women centre-stage … It’s about giving women a fair chance to live
up to their potential. Women’s studies brings together our personal
experiences and the study of ideas. It is a way of examining the world from
women’s points of view, coming to understand it and then making changes.
Into the twenty-first century, we women need to take hold of our future.”33
By “we,” she refers exclusively to women (as if men could be neither
interested in nor affected by anything under discussion). This definition is
clearly gynocentric. Given the topic of women’s studies, which is women,
gynocentrism is an occupational hazard in the field. Worse, this definition
of women’s studies fuses the academic study of ideas with the nonacademic
experiences of political identity and political mission. No wonder Simon
Fraser University’s Department of Women’s Studies advertised for a
professor with the following qualifications: “extensive experience in
academia, the professions, or as an activist.”34
Worth noting here is the fact that Magezis defines feminism in much the
same way:

Feminism is based on the idea that society is not treating women fairly. It
looks at why this is so and how women are oppressed. It works for women’s
liberation … [F]eminism means different things to different women. For
example, some would say it is working for equality with men in our society,
while others say it is out to change the whole way society is set up.
Feminism is a broad social movement which allows different points of
views under the umbrella of working for women’s rights and against female
oppression. Whether or not you want to call yourself a feminist is
something that only you can decide. But don’t feel that you have to use the
title in order to find out about women’s studies.35

Note that word “feel,” once more, presumably a synonym for “think.”
Magezis admits that “feminism” is a controversial word, although she
argues that this problem amounts to nothing more than public relations, and
therefore prefers “women’s studies.” It makes no difference to her, because
both words mean much the same thing. But the latter does sound more
respectable, certainly in academic circles, and is more likely to attract new
recruits (along with more funding). In short, women’s studies operates as a
front, in the old Marxist sense, for feminism.
Many code words and phrases are used to disguise the fact that women’s
studies is a front for feminism. The classroom devoted to women’s studies,
for example, is supposed to create a friendly “environment” in which
women not only learn but also feel “affirmed” or “empowered.” Academic
journals refer to the need for a climate in which women feel fully integrated
and fully valued within the academic community. Unfortunately, they often
fail to specify precisely what doing so would actually entail. Universal and
uncritical acceptance of feminist ideology? If so, that in turn would entail
orthodoxy and censorship – both of which should be intolerable in any
community, particularly in an academic one, but also in one that ostensibly
values “diversity.” An academic community exists mainly to encourage the
free exchange of ideas and development of new knowledge. If this is
undesirable in the university, then the university has ceased to be a
university.
The same problem emerges in connection with another proposal about
“valuing” and “developing” academic fields of particular interest to women.
This sounds benign, but it could be a thinly veiled reference to some
requirement that the university actively promote feminism, even ideological
feminism. Universities are no more obliged to promote feminism than they
are to promote capitalism, nationalism, communism or any other ism. On
the contrary, secular universities exist primarily to collect data, describe
phenomena, test hypotheses, and question ideas whether they originate in
the most established orthodoxies, the most radical ideologies, or anywhere
in between. Universities should be places where scholars can discuss ideas
openly and freely but not necessarily where they do so comfortably.
Decorum is one thing, a good way to facilitate the exchange of ideas,
therapy another. If you believe that emotional comfort is more important
than intellectual energy, then you need a therapeutic community rather than
a scholarly one.
But Patai goes much further in her critique of women’s studies, arguing
that women’s studies is not an academic discipline at all but the academic
arm of an political movement – what we, once again, call a respectably
academic front for ideological feminism. Not surprisingly, many reviewers
in women’s studies have attacked her. In responding to them, she has been
required to repeat her initial premise over and over again.

Women’s studies is quite explicitly feminism in action in an academic


setting … [Courses] are far too often … not about women’s contributions
but about women’s victimization … These issues typically are not presented
as problems to be studied from many points of view but rather as problems
to be exposed by feminist ideology. The bottom line to me is that far too
often women’s studies classrooms convey attitudes to be endorsed by the
students rather than substantive knowledge.36

Academic disciplines are supposed to be objective and therefore


apolitical. They maintain the ideal of scholarship, in other words, even
though individual teachers and authors sometimes insist on promoting their
own perspectives at the expense of free inquiry. Ideologies, on the other
hand, are supposed to be political. And because every ideology has a point
of view, one that gives adherents a sense of purpose both individually and
collectively, ideologies are to that extent also subjective. In this case, Patai
argues, that point of view includes hatred both of men and, either implicitly
or explicitly, of heterosexuality. She must have expected feminist advocates
of women’s studies to keep on trivializing or attacking her point of view.
And indeed they have.37 But by doing so en masse, ironically, they
undermine their own counterclaim: that those in women’s studies welcome,
or at least tolerate, criticism.
Opening what feminists consider an infamous colloquy on the state of
women’s studies, hosted online by the Chronicle of Higher Education, Patai
made her claim very clear: “It’s an unusual opportunity, in my experience,
for in fact one of my fundamental criticisms of women’s studies is that it
has not been open to discussion with critics but has instead too often
maligned their motives, which makes it impossible for substantive debate to
take place.”38 In any case, we suggest, Patai’s critics adopted six basic
strategies (usually combined): who, me?; everyone’s doin’ it; reversal;
necessary evil; much ado about nothing; and shifting the blame.
Most of the arguments against Patai include tiresome variations, by both
teachers and students, on the theme of “who, me?” “But I don’t proselytize
in my courses,” they protest. “I don’t turn my classes into group therapy
sessions. I don’t teach my students to hate men.”39 Patai is a malicious
turncoat, they say, who cites a few preposterous exceptions in order to
defame women’s studies or even women themselves. Besides, they add,
feminists are such a diverse lot. Why take Patai’s criticism seriously? Listen
to Jenea Tallentire, a graduate student at the University of British Columbia:
“I noticed that young men especially were interested in hearing me out,
though I had a few heated discussions with some. I sensed their
bewilderment because they had ‘heard of’ that mythical fire-breathing
feminist and [instead] got me – I kept my ‘fires’ to a minimum. I tried to
stress the varied opinions in feminist studies (also news to most people),
and the fact that many who say they are feminists are nothing of the kind, or
at least do not ‘represent’ even a good number of feminists.”40 Notice that
she refers to feminist studies, not women’s studies, something that might be
more significant than she realizes. On the one hand, she argues that
feminism has room for “varied opinions.” On the other hand, she continues
the same sentence by declaring that those who hold undesirable opinions
are either not really feminists at all or too marginal to be worth taking
seriously! Well, that must have helped those bewildered young men.
Listen now to Christine Littleton, whose specialty at the University of
California, Los Angeles, is feminist law: “shi [the Sexual Harassment
Industry] is, of course, a construct of Professor Patai’s.”41 In other words,
Patai has set up a woman of straw only to illustrate her own point by
torching it. Later on, Littleton says that “It is possible that particular party
lines ‘own’ the sexual harassment issue at Amherst in a way that most
institutions have outgrown, discarded, or never experienced. Whether or not
Patai has mistaken her small corner of the world for the world itself,
however, this book does not admit of any more modesty in its claims than
its title [Heterophobia].”42 Or listen to Beatrice Kachuck at the City
University of New York: “I have never encountered anything like a
‘therapy’ class.”43 Or Heather Kleiner, a retired professor from the
University of Georgia: “The women’s studies scholars I was associated with
for over twelve years were engaged in the same activities as all good
academics: analyzing and critiquing the ‘givens’ of their respective fields
and of society, guiding students to awareness, understanding and action.”44
Or Adrienne McCormick at the State University of New York, Fredonia: “I
have always taught the pro-sex and anti-porn positions on pornography; I
have students45 preparing a presentation right now on abortion that will take
into account women who are pro-choice and pro-life; I have men in my
classes and encourage them to take more courses. These approaches to key
women’s studies issues are mirrored in many of my colleagues’ classrooms
in women’s studies as well.” In short, Patai is said to be misrepresenting the
field “by imposing a homogeneity upon them that does not exist.”46 Here is
Patai’s response:

It’s interesting to me that to make criticisms gets one cast as imposing


“homogeneity.” Let us suppose that Adrienne is perfectly accurate in her
description of her own teaching and [that] of colleagues. That in no way
contradicts my claim and that of other critics that there are serious problems
of ideological browbeating and indoctrination passing as teaching going in
women’s-studies classrooms. This is an old question. What percentage of
programs and classes have to reveal problems before women’s-studies
faculty take these problems seriously and address them instead of saying as
I have been repeatedly told, “It doesn’t happen here”? My experience is that
even at schools where the women’s-studies people are making this claim the
problems do indeed exist, as I hear behind the scenes from students and
other faculty at these institutions and as is even confirmed by the fact that
some of these institutions, which claim there are no such problems in
women’s studies, that at some of these institutions women’s-studies people
have actually attempted to have rescinded invitations that I have gotten
from other groups to speak there. This hardly shows the openmindedness
and tolerance and nondoctrinaire attitudes that these same feminists
characteristically claim.47

Those who claim, in effect, that “everyone’s doin’ it” rely implicitly on
two highly questionable notions, one traditional (that two wrongs can
indeed make a right) and the other postmodern (that there is no such thing
as apolitical scholarship in the first place). “Given the inevitably political
nature of deciding what ideas to disseminate,” says Diana Blaine, at the
University of Southern California, “how would you describe the political
agenda of non-women’s studies courses? And why are you more
comfortable with the propagation of these unacknowledged agendas than
you are with the ideas overtly being articulated in women’s-studies
courses?”48 Kristin Rusch, at the University of Maryland, asks a very
similar question: “Isn’t a specifically feminist viewpoint (and variations
thereof) a legit perspective to study on the issues you [Patai] mentioned?
Certainly Marxists have something important to say about these issues, as
do Freudians, theologians, and others. What’s wrong with looking at
feminist views on these issues?”49 According to Lisa Jadwin of St John
Fisher College, the field “may simply be trying to bring the study of gender
into systematic focus, and to ensure that the contributions of women to
human history are acknowledged and studied with the same consistency as
the contributions of men.”50
Responding to arguments of this kind, Patai challenges the double
standard of those who make them. “My Spanish and Portuguese department
does not have a mission statement that involves political transformation.
Most women’s studies programs do. Women’s Studies is feminism, by
definition, in most programs/departments, and feminism is a political
program. (Have a look at the National Women’s Studies Association’s
mission statement. It makes absolutely clear that Women’s Studies is
providing feminist/womanist education in the service of a political mission
– to free the world of a variety of isms.)”51 She adds that the “idea that
leading scholars [in those other fields] are forcing their graduate students to
toe a particular line is more parody than reality – and wherever it does
happen, it’s unfortunate and should be resisted. However, that sounds like a
very peculiar defense of women’s studies. ‘We force our students to toe the
line, but so does everyone else’ is hardly a recipe for change or
improvement.”52 Of course, both Patai and her critics use the argument of
“more parody than reality.” Even so, Patai’s point is well taken. Many
advocates of women’s studies do indeed reject a double standard (in this
case), but they do so by actively promoting bias instead of challenging it
and then, either implicitly or explicitly, justifying it on postmodernist
grounds.53
In response to a question about whom she would consider fit to teach
women’s studies, Patai notes that this field

was created to be the “academic arm of the women’s movement,” and this
phrase is still repeated again and again in the mission statements of various
programs. I don’t believe it’s appropriate for a secular university to have a
program committed to a particular ideology. To the extent that women’s
studies is feminism [as distinct from being about feminism], it is, in my
view, academically illegitimate. The study of women, our history, gender
roles, etc., on the other hand, are all entirely legitimate and important
subjects. One can be a feminist, as I am, and not a supporter of women’s
studies or of feminist activism [specifically] in education.54

Other critics focus on reversal. Because Patai accuses women’s studies


of promoting a double standard, they find it convenient to accuse her of the
same thing. Littleton admits, for example, that the stories of those accused
falsely of sexual harassment do need to be told. “It is troubling, however, in
a book that takes other feminists to task for telling the story from only one
side, that Patai makes little or no effort to be fair to the accusers [in
harassment cases].”55 But Patai has documented a mountain of literature
about the experiences of victims or alleged victims of sexual harassment.
“By contrast, there is a mere handful of books questioning the legal
arguments for treating sexual harassment as discrimination, and casting
doubt on the claims of uniquely grievous harm done to women
(“survivors”) by men’s sexual or gender-related words or gestures. Given
this imbalance, it hardly seems excessive for me to have devoted two
hundred pages or so to a challenge to the prevailing views.”56 She could
have underscored the word “prevailing.”
Still other critics acknowledge some excesses in women’s studies but
claim that the field is (in effect, because they never use these words) a
necessary evil. They point to the lack of a better alternative, suggesting that
the end might justify the means: “Isn’t it possible to teach women’s
studies,” asks Jane Elza of Valdosta State University, “without going to
extremes? Imagine the world without women’s studies – would it be better
off?”57 This is an important question, and we will return to it at the end of
this chapter.
Some critics argue that Patai has been guilty of much ado about nothing.
She admits that some individual teachers in women’s studies “are
committed to education and not to replicating in their students their own
attitudes and trajectory. The question, of course, is what happens to those
teachers in the institutional framework of women’s studies. And there the
news isn’t so great. What you [Jane Elza] call not going to extremes, many
women’s studies faculty would call caving in to discredited liberal ideas.
An entire analysis of the world and of education – a very flawed analysis –
underlies women’s studies and is used in defense of its orthodoxies and
‘extremes.’”58
The troublesome relation between women’s studies and feminism has
not gone unnoticed in the academic world. In some places, the problem is
resolved by calling a spade a spade – “feminist studies” – although that
hardly settles the question of why any political movement should have its
own department in a university. In other places, it is resolved by resorting to
a euphemism: “gender studies.”59 Even when the word “gender” is used in
the United States and Canada, it is almost always associated either directly
or indirectly with women and, more recently, with gay people. Because
“gender” originated as a linguistic term, referring to both feminine and
masculine nouns, you would expect gender studies to include the study of
both women and men, both straight and gay. But you would almost always
be wrong. Men are hardly ever studied or even mentioned – except, of
course, insofar as they are said to oppress women (a topic that we discuss in
appendix 10).
Knowledge, we conclude, is truly on trial. Yes, there have been some
debates over freedom of expression and even some critiques of women’s
studies. But these have not halted the advance of “engaged scholarship.” By
the late twentieth century, it had been established, institutionalized, and
even bureaucratized. It had come, therefore, to have a life of its own. The
university had become a laboratory for experiments in the larger world that
resulted in social revolution on an unprecedented scale and, given the lack
of accountability to either scholars or legislators, in unprecedented secrecy.
Through the back door, as it were, ideological feminists had
institutionalized gynocentrism at best and misandry at worst.
Programs in women’s studies proliferated at universities during the last
quarter of the century. According to Joan Korenman, there are
approximately 650 women’s studies programs, departments, and research
centres. In 2001 most Canadian universities were offering women’s studies
courses: 35 out of 45 had minors programs; 29 had majors programs; some
had honours or joint honours programs (no statistics were provided for that
category), and 16 had graduate programs as well.60
One function of women’s studies is to create a lobby group. And one
way of achieving that is to, well, lobby for its own expansion. A Canadian
academic bulletin advocated that universities hire more tenured feminists
and more people to work on their support staffs, enlarging their quarters,
promoting their field by all levels of the administration, and even “outing”
any feminists who might remain “closeted.”61 The bulletin triumphantly
announced that a thousand undergrads and eighty grads would be promoting
feminist networks in every major profession.
In addition, teachers in women’s studies have increased their influence at
the professorial level through books and articles. Feminism has become
institutionalized not only in the university, therefore, but also in the
publishing industry. Ideologically oriented feminists have generated an
enormous literature over the past few decades. You might think that their
works are published only by university presses, but many are in fact
published by trade houses, which explains why the academic jargon of
feminism has become part of popular parlance.62 Publishing houses now
hire feminists, thereby succumbing to pressure from those who want major
works to include contributions from women. Think, for instance, of the
Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy.63 Writing for the New York Times
Book Review, George Steiner mentions a “disturbing feature” of this
project:

Known to be a lucid ironist with a sharp nose for the fraudulent, chief editor
Edward Craig confesses that the encyclopedia has had to cater to
“devotees” of current French feminist incantations. Why so? Whence this
modish obligation? Whatever the motives, the consequences are regrettable.
The most fanatic and self-advertising of post-structuralist, post-modernist,
deconstructionist and feminist French gesturing are accorded space and
regard. A special editor shepherds their bacchanalia. Yet there is every
likelihood that sanity will be regained before too long and that these
illegible outpourings and their begetters will be seen to have risen without
any lasting trace.64

All these books, no matter who publishes them, are used as texts in
countless university courses and promoted on the Internet in countless lists
of core books for those interested in feminism, “women’s studies,” “gender
studies,” “cultural studies,” and so on.

This brings us to the important topic of feminist networks, which link elite
members of university departments with their grassroots counterparts, on
the one hand, and with professions, on the other. Networking begins in the
universities themselves. Departments of women’s studies increase their
power base within the university by networking with campus groups such
as women’s resource centres and women’s unions.
Networking is easy these days because of the Internet. By now most or
all women’s studies programs have their own websites that contain
information on courses, research centres, archives, libraries, databases,
archived files, chatrooms, correspondence courses, and other resources.
Surfers can find both national and international guides on using the Internet
to locate and assess these resources.65 Academic websites are often linked,
in turn, to nonacademic sites on women’s studies (an oxymoron, but never
mind that for the moment).
At one site, Women’s Studies Programs in North America, visitors can
find alphabetical listings by state and university, that were compiled not by
an academic but by a musician, Gerri Gribi, “who strives to bring the
diverse ‘unsung’ history of women and minorities to life” with a show
called A Musical Romp through Women’s History.66 Besides promoting both
the show and her album, The Womansong Collection, she sells mailing
labels for the women’s studies list as well as for her list of women’s centres.
Clearly, academic and nonacademic networks overlap, and the term
“women’s studies” is popular enough among women to be appropriated for
advertising.
Joan Korenman has linked her list of women’s studies programs,
departments, and research centres to syllabus collections and film reviews.
Commenting on this site, which had been visited by 4,400 people in 47
countries when she checked, Korenman says, “When I need information, I
have an international body of well-informed virtual colleagues to whom I
can turn.”67 She presented her research about online resources for women,
what she calls “cyber-feminism,” at the United Nations Conference on
Women held in Beijing, as well as at numerous other conferences and
workshops.
Our only point in discussing feminist sites on the Internet, however, is to
illustrate the remarkable growth of women’s studies (or whatever academics
call this field) over the past few decades. Its influence radiates from the
classroom to both the university as a whole (through students who learn
what to demand from academic and administrative officials) and the larger
society (through countless graduates who have gone on to work in private
and public institutions). Its influence radiates also from academic networks
(such as the American Association of University Women or the Canadian
Federation of University Women) to professional societies representing
many academic disciplines (each of which has its women’s caucus or
women’s wing). These networks are linked, in turn, with both government
bureaucracies (the Department of Education and the Violence against
Women Office, say, or Status of Women Canada) and nonacademic groups
(such as “grassroots” websites on women in popular music, women in the
arts, and so forth).
Established in 1966, the National Organization for Women (NOW)
currently has a membership of over 500,000 in 550 chapters throughout the
United States. Its mission statement claims that now “advances women’s
rights and promotes the goal of equality in the United States and around the
world through education, litigation, advocacy, networking, conferences,
publications, training and leadership development.”68 An affiliate, the
National Organization for Women Foundation, raises money for its
projects.69 NOW produces a steady stream of press releases on topics of
interest to women that focus heavily on abortion but also on rape and other
forms of assault, the “feminization of poverty,” affirmative action, pay
equity, the “glass ceiling,” misogyny in movies and ads, women’s rights in
countries such as Afghanistan, women’s health, and lesbian interests
(adoptions, hate-crime legislation, and same sex marriage). NOW runs
workshops and conferences for young women to encourage them to call
themselves feminists and act accordingly. This organization pays particular
attention to the legal and political processes that affect women. It mobilizes
women for causes, urges them to sign petitions, to lobby, to march, to vote.
In 1998 the cause was lobbying against the impeachment of President
Clinton (who might have cheated on his wife but nonetheless supported
women’s causes). In 1999 it warned Congress against those who were
supporting the rights of fathers (even though women were simultaneously
urging men to take fatherhood seriously). In 2000 it promoted presidential
debates on matters of interest to women. In 2001 it prevented conservative
John Ashcroft from becoming the attorney general. In 2002 it organized a
national conference on “gender” and a Gender Lobby Day in Washington, a
national conference on domestic violence, the fifth annual Love Your Body
Day, and a forum for disabled women. In every case, the word “gender”
really did refer specifically and exclusively to women. One mantra keeps
recurring in NOW’s publicity: “Turn anger into activism.”70
Of particular interest to us, having discussed negative stereotypes of men
in Spreading Misandry and the fact that so few people are willing to
acknowledge that problem, is NOW’s annual report card on the state of radio
and television programming. Its campaign is called “Watch Out, Listen
Up!” Topics for assessment include the number and severity of violent,
threatening, or hostile acts against women; sexual exploitation; social
irresponsibility; and inadequate sexual ratios on shows. The latter problem
is defined as the percentage of women or girls in the cast, with deductions
for negative stereotypes and bonus points for positive ones, or “role
models” (especially for minority women and lesbians). NOW encourages
women who are offended by programs to contact radio stations, television
channels, broadcasting networks, production companies, newspaper editors,
and other public figures; to organize house parties so that participants can
listen to or watch shows, discuss them, and plan letter-writing campaigns or
other events; form local task forces; demonstrate at stations or channels
with low marks; and, ultimately, to lobby in Congress.71 A website provides
all the names and addresses. In its survey for 2000, NOW named Fox a
“network of shame” for its routinely shabby presentation of women (even
though its presentation of men was, arguably, no better). The publicity
around this designation and related picketing led to a discussion between
Patricia Ireland, president of NOW, and the incoming president of Fox
Entertainment. A subsequent press release by Ireland indicated that more
“woman-positive” shows would be in the works. Staged for publicity? You
bet.
The Ms. Foundation emerged from Ms., the magazine founded in 1972
by Gloria Steinem and Dorothy Pitman Hughes.72 Every year, the
foundation honours five “women of vision,” each of whom receives the
Gloria Steinem Award. Its mission statement refers to its support of
measures to help women and girls govern their own lives and to break down
“barriers based on class, age, disability, sexual orientation and culture” by
changing public awareness, promoting law reform, and establishing social
programs on abortion, violence, pay, and health.73 It provides funds to local,
regional, and national organizations for improving women’s economic
opportunities, education, advocacy skills, and leadership training. One of
the foundation’s main projects was Take Our Daughters to Work Day, the
premise of which was that consciousness raising must start early (although
the event is now called Take Our Daughters and Sons to Work Day). The
foundation gets endorsements for this event from famous women,
especially those who choose nontraditional careers and those who become
politicians. Moreover, it sells gifts to mark the occasion: hats, t-shirts, tote
bags, calculators, buttons, and stickers.
A close ally is the Feminist Majority Foundation, another American
advocacy group working to improve women’s lives through economic,
social, and political policies. Here is its mission statement: “Our
organization believes that feminists – both women and men, girls and boys
– are the majority, but this majority must be empowered.”74 Despite the
inclusive language, the exclusive focus on women is quickly apparent with
talk of “countering the backlash to women’s advancement, and recruiting
and training young feminists to encourage future leadership for the feminist
movement in the United States.”75 Its sister organization, the Feminist
Majority, lobbies on causes such as preventing the Supreme Court from
being stacked with conservative judges and recruiting young feminists by
sponsoring rock concerts. This foundation has a feminist canon posted on
its web site. To ensure dissemination of its point of view, the site includes
lists of feminist bookstores, electronic versions of books, publishers,
reviews, and specialized bibliographies.76
Even though feminism began at the elite level,77 especially in the
universities, its influence spread rapidly to the popular level through
networking, and it now has a life of its own.78 Many of the organizations
accessible over the Internet are big – remember that NOW has 500,000
members – and politically savvy enough to link elite feminists, especially
members of the academic elite, with grassroots feminists.
Canada, too, has many feminist advocacy groups. The largest is the
National Action Committee on the Status of Women: “A Coalition of over
700 member groups, NAC is the largest feminist organization in Canada,
respected around the world for its ability to shape public opinion, influence
decision makers and mobilize its membership and the Canadian public to
work for equality and justice for all women.”79 All Canadian taxpayers,
including male ones, fund a feminist advocacy group within the government
itself. Called Status of Women Canada, it “is the federal government agency
which promotes gender equality, and the full participation of women in the
economic, social, cultural and political life of the country … It promotes
women’s equality in collaboration with organizations from the non-
governmental, voluntary and private sectors. In promoting women’s
equality globally, S.W.C. works with other countries and international
organizations.”80 Its specific goals are

to promote policies and programs within key institutions that take account
of gender implications, the diversity of women’s perspectives and enable
women to take part in decision-making processes; to facilitate the
involvement of women’s organizations in the public policy process; to
increase public understanding in order to encourage action on women’s
equality issues; and to enhance the effectiveness of actions undertaken by
women’s organizations to improve the situation of women … The
principles, objectives and activities or organizations receiving funding from
the Women’s Program should support the attainment of women’s equality as
defined in the United Nations Convention on the Elimination of
Discrimination Against Women, the Federal Plan for Gender Equality, the
Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms and the Beijing Platform for
Action.81

Status of Women Canada organizes the annual International Women’s


Day, which always focuses on a specific theme. The theme of 2002, only a
few months after the terrorist attacks on New York and Washington, was
how to replace a global culture of violence with one of peace. In addition,
Status of Women Canada provides tool kits for every occasion that include
questions and answers about events, suggested videos about women, and
background information on women. They encourage women to e-mail their
friends and to put special messages on fax cover sheets, voice mail, web
sites, and computer screensavers, or in the pay envelopes of employees.
They urge women to put up posters, show videos, and hold brown-bag
lunches, so that women of all ages and backgrounds can discuss their
experiences in the battle for equality. In addition, the kits encourage women
to set up information fairs with displays about local or national
organizations and resources for women, and to interview women, present
shows or concerts, organize conferences or panel discussions, set up photo
or art exhibits, and, of course, raise funds. They ask teachers to lead student
discussions and organize projects about women. They … well, the list goes
on and on. The point is for women not only to copy and distribute these kits
but also, if possible, to come up with their own ideas. A list of coming
events across the country is always posted on the Internet. These events are
sponsored by government groups but also by local groups (mobilizing
against sexual assault, say, or domestic violence), universities, arts centres,
museums, political parties, religious organizations (notably the United and
Unitarian Churches), and so on.
Status of Women Canada provides tool kits, with posters, for an
additional annual event, the National Day of Remembrance and Action on
Violence against Women, which is held every year on 6 December. This
event was established by Parliament in 1991 to commemorate the day that
Marc Lépine, whom we discussed in chapter 4, murdered fourteen women
in Montreal. According to the website, it “represents a time to pause and
reflect on the phenomenon of violence against women in our society. It is
also a time to have a special thought for all the women and girls who live
daily with the threat of violence or who have died as a result of deliberate
acts of gender-based violence. Last but not least, it is a day for communities
and individuals to reflect on concrete actions that each of us can take to
prevent and eliminate all forms of violence against women.”82 The site
notes that members of Parliament will observe a minute of silence and urges
all Canadians to do the same and to signify their support for women by
wearing a white ribbon. The white-ribbon campaign, as we noted in chapter
4, provides an opportunity for male feminists to pledge their help in
educating other men about violence against women. As it does for
International Women’s Day, this site posts a schedule of activities occurring
across the country. Many of the same groups sponsor this event, but those
dealing with violence have a more prominent role than other groups. Also,
these events are more overtly religious than those associated with
International Women’s Day: candlelight vigils, memorial services, and even
pilgrimages to shrines such as the one on Decelles and Queen Mary Road in
Montreal and the one at Hawthorne Park in Vancouver. Some groups show
videos such as After the Montreal Massacre and Waking Up to Violence.83
Others encourage testimonials by women who have been abused.
No opportunity for political or ideological advocacy is lost. On its web-
site, Status of Women Canada tells academics doing studies on women how
to promote their research. It offers to disseminate results throughout the
federal government, distribute them to cabinet ministers, send them to
hundreds of libraries, develop fact sheets, and post everything on its web
site. The site tells visitors how to be “proactive” in communicating with
those who run the mass media and how to write a press release that
everyone will notice. Women should “dress it up to look and sound like
news,” make it appear urgent by faxing instead of mailing, and use a
“grabber headline.”84 The site explains how women can use advocacy
groups, the public relations departments of universities, and friends to
review their reports in policy journals. And it provides an extensive list of
publishers, web sites, research networks, and academic journals.
Remember, this group operates within the government and is funded by tax
dollars.
In appendix 12, we discuss a report titled “School Success by Gender: A
Catalyst for the Masculinist Discourse,” by Pierrette Bouchard, the primary
author, along with Isabelle Boily and Marie-Claude Proulx, that was
sponsored by and has been promoted by Status of Women Canada.85 It
describes the baneful effect of “masculinist discourse” on “progressive”
theories of education. (As we explain in a moment, “masculinism” is an evil
reversal of feminism.) Here now are a few comments on the status of the
report in strictly academic terms.
The report began as an investigation into the education of boys and girls,
but for a report that purports to represent the best of current scholarship in
the social sciences, this one is notable for its lack of methodological rigour.
It does have an academically respectable veneer, true, but as the authors
describe it, their method86 presents at least three problems. As we say in
appendix 12, the research question is overtly politicized. It assumes that
concern for the education of boys is tantamount to lack of concern (or
worse) for the education of girls. Moreover, the authors admit that they
expanded the scope of their research at some point from the education of
boys and girls to the more general topic of “the backlash against
feminism.”87 That might explain why their list of keywords for content
analysis includes not only “education,” “boy,” “girl,” “gender difference,
“academic success,” “men,” “male,” and “fatherhood” but also “violence”
and “suicide.”
Although this project began as research on the print media, it was
expanded at some point to include websites. The authors do mention this at
the end of a section on method,88 but they say nothing at all about the
method used for these websites. Compared to the authors’ rigorous (but
tendentious) analyses of print material, their analyses of the websites seem
highly impressionistic. The authors merely present readers with a few
misogynistic quotations, a few misogynistic cartoons, and then launch into
a discussion of using hate legislation to ban them. Although these items are
important,89 because expressions of hatred are always important, the
process by which they were selected is unacknowledged. The authors offer
no evidence that these items are pervasive or even common. Nor do they
make any attempt to distinguish between crankiness or rudeness and hatred.
And there is a difference. A big one.
Nor, of course, do they refer to feminist sites that use misandric
quotations and jokes. (We discuss some of those in appendix 9, but they are
by no means the nastiest; we chose them for subject matter rather than
style.) There is no reason to blame Bouchard and her colleagues for
confining their search to what men are saying about themselves or even to
what hostile things some of these men are saying about women in general
and feminists in particular. These are phenomena like all others and thus
worthy of research.90 There is a reason, however, to blame them for
deliberately creating the impression – they could hardly have done so
accidentally – that women are not doing precisely the same things on their
own websites: saying hostile things about the opposite sex. At no point, not
even once, do the authors either say or imply that women routinely engage
in the equivalents of everything that they scold the men in question for
doing: blaming them for every conceivable human problem; either stating
or insinuating that most (sometimes all) of them are guilty and deserve to be
ignored, ridiculed, or punished; and spreading theories developed by others
(without explaining why that would be problematic in the first place).
The report contains so many passages that betray double standards that
we must be content with one example here (and refer to others in appendix
12).

Toward the middle of the decade [the 1990s], we begin to see in the media
discourses that cast suspicion on female elementary teachers, single
mothers and feminists, blaming them for the problems experienced by boys.
A key element seen in this period is the emergence of a victimization
theme, in which boys are portrayed as being discriminated against by an
education system that has become a feminist environment. Co-educational
schools are challenged and, toward the end of the decade, we see systematic
links established to the male suicide rate, boys on Ritalin, fathers gaining
custody of their children, the suffering of male abusers, the loss of male
identity, false allegations of violence against men, etc.91
The information here is correct (except for the part about the suffering of
male abusers, which is made out to look like sympathy for people whose
behaviour is unacceptable but is actually nothing more than an explanation
for the origin of their behaviour). Yet readers would never know from this
passage that feminists were at that very moment developing an ideology
based on a conspiracy theory of history. It was in this climate that we
plunged into something approaching mass hysteria over satanic-ritual abuse
and recovered-memory syndrome. And, apart from anything else, that left a
cloud of suspicion over all male teachers, daycare workers, and fathers
(whether divorced or not).
According to many feminists, not only ideological ones, girls are the
victims of discrimination by an education system that has ignored them.
Some feminists have defended the continued existence of separate colleges
for women and separate schools for girls. Other feminists have advocated
separate sports teams for girls (even though they have refused to accept
separate teams for boys).92
The report’s failure to define its central concept undermines its academic
credibility. The word “masculinism” does not appear in its glossary of
technical terms, although it is explained in a note according to the usage of
Martin Dufresne, a feminist who writes in French.93 Readers are expected
to know that “masculinism” signifies an evil reversal of feminism, which is
why its main product is described invariably as a “backlash” against
feminism.94 The implication is that the only possible reason for anyone to
question feminist positions, or even merely to discuss the problems of
schoolboys, would have to be a nefarious one, which makes it clear that
“masculinism” has been created largely by feminists themselves. A useful
analogy would be the mediaeval Christian notion that witchcraft must have
been a sinister parody of Christianity and its “black sabbath” of the
eucharist, say, or the Christian notion of Judaism as a religion that revolves
around the blasphemous rejection of Christ. What could better illustrate the
close relation that we have identified in both this volume and in Spreading
Misandry between gynocentrism and misandry?
The “masculinism” discussed by Bouchard and her colleagues could be
described as an ideology,95 actually, in the Marxist sense: it involves hidden
assumptions about the way things are that allow a ruling class to perpetuate
its hegemony over other classes. By tacitly encouraging readers to assume
that “masculinism” is an ideology in the Marxist sense, the report tacitly
discourages readers from wondering if feminism is also an ideology in
some sense. That is why it refers over and over again to the “masculinist
discourse”96 (the latter word being postmodernist jargon, most often, for the
absence of any relation to reality at best and the presence of a sinister
conspiracy at worst).97 Using this word for the opposing position implies
also that it has no legitimacy whatsoever, that it is intended only to
hoodwink people and thus oppose the truth of feminism. This is ironic in
view of the fact that postmodernism claims to have exposed the folly of all
claims to objective truth. In theory, all of these claims can be – and should
be – “deconstructed.”98 In practice, there are exceptions. Postmodernists
use deconstruction only on whatever they dislike and want to destroy.
Consequently, the authors of this report refer to “masculinist discourse” but
“feminist knowledge.”99 Masculinism is by definition based on either
illusions or lies; feminism, on the contrary, is by definition based on truth.
(Just in case anyone fails to get the message, however, they often add words
such as “alleged,” or “seems” to the claims of their adversaries.)100
Like other ideologues, Bouchard, Boily, and Proulx do not consider
themselves bound by any requirement for either intellectual or moral
integrity. Otherwise, how could we explain a contradiction that is repeated
over and over again in their report? On the one hand, they insist on
aggregated data, on generalizations. On the other hand, they actually use
disaggregated data, which are broken down into categories that are defined
by context. Women benefit either way, as we explained in chapter 5,
because the disaggregated data show the specific contexts where men
dominate and therefore where affirmative action for women would be
helpful; the contexts where women dominate, though, are usually ignored.
At the same time, aggregated data generally show that women as a class are
behind men as a class; this provokes the demand for change.
Bouchard and her colleagues are very explicit about the “limitations of
the masculinist discourse on education,” one of the primary ones being
“generalization to an entire gender.”101 They claim that the “issue should be
framed in terms of gaps between the sexes, taking into account such facts as
social origin and family and cultural environment. Generalizations must be
avoided. It is also important to differentiate between school success,
educational achievement and social success, because they are not all the
same thing.”102 Even so, they continue in the very next sentence by
contradicting themselves. “The data … show that girls are still confined to
traditional areas of schooling, although they now graduate from university
in greater numbers.”103 Well, which girls? Girls with which origin, which
type of family, which cultural environment? They refrain from offering any
answers. The entire feminist project, after all, is based on precisely the idea
that generalizations can and should be made. Otherwise, how could they
argue that women are an oppressed class (one that transcends the economic
or other criteria that apply to some women but not others) and that men are
an oppressor class (one that likewise transcends economic or other criteria
that apply to some men but not others)?
Examples of this contradiction and the double standard on which it is
based occur not once or twice, please note, but throughout the report.104
It is a fundamental feature of the method, not a careless lapse. The
authors try to make two points: that boys in general have no serious
problems and that girls in general do. Sometimes, they bring out statistics to
support these claims. Failing that, they resort to what could be called
“globalization,” even though they explicitly condemn that phenomenon in
its economic sense. Okay, so girls in the industrialized world are doing well
in school. But girls in other parts of the world are not! Ergo, considering the
entire world’s female population, Canadian girls need all – not some or
even a great deal but all – of our compassion, research, and funding. This
tactic is out of place, to say the least, in a document that is intended to
advise and is paid for by the government of one heavily industrialized
country. Given this situation, no one should be surprised to find that the
authors of this report attack men’s groups for having the audacity to
demand government funding for research on men and projects that would
help men but demand it for themselves alone over and over again.
Even though this report began, as we have said, as an investigation into
the education of boys and girls, a very specific topic, its authors use all the
arguments that we have identified in this book as the all-purpose trump
cards of ideological feminists. Women have less power (whatever that is)105
than men. Women are paid less than men for the same or similar work.
Women do more unpaid work than men do. Women are more likely than
men to be poor. Whatever. It came as no surprise to us that this report on
education includes a long discussion of violence against women (even
though the statistics presented are contradicted by a study conducted by
another agency of the federal government, Health Canada)106 and ends with
a proposal for more censorship and more hate legislation.
At the heart of this mentality is what we call “comparative suffering”
(which we will discuss more fully, in connection with competitive suffering,
toward the end of Transcending Misandry): the pervasive belief that human
suffering (apart, perhaps, from purely physical suffering) can and even
should be quantified. As a result, segments of the population – segments
usually defined in connection with “identity politics” – come to be pitted
against each other in a relentless contest over which one suffers most and
thus deserves all of society’s compassion (let alone its tax dollars). So, who
suffered more? Jews who endured twelve years under National Socialism
and ended up in death camps? Or Africans who endured three hundred
years of slavery in America and another hundred of segregation? If you
believe that a morally acceptable answer can be given, then you believe in
comparative suffering. Although they never actually define “suffering,”
Bouchard and her colleagues clearly believe that women suffer more than
men and therefore feel entitled to demand a monopoly on sympathy (and
funding). Even so, their position is based on a nonsequitur. The fact that one
group suffers more than another, after all, does not mean that it should
enjoy a monopoly on public sympathy (or funding). They know this, and
even say so, but with the kind of disclaimer that is so out of sync with
everything else they say as to have no meaning. “We must resist attempts to
place male and female victims into a competition for resources or
credibility,” Frederick Mathews observed several years earlier. “We can no
longer afford the divisiveness along gender lines that permeates discussions
about male and female victims’ experiences. If we are to advance the anti-
violence movement at all in Canada, we have to move more toward ‘gender
reconciliation’ and away from the bullying of one another that passes for
advocacy in many public discussions.”107 Sure.
Throughout “School Success by Gender,” from cover to cover, is a belief
that the authors consider beyond question: that only girls and women are
victims. Many readers of the report, we hope, will ask why the authors find
it impossible to take the needs and problems of boys as seriously as they do
for girls. The thought does occur to them at one point, when they ask the
following questions: “[S]ocially, should attempting or committing suicide
create some hierarchy of concern? Can death or the desire to take one’s life
– man or woman – be ranked on a scale of importance?” But without
actually answering their own questions, they continue directly as follows:
“Masculinists stress this aspect to create a picture of the
discrimination/victimization of men in society without any ethical
consideration.”108 Throughout the report, in fact, these authors either
ridicule or condemn the very idea that boys or men might be victims in any
way. Moreover, they accuse those who assert it of perpetuating the
pernicious cult of victimization.109 (Never mind that women themselves
have been playing that very game, effectively, for decades and that women
were actually the pioneers.) Giving any consideration to the idea that boys
and men might be victims, even lesser victims, would be to ignore the
notion of male hegemony and its expression in a “masculinist discourse”
(which is to say, a patriarchal conspiracy). This belief had already been
challenged by Mathews in his report for Health Canada, The Invisible Boy.
Given the heavy rhetoric from Bouchard and her colleagues, it is worth
quoting Mathews at length – remembering that he wrote his report no fewer
than seven years earlier.

Male victims, like female victims before them, have encountered their share
of critics and detractors, people who refuse to believe them, ignore
prevalence statistics, minimize the impact of abuse, appropriate and deny
males a voice, or dismiss male victimization as a “red herring.” When
prevalence statistics are given for male victimization, it is common to hear
the response that the vast majority of abusers of males are other males, a
belief which is simply not true. This comment is usually intended to frame
male victimization as a “male problem.”110

Here is a serious moral problem. The fact that one man is injured by another
man does not mean that the former should be held responsible for his own
injury. That would be what feminists call “blaming the victim,” when the
victim is female.

In many respects, male victims are where female victims were 25 years ago.
Most of us forget the enormous opposition the women’s movement
encountered as women began to organize and claim a voice to speak against
violence and name their abusers/offenders. The services and supports that
exist presently for women were hard won and yet are still constantly at risk
of losing their funding. By comparison, there really is no organized male
victims “movement” per se. Males, generally, are not socialized to group
together the way women do, to be intimate in communication or see
themselves as caregivers for other males. In short, much of what male
victims need to do to organize a “movement” requires them to overcome
many common elements of male socialization, all of which work against
such a reality ever happening.”111

That was several years ago. Despite the psychological problem for men of
acknowledging vulnerability, more and more of them are willing to do so.
Some of them – not all of them, not even most of them, but some of them –
do so by expressing hatred toward feminists or even toward women in
general. Bouchard, Boily, and Proulx surely are correct about that.
Unfortunately, they do not understand the main reason for that hatred:
women who refuse to take them seriously as people. This does not mean
that women deserve hatred in return – hatred is inherently evil no matter
what the circumstances – but it does mean that women, the ones who
ridicule or ignore the claims of men, are part of the problem and that
feminists should clean up their own house.

Male victims walk a fine line between wanting to be heard and validated, to
be supportive of female victims and to be pro-woman, while challenging
assumptions they feel are biased stereotypes. Their challenges to some of
these stereotypes are often met with accusations that they are misogynists,
part of a “backlash” against feminism, or have a hidden agenda to
undermine women’s gains. If any of these accusations are true, they must be
confronted by all of us. But if they are based only on the fear that
recognition of males as victims will threaten women’s gains, then that is the
issue we should be discussing right up front, not minimizing male victims’
experiences in a competition to prove who has been harmed the most.
Nonetheless, it is important for all of us to recognize that it may be difficult
for many women to listen to male victims’ stories until they feel safe in this
regard.112
We have established in this chapter that ideological feminism, usually in the
guise of “women’s studies” (but sometimes in that of “gender studies” or
even “queer studies”), has had a profound impact on education and, in turn,
on those who are educated. Through many networks, ideological feminists
have contributed heavily to the gynocentric worldview that is now prevalent
in our society. Based on a feminist epistemology, it is preoccupied
exclusively with the needs and problems of women. In theory,
gynocentrism need not be misandric (just as androcentrism need not be
misogynistic). In practice, that is seldom the case. To the extent that this
worldview encourages citizens to ignore the distinctive needs and problems
of men, even if it refrains from overtly attacking them, we must consider it
a misandric one. The inevitable result is gynocentrism at best or misandry at
worst. Either way, scholarship is compromised by advocacy. What feminists
call “engaged scholarship,” in other words, is nothing more than feminist
ideology masquerading as scholarship.
Among the most troubling aspects of all this is the pervasive influence of
ideological feminism on law. In The Charter Revolution and the Court
Party, F.L. Morton and Rainer Knopff113 write that in the United States
during the 1960s,

the heyday of the Warren Court, there was a popular joke in American
universities about where to locate sovereignty in the U.S. The American
people seized sovereignty from King George III in 1776 and transferred it
to the Constitution in 1787. But since the Constitution has come to mean
only what the judges say it means, and since the judges say only what they
read in the Harvard Law Review, sovereignty in the U.S. now rests with the
faculty at the Harvard Law School. As recently as 1994, Mary Ann
Glendon (of Harvard Law School) confirmed the underlying truth of this
joke. Writing about the “powerful synergy [that] links the appellate
judiciary and the legal academy,” Glendon maintained that just as “[m]any
professors strive mightily to influence the course of judicial opinions, [so]
many judges reach out in their opinions to ‘constituents’ in the
professoriate.”114

Postmodernism, as everyone knows by now, has had as great an impact


on law schools as it has on departments of philosophy, religious studies,
literature, and so forth. In this particular field, it is often called “critical
literary studies” (CLS, an offshoot of Marxist Critical Theory).

The postmodernist contention that all knowledge is constructed found a


receptive audience among lawyers trained in the adversarial method of
argument. Constructing one-sided and self-serving accounts of conflicts is
what common-law lawyers are trained to do. Under the CLS banner
minority, multi-cultural, native, feminist, and gay-rights advocates have
deconstructed such traditional legal norms as judicial independence, judicial
impartiality, and the rule of law as nothing but disguises for class privilege,
racism, sexism, and heterosexism. By the 1980s, the ‘Crits,’ as they are
known, had become the dominant faction at the most prestigious American
law schools.115

We are not talking about isolated radical institutions, by the way, but about
truly mainstream ones. Morton and Knopff report that

[t]he prestigious Yale Law Journal recently published an article by Paul


Butler, a black law professor, who defended the right of black jurors to
ignore evidence and to acquit black defendants in non-violent cases as a
way of protesting racism in the criminal justice system.116 Patricia
Williams, a black law professor at Columbia University, has defended a
young black woman who made up a story about being raped by a gang of
white men. This lie was justified, Professor Williams argues, because “her
condition was clearly the expression of some crime against her, some
tremendous violence, some great violation that challenges comprehension.”
The lie was justifiable, the Columbia University professor continued,
because it “has every black woman’s worst fears and experiences wrapped
into it.”117

It would be hard to imagine a law school in the United States or Canada


that does not yet offer courses in feminist legal theory. Some publish
journals devoted exclusively to feminist law: Harvard Women’s Law
Journal; Women and Rights Law Reporter; Yale Journal of Law and
Feminism; Yale Journal of Law and Liberation; Berkeley Women’s Law
Journal; Cardozo Women’s Law Journal; Duke Journal of Gender Law and
Policy; Hastings Women’s Law Journal (from the University of California);
UCLA Women’s Law Journal; William and Mary Journal of Women and the
Law; Wisconsin Women’s Law Journal; New York University Review of Law
and Social Change; Women’s Law Journal of Legal Theory and Practice
(from the University of Pennsylvania); and University of Michigan Journal
of Law Reform. Some idea of the content can be gleaned from the mandate
of the Women’s Law Journal of Legal Theory and Practice, which is

to provide a meaningful forum for women’s and men’s voices on a variety


of issues surrounding women’s relationship to jurisprudence generally, and
to the practice of law specifically. Topics that will be addressed by the
Journal will include, but will not be limited to, the following: women
attorney’s experience in the workplace, in the courtroom, and in other
professional settings; how race, ethnicity, sexual orientation, disability and
spirituality affect women practitioners and their clients; balancing a legal
career with family; feminist lawyering; feminist legal theory; the history
and evolution of women lawyers and litigants in American jurisprudence;
and women’s narrative and creative expression of their experience in and
around the legal system.118

Writing in the Harvard Women’s Law Journal are feminist legal


luminaries such as Martha Minow, Catharine MacKinnon, and Andrea
Dworkin (even though she is not a lawyer). Here are the titles of some
articles: “Against the Male Flood: Censorship, Pornography and Equality”;
“‘To Give Them Countenance’: The Case for a Women’s Law School”; “A
Reasonable Battered Mother?: Redefining, Reconstructing, and Recreating
the Battered Mother in Child Protective Proceedings”; “Public Women and
the Feminist State”; “Race, Gender, and Social Class in the Thomas Sexual
Harassment Hearing: The Hidden Fault Lines in Political Discourse”;
“Anti-Stalking Laws: Do They Adequately Protect Stalking Victims?”;
“Single-Sex Public Education after VMI: The Case for Women’s Schools”;
“Rape, Genocide, and Women’s Human Rights”; “Comparable Worth in
Ontario: Lessons the United States Can Learn”; “Rape and Women’s
Credibility: Problems of Recantations and False Accusations Echoed in the
Case of Cathleen Crowell Webb and Gary Dotson”; “Melodrama and Law:
Feminizing the Juridical Gaze”; “Gender in Evidence: Masculine Norms v.
Feminist Reforms”; “Recognizing Violence against Women: Gender and the
Hate Crimes Statistics Act”; “Perspectives on Our Progress: Twenty Years
of Feminist Thought”; “Legal Limbo of the Student Intern: The
Responsibility of Colleges and Universities to Protect Student Interns
against Sexual Harassment”; “Feminism, Epistemology, and the Rhetoric of
Law: Reading Bowen v. Gilliard”; “Criminalizing the Exposure of Children
to Domestic Violence: Breaking the Cycle of Abuse.” Some issues even
have poetry with titles such as “I said, ‘No.’”119
Feminism in Harvard Law School, according to John Sedgwick, has
created a veritable war zone. In “Beirut on the Charles” he describes – no,
reveals – the rampant politics at one of the nation’s most prestigious
institutions that have

pitted faculty members against faculty members, faculty members against


students and, perhaps most viciously of all, students against students.
Relations have broken down so completely that Dean Clark recently
appointed Professor Emeritus Roger Fisher, the famed negotiator who has
attempted to reconcile Kuwait and Iraq, to act as a kind of marriage
counselor for the law school “community.” Few expect that he and the
faculty members working with him will succeed. “It’s a shark tank here,”
one student said. Harvard Law School is not the only law school that suffers
from such political tensions. “Diversity issues are in the air at all leading
law schools and all leading universities,” said Harvard Law’s Dean Clark
… But at Harvard, even if you don’t take a side, you are given one.
Everyone is typecast by his or her race, gender, sexual orientation and
political perspective, be it Left, Right or center. Such details are like being a
Virgo or a Gemini to an astrologer. They tell Harvardians everything they
need to know about someone. The personal is political at Harvard Law, and
the political is personal. Both can get nasty.120

Sedgwick traces the trouble, correctly, to CLS.

The current troubles may have drifted down to the students, but they started
with the faculty, back in the Seventies, with the battles over the Crits, or
Critical Legal Studies movement, led by lanky, boot-wearing Professor
Duncan “Funky Dunk” Kennedy. The Crits made the fairly strict Marxist
argument that, for all its attempts at justice, the law merely perpetuated the
interests of the ruling class. Kennedy laid out the philosophy in a small,
privately printed volume called Legal Education and the Reproduction of
Hierarchy, which was quickly nicknamed “Duncan’s Little Red Book” …
But even bad movies occasionally get remade, and, to many observers,
those issues of the current PC era that are uppermost in the minds of the
students are simply restylings of CLS’s neo-Marxism. Now, instead of
directly decrying the ruling class, the students pick at its racism, sexism and
homophobia. In fact, they invoke those terms so often and so loudly that
that troika might stand as Harvard Law’s holy trinity … Through an
organization called the Coalition for Civil Rights, the students went so far
as to sue the university for discrimination in faculty hiring, claiming that
their education has suffered due to the lack of minority and women
professors. The suit got as far as the Massachusetts Supreme Judicial
Court.”121

Here is Sedwick’s parting shot at Beirut on the Charles: “Many things


are distorted at Harvard Law, not the least of them gender relations. As I
looked around the Bow, it seemed to me that the women, for all their talk of
victimization, were the sexual predators in this ecosystem, and the men the
prey.”122
Much the same thing has happened in Canada. Canadian law schools
began to grow most rapidly, during the 1960s and 1970s, at the very
moment when political and ideological movements were becoming
prevalent in universities. “CLS was carried back to Canadian law schools by
the increasing number of law graduates choosing to do their LL.M’s at
Harvard and Yale rather than Cambridge or Oxford.”123

The new autonomy of Canadian legal education coincided with the triumph
of postmodernism among university-based intellectuals. Postmodernism
rejects the possibility of scientific or objective knowledge, claiming that all
knowledge is self-interested and reflects (and supports) unequal power
relationships based on class, gender, race, and so forth. It portrays the
political, legal, and cultural traditions of western civilization as the corrupt
legacies of “dead, white, heterosexual, male” privilege. For example,
deductive logic and concepts of evidence are often dismissed as
phallocentric modes of reasoning. Convinced of their own unique virtue and
the corruption of all who disagree or question, postmodernists fuel the new
reign of political correctness that has stifled intellectual freedom at
Canadian universities over the past decade … In Canada, the postmodern
angst has focused more on gender and sexual orientation than race.
Recently, however, the Canadian Bar Association released a report alleging
wide-spread racism throughout the legal system. A subsequent inquiry
revealed that the CBA’s finding was based not on reliable data, but on the
committee’s embrace of “critical race theory.”124

All of this has been supported by what Morton and Knopff call advocacy
scholarship (what ideologues call engaged scholarship and what we call
ideology). “While the simple view is that interpreting the Charter is the
responsibility of the judges,” they write, “the interpretive community is in
fact much broader and clearly includes legal academics … The burst of
advocacy scholarship that followed the adoption of the Charter was a
calculated component of Court Party strategy to maximize the political
utility of Charter litigation.”125 By 2002, 60% of the students in most law
schools were women. That in itself, given the heavily politicized orientation
of many, should be a good indication of things to come for men.

University-based intellectuals are at the heart of the postmaterialist left in


all Western democracies. They diagnose our social ills – racism, sexism,
heterosexism, etc. – and prescribe the cures. What distinguishes American
and now Canadian politics is the extent to which this new knowledge class
successfully pursues its agendas through litigation and the courts. The
consequent politicization of legal scholarship in Canada parallels – indeed,
emulates – post-war American practice … The process has not been
spontaneous and happenstance. In the U.S., “flooding the law review” with
favourable articles has been an established tactic of movement interest
groups … In Canada, it became part of an explicit strategy of influencing
the influencers adopted at the outset of the Charter era. It has been an
astoundingly successful strategy, in large part because it has been largely
unopposed. The legal commentators are all singing from the same hymn
book.126
Law schools are closely linked to advocacy legal groups. One major
player in feminist legal politics in the United States since 1972 has been the
National Women’s Law Center, a nonprofit organization based in
Washington, dc. It defines itself as follows: “The Center uses the law in all
its forms: getting new laws on the books and enforced; litigating ground-
breaking cases in state and federal courts all the way to the Supreme Court
… educating the public,” and so on.127 It has worked to improve conditions
for women in terms of money (enforced child-support programs, social
security), employment (high-quality child care, anti-harassment legislation,
affirmative action, equal pay, military jobs), education (educational and
athletic opportunities, anti-harassment policies, affirmative action), and
health (women’s-health report cards, family-planning programs,
reproductive-health services).

The National Women’s Law Center is supported by the Department of


Health and Human Services, foundations, corporations, unions, law firms,
and professional associations (such as the National Association for Public
Interest Law and the National Education Association). Its interest-group
orientation is clearly indicated on its web site, which invites women to
become informed about current debates and legislation, become involved
by contacting members of Congress, and join its e-mail alert network. The
National Women’s Law Center has litigated in several important cases. One
of these was Brentwood Academy v. Tennessee Secondary School Athletic
Association (2001),128 the result of which makes state athletic associations
provide equal opportunities for girls and boys. It monitors judgments in the
Supreme Court and warns women of their political implications. In 2001,
for instance, it noted that some protections for women were being cut back
and some challenges to women-friendly legislation were being defeated
only by slim margins. Women were told to get politically active and prevent
another conservative judge from being appointed to the Supreme Court,
because even one more could have a critical impact on “women’s
constitutional rights to privacy and equal protection, and the federal
statutory protection of women’s rights in employment, education, and
health, safety and welfare.”129
In Canada, the major feminist legal advocacy group since 1985 has been
the Legal Education and Action Fund (LEAF). Even though LEAF is a
nongovernmental and nonprofit organization, it was inspired by a report
issued by the Canadian Advisory Council on the Status of Women. This
report told feminists how they “could take advantage of the unique
opportunity provided by this forum [the Charter] to pursue social change
through litigation” and recommended “the establishment of a single
national fund, the direct sponsorship of (preferably winnable) cases, and a
complementary strategy of education and lobbying.”130 LEAF’s official
website defines its mission this way:

LEAF is a national, non-profit organization working to promote equality for


women and girls in Canada. Using the equality provisions from Section 15
of The Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms as a basis to advance
women’s rights, LEAF presents arguments, or intervenes, in cases where
women’s rights are at risk in Canadian courts…

At LEAF, we recognize the complex issues related to women’s rights, and


we know that, in an ever-changing society, the importance of these rights
must not be overlooked. That is why we believe strongly in working,
through the courts, to protect the rights of all women, of all ages, in
Canada, and in communicating to Canadians the scope of these Charter
equality rights.131
Because LEAF is a women’s organization, there is no reason for any
reference to the rights of men. Still, we should at least ask questions about
the rights of men. Christopher Manfredi argues that LEAF’s objective is

not merely to defend women’s legal rights, but to use legal action as a way
of advancing a favorable policy agenda. In the micro-constitutional political
arena of charter litigation, this meant occupying the equality rights field and
pursuing a secondary constitutional rule that equality must be given a
substantive, rather than purely formal, meaning. The problem with formal
equality, LEAF argued, is that its emphasis on equality of opportunity and the
neutral application of the law does nothing to compensate women for the
accumulated disadvantages of past exclusion. In order to be “truly” equal,
the law must be sensitive to the substantive differences in the economic,
social and political status of various groups.132

He goes on to note that LEAF’s strategy included the generation of


“respected theory,” or “engaged scholarship,” to ground the notion of
substantive equality. This was created by feminist law professors, including
LEAF founders such as Beth Atcheson, Marilou McPhedran, Elizabeth
Symes, Shelagh Day, Gwen Brodsky, Mary Eberts, and Lynn Smith.
Together, they produced more than thirty books and articles between 1981
and 1992.
Manfredi observes that “this literature tended to be proscriptive and
prescriptive rather than retrospective and descriptive, suggesting that the
feminist movement’s use of ‘legal literature is part of a long-run approach,
in which indirect influence in the form of shaping the climate of opinion’ is
the key objective.”133 The Canadian Journal of Women and the Law,
established by the National Association of Women and the Law in 1985,
greatly facilitated the publication of this legal literature. In the 1960s and
1970s, according to Manfredi, there were only fifty entries on the subject of
equality in the Index to Canadian Legal Periodical Literature. Between
1981 and 1992, there were 283.134
More than anything else, LEAF has been aided by the Court Challenges
Program. It began in the mid-1970s as a government agency to provide
financial assistance for important court cases, those that tested language and
equality rights guaranteed in the Charter, and thus to develop principles for
deciding when discrimination has occurred.135 Funding was provided for
research and consultation before cases went to court, for the actual process
of litigation, for research on the possible effects of court decisions, and for
strategic meetings to promote equality and facilitate access to it.136 Between
“1982 and 1991, LEAF received $1.4 million in general funding and at least
$84,400 to finance its intervener participation in six cases.”137 In fact,
federal and provincial sources amounted to about half of LEAF’s entire
budget.138

LEAF’s position has been adopted on 37 of 52 issues in the 31 Supreme


Court cases in which it has participated since 1988 … it has been the most
frequent non-government intervener in Charter cases, intervening in almost
ten percent of the Supreme Court’s Charter cases decided since 1988. LEAF
also accounts for about fifteen percent of all non-government interventions,
and appears in approximately one of every five Charter cases that attract at
least one intervener. Moreover, its success rate (71.2%) has been more than
twice as high as that of Charter claimants in general (30%).139

Manfredi concludes by discussing the reasons for feminist success in


Canada. First, a set of general interpretive principles that can be exploited
for specific litigation has been introduced. This makes it possible to bring
about policy changes and to develop strategic alliances with other groups.
(The Canadian Civil Liberties Association and real Women, a right-to-life
group, have been its only serious opponents.) Second, there are extremely
close ties with the Court Challenges Program (members sitting on its board
of directors, its advisory committee, and its equality panel), various human
rights tribunals with similar interests, university law schools, and women’s
organizations.140 Third, there is government support from both the Court
Challenges Program and Status of Women Canada (its own lobby group
within the federal government and provincial counterparts). Finally,
strategies have been developed by the United Nations. Canada, in turn, has
ratified documents produced by the United Nations. “Once LEAF was
established, it adopted a self-styled campaign of influencing the influencers
that included fostering supportive legal scholarship. LEAF organizers clearly
considered this to be much more than an academic exercise. ‘The shaping
of the Charter will be an intensely political process,’ Sheila McIntyre
explained to fellow feminists, [one that is] ‘far more responsive to public
pressure than [to] constitutional law.’”141
Throughout this analysis of equality legislation in Canada, we have
pointed out the judicial activism on the part of feminist interest groups. We
are now in a position to put their role in broader perspective. Morton and
Knopff define the “Court Party” as a coalition of groups that have promoted
judicial power over legislative power.

In addition to litigating on behalf of their respective policy agendas, Court


Party groups use the Charter in a variety of other ways. They employ the
Charter and its judicial glosses as symbolic resources in the normal course
of political lobbying. In an ongoing campaign of influencing the
influencers, they attempt to affect Charter interpretation through Charter
scholarship, the politics of judicial appointment, and judicial education
seminars after appointment. A well-organized group pursues the judicial
protection and expansion of its Charter turf on all of these fronts
simultaneously.142

The authors add that

In addition to legislative and financial resources, the Canadian state


provides the Court Party with a rapidly expanding rights bureaucracy. This
resource is what Les Pal describes as “positional support”: “access for some
groups and not others to information or to decision-makers or to a formal or
quasi-formal role in decision making … This new rights bureaucracy
includes courts themselves, of course, but also administrative tribunals,
human rights commissions, legal departments, law reform commissions,
law schools, and judicial education programs. Together, these constitute a
web of bureaucratic nodes for initiating, funding, legitimating, and
implementing the rights claims of Court Party interests.143

They note also that these equality players have affiliations with many
agencies. Ultimately, they accuse the universities.

In this chapter, we have argued that something has gone seriously wrong
with women’s studies. With respect to the history of women, a profound
change in scholarship has taken place over the last few decades.
Information on women was once much less widely available than it is now,
either because scholars were not interested in women, or because they
lacked access to women. Female informants might have been off limits to
male anthropologists. Or female accounts might not have been written
down. This history has now been reclaimed and the problems faced by
women exposed, thanks largely to the interest and tenacity of female
scholars. As a result of this scholarship, much of which is now done by and
taught by those in the field of women’s studies or by women in other fields,
our view of the world is more complex and nuanced.
But this field has been infiltrated – we dislike using that word but have
found no adequate alternative – by ideological feminists. They have tried
out several excuses for doing so: the alleged invisibility of women, the
alleged need for a social revolution, and even the allegedly flawed notion of
scholarship itself. They were cautious for a while but gradually realized that
they had no need for caution. They referred openly to “engaged
scholarship” and the need for partisan politics within the university or even
within the classroom. To the degree that female scholars considered
themselves a women’s political movement and wanted to improve women’s
role in society, they approved of this new dimension of women’s studies.
More recently, some have decided that scholarship and politics are
incompatible. A few have taken the risk of acknowledging that to be in
women’s studies means to accept not only gynocentric orthodoxy but also
ideological misandry.
Clearly, women’s studies has been turned into a front for feminist
ideology. How could there really be a front in the old Marxist sense?
Because gender has replaced class as the all-purpose explanation. And
because that change has coincided with the rhetoric of pluralism. And
because this ideological worldview has become so firmly entrenched in
popular culture that it is hard to stand back far enough to see the problem.
This takes us to the topic of our final chapter: a quiet revolution.
11
Misandry v. Equality: A Quiet Revolution
This is no simple reform. It really is a revolution. Sex and race because they
are easy and visible differences have been the primary ways of organizing
human beings into superior and inferior groups and into the cheap labour on
which this system still depends.1

God knows, in the last twenty-five years, man as “the enemy” has certainly
emerged [within feminism].2

The title of this book, like the first and third volumes of this trilogy,
includes the word “misandry.” We define “misandry” as hatred of men. It is
therefore the counterpart of misogyny, hatred of women. We showed in part
1 of this book that misandry has become acceptable in public debates
mediated by journalists, talk show hosts, academics, and other shapers of
public opinion. In the court of public opinion during the 1990s, men were
routinely stereotyped in connection with high-profile cases. They were
routinely attacked by feminist ideologues as a class of demons (“satanic
ritual abusers”), sexual abusers, sexual harassers, and mass murderers. Even
Karen DeCrow, former president of the National Organization for Women,
noticed the phenomeon. Hence the second epigraph for this chapter.
We shifted attention in part 2, though, from misandry to gynocentrism.
The latter, we said, is a worldview based on the implicit or explicit belief
that the world revolves around women. It is therefore the counterpart of
androcentrism, a worldview based on the implicit or explicit belief that the
world revolves around men. Our point was that gynocentrism has become
de rigueur behind the scenes in law courts and government bureaucracies,
which has resulted in systemic discrimination against men. This focus on
gynocentrism continued into part 3, where we examined the role of
academics in creating the new worldview.
In this brief concluding chapter, we tie up some loose ends by discussing
the relation between misandry and gynocentrism, the underlying premises
of ideological feminism with those things in mind, the strategies that
ideological feminists have used, ideological feminism as a revolutionary
world-view, and the link between this “quiet revolution” and earlier
revolutions.

Misandry and gynocentrism are not necessarily linked at all. People can be
preoccupied with their own needs and interests without denying those of
other people, much less hating them. And so it is, no doubt, for many
feminists. They want sexual equality, period. Other feminists are more
preoccupied with the problems faced by women, some devoting their lives
to the cause. These women are clearly gynocentric. But even they are not
necessarily misandric (just as androcentric men are not necessarily
misogynistic or, for that matter, just as Christians are not necessarily anti-
Jewish).3 But some women do become misandric (just as some men become
misogynistic and some Christians anti-Semitic). What transforms a
nonideological worldview into an ideological one is the presence of not
only essentialism (the focus on “us” and “our” virtues or needs) but also
dualism (the focus on “them” and “their” vices or just deserts). There is
nothing subtle about ideology, but there is something subtle about the ways
in which people adopt it. Dualism involves hatred, after all, and who
believes in that? No one. Certainly not consciously. Those who do hate,
therefore, must find ways not merely of justifying it or even excusing it but
of denying it even to themselves.
But wait. Even though misandry is not an inherent feature of
gynocentrism, it is an inherent possibility (just as misogyny is an inherent
possibility of androcentrism). If the world revolves around women, then it
follows that nonwomen – which is to say, men – are irrelevant except for
purposes of sexual pleasure (something that even some heterosexual women
are willing to forego on ideological grounds) or reproduction (which
requires nothing more than a “teaspoonful of sperm”). All it takes to
produce misandry is the ideological proposition that “they” are not merely
irrelevant but inadequate or evil. Women, including egalitarian feminists,
find it easy to scoff at those prissy critics who insist on pointing this out.
Unfortunately, they do so by ignoring history and what it reveals about the
human tendency to simplify problems by resorting to ideologies. That
tendency was present even among those who produced the biblical
tradition.4Not everything in that tradition is as lofty as the Book of Hosea,
say, or the Sermon on the Mount. Some sections are not so easily admired,
at least not today. According to the Old Testament, many ancient Israelites
had nothing but loathing for their “heathen” neighbours.5 According to the
New Testament, some early Christians had nothing but hostility for “the
Jews.”6
In theory, as we say, only gay women can take feminist ideology to its
logical conclusion: separation of women from men. Most women,
especially those with sons, are more willing to compromise. But, as we say
also, in connection with Daphne Patai’s theory of “heterophobia,” even
straight women sometimes find it expedient to support or at least tolerate
the latent separatism of feminist ideology. Implicitly or explicitly, directly
or indirectly, consciously or subconsciously, many women – not merely a
tiny minority of lesbians – either support or tolerate a movement that
deliberately fosters excessive fear of men (and fear of life in general)7 and
therefore the development of policies and laws intended to make the world
safe for women by discouraging contact with men. Even though misandry is
generated by an elite stratum of gynocentric academics, therefore, its
institutionalization presents all women (and therefore men) with serious
legal and moral problems. It is easy to recognize overt hatred and condemn
it but not so easy to recognize covert hatred and, given political conditions,
condemn it. Feminist ideologues have found ways of embedding misandry
in culture, ultimately in the form of law, without calling it that. Even men
find it hard to see systemic discrimination against themselves, although that
situation is changing, just as women once found it hard to see systemic
discrimination against themselves.

This book has identified one fundamental feature of the laws, American and
Canadian, that now govern relations between men and women: systemic
discrimination against men. By “systemic discrimination,” we refer to
several things.
First, legal discrimination against men is part of a pattern with deep roots
in culturally transmitted beliefs, not merely an isolated phenomenon.
Anyone who looks can see this pattern in laws governing affirmative action,
pay equity, maternal custody, child support, pornography, prostitution,
sexual harassment, and violence against women. In all cases, directly or
indirectly, men are identified exclusively as the villains (even though that
sometimes amounts, as in the case of affirmative action, to the villainy of
their ancestors).
Second, legal discrimination against men is pervasive, not merely a
collection of anomalies. The same arguments are used over and over again,
differing just slightly from one context to another. The most obvious
example is provided by those who believe that rape is only one extreme
point along a continuum, which begins with the mildest expression of
heterosexual interest and ends with murder.
Third, legal discrimination against men is the result of both conscious
and subconscious motivations. This is more complicated than it sounds.
Ideological feminists are certainly prejudiced against men, and they are
certainly aware that men are paying the price for legal changes that benefit
women. Some of them believe that men deserve to pay that price. Others
merely do not care. But most of the people involved in passing or
administering laws are not ideological feminists. They are not directly (or
even indirectly in some cases) motivated by hostility or indifference.
Egalitarian feminists care about society as a whole, at least in theory. Some
might genuinely care about men but not see any other way of achieving
their goals for women. Others might believe that men, given their godlike
power, cannot be seriously harmed in any case. And what about men
themselves, or at least those who have some say in what goes on? Some
male politicians care about nothing more than getting votes; if more women
vote than men, they might think, then so be it. Not very different are some
male academics or journalists and other public figures; for whatever
personal or professional reason, whether cynical or altruistic, they want the
approval of women and look the other way when considering the cost for
men. The result is a mentality that accepts systemic discrimination against
men. Almost anything can be said about men or done to men, in short,
without the expectation of a public outcry. Only now is that mentality being
questioned and even challenged.
The premise that underlies systemic discrimination against men is that
women need to be protected from the power of men in every aspect of daily
life. And underlying that premise are the various characteristic features of
feminist ideology. We have discussed them several times in this book but
find it worthwhile to summarize them now in connection with the specific
topics under discussion here.
Essentialism and dualism are really two sides of the same coin; each
implies the other. Essentialism is about “us,” dualism about “them.” In
other words, “we” as a class are good (victims), and “they” as a class are
evil (oppressors). Both are most clearly revealed, simultaneously, in
ideological discussions about child custody. Ideological feminists classify
fathers routinely as people who should not be trusted with children (and are
not needed by children in any case, except for support payments). At the
same time, they classify mothers routinely as people who should be. Forced
to choose in the interest of children, they claim, the law should side with
mothers and against fathers. Even when they do not feature essentialism,
though, ideological feminists do feature dualism. Every topic that we have
discussed in this book is founded on the premise that women are innocent
victims who must use legal measures to curb the oppressive and
overwhelming power of men. In every case, according to ideological
feminists, the problem is not merely a legal anomaly but a legal principle
that is rooted ultimately in a clash between two irreconcilable worldviews.
And the worldview of women (along with political allies), they claim, must
destroy that of men. They make this point most dramatically in connection
with violence against women, of course, but they make precisely the same
point in connection with sexual harassment and even pornography.
The other characteristic features of ideology follow from those two and
are all closely interrelated. Hierarchy, for instance, is a logical result. If
“we” are good and “they” are evil, after all, then it follows that the former
rank higher in a moral hierarchy than the latter do. In a democracy,
especially one that is based increasingly on opinion polls, that gives “us” an
enormous political advantage over “them.” One likely result, as we have
already suggested with regard to identity politics in general and affirmative
action in particular, is the development of a caste system (or, if you prefer,
the replacement of one caste system with another). One result of dualism is
selective cynicism: adopting a cynical attitude toward “them” (but not
toward people like “us”). Even though the most ideological of feminists
would admit that not all men are likely to beat their wives and molest or
abandon their children, they have shifted the burden of proof. Men are
guilty, in this moral universe, unless proven innocent. In that case, why not
try to change divorce and custody laws accordingly?
Ideological feminism is a collectivist movement, which is why adherents
make claims about women (or men) as a class. They must explain away
individual women who disagree with this or that claim – and there are many
in some cases – as the victims of “false consciousness” and thus the dupes
of men. This is certainly what happens in connection with pornography.
Ideological feminists make it clear that women who tolerate or even
approve of it are beneath contempt, female Uncle Toms. Because
collectivist movements care about classes of people, not about the fate of
any individual, they embrace an ethic of consequentialism. And because the
end justifies the means in connection with the fate of individuals, it does so
in connection with the fate of classes as well. Consider the arguments in
favour of affirmative action or pay equity. Sure, say feminists (and not only
ideological ones), these programs discriminate against men. But that means
is justified, they add, by its noble end: creating a “level playing field.” They
use the same rationale, at least privately, to justify the scams that we have
discussed in connection with statistics abuse. Okay, they might admit when
cornered, so lying to the public and even to government officials is wrong.
Sort of. But, they might add to themselves and their supporters, doing so is
justified in light of the struggle to improve things for women. And once the
deed is done, it can never be undone; phony statistics continue to do their
job, still cited repeatedly and still embedded in public consciousness, no
matter how hard anyone tries to challenge them. When repeated like
mantras, they create their own reality.
Three more characteristic features of ideological feminism (or any other
ideology) should be discussed together, because they are three aspects of
the same thing. Revolutionism is about using power, whether physical or
legal, to force society into radically new directions. This characteristic
explains the impatience of ideological feminists with reform, which they
regard as an obstacle in the way of revolution. In universities, they
campaign not merely for the admission of new ideas about women (and
men) but also for the replacement of one epistemology with another.
Without that, they believe, women will be confined to tinkering with this or
that reform; the new world will never be born. And utopianism is the belief
that humans can remake this world to such an extent that the result really
would be, in effect, a new world. In this new world, women would no
longer be faced with violence from men. Moreover – and this is the sine qua
non of utopianism – they would no longer be faced with any limits at all to
personal freedom or fulfillment. (We say “personal,” because collectivism
would no longer be necessary; having achieved their class goals, women
could end the class struggle against men.) Women would no longer have to
choose between children and careers, for instance, and no longer have to
endure the slightest emotional discomfort in the presence of men. In fact,
they would no longer have to live with men at all; this would be a utopia for
women, not for women and men. Knowingly or unknowingly, this is why
some feminists have pushed for laws and policies that separate the sexes by
making heterosexual interactions, including the most harmless words or
gestures, increasingly perilous for men. As for quasi-religiosity, this is the
ultimate context of “heterophobia.” It is surely no accident that some of the
phenomena associated with ideological feminism are strongly reminiscent
of overtly religious ones. Consider only some of the most obvious ones that
we have discussed in this book: Take Back the Night parades, for instance,
and memorials for the victims of Marc Lépine. These events are overtly
secular, at least in most cases, but they are covertly religious in several
important ways. For one thing, they draw heavily on religious prototypes
(liturgies, say, or pilgrimage shrines). Moreover, they focus on collective
identity and collective mission. In short, they generate an emotional
intensity that can be compared legitimately only with overtly religious
events.

Theory is one thing, reality another. How have feminists, especially those of
the ideological kind, actually achieved their goals so effectively? What have
their characteristic strategies been? To produce the pattern of systemic
discrimination against men (even as a by-product) and to represent its
underlying premise (along with the premises that underlie that), ideological
feminists have had to invent or refine several specifically legal strategies.
We can identify at least five distinct types.
One type of strategy involves defining or redefining a problem so that it
has ideological significance and political power. It is true that some of the
legal changes demanded by feminists over the past several decades
originated in problems that they faced by entering both higher education
and the work force in massive numbers for the first time. But some of them
originated in the emotional confusion of heterosexual relations at a time of
rapid change. To establish these legal changes as legitimate solutions to
bona fide problems, feminists have exploited ambiguity in their definitions.
Even when quantitative information is available, though, it can be
manipulated. Some feminists have used aggregated statistics, for instance,
which have skewed the results to support their claims. Others have
fabricated statistics. Even academic feminists have indulged in statistics
abuse by publishing false statistics in professional journals, often
specialized ones that are accountable only to feminist editorial boards.
Having defined or redefined problems ideologically, these feminists have
had to get them onto the agendas of justices and legislators. This goal has
always involved the mobilization of resentment. Like all other activists,
they have made effective use of the mass media. They have appeared on
talk shows, for instance, and written for popular magazines. Almost made
to order for this purpose have been highly sensationalized trials about child
abuse (the McMartins), domestic violence (Lorena Bobbit and O.J.
Simpson), sexual harassment (Clarence Thomas), mass murder (Marc
Lépine), and so on. Public debate over cases of this kind has not only raised
the consciousness of women (and many men) but also politicized the legal
process more than ever.8
This strategy would have been inconceivable without the prevalence of
identity politics. Ideological feminists have usually relied on public
perceptions about the vaunted power of men and therefore on the rhetoric of
either victimology (defining women as a victim class) or demonology
(defining men as an oppressor class) – or both. They have sometimes relied,
however, on the distinctive vulnerability of men. Because men have
traditionally seen themselves – and have been seen by society – as
protectors of women (and children), feminists have found it easy to shame
men into accepting whatever is allegedly necessary to protect women (and
children). Moreover, most men are still adept at maintaining a “stoical”
attitude: not complaining when attacked, especially by women. Feminists
have found, not surprisingly, that most men would at least keep quiet about
their own victimization by “gendered analysis.”
To be successful, these feminists have had to expand their networks on a
continuing basis. A few radical activists can do very little, but an army of
angry citizens can do a great deal. Elected officials cannot afford to ignore
them. Even appointed officials, in many cases, must be confirmed by
government bodies that are responsive to political movements (a fact that
Clarence Thomas learned the hard way). With all that in mind, feminist
ideologues have taught women how to be politically savvy, how to “get
things done” in legislatures, how to initiate e-mail campaigns, how to
contact journalists and political representatives, how to arrange press
conferences, how to organize boycotts or petitions, how to raise money for
worthy causes, how to shame or intimidate the men who run legal or
political institutions, and so forth. Among the most important way of
expanding feminist networks, however, has been to infiltrate institutions.
Working within the political system, ideological feminists have managed
to create special bureaucracies for women that have functioned as advocacy
organizations operating within the government itself. In addition, they have
fostered the appointment of feminist lawyers to human rights tribunals at
various levels of government. These tribunals can now force government
departments to create laws that suit women or to implement them more
effectively.
Not all women vote for feminist or feminist-influenced candidates.
Ideological feminists would still have had a hard time, therefore, without
cultivating other segments of the population. To ensure that they will
always have a majority, feminists have made alliances with minority groups
under the banner of “diversity” or “multiculturalism” (even though the main
beneficiaries have always been women). As a result, the process of
legalizing gynocentrism (with its shadow of misandry) has taken on a life of
its own in city councils, state or provincial legislatures, federal
governments, and international organizations such as the United Nations.
Ironically, some feminist ideologues have probably been disappointed to
find that women are not always losers and men not always winners
(although not one would ever admit that). When women at home are doing
well, therefore, feminists often emphasize the deplorable condition of
women in other parts of the world. Who would care about what happens to
American or Canadian men in universities, after all, when the women of
Afghanistan or Iran are excluded even from elementary schools? Never
mind that elected officials here are responsible for making laws that affect
their own citizens, including men, and not for laws that affect the citizens of
other countries.
Ideological feminists have become major players in our legal systems as
researchers, lawyers, judges, and bureaucrats. Not surprisingly, they have
come up with several specifically legal strategies: ways of using the law to
serve the interests of women.
One obvious strategy is to create new laws. To do this, they have
sometimes referred proposed legislation from lower to higher
administrative levels, federal laws having more status than state or
provincial ones and criminal laws having more status than civil ones.
Sometimes, though, they have referred proposed legislation from higher
administrative levels to lower ones, national governments having more
clout at home than international organizations. They have done that
surreptitiously by coaxing their governments to sign international treaties
with conservative riders, or opt-out clauses, but later coaxing them to
abandon those riders and join the “progressive” world. Recently, the World
Court gave feminists a “vagina dentata.” No, not the Freudian metaphor
about neurotic fear of an imaginary threat. This is a real threat, one with
“teeth”: taking legal action against recalcitrant governments.
Another strategy is to change constitutions or reinterpret existing ones.
Ideological feminists in Canada have managed to get protections for women
written into the nation’s Charter of Human Rights and Freedoms, which is
attached to the Constitution. American feminists have lobbied hard for the
Equal Rights Amendment but have not yet been successful. Even so, they
have been able to reinterpret constitutional amendments through court
challenges, reinterpreting the Fourteenth Amendment to include special
protections for women, say, or the Commerce Clause to regulate child
support and pornography.
These feminists have used several additional legal strategies, including
biding their time by lobbying for incremental changes (creating very broad
and ambiguous definitions and then adding greater specificity for women
by means of court challenges or linguistic inflation); shifting negative rights
to positive ones (from equality of opportunity, based on the negative right to
freedom from discrimination, to equality of result); changing strict
standards for legal tests, which assess the constitutionality of laws, to
moderate ones; creating new standards (replacing the “reasonable person”
with the “reasonable woman,” objectivity with subjectivity, reason with
feeling, damage with discomfort); exploiting emergency situations to give
women the benefit of any doubt (police interventions, for instance, before
charges are laid); bypassing due process in the interest of quick processing
(establishing special courts, for example, that lack the usual safeguards);
exploiting exceptions to establish new norms, even though doing so creates
double standards (creating modified equality of opportunity, with special
protections for pregnant women, and then expanding it to argue for equality
of result); and encouraging change by establishing bureaucracies and
industries to implement, reinterpret, and extend the law or its quasi-legal
version of codes and policies into all institutions (universities, corporations,
government departments – you name it – which are either bribed with
financial “incentives” or intimidated with specific penalties).
Yet another strategy is returning to the barricades. When people do
notice and protest the legal revolution – those who do are often men,
because gynocentric legislation discriminates against them – they are
immediately attacked as “masculinists,” shamed into conformity, or sent for
“reeducation,” “sensitivity training,” or whatever it might be called. When
all other strategies fail, ideological feminists have pulled out their trump
cards: “violence against women,” the “glass ceiling,” and “backlash.” They
have always realized that few people would be willing to challenge what
has long been presented as conventional wisdom, even though the statistics
that support them are sometimes skewed or even fabricated.
Although these strategies have not always worked the first time, they
have gradually had a massive effect on the legal systems of both the United
States and Canada.
Why do many people still find it hard to see the magnitude of these
changes? Because they have been disguised. Ideological feminists have
hidden behind various fronts. Some of these fronts have been linguistic,
mainly euphemisms: human rights, parental rights, or even children’s rights
fronting for women’s rights; equality for superiority; gender balance or
equity for affirmative action; gender-based analysis for feminist analysis;
gender studies for women’s studies; women’s studies for feminism; targets
for quotas; diversity for uniformity; and reform for revolution. Other fronts
are more than linguistic (postmodernism being a front for ideologies, for
instance, and pluralism for essentialism). These fronts cannot, actually, be
separated so easily. They all rely heavily on rhetoric, which takes on a life
of its own; euphemisms become integrated in a worldview that presupposes
them. Ideological feminists have hidden also as insiders. They have
infiltrated institutions such as government bureaus, human right’s tribunals
(which can trump government departments), the mass media, and
professional societies by demanding that more women – that is, feminists –
be appointed.

All of this amounts to a cultural revolution, we suggest, not merely the


inevitable drift caused by “change.” It might be tempting to dismiss us as
alarmists and thus not so different from the ideologues we are attacking
were it not for the fact that feminists themselves often discuss their
movement in overtly revolutionary terms. Hence this chapter’s first
epigraph, by Gloria Steinem. For ideological feminists, “revolution” has
exclusively positive connotations. You need not actually join a Goddess
cult, after all, to believe that the most important historical change since the
origin of patriarchy has been the advent of a movement to overthrow it.
That idea could be accepted by liberal feminists (who believe that the
elimination of gender distinctions will make true equality possible for the
first time in history) almost as easily as by ideological feminists (who
believe that the destruction of patriarchy will initiate a return to paradise).
Even the nineteenth-century suffragists, most of them very respectable
members of society, considered their movement the harbinger of a new era.
They argued that giving women the vote would provoke a radical break
with the past and usher in a new golden age of peace, harmony, justice,
connectedness, or whatever.
On this, at least, we agree with ideological feminists. Their movement
has indeed been revolutionary. We disagree only on our evaluation of that
revolution. If equality had remained the chief goal of feminists, it would
have continued and enhanced the liberal revolution that began, falteringly,
more than two hundred years ago. But equality has not remained the goal of
all feminists. Some of them, fewer in number than egalitarian feminists but
greater in influence by the late twentieth century, have moved considerably
beyond political equality in connection with “life, liberty, and the pursuit of
happiness” or, in the Canadian version, “peace, order, and good
government.” What they want, and what they are in the process of
achieving with the support of their allies and under the protection of
postmodernism, is either utopian or dystopian, depending on your point of
view: a radical reorganization of society, one that requires either writing
new constitutions or reinterpreting current ones in ways that would have
seemed not merely dangerous but unintelligible to their original authors,
certainly those of the eighteenth century.
There is something quasi-religious about secular, political, ideologies, as
Mircea Eliade observed decades ago. Mark Cimini argues that ideological
feminism functions as a religion, as the functional equivalent of Christianity
or any other traditional religion. He argues in addition, however, that the
American government supports this religion – it not only legislates but also
taxes citizens on that basis – and therefore breaches the wall of separation
between church and state.9
Ideological feminism must therefore be discussed as a revolutionary
movement in the same sense as the movements that produced other radical
revolutions – in France, Russia, Germany, China, and so on. How did we
get here? No revolution comes out of the blue or for any one reason. We all
passed history tests in high school by writing about the many causes of this
or that revolution and how they converged at a particular moment in
circumstances that might otherwise have had no importance. And so it is in
this case.
Like many revolutions, this one originated not with those who had the
most to gain economically but with those who had most to contribute
intellectually. In short, it originated among the members of an educated
elite. They were in college during the 1960s, absorbed the Marxist tradition,
and then modified it to suit their own needs. Even though women were
dissatisfied with the lack of respect they found in neo-Marxist, or New Left,
circles, they found that this environment provided them with valuable tools.
Among the most valuable were literary and critical techniques, known
collectively as “critical theory,” established by the Frankfurt School of
Marxism. Out went old-style rabble rousing among the workers (who were
growing fewer due to economic changes, in any case, and played hardly any
role in the new movement). In came clever, sophisticated, hermeneutical
critiques of bourgeois and especially of patriarchal culture. The movement
prevailed only among students, at first, because only they could understand
the critiques (or had time to study them). By the 1980s, though, many of
those students had become “tenured radicals.”10 Eventually, they became
heads of departments or lawyers, judges, and politicians.
By the 1990s, this revolution had entered a new phase that was made
possible by the Internet. No longer were ideological points of view on either
side of the political spectrum limited to a few initiates at universities and
their immediate social or professional networks. Websites welcomed
everyone. And just as ordinary people began investing eagerly and heavily
in the stock market, ordinary people began reading and responding to what
they found on the Internet. Many observers warned of websites produced by
right-wing ideologues, who were obviously dangerous because of their
ignorance, and the population at large. Few warned of websites produced by
left-wing ideologues who were anything but ignorant. Some feminist
websites spread information that all women (and many men) found useful
in their quest for reform in the interest of equality. Others spread
information that ideologues found useful in their quest for revolution in the
interest of something other than equality (though usually in the name of
equality). A public debate emerged over the government’s role in
monitoring the Internet, true, but only in connection with pornography and
right-wing hate literature; no one ever went after sites purveying the hate
literature of ideological feminists.
After the collapse of communism in Eastern Europe (and its unofficial
collapse in China), Marxism per se declined. But neo-Marxism morphed
directly into postmodernism. Many aspects – its focus on the problem of
“hegemony,” say, and the need for “unmasking,” “exposing,”
“deconstructing,” and other forms of “subversion” – remained unchanged.
It could be argued in addition that neo-Marxism morphed indirectly into
ideological feminism and several closely related ideologies on the political
left. It took very little imagination to replace the word “bourgeoisie” with
“patriarchy” and “class” with “gender.”
Despite all the rhetoric and techniques derived from neo-Marxism, not
all ideological feminists make the connection with neo-Marxism. And with
good reason. Another factor sometimes hides it. Marxism, both old-style
and new-style, can be traced back to the Enlightenment and its dream of
creating a utopia based on reason. But some feminists rejected the part
about reason, which, they argued, was inherently “male.” Their search for a
female essence led them to neo-Romanticism and its dream, when applied
to the collectivity and taken to its logical conclusion, of creating a utopia
based on nation or race. In one notorious case, this was called “blood and
soil.” Ideological feminists replaced both “class” and “race” with “gender.”
The result is thus an ironic marriage (you should pardon the patriarchal
expression) of both the Enlightenment and Romanticism.
Long before the turn of the century, ideological feminists were earning
graduate degrees and becoming university professors. But just as the civil
rights movement had been overtaken by the black power movement slightly
earlier, egalitarian feminism was overtaken in the universities by
ideological feminism. Integration was definitely not the goal. It was
separatism of one kind and degree or another. With that in mind, new
programs were established within old departments and, best of all, new
departments or even new “disciplines” were established. The most
important were women’s studies, gender studies, or queer studies (fronts, as
we say, for feminist ideology or closely allied gay ideology) and cultural
studies (a front for closely allied postmodernist doctrine). For various
reasons, mainly political ones – no university wanted to be seen as anti-
women, for instance, because so many women were entering as students –
these new disciplines were left largely immune to academic criticism. Even
as other feminists have rejoiced in the successful entry of women into every
sphere of life, ironically, ideological feminists in universities have nursed
grievances and mobilized resentment. And they have taken their revolution
to the streets, as it were, by training ideologically motivated cadres of
lawyers, journalists, social workers, social scientists, statisticians,
bureaucrats, psychologists, and therapists who have created the industries
that focus on child support, sexual harassment, and so on – with their vested
interests.
As we have said repeatedly, not all feminists are ideologically oriented,
not necessarily even in universities. Most women surely prefer integration
to separation, in fact, and reform to revolution. So how can we explain the
success of ideological feminists? And they have been astonishingly
successful, by the way, if success is measured in terms of legislation and
bureaucratic sleight of hand.
For one thing, most citizens – both women and men – are likely to
support what is clearly in their own interest. And this is appropriate, by and
large, in any modern democracy. Legislation to mandate affirmative action
or prevent sexual harassment, for instance, is seemingly in the interest of all
women (although the latter will increasingly be in the interest also of men
who work for women). The fact that this legislation can be motivated by
something other than the desire for justice or belief in egalitarianism, that it
can have either unintended or undesirable effects, is not disturbing enough
to prevent most women from supporting it anyway. In numbers and
solidarity, after all, there is strength. And if the drive for new legislation
comes from ideologues, even those who sometimes say or write loony
things, so be it. What matters, many believe, is that all women stand to
benefit in the long run from anyone who expands public perceptions of
what women can do. Very few women or even feminists would agree with
much of what Andrea Dworkin says, but even fewer would be willing to
denounce her promotion of hatred. On the contrary, most would rather
apologize for her as someone who nonetheless “pushes the boundaries” for
women.
Moreover, modern democracies are governed largely according to public
opinion. And public opinion in our society supports altruistic rhetoric, at
least in theory. Even though democracies explicitly encourage citizens to
vote on the basis of their own needs, after all, they also implicitly encourage
citizens to consider the needs of society as a whole. Many are swayed by
the ideals of justice and tolerance – today, these ideals are often known as
“pluralism,” “diversity,” and “multiculturalism” – which might or might not
coincide with personal or group self-interest. And feminists have been very
effective in causing citizens, except for those who overtly oppose feminism,
to equate their movement with justice and tolerance (an equation that is
usually correct in the case of egalitarian feminism). Not surprisingly, they
equate opposition to these ideals with tyranny. Feminist policies are
explained in ways that promote, or seem to promote, both justice (even
though that is often confused with revenge) and tolerance. Many women
sincerely identify themselves with these ideals. So do many men, for that
matter, including white men.
Who is going to argue, in public at any rate, that there could be anything
wrong with “equity,” a term derived from the exalted rhetoric of human
rights and used in connection with civil rights for women, black people, gay
people, and all other people who have experienced prejudice or
discrimination? The ability to examine it in connection with specific claims
and specific proposals by specific political organizations or leaders,
unfortunately, is not one that our society has cultivated. Even universities
now encourage the deconstruction only of “traditional” ideas or institutions;
others are granted privileged status and thus immunity to challenge.
This brings up the strategic alliance between ideological feminists and
ideological gay people. The alliance was hardly inevitable for gay men.
They could have tried to ally themselves with other men. Not all men’s
movements were receptive to gay men, true. But not all women’s
movements were open to gay women – in fact, not even all gay women
were open to gay men or any other men – and that never discouraged
lesbian feminists. Nonetheless, many gay men found it politically expedient
to ride on the coattails of ideological feminists. Because feminists had
already argued that women suffered under the gender system of patriarchy,
all they had to do was show that gay men (and gay women) suffered just as
much or even more under the same system. The alliance with feminism was
almost inevitable for gay women. Much more easily than other women,
they could take feminism to its ideological conclusion: separation from
men.
Of importance here, though, is the mere fact that this alliance has made
political sense. Two or more groups making the same arguments and
demanding the same measures, after all, greatly strengthen the position of
each. This is how “identity politics” works. Although any one group might
have little in common with the others, all have at least one important thing
in common: hostility toward whatever is considered the “dominant” or
“traditional” culture. As the ironically traditional proverb has it, the enemy
of my enemy is my friend.
In some ways, our society really is more tolerant than it once was. Very
few people today would actually want to restore institutionalized
discrimination against black people, gay people, or women. (In other ways,
as we have shown in this book, our society tolerates and even demands
institutionalized discrimination.) But more than tolerance is involved in the
success of ideological feminism. The political lingua franca of our time is
spoken only by those who claim to be victims. And this language, in turn, is
tied up inextricably with emotionalism – that is, the glorification of emotion
at the expense of reason.
Emotionalism, no less than nationalism and ethnocentrism, is clearly the
direct descendant of Romanticism (although emotionalism, unlike
nationalism and ethnocentrism, derives also from evangelical
Protestantism).11 But the current popularity of emotionalism cannot be
explained entirely in that way. For one thing, it has been aggressively
marketed by a consortium, as it were, of therapeutic industries. Pop
psychology both dominates and permeates many fields, most obviously the
field of entertainment. Daytime talk shows focus explicitly on therapy.
“Reality shows” reward contestants for screaming about their emotional
pain, weeping over their abuse, and revealing their most intimate feelings.
Crime shows provoke unrealistic fear. Like sitcoms, most pop songs rely
exclusively on sentimentality. Other songs satisfy the desire for
“empowerment” by expressing rage and fostering resentment. Think of
journalism. “In your face” news shows dominate the ratings. Advocacy
replaces objectivity as the goal. And what about the courts? Victims give
dramatic speeches in court to influence sentencing. Crusading ideologues
argue that angry or fearful victims of domestic abuse are not guilty if they
resort to murder. Others have reversed the principle of “innocent unless
proven guilty” in connection with charges of sexual harassment. And the
legislatures? They redefined marriage to bolster the self-esteem of gay
people. Education? Reformers institute regulations designed to promote
both personal and collective self-esteem at the expense of scholarship.
Public life? People demand extravagant mourning for celebrities. Political
correctness becomes a way of bolstering collective self-esteem. Officials
give public apologies for brutal events or institutions that ended decades or
even centuries earlier. Lobby groups define themselves in connection with
collective victimization. Politicians claim to “feel your pain.” Officials base
policies on public opinion, rather than any coherent philosophy. And
ecclesiastical authorities revise or reinterpret liturgies that function
primarily to provide group therapy or “build community.”
At the same time, as we say, feminist ideologues have promoted
essentialism – especially the idea that women are innately guided more by
feelings or intuitions, not ideas, and are therefore superior to men – by
using the front of pluralism. Whether emotionalism in our time originated
in the personal self-indulgence fostered by popular culture or the collective
self-indulgence fostered by elite culture is debatable. The point is that these
two phenomena are interdependent; each feeds on the other (and both on
the anti-intellectual legacy of Romanticism). They make it easy and even
necessary to couch all political claims in the rhetoric of victims (who
deserve sympathy for their current or historic suffering) and victimizers
(who deserve contempt).
All these things are happening at the same time, moreover, as unusually
rapid social, economic, and technological change. Which came first, the
chicken or the egg? It makes no difference for our purposes here. What does
matter is the resulting stress, which leads directly, as it often has throughout
history, to scapegoating and moral panics. People not only want but also
need to identify the source of their anxiety and thus regain a sense of being
in control over what would otherwise have to be understood as the random
forces of a chaotic universe. The source of severe problems is seldom easy
to identify correctly, though, because it is usually complex and ambiguous.
These problems often have many causes, not just one. And some of them
originate within ourselves as individuals or communities, not among those
who can be considered outsiders. Western societies, like many others, have
inherited a long tradition of dualism: seeing life in terms of good versus evil
and, not coincidentally, “us” versus “them.” Once “they” have been
identified with evil and threat, a process backed up these days by
ambiguous or even bogus statistics, it makes sense to use the law
accordingly. And if constitutions get in the way of new legislation, having
been written in naive or misguided times, then existing laws can be
reinterpreted or implemented in appropriate ways by judges and bureaucrats
on the advice of experts in the social sciences. It could be argued cynically,
in fact, that these experts are produced by professional industries with
vested interests in continuing social problems. The more problems that
remain unsolved, after all, the more jobs for experts.
But in what sense is this a quiet revolution? The term “quiet revolution”
originated in Quebec during the 1960s. After centuries of rural passivity
and docility under the Roman Catholic Church, people decided to create a
modern, dynamic, urban, and industrial society. Within a decade, life in
Quebec had changed almost beyond recognition. People abandoned the old
religion en masse. Convents and monasteries emptied. Cities and suburbs
grew. Women entered the workforce. The birth rate fell dramatically. As for
the ancien régime, a quasi-fascist one, it was quickly voted out of office for
the first time in decades. The new regime, a liberal one, emphasized
education, business, and bureaucracy (which took over many functions
formerly given to the church). This quiet revolution was soon accompanied
by a not-so-quiet one fueled by nationalism, which, in many ways, replaced
Catholicism. Despite a few violent incidents, however, this revolution never
turned into a rerun of the French Revolution. Politicians reorganized society
from top to bottom, democratically, by changing public opinion in favour of
reform and enacting legislation accordingly. The same strategy was used,
slightly later, elsewhere in Canada and the United States. Although neither
Marxists nor feminists in those places were aware of it, the quiet revolution
in Quebec was a prototype for their movements.
Have all those movements, or even the one in Quebec, been entirely
benign? The answer clearly depends on who is answering. Many people are
better off, but others are worse off. Some problems have been solved, but
new ones have been created. Even though democracy has been preserved,
surely a good thing, an inherent problem of democracy – one that was well
known to the founders of American democracy as the potential for mob rule
– has been revealed. Democracy is a political system, albeit the safest one
that we know, not a moral principle. Whether it promotes the good or not
depends almost entirely on the moral awareness of voters – not on their
moral sensitivity in any sentimental sense but on their ability to think
analytically and critically about moral problems.
To the extent that feminism has endorsed egalitarianism, then, we are
surely better off than we would have been without it. Every movement that
supports equality, after all, strengthens the moral fabric of democracy. To
the extent that feminism has endorsed ideology, on the other hand, we are
surely worse off (although we should add, in fairness, that the feminist
version of ideology is only one form among several and by no means the
original one). What will happen in the future is beyond knowing, of course,
but the fragmenting legacy of identity politics is not encouraging. We still
face instititutionalized polarization not only between men and women but
also between blacks and whites and many other groups. In addition, we face
the institutionalization of a group hierarchy analogous to caste (which we
discuss in appendix 7).
The new century has produced a few signs of reversal. The most obvious
one, for men and women, was public response to the events of 11
September 2001. For the first time in many years, it was widely and
publicly intuited that men – those who tried to rescue people trapped in the
World Trade Center, say, and those who fought the hijackers over
Pennsylvania – could make a distinctive, valued, and necessary contribution
to society. If those images of specifically masculine heroism remain fresh,
then men can still hope to establish a healthy identity and thus help create a
healthy society. But it would be unwise to see this, yet, as a decisive turning
point. For one thing, the terrorists themselves were all men. Also, very
different images of men have been purveyed for many years. Egalitarian
feminists have argued that women can do everything that men can do,
which leaves men with no possible source of identity. And ideological
feminists have argued that women are better than men, which leaves men
who believe them with a highly negative identity. The damage will not be
undone in a day, a year, even a decade. Besides, an identity based
exclusively on physical courage and physical aggression might prove no
different from earlier forms of masculinity – the very situation that gave rise
to problems for both women and men in the first place.

It is with this in mind that we will turn in the final volume, Transcending
Misandry, to a discussion of men themselves – of men, that is, as distinct
from public perceptions of men in popular culture and the effects of those
perceptions on legislation. There, we will devote much more attention to
men as seen through scholarship than through ideology. Meanwhile, our
main points are that gynocentrism has entailed misandry and that misandry
has been institutionalized as systemic discrimination in the laws of our
countries and the policies of our institutions. This is not merely a matter of
perception, even perception filtered through the mass media, but of the
fundamental social, economic, and political forces that shape our lives. In
some ways, changes over the past thirty years have been beneficial. They
have made women full participants in society. In other ways, however, old
problems have merely been replaced with newer ones.
We conclude this book on a note of pessimism. Like many other
segments of our increasingly fragmented society, women now have a very
heavy investment in the rhetoric of victimhood. Not all women, therefore,
want to correct or even acknowledge the problems we have examined here.
One way of perpetuating the struggle of women no matter how many gains
are made is to identify the underlying problem as maleness itself, which can
never be corrected (except by eliminating men in some way). Another is to
make the standard of correction utopian, which can never be satisfied
(except by establishing a totalitarian regime).
APPENDICES
APPENDIX ONE
Responding to Our Critics: Spreading Misandry
Revisited
Spreading Misandry, the first volume of this trilogy, sold well enough.
Within a few months, in fact, it was reprinted. It sold so well, though, in
part because of its controversial topic. Critics – we include here reviewers
and talk show hosts, along with their guests and callers – either liked the
book intensely or disliked it intensely. Only two reviewers occupied
something like the middle ground. They said, in effect, ho hum. Though
clearly irritated by the topic of our book, one reviewer was prepared to
tolerate it as almost inevitable in a world preoccupied by gender. Because
our point of view was necessary for academic balance, at least in theory, he
admitted that this book was possibly useful for university libraries.
Those who liked the book deluged us with calls and letters to thank us
for going public with this long-suppressed topic. A few offered to help us
publicize the book. One was planning to make a documentary film on the
topic. Among these supportive responses, the most poignant were from men
who had personally encountered institutionalized bias against men. Most of
these men, trying to make sense of things in the aftermath of divorce and
custody battles, understood that the double standards they faced in court
were closely related to the patterns of misandry we had discussed in
connection with popular culture.
Those who disliked the book, on the other hand, were either
contemptuously or ferociously hostile. A few resorted even to ad hominem
attacks on us. One reviewer, for example, called us “Beavis and Butthead.”
Another called us “Robin Hood and Maid Marion” – but could not decide
which of us was which! Yet some of these hostile critics raised interesting
questions, and we would do well to answer them.

Some critics praised us for providing such relentless documentation of


misandry in popular culture, but others scolded us for not being relentless
enough. Even though we did not attempt a scientific study – we admitted
that, although one critic accused us of “bragging” about not doing so – we
did what we could with the resources available to us, enough to indicate the
existence of a phenomenon worthy of more study.
A truly scientific study would have required much more money for
personnel and travelling. For one thing, we would have required a
sociologist to supervise the collection of data. To collect the data, moreover,
we would have required people in randomly selected regions of the United
States and Canada – urban, suburban, and rural – at randomly selected
times over a decade, merely to monitor television viewing. We would have
required additional people to monitor movies released in those regions at
randomly selected venues – both cineplexes and “art houses” – during the
same period. Other media would have required equivalent methods. Finding
money to support this politically incorrect project was very hard in any
case, but finding money to support it on a larger scale would have been
impossible. Our stated aim was not to have the last word on this topic, in
any case, but to establish the existence of a major problem and open it up
for discussion – that is, to stimulate more research. The decade that we
studied has now passed, but we would like very much to see some social-
scientific microstudies of current popular culture.
Other critics ridiculed us for wasting time on popular culture, supposedly
a trivial topic, in the first place. All of the productions we examined were,
well, nothing more than entertainment. Why make a big fuss, they asked,
over productions that no one takes seriously in the first place? But there are
people who do, in fact, take popular culture seriously. And many of them,
ironically, are feminists. They have never tolerated the trivialization of
popular culture in connection with its characteristic portrayals of women.
Negative portrayals, they say over and over again, indicate nothing less than
rampant misogyny: hatred of women. It is worth noting one critic,
therefore, who actually denied that the admittedly negative portrayals of
men in popular culture have anything to do with hatred. According to this
academic – she is the director of a feminist institute – these portrayals are
merely innocent and amusing comments on the “foibles” of men. But would
she say the same thing about the negative portrayals of women in popular
culture – including rap, the one musical genre in which misogyny is still
tolerated? If she did, she would be ostracized immediately by every
feminist of her generation.
In this sense, the feminists – like the Marxists before them – have been
correct. Entertainment really is never just entertainment, although it is
nonetheless also that.1 No matter how innocuous, it always reveals
something about the society that produces it and – more importantly – about
the society that consumes it. At the very least, it reveals familiar notions
about the way things are – what could be called the prevalent worldview.
Why do we need scholars to reveal these familiar notions? Precisely
because they are so familiar. The more obvious something seems, after all,
the easier it is to escape notice. To put it another way, entertainment must
always be intelligible – and thus reasonably familiar – to those who
experience it. Otherwise, there could be no suspension of disbelief.
Consider what actually happens when viewers watch a movie, say, or a
television show. For an hour or two, they enter a world that is clearly not
real but is nevertheless realistic enough to allow for the suspension of
disbelief. All they know of the world being presented to them, however, is
what they actually see on the screen and hear from the speakers. For all
intents and purposes, during that one or two hours, this is the real world. In
connection with portrayals of men and women during the 1990s,
lamentably, movies and television shows were often characterized by
extreme polarization: evil or inadequate men versus virtuous or victimized
women.
If this were merely a theory about sexual polarization in mass
entertainment, it might make very little difference to anyone except a few
academics in fields such as popular culture and film studies. But we
gathered a great deal of corroborating evidence from highly publicized
events in real life during that same period – evidence that was not presented
in the first volume but is presented in this second one. Was it purely a
coincidence that men and women were sharply polarized in mass
entertainment, after all, even as they were sharply polarized in the public
square – even as one wing of a major political movement explicitly justified
this polarization in ideological terms? Not likely.
But did misandry in popular culture have any effect on either men or
women? Did it actually cause misandry in real life? Some reviewers,
referring to misandric jokes and sitcoms, asked a few of their male friends
or colleagues if they felt threatened by misandry. Not surprisingly, some of
these men admitted nothing of the kind. Our immediate goal in Spreading
Misandry, however, was to discuss not the psychological damage
potentially done by misandry to boys and men (a topic that we will discuss
in the final volume of this trilogy) but the moral damage done to society as
a whole. To put it bluntly, double standards – hatred is verboten when
directed toward women or minorities, in this case, but acceptable or even
amusing when directed toward men – must undermine the moral fabric of
any society. It is impossible to teach children effectively that hatred or
revenge is wrong, in short, if they learn directly or indirectly that either is
apparently right in some cases. It makes no moral sense. Given the facile
arguments put forward in all seriousness by our adult critics, arguments that
either ignore moral thinking altogether or distort it in the interest of political
expediency, the future of our society looks bleak indeed. In that case, then,
we should surely use this discussion of misandry as one way of fostering a
larger discussion about the nature of society, democracy, civic virtue,
ideology, political correctness, and so on.
There is no point in rehashing the old chicken-and-egg question. Movies
do reflect cultural trends, to be sure, but they also create those trends. And
that is not considered a controversial statement among scholars in film
studies. If the world is presented in polarized terms often enough – and we
presented enough evidence to indicate that this was indeed the case during
the 1990s – it surely makes sense to suggest that viewers bring back
something of that experience into the real world. Just as simulated violence
probably desensitizes viewers to real violence, simulated polarization
between men and women (or any other segments of the population)
probably desensitizes viewers to real polarization. In other words, any
discrepancy between the reel world and the real world becomes blurred;
viewers come to take for granted that the gender stereotypes presented are
just as realistic – not only familiar but also expected and acceptable – as the
cars and clothing presented.
It will not do, therefore, to trivialize popular culture. Nor will it do to
adopt a double standard, trivializing entertainment in connection with
portrayals of men but not in connection with portrayals of women. And
judging from the public response to Spreading Misandry, that is precisely
what some feminists, including male feminists, continue to do, even though
this double standard inherently undermines their own point of view about
women in popular culture.
Some critics argued that we had ignored inconvenient features of popular
culture. Not all movies and television shows, for instance, present viewers
with negative stereotypes of men. Some actually glorify men. And we
agree. But there is more to this glorification than meets the eye.
In Spreading Misandry, we showed that pop cultural misandry in the
1990s could be arranged along a continuum from the relatively trivial
mockery of men to the much more disturbing dehumanization or even
demonization of men. It is true that not all productions could be placed
legitimately along this continuum. Some had nothing much to do with
gender at all. Others were called misogynistic merely because they were
about misogyny – and one of these, In the Company of Men (Neil LaBute,
1996), was really misanthropic rather than misogynistic. But still others did
indeed glorify men.
How were men, as such, glorified in popular culture? Almost always in
connection with combat of one kind or another. After a lull in the 1960s and
1970s the popularity of movies such as Rambo: First Blood II (George
Cosmatos, 1985) and Top Gun (Tony Scott, 1986) indicated a revival of
machismo during the next decade. Suddenly, soldiers and other fighters
(often human-robotic hybrids) were “in” again. Arnold Schwarzenegger and
Sylvester Stallone, to name only two action stars, were big hits at the box
office in films that were often addressed directly and primarily to
adolescent boys. But several new trends emerged in the 1990s and have
continued into the new century.
For one thing, the old machismo now has a rival. The new machismo, as
presented by Hollywood, is based on a rejection of mature manhood as
defined by some distinctive, necessary, and valued contribution made to
society by adult men. Even though the warrior archetype is a very
dangerous one when other archetypes are either absent or marginalized,
warriors of one kind or another – soldiers, say, or policemen – have often
served society well. An earlier generation understood this. Gary Cooper is
emotionally remote in High Noon (Fred Zinnemann, 1952), for instance, but
he does what has to be done. He exemplifies both moral and physical
courage. That much can hardly be said of the grotesquely vulgar and
socially inadequate male protagonists of recent movies such as Dumb and
Dumber (Peter Farrelli, 1994), Dude, Where’s My Car? (Danny Leiner,
2000), Freddy Got Fingered (Tom Green, 2001), Deuce Bigalow, Male
Gigolo (Mike Mitchell, 1999), The Animal (Luke Greenfield, 2001), Jay
and Silent Bob Strike Back (Kevin Smith, 2001), and so on.
Also, more and more of the action stars have been female. This is
particularly true of fantasy and science fiction (genres that give them
supernatural or genetically enhanced powers) and action pictures (in which
Asian martial arts even out the anatomical difference between men and
women). The most obvious examples on television, recently, have been
Sarah Michelle Geller in Buffy, the Vampire Slayer, Jessica Alba in Dark
Angel, and Jennifer Garner in Alias. In film, we have had Drew Barrymore,
Lucy Liu, and Cameron Diaz in Charlie’s Angels (Joseph McGinty Nichol,
2000). These productions focus directly or indirectly on the future. At the
same time, productions that feature male fighters often focus directly or
indirectly on the past.
World War II, for instance, has become more popular than ever as the
venue for male action stars. Cinematic examples would include The Thin
Red Line (Terrence Malik, 1998), Saving Private Ryan (Steven Spielberg,
1998), Pearl Harbor (Michael Bay, 2001), and Hart’s War (Gregory Hoblit,
2002). The male characters in these movies are clearly glorified as self-
sacrificing contributors to the common good of society, not ridiculed as
buffoons or attacked as maniacal fiends. This should be good news for men,
right? Not so fast. World War II, like Vietnam, was fundamentally different
from more recent wars in one way of particular importance here. It was
sexually segregated. Only young men engaged in combat, and only young
men came home in body bags. Unlike Vietnam, however, World War II can
still be considered morally acceptable (and militarily effective). In short,
movies or shows about it encourage male viewers to feel nostalgic for a
time when it was still possible to have a healthy masculine identity as men.
In the real world of everyday life, that situation no longer exists. Sexual
segregation is no longer acceptable. Even combat, the final frontier, is now
in the process of being sexually desegregated, although the process will not
be complete until a generation of young women has grown up with the
expectation of being drafted into combat – and the rest of society has
accepted the fact that young men will no longer be the only ones to come
home from war in body bags.
Although these movies cannot be classified as misandric, therefore, they
are just as disturbing from our point of view as misandric ones. They
present men, consciously or subconsciously, with a central question: What
can it possibly mean to be a man – not an individual, not a citizen, not a
Christian or a Jew, not an athlete or an intellectual, but a man – in our
society? And they provide no obvious answer. Any notion of masculinity
based heavily or even exclusively on the heroism of young men during
World War II is easily reduced to the level of nostalgic and atavistic fantasy
in our time – just as the jousting tournament became a ceremonial vestige of
aristocratic identity at a time of rapid military, economic, and social change.
And as we say, combat is in the process of being sexually desegregated.
References to soldiers killed in World War II and Vietnam, say, are now
routinely neutered on days of remembrance. Politicians and commentators –
even advertisers – refer piously to the “men and women who fought for
their country,” even though all of those who actually fought were (by law)
men. The same is true in connection with other forms of combat. Most
people hailed the hundreds of New York “firefighters” who risked or even
lost their lives while trying to rescue others on 11 September 2001 – even
though all of them were men, not women. The mere fact of this anomaly,
which prompted a few men to argue that we still need specifically male
heroes (partly to offset all the specifically male villains presented in popular
culture), indicates that political correctness will not solve the underlying
problem of masculine identity and that the events of 11 September 2001
have not yet resulted in a renewed appreciation of men per se. Everyone
appreciates the people who risked their lives, to be sure, but not everyone
appreciates them specifically as men. The sexual desegregation of combat
would surely be a good thing for providing an ultimate symbol of sexual
equality, thus supporting all other forms of equality (and preventing the
state from sacrificing citizens who happen to be male), but it would also be
a bad thing to the extent that it would diminish the possibilities for
establishing a specifically masculine identity. We will discuss the
implications of that situation in Transcending Misandry.

Over and over again, critics asked rhetorically how so many misandric
productions could have been created by men themselves? That question is
based, however, on several unwarranted assumptions.
For one thing, these critics assumed that only men were (or are) involved
in the entertainment industry, which was (and is) not the case. Despite its
male director, for instance, the screenplay of Thelma and Louise (Ridley
Scott, 1991) was written by Callie Khourie. And He Said, She Said (Marisa
Silver; Ken Kwapis, 1990) had a female director as well as a male one. But
at least two other unwarranted assumptions, much more important ones, are
involved.
These critics assumed that those who create popular culture restrict
themselves to productions that they personally consider virtuous or
educational or edifying or whatever. In fact, nothing could be further from
the truth. These folks are in business. They want to make money. They
produce and sell, therefore, whatever they believe people will buy. And if
misandry sells, as misogyny once did, then so be it.
Not many studio executives would be able to identify or even define
misandry, of course, much less either to approve of it or disapprove of it.
But their approval or disapproval is beside the point here. We have learned
in connection with other forms of hatred that those who purvey it often do
so unwittingly. Few in the 1920s deliberately fostered hatred on the
vaudeville stage, but the ethnic jokes enjoyed by audiences then would now
be considered racist and thus intolerable. Why, then, does misandry still
sell? The quick answer is that misandry, unlike any other form of hatred, is
still considered politically correct; no one is considered righteous for
protesting against something that is generally considered acceptable. The
long answer is more complicated.
In a very few cases, this phenomenon might be explained in connection
with “self-hatred” (a phenomenon long known to Jews who worry about
other Jews assimilating anti-Semitic stereotypes.) There are male converts
to feminism, especially among academics. What they lose in self-esteem by
being ashamed to be men they hope to gain in gratitude or admiration from
women. But most men do not fit that description and strongly resent men
who do. Why do they not protest against misandric productions? One quick
answer is that they do, in fact, protest. Warren Farrell, for instance, has been
doing so for years.2 Another quick answer is that many men are afraid to
protest. Some are afraid of losing their jobs, others their respect from their
female colleagues (or wives and daughters), and still others their own
identity as liberals. The long answer, once again, is more complicated.
Most men are still either unable to recognize misandry (although that
situation, judging from public response to our book, is changing very
quickly) or unwilling to do so. Why unwilling? Because acknowledging
that men have a serious problem is tantamount to acknowledging that they
are not in control of their own lives – that they are not, in other words, real
men, especially if the problem confronting them is presented by women. On
one radio talk show after another about Spreading Misandry, at least one
man would call in to say that he felt perfectly secure about his masculinity
and could not see why these so-called men were whining about misandry.
One man said that he took pride in being oafish or piggish and thus
deserved to be ridiculed by women (even though that makes no sense).
Were they trying to convince women to pin medals on them? Were they
trying to convince themselves that they had nothing to worry about? Or
were they simply agreeing that men are oafish or piggish and – because
they have no urge to change their own behaviour – so be it?
The same critics assumed that our primary purpose in Spreading
Misandry was to examine the motivations of those who produce popular
culture. Nothing could be further from the truth. Our primary purpose was
to understand not the individual psychology of those who produce it but the
collective psychology of those who do so and – more important – those who
enjoy it. Our first task, therefore, was to document the existence of
misandry in popular culture during one decade. As scholars, after all, we
realized that no phenomenon can be explained before it has been carefully
documented and described. We offered an explanation for this phenomenon
in chapter 8: that the origin of misandry in popular culture is a top-down
phenomenon, not a grass-roots phenomenon, and has its ultimate source in
the ideological branch of feminism. We expected critics to argue with us
over that. We expected them to raise questions, moreover, about our
interpretation of this or that production. We did not, however, expect them
to deny the very existence of misandry. And, in fact, very few have done so.
What some have indeed denied is that anyone should care about it. Since
that lies at the very heart not only of controversy over Spreading Misandry
(and, no doubt, over the second and third volumes of this trilogy) but also
of our own purpose in writing, it is worthy of a very careful response here.
To ask why anyone should care about the highly negative portrayal of
men in popular culture is to deny that one segment of society is worthy of
respect, let alone common decency. Nevertheless, many reviewers of
Spreading Misandry – including some men – did so. How could they argue,
in an allegedly egalitarian society, against the fundamental premise of
equality? Possibly because they were either unable or unwilling to think
carefully about the meaning and implications of equality. They had come to
believe that only victim classes should have a right to speak in the public
square and that men may not be considered a victim class (although they
make exceptions for minority men).
Many feminists, moreover, had come to believe a self-serving fantasy.
Men, they had become convinced, have such godlike power that they are
incapable of being damaged. Therefore, anything goes (especially for
ideological feminists, who believe that the end can justify the means). That,
we suggest, is probably the single most serious mistake ever made by
feminists. In both this volume and Spreading Misandry, we have shown that
men are indeed the targets of hatred (and, in the third volume of this trilogy,
we will argue that men can be seriously damaged by that hatred).
In any case, our underlying aim was not to add yet one more class to the
long list of society’s official victims, although we were obliged to use the
current lingua franca of victimization. Our underlying aim, in fact, was to
move beyond the polarizing and paralyzing rhetoric of victim class versus
oppressor class toward what we call “intersexual dialogue” (which we will
discuss in the third volume of this trilogy). If even men can be victims of
hatred, after all, then all people can be. And if even feminists can propagate
hatred, then all people can do so. Therefore, it would surely make sense to
frame public debates in terms other than the facile notion, which originated
in Marxism but has been used routinely by movements on both the left and
the right, that every significant human conflict can be explained in terms of
a victim class versus an oppressor class.

Some critics claimed that we were attacking all feminists, not merely
ideological ones. How could they make that claim in the face of our
countless – and often very tiresome – qualifying words such as “some
feminists,” “in some feminist circles,” “ideological feminists,” and so on?
Many feminists brag about the “multivocality” of their movement,
claiming to respect “diversity,” “pluralism,” and so on (although they often
rely on those words to hide conflict, thus defending even aspects of
feminism that they, personally, dislike.) We were extremely careful,
therefore, to specify precisely which type of feminism we were attacking. In
fact, we identified no fewer than nine criteria, all or most of which must be
present for a movement of any kind to qualify as ideological. Even so, we
were accused over and over again of attacking feminism in general rather
than one school of feminism in particular.
This would seem hard to explain at first glance, at least in connection
with those critics who had actually read the book, except for two
possibilities. Some feminists might have liked these nine characteristic
features of ideology and agreed that all or most of them are indeed essential
to feminism. In that case, it would have made sense to believe that we had
attacked all feminists worthy of the name. But others might have disliked
those same features of ideology and been either embarrassed that any
feminists had adopted them or ashamed that they themselves had done so.
In that case, it would have made sense to defend all feminists and thus close
ranks against an external threat.

Directly or indirectly, the critics we have just mentioned challenged our use
of analogies. One guest on a talk show, for instance, found our analogy
between ideological feminists and Nazis “very disturbing.” The analogy is
very disturbing, of course, but not for the reason she had in mind: How dare
anyone make such an ugly and extreme comparison. For one thing, as we
say, our analogy was not between feminists and Nazis. It was between
ideological feminists and Nazis, and not only Nazis, or ideologues on the
right, but also ideologues on the left.
But her main point was that the content of feminism, presumably in any
form, is benevolent and thus has nothing in common with that of
malevolent National Socialism. And that is true of feminism in general,
though not of ideological feminism. But our analogy was not about the
content of these ideologies. Moreover, our analogy was not about the results
of these ideologies. It was about the mentality of those who produced them.
Given the horrific results of Nazi ideology, it is worth pausing here to
examine the nature of any analogy. There is no such thing as a perfect
analogy. A perfect analogy would not be an analogy at all, by definition, but
an equation. Why use analogies? Because many fields of scholarship would
be impossible without them. History is certainly one example. Those who
ignore history, according to the old saying, are doomed to repeat it. The
truth is a little more complex. Historical events do not recur in precisely the
same way, ever,3 but general patterns often do. If enough characteristics of
an earlier situation are similar to those of a current one, it surely makes
sense for historians and others to ask if the likely results will be similar. But
historians are by no means the only ones to examine historical patterns. Of
interest to us in the historical record of ideological movements is the moral
(or immoral) perspective that all have in common. It is very unlikely, to say
the least, that ideological feminists, if given enough political power, would
ever produce extermination camps for men. (Apart from anything else,
exterminating men would be counterproductive unless women could
reproduce themselves.) But that does not excuse ideological feminists, on
moral grounds, for hating men. Even if the Nazis had never murdered a
single Jew, likewise, that would still not have excused them, on moral
grounds, for hating Jews. The importance of our conviction that hatred is
inherently evil (although no person or community can be innately evil,
which would leave them with no choices) is profound. It comes up over and
over again, in one way or another, throughout this trilogy. The absence of
that conviction, unfortunately, underlies many comments by our critics.

Some critics actually tried to justify misandry in popular culture by arguing


that it represents nothing more than payback time after years of misogyny
in popular culture. So what if men were ridiculed in the 1990s or even if
they are still ridiculed? (Most of these people had fixated on the first one or
two chapters of Spreading Misandry, which were about misandric humour,
but had ignored later chapters about more disturbing forms of imagery.)
This way of “thinking” reveals a frightening inability or unwillingness in
our democracy to think clearly about fundamental moral principles.
Justice is not the same, after all, as revenge. Justice leads to healing and
reconciliation; revenge, on the other hand, leads to hatred and polarization.
How could such a basic distinction be ignored even by journalists, who
supposedly encourage people to think about what goes on in the public
square? The answer, we suggested in Spreading Misandry, was to be found
not among the ignorant masses but among the intellectual, artistic, and
political elites – whose mentality slowly filters down through the mass
media of popular culture and develops a life of its own.
For at least thirty years, the dominant worldview in those circles has
been post-modernism. As the name indicates, postmodernism originated as
a reaction against modernism. And modernism was (still is in some circles)
characterized by its glorification not only of progress in general but also of
reason in particular. Modernism can be considered the most recent version
of a worldview that goes back to the eighteenth-century Enlightenment (or
even to the Renaissance). Postmodernism, on the other hand, can be
considered the most recent version of a world-view that goes back to late
eighteenth-century romanticism (and, indirectly, to the Reformation).4
Deconstruction is the favourite analytical technique of postmodernists:
casting doubt on every premise held or hidden by their adversaries. They
characteristically ask two questions: What is truth? And whose truth? And
their answer to both is simple: There is no such thing as truth, only “our
truth” versus “their truth” (or, as they like to say, “our discourses” versus
“their discourses.”) If there is no such thing as truth, of course, there can be
no such thing as justice either – only “our justice” versus “their justice.”
Postmodernist academics are usually careful not to draw that conclusion
(even though it is the only logical conclusion). Why? Because they actually
do believe in the existence of truth – that is, truth according to their own
ideologies. (An ideology is not merely any set of ideas or any philosophy. It
is a worldview or, as we define it, a systematic re-presentation of reality in
order to attain specific social, economic, and political goals.) When
popularized, however, postmodernism fosters moral relativism and thus
discourages people from even thinking carefully about moral problems such
as the distinction between justice and revenge.
One result of postmodernism is pervasive – but selective – cynicism.
Everything that “they” say is suspect and should therefore be deconstructed
but not, of course, what “we” say. And the result of that, in turn, is to
legitimate dualism. In other words, “they” are part of a titanic conspiracy
against “us.”
Of course, this leaves us open to the accusation of being dualistic
ourselves. After all, we believe that “they” (ideological feminists) are
wrong. But dualism is not about opposition toward this or that idea. It is
about hostility toward people – not individuals but groups – who are
classified as inherently or even innately evil according to class, race, sex, or
whatever. These perpetual enemies, they say, must be destroyed in one way
or another – if not killed then at least marginalized – before the dawn of a
new golden age becomes possible. To oppose the ideas of some women (or
men) is not dualistic, in short, but to hate women (or men) as such really is.
To put it another way, we believe in tolerance for everything except
intolerance. And intolerance, unfortunately, is one effect of ideological
thinking.
APPENDIX TWO
Birth of the Bogeyman: One Subtext of Modern
Witch Hunts
According to Judith Levine, the modern pedophile has a “genealogy.” It
began with his first appearance at the height of industrialization during the
nineteenth century. Social tension at that time was brought on by the
exploitation of children in factories. Most people were either unable or
unwilling to remove children from those satanic mills until reformers made
them do so. But they noticed that these children were affected not only by
hard work for little pay but also by more opportunities for sexual contact. In
fact, many took to the streets and became prostitutes. Parents fixated on this
problem, which took on even greater symbolic importance than economic
problems. It was in this context that modern notions of the pedophile were
born, along with the notion of “white slavery,” a racially charged fantasy
propagated by both tabloid journalists and idealistic reformers. It was one
thing to allow the corruption of innocent children – they were now defined
primarily in connection with innocence – by working them to death; many
families simply needed the money brought in by their children, and a few
powerful families grew rich by employing them for next to nothing. It was
another thing to do so by allowing molesters to defile them sexually. The
result was law reform on a colossal scale. Apart from any other measures,
the age of consent was raised from as low as seven to as high as eighteen1
and homosexuality was criminalized.
The “sex monster,” as Levine calls him, went into hibernation as a result
of this crackdown. He reappeared briefly during the Depression, when
social tension, particularly in connection with hordes of unemployed and
possibly dangerous men, reached a new high. It disappeared promptly,
though, when World War II presented people at home with clear external
enemies and those on the front (or even at home in countries close to the
front) with many more opportunities than usual to indulge in sex on their
own. After the war, he returned. The threat of perverts on the loose
symbolically expressed widespread anxiety about not only the restoration of
normality within the family but also the possibility of communist spies
within the community. By now, the moral rhetoric had been heavily infused
with clinical jargon, and whole industries had been developed to deal with
the problem. The “sexual psychopath,” as he was now called, was governed
by “uncontrolled and uncontrollable desires.”2 Even though statistics
recorded no rise in violent crimes against children, “commissions were
empaneled, new laws were passed, and arrests increased. Whereas most of
these, like most arrests today, were for minor offenses such as flashing or
consensual homosexual sex, a few highly publicized violent crimes drew a
clangor of public demand for dragnets, vigilante squads, life imprisonment,
indefinite incarceration in mental institutions, castration, and execution of
the psycho killers, all of which were revived in the 1980s and 1990s.”3
Meanwhile, pornography became a major target, due partly to a rare
convergence between conservative and radical political forces. From the left
came ideological feminism. Even though ideological feminists represent the
left in many ways, they have moved far to the right in other ways. Believing
in both female essentialism (a kind of sexual nationalism) and feminist
dualism (a kind of sexual racism) is characteristic of what Levine calls
“sexual conservatives.” For them, she says, sexual relations – at least those
with men – are inherently evil and must be either surrounded with elaborate
(and enforceable) codes or eliminated entirely. Every venue that might
bring women together with men is suspected of leading directly to the
sexual harassment of women. And that, they believe, includes everything
from risqué banter to domestic violence and rape. In fact, they give almost
as much attention to symbolic struggles, such as the one against
pornography, as they do to more obviously urgent ones against violence
itself. From the right, of course, came religious conservatives. These two
streams flowed together, we suggest, at a summit meeting in 1986: the
Meese Commission on pornography. They agreed
to legitimate a wholesale crackdown on adult porn and,
eventually, on an alleged proliferation of “child pornography.”
The satanic-abuse witch-hunts (which dovetailed with the
pornography scare and later became a more general panic over
child abuse) also alchemized feminist and right-wing fears.
Feminist worries about children’s vulnerability to adult sexual
desire gradually reified in a therapy industry that taught itself to
uncover abuse in every female patient’s past. Religious
conservatives, mostly middle-class women who felt their
“traditional” families threatened by the social-sexual upheavals of
the time, translated that concern into the language of their own
apprehension. They saw profanity – in the form of abortion,
divorce, homosexuality, premarital teen sex, and sex education –
everywhere encroaching on sanctity. To them, it made sense that
adults, with Satan as chief gangbanger, were conspiring in “rings”
to rape innocent children.
Throughout the quarter century, in a complex social chemistry of
deliberate political strategy, professional opportunism, and
popular suspension of disbelief, sexual discomfort heated to
alarm, which boiled to widespread panic; hysteria edged out
rational discourse, even in the pressrooms of established news
organizations and the chambers of the highest courts. The media
reported that children faced sexual dangers more terrible than
anything their parents had ever known. Along with lust-crazed
Satanists, there were Internet tricksters, scout-leader
pornographers, predatory priests – an army of sexual malefactors
people the news, allegedly more wily and numerous than ever
before.4
At any rate, the man who either produced or “consumed” pornography
(and this category included Clarence Thomas for those who tried to prevent
the confirmation of his nomination to the Supreme Court) became a new
version of the old “sex monster.”
Within a few years, police testified that child porn had never been
more than a boutique business even in its modest heyday in the
late 1960s. The first law wiped out what little kiddie porn
remained on the street, and by the early 1980s, the head of the
New York Police Department’s Public Morals Division
proclaimed the stuff “as rare as the Dead Sea Scrolls.” The 1.2
million figure [for victims], which [child psychiatrist Judianne]
Densen-Gerber subsequently doubled, was revealed to be the
arbitrarily quadrupled estimate of an unsubstantiated number one
author said he’d “thrown out” to get a reaction from the law
enforcement community. Densen-Gerber would soon slip from
the public eye under suspicions of embezzling public monies and
employing coercive and humiliating methods at [New York’s drug
rehab centre] Odyssey House. [Collaborator Lloyd] Martin would
later be removed from his post at the LAPD for harassing witnesses
and falsifying evidence.5
But, as Levine points out, their work had already been done very
effectively. Journalists continued to spread bogus statistics. In the United
States, Congress passed the Protection of Children against Sexual
Exploitation Act of 1977. In Canada, Parliament established the Meese
Commission in 1986 (which are discussed in chapter 7).
Right-wing groups dropped moralistic talk of “decency” and adopted
that of “family values.” As Levine says, the “wide, fat enemy
‘pornography’ began to fade from view. Now both antiporn feminist and
conservative propaganda aimed at the sleaker [sic], ‘hard-core,’ the scarier
‘child pornography.’”6 Feminists were not terribly interested in porn
featuring boys, partly because that was gay porn – which is to say,
something that was politically touchy. “And where was this new
pornographer? Densen-Gerber and Martin had been unable to run him down
on the urban streets. He’d eluded capture in the suburban childcare centres.
Now, said his pursuers, the fugitive had found his way to everywhere and
nowhere. He was on the Internet, where he had joined a vast club that
zipped pictures of copulating kids among them, sidled up to children in chat
rooms, and enticed them into real-world motels and malls. With the family
room connected by a mere modem to the wild open cyberspaces, even the
home was no longer safe.”7
Most of those caught by police are caught as a result of sting operations,
of entrapment. At one time, undercover cops would solicit their interest in
pictures and then arrest them for trying to buy it. Now federal agents pose
on the Internet as minors, arrange meetings with children, and then arrest
anyone who shows up. Officials claim that they are preventing crimes. But
another possibility, suggests Levine, is that “the government, frustrated with
the paucity of the crime they claim is epidemic and around which huge
networks of enforcement operations have been built, have to stir the action
to justify their jobs. The same logic can explain why the volume of antiporn
legislation has increased annually. From a relatively simple criminalization
of production and distribution, the law eventually went after possession and
then even viewing of child-erotic images at somebody else’s house.”8

To understand the witch hunts, though, means more than sifting through the
historical evolution of a bogey man. “Our culture fears the pedophile,” says
Levine, “not because he is a deviant, but because he is ordinary. And I don’t
mean because he is the ice-cream man or Father Patrick. No, we fear him
because he is us.”9 She refers to the fact that what is commonly attributed to
the dirty old pedophiles – being sexually attracted to children (especially
girls) – is, in fact, something experienced also by “us.” To explain that,
Levine draws on the work of literary critic James Kincaid, who traced the
cultural history of child molesters back to the nineteenth century.
Anglo-American culture conjured childhood innocence, defining
it as a desireless subjectivity, at the same time as it constructed a
new ideal of the sexually desirable object. The two had identical
attributes – softness, cuteness, docility, passivity – and this
simultaneous cultural invention has presented us with a wicked
psychosocial problem ever since. We relish our erotic attraction to
children, says Kincaid (witness the child beauty pageants in
which JonBenét Ramsey was entered). But we also find that
attraction abhorrent (witness the public shock and disgust at
JonBenét’s “sexualization” in those pageants). We project that
eroticized desire outward, creating a monster to hate, hunt down,
and punish.10
The problem with Levine’s explanation is that she actually refers by
“we” and “us” only to “they” and “them” – that is, to men. But because
women are at least as anxious about pedophilia as men are, possibly more
so, the panic can hardly be attributed to the sexual fantasies that women
have about men. After all, not many women are erotically attracted to men
who could be described as soft, cute, docile, or passive.
But the story is even more complicated than that. Levine points out that
something else was going on, or was widely believed to be going on, at the
very moment that all these witch hunts were erupting. And this was hardly
coincidental. “The story behind these stories – one that was more plausible
and therefore perhaps more frightening to baby boomer parents than tales of
baby-rapists in black robes – was that of more teen sex, starting earlier and
becoming more sophisticated sooner, with more dire consequences.”11 As
we see it, parents are terrified of not being able to help their children
become healthy adults, partly because so few have thought carefully enough
about what it means to be a healthy adult in the first place. Instead of
blaming themselves for creating a self-indulgent and hedonistic society, one
that must therefore blur the distinction between childhood and adulthood,
they blame some sinister Other or group of Others. In this case, they blame
it on male predators – and, either implicitly or explicitly, on males as sexual
beings.
What, precisely, was so disturbing about early or frequent sexual
activity? This is the question that got Levine herself into so much trouble.
The mere fact that she could ask it indicated to some readers that she
wanted to promote perversion. As Levine points out, though, the current
revulsion toward childhood sexuality is a relatively modern phenomenon.
For many centuries, Europeans assumed that children were born in sin –
that is, in a state of moral or spiritual corruption – and required conversion
to Godfearing adulthood. But then in the late eighteenth century, that
paradigm was reversed. Europeans and Americans began to believe that
children were born innocent and gradually corrupted by the sinful world of
adults. (The same paradigm was applied to remote places, which were
inhabited by “noble savages” and thus uncontaminated by “civilization.”)
As the cultural critic James Kincaid has shown, the English and
French philosophers of the Romantic Era conjured the Child as a
radically distinct creature, endowed with purity and “innocence”
– Rousseau’s unspoiled nature boy, Locke’s clean slate. This
being, born outside history, was spoiled by entering it: the child’s
innocence was threatened by the very act of growing up in the
world, which entailed partaking in adult rationality and politics.
In the late nineteenth century, that innocence came to be figured
as we see it today: the child was clean not just of adult political or
social corruption, but ignorant specifically of sexual knowledge
and desire. Ironically, as children’s plight as workers worsened,
adults sought to save them from sex.12
In the early twentieth century, the notion of childhood innocence was
challenged. This time, innovation took the form of psychoanalysis. For
Freud, children were indeed born with sexual desires, although he added
that these desires lay dormant, or subconscious, until puberty. For him,
moreover, sexual desire was not inherently problematic; it was problematic
only because of the ambivalence generated by “civilization.” But G. Stanley
Hall, who brought Freudian theory to America, painted a somewhat darker
picture. Adolescence – he coined that word – was fraught with danger,
especially sexual desire.
All this history lives on in us: zeitgeists do not displace each other
like weather systems on a computerized map. We still invest the
child with Romantic innocence: witness John Gray’s cherub-
bedecked Children Are from Heaven. The Victorian fear of the
poisonous knowledge of worldly sexuality is still with us; lately
it’s remembered in the demonic power we invest in the Internet.
Hall’s image of teen sexuality as a normal pathology informs
child psychology, pedagogy, and parenting: think of “risk
behaviors” and “raging hormones.”
Since Freud, the sexuality of children and adolescents is
officially “natural” and “normal,” yet the meanings of these terms
are ever in dispute, and the expert advice dispensed in self-help
books and parenting columns serves only to lubricate anxiety: Is
the child engaging in sex too soon, too much? Is it sex of the
wrong kind, with the wrong person, the wrong meaning?13
Levine discusses the implications of all this in chapters on the censorship
of material addressed to children, our perceptions of “deviant” children,
statutory rape (and the implication that girls, like women, do not really want
sexual activity), the rejection of sex education, and so on. Of particular
interest here, however, is her chapter on the “pedophile panic.”
By now, we are all familiar with what countless television journalists and
government officials have said about the problem of rampant sexual activity
and violence among students in high schools or even some elementary
schools (along with their use of drugs). We are all familiar, in addition, with
what they have said about the legions of pedophiles waiting to abduct and
rape those same students. “I believe that we’re dealing with a conspiracy,”
said Kee MacFarlane, director of the Children’s Institute International in
Los Angeles and central figure in “satanic-ritual abuse” (being among those
who fomented hysteria), “an organized operation of child predators
designed to prevent detection. If such an operation involves child
pornography or the selling of children, as is frequently alleged, it may have
greater financial, legal, and community resources at its disposal than those
attempting to expose it.”14 But is the rhetoric overstated? Levine thinks that
it is. “The problem with all this information about pedophiles is that most of
it is not true or is so qualified as to be useless as generalization.”15
One problem is how to define “pedophilia” in the first place. “That’s
because a ‘pedophile,’ depending on the legal statute, the perception of the
psychologist, or the biases of the journalist, can be anything from a college
freshman who has once masturbated with a fantasy of a ten-year-old in
mind to an adult who has had sexual contact with an infant.”16 The resulting
confusion and hysteria are due at least partly to those who practise
linguistic inflation: blurring the distinctions between trivial and truly
dangerous behaviours – not to make the latter seem harmless but to make
the former seem harmful.
Another problem is the association between pedophilia and violence.
“Pedophiles are not generally violent,” says Levine, “unless you are using
the term sexual violence against children in a moral, rather than a literal,
way. Its perpetrators very rarely use force or cause physical injury in a
youngster … Bringing themselves down to the maturity level of children
rather than trying to drag the child up toward an adult level, many men who
engage in sex with children tend toward kissing, mutual masturbation, or
‘hands-off’ encounters such as voyeurism and exhibitionism.”17
It is worth noting here, by the way, that the very things said by some
people about sexual relations between children and pedophiles – that is,
between girls and men – is said by some feminists about sexual relations
between women and men: that these behaviours by men are inherently evil
and can therefore be morally evaluated without regard to actual physical or
even psychological harm to women and that women are incapable of giving
their consent due to an eternal and universal “power imbalance” between
the sexes.
Levine stresses the fact that children are sexual beings. All children
explore their bodies and seek physical pleasure by touching, fondling,
flashing, mooning, masturbating, playing “doctor,” and so on. These
behaviours are not only inevitable features of growing up, she says, but also
valuable and even crucial ones. Levine concludes that children should not
be “protected” from that basic fact of life and that they cannot be without
grave consequences for them, their families, and society in general. Her
critics notwithstanding – they tried to prevent the book’s publication on the
grounds that it is “evil,” “blasphemous,” “vile, and “subversive” – Levine
does not advocate juvenile intercourse, rape, or pedophilia. What she
advocates is common sense in the face of yet another witch hunt. To put it
another way, Levine warns us against pathologizing (and criminalizing)
behaviours that would seem perverted or dangerous in very few societies (if
any) except our own. This might sound strange at a time when promiscuity
has become prevalent among adults recently liberated from the repressive
restrictions of Victorianism – we discuss these restrictions in chapter 8 –
until you realize that many feminists have reacted against the sexual
revolution and established new codes of “sexual correctness,” ones that
strongly reinforce the Victorian notion that sex is inherently bad – not only
dangerous but also wrong – for women.
Levine concludes that the cure (convincing parents that sexual activity in
their children is inherently dangerous or evil, warning children that sexual
predators are everywhere, and creating legislation that undermines both
privacy and democracy) can be worse than the disease (a very small number
of truly dangerous people). She examines “the policies and practices that
affect children’s and teens’ quotidian sexual lives – censorship, psychology,
sex education, family, criminal, and reproductive law, and the journalism
and parenting advice that begs for ‘solutions’ while exciting more terror,
like those trick birthday candles that reignite each time you blow them
out.”18
APPENDIX THREE
Misleading the Public: Statistics Abuse
One of our problems in writing this book has been to find reliable statistics
that would either support or undermine our hypotheses, not because we
have so few statistical studies but partly because statistical studies are so
often ambiguous and partly because of what we call “statistics abuse.” This
problem has surfaced in almost every topic under discussion here.
We are not social scientists. Our book is based primarily on moral
arguments, not statistical ones. Nonetheless, we cannot easily avoid
referring to statistics. We need to know something about the facts before we
can come to moral conclusions about them. Our point in this appendix is
not that statistics are useless. Clearly, scholars need to work with some
figures, but they need also to be cautious in doing so and to be suspicious of
figures that sound shocking, especially if they either confirm or undermine
politically charged arguments.
This appendix begins with a look at statistics in connection with ethics
and democracy and continues with a look at statistical scams in connection
with two topics: standards of living after divorce and violence against
women.

This could be described as a golden age of statistics. Most people in our


society, having acknowledged the supremacy of science as a way of
knowing about the world, demand hard evidence (or at least what seems
like hard evidence) to support their points of view on public policy. Not
surprisingly, most books on relations between men and women rely heavily
on statistics.
Why do so many people, both scholars and laypeople, now take it for
granted that positions on moral problems can be legitimated or even proven
by statistical evidence? At least four reasons should be considered. One
reason is simply the prevalence of utilitarianism summed up in Jeremy
Bentham’s famous dictum: “The greatest happiness of the greatest number
is the foundation of morals and legislation.” How can we know what would
make the greatest number of people happy? In our time, through statistics.
Most advocates of this approach are probably unaware that their way of
thinking is rooted in a particular school of philosophy, believing instead that
it is rooted in common sense. The fact remains that the world-view of any
commercial and industrial society is based fundamentally on the closely
related principles of efficiency and cost-effectiveness, which depend on the
effective use of statistical analysis.
For decades, moreover, prominent psychiatrists propagated the notion
that being healthy meant primarily “fitting in,” being “well-adjusted,”
conforming happily to some standard. Because their goal was to turn
“deviant” people into “normal” ones, they used words such as “norm” and
“normal” not merely to describe statistical patterns but to prescribe moral
ones. But is the statistical norm always desirable? Is a majority opinion
always ethical? History certainly provides no reason, in either case, to
assume that the answer is yes.
Also the rise of welfare states has encouraged our reliance on “hard
facts” when making moral choices. Armies of social scientists are required
to conduct research; legions of bureaucrats, social workers, and other
professionals are required to implement their findings and proposals. The
lingua franca of government and, therefore, of newspapers, classrooms, and
talk shows is a numerical one: statistics. Many people have come to believe
that almost any social problem can be reduced to quantifiable terms. Even
now, though, some people maintain that a few forms of behaviour are
inherently right or wrong, regardless of how convenient, practical, or
popular that conclusion might either be or seem at the moment.
Finally, there is something about democracy itself that encourages
“groupthink.” Although modern democracies are founded on the principle
of individual rights matched by individual responsibilities, they are founded
also on the principle of majority rule. Policies are established by counting
heads (although most democracies have found ways of avoiding tyrannies
of the majority).1 Those who think for themselves – those who depart, in
other words, from the consensus – are unlikely to see their positions upheld
by the state, unless they can convert a large enough group to their position.
But modern democracies are founded also on the assumption that elected
representatives are better informed and thus more competent than ordinary
citizens to make decisions. What does it mean, therefore, when public
policy is established more and more often on the ephemeral basis of public
opinion polls or popular demonstrations? What does it mean when elections
themselves are subverted time after time by broadcasting the results of exit
polls on television? It means that positions, even moral positions, are
considered legitimate to the extent that most people seem to agree with
them. Consensus is necessary to hold any society together, true, but only if
it is based on the consistent application of philosophical, legal, theological,
or moral principles.
Part of the problem in any research project is methodological. Which
variables should be considered? Which groups of people should be
questioned? How should the questions be formulated? How should the
results be tabulated? Another part of the problem is implicit bias. Even the
most academically responsible researchers make assumptions about men
and women that are reflected in both the questions they ask and the answers
they supply. Still another part of the problem, however, is explicit bias.
Some researchers are more interested in promoting feminist ideology and
thus the political and economic interests of women, for instance, than they
are in finding out privately, let alone acknowledging publicly, that women
not only can but often do resort to domestic violence. Consequently, they
overtly denounce studies that make their political or ideological programs
more complicated. They have good reason for fearing the results of many
studies, actually, because they indicate that the most fundamental
assumptions of ideological feminists about both men and women cannot be
supported by close scrutiny of the empirical evidence.
In any case, statistics are notoriously unreliable, perhaps because of
changes in the methods used by social scientists. From their inception over
a hundred years ago, the social sciences have been subject to raging debates
over method. Because social scientists themselves have repeatedly raised
questions about the validity of various methods, no one should be surprised
when “outsiders” raise questions of their own. Consider the words of Frans
de Waal, an ethologist:
I speak from years of frustration with the literature on human
behavior. How do people actually behave? Available are answers
to questionnaires, which at best reveal how people perceive
themselves and at worst how they wish to be perceived.
Available, too, are data on the behavior of human subjects in
experiments. People who do not know one another are brought
together in a laboratory room. All variables supposedly are under
tight control in such settings, but the link with real life is lost. The
observed social relationships have neither past nor future. We
might as well investigate the swimming of fish by taking them out
of the water. Where are the basic observations of human conduct
within the family, at work, at school, at parties, on the street, and
so on? Granted, there are methodological problems, but it should
not be too difficult to take notes on people in action – not more
difficult, surely, than fieldwork on dolphins or arboreal primates.
In the natural sciences, simple descriptive data form the bedrock
on which theories are built. Linnaeus preceded Darwin. The
social sciences, however, seem to be trying to skip this tedious
phase. Studies matching the descriptive detail of ethological work
on animals are not easily come by.2
Actually, anthropologists do try to provide this kind of descriptive detail.
Whether anthropology should be classified within the social sciences or the
humanities, however, is still a matter of debate. Depending on the interests
of any given anthropologist, it can have affinities with either.
Like the natural sciences, the social sciences are self-correcting. Social
scientists continually challenge the findings of their colleagues and revise
the findings of their predecessors. This is as it should be. Unfortunately,
many laypeople need to be warned against placing undue confidence in the
methods and findings of any particular researcher or even those of many at
any particular time and place. The answers are only as revealing, after all,
as the questions asked. Sometimes, questions are poorly framed. “After a
year of hand-wringing over a Roper poll that seemed to indicate that nearly
a quarter of Americans believed the Nazi Holocaust might never have
happened,” writes Jerry Adler, “the poll was shown to be flawed because
many people didn’t understand the question. In a new poll with better
questions the number of Americans who agreed that it was “possible … the
Nazi extermination of the Jews never happened” went down to 1 percent.
But the mere fact that professional researchers could make such a mistake
by inadvertence suggests the vast potential of statistics for misleading the
public by intention.”3
And the questions asked, as feminists themselves know well, are often
heavily influenced, whether consciously or unconsciously, by the
backgrounds and political interests of those who ask them. They might be
influenced also, unfortunately, by the conscious or unconscious
manipulation of figures by scholars with political or ideological axes to
grind. This should come as no surprise to anyone. Scholars in both the
social and physical sciences have long been aware – long before the advent
of postmodernism – that bias with respect to either the expected or the
desired results can present a problem in research.
It is good to be wary also of those who question statistics. Those who
dispute this or that figure might have much to lose if it is accepted. Denial,
too, is a form of bias. Sometimes denial is based on naivete; at other times,
though, it is based on something more sinister. What can we say about those
who argue, for instance, that “only” two or three million Jews were
murdered by the Nazis? Nazism would have been no less evil had it led to
the murder of one million, one hundred thousand, one thousand, or even
one hundred innocent victims. Notwithstanding the utilitarian point of view,
evil is a function of motivation in strictly moral terms, not of extent. In
emotional terms, of course, it is otherwise. We are much more disturbed by
murder on a colossal scale than murder on a smaller scale. Numbers do
count, therefore, when it comes to political action.
Nevertheless, not all challenges to statistical figures should be dismissed
or attacked as forms of denial. Sometimes, there really are good reasons for
avoiding statistical arguments or questioning them.4 Statistics are often
misused, whether intentionally or not. It is the mandate of scholars to insist
on the pursuit of truth, not expediency, but scholarly integrity is not the only
thing at stake. In a democratic society public policy, which is intended to
correct major social problems, is at stake too. If the facts we use to
understand these problems are nothing more than artifacts manipulated by
those of this political persuasion or that, then problems can never be
solved.5 “Great issues of public policy,” observes Adler, “are being debated
by people who have no idea what they’re talking about. Estimates of
homelessness range from 223,000 to 7 million. A United States senator
announced in debate that 50,000 American children were abducted by
strangers every year – a figure so striking that it took five years to dislodge
from public consciousness, although it exceeded the real number by
approximately 45,000.”6
Almost everyone has been caught off guard by the fact that not all
feminists are above bias. After all, ideological feminists have been very,
very vocal in condemning the bias of male scholars. (Their general support
for postmodernism notwithstanding, few feminists claim that all statistics
are biased; making that claim and including figures that support their own
positions would be self-defeating.) It is true that not all feminists are taken
in by ideologically biased statistics. Admitting in public that figures are
biased, though, is another matter entirely. Even to question the figures used
by ideological feminists is to invite the accusation of being part of a
“backlash.” Philip Sullivan has identified this as a major problem in
Canadian universities.7 Feminism has not attained universal respectability,
he writes, and for good reason. It is not merely a matter of men feeling
threatened by feminism and thus creating a hostile work environment for
feminists. It is a matter of distinguishing between rigorous and shoddy –
that is, tendentious – scholarship (which we discuss in chapter 10).
Moreover, men are not the only ones who question the work of feminist
academics.

One example of statistics abuse emerged in connection with divorce and


child custody. It began with the publication of The Divorce Revolution, by
Lenore Weitzman, who provoked a massive uproar by presenting statistics
to show that men experienced a much higher standard of living after
divorce and women a much lower one.8 Weitzman claimed that the standard
of living for men increased by 73% after divorce and that for women it
decreased by 42%. But scholars questioned her approach. “Amid the
hosannas for Weitzman’s findings that echoed in the nation’s courtrooms,
lecture halls, and legislative chambers … critics charged that her sample –
228 people who had been divorced in 1977–78 – was too small to be
representative. Furthermore, the respondents were all from Los Angeles, an
area which has its own unique culture of divorce and divorce laws. These
concerns, however, received little play in the press, and Weitzman shielded
her research from further scrutiny.”9 It was Richard Peterson, of the Social
Science Research Council, who first discovered that Weitzman had gotten
the math wrong.10 Using Weitzman’s own data, he observed, she should
have come up with 27% and 10% instead of 73% and 42%. But even his
figures were inadequate,11 as Geoffrey Christopher Rapp and others have
pointed out, because they were based on Weitzman’s questionable data and
failed to account for several significant variables.12
A much larger study was conducted by Atlee Stroup and Gene Pollock
on the basis of data collected between 1983 and 1987 by sociologists at the
National Opinion Research Center, which is affiliated with the University of
Chicago. Stroup and Pollock found that both wives and husbands have
financial problems after divorce. In the first year, according to their study,
the income of women declines by an average of 22% (30% for unskilled
women and 12% for professional women), far from the 73% found by
Weitzman. What they discovered about the income of divorced men,
though, was even more startling. Not only did their income not increase by
42%, it actually decreased by approximately 10% (19% for unskilled men
and 8% for professional men). These findings were reported at the National
Council on Family Relations in 1992 and then as “Economic Consequences
of Marital Dissolution” in the Journal of Divorce and Remarriage.13 Not
many academics were interested. “Weitzman’s claims having by that time
achieved a hammer-lock on public opinion,” challenges were very
politically incorrect.14
Meanwhile, her figures were being quoted and used in the most
influential venues. The American Sociological Association awarded
Weitzman its book award in 1986 for her “distinguished contribution to
scholarship.” Her statistics were so widely accepted and so tenaciously held
at all levels of society, represented by academic journals no less than
popular daytime talk shows, that even research from prestigious institutions
was ignored or attacked if it conflicted with what Weitzman had found. “It
was taken as a given that [the numbers] were correct,” says Angela James, a
sociologist at the University of Southern California. “I think there were
some concerns raised on the part of scholars in that area of research, but
they did not get nearly as much attention as the statistics themselves.
Almost every article on the subject – and on many related subjects – cited
that statistic … New scholars coming to the arena may not have read the
skeptical reviews but they definitely knew of Lenore Weitzman’s book.”15
As for Weitzman, she continued testifying in Congress and in state
legislatures across the country, influencing fourteen laws in California
alone. Eventually, in spite of evidence to the contrary, her figures were cited
in President Clinton’s budget for 1996. They had “attained the status of
received truth” (or, as we would put it in connection with ideology of any
kind, revealed truth).16
Whatever might be said about the motivation of Weitzman herself – no
one can ever know whether she made a stupid mistake or a clever one,
although the fact that she stonewalled for ten years before allowing the truth
to come out could make anyone suspicious – the motivation of those who
use her statistics is obvious. How, asks Rapp, did all this happen?
The answer was that in the increasingly radicalized atmosphere
that characterized the debate over the economics of divorce, the
73/42 statistic had the force of an idea whose time had come. The
disparity it pretended to uncover was so dramatic that it became
the perfect media sound-bite, a shocking factoid which after many
repetitions seemed to ring true. Perhaps more importantly,
Weitzman’s numbers could be used to promote just about any
agenda, further ensuring the statistic’s popularity. Weitzman
herself, for example, said that her study indicated the need for
changes within the no-fault system of divorce which by 1986 was
in place in 48 states. Others saw the statistics and recommended
scrapping no-fault entirely.17
Well, not any agenda. The numbers precluded any movement that might
have taken divorced fathers seriously. Susan Faludi and some other
feminists were out-
raged by public acceptance of Weitzman’s findings, sure, but they were
outraged only by what they took to be a backlash against the gains already
made by divorced women. Why interpret the phenomenon in that
counterintuitive way? Because they believed that “the media” had conspired
to scare women who might consider divorce by convincing them that doing
so would leave them on a downward economic spiral.18 Most feminists,
however, realized that the intentional or unintentional scare would
ultimately serve the interests of women by provoking demands for law
reform. Only Christina Hoff Sommers, as far as we know, understood that
these two conflicting interpretations really amounted to the same thing.
“Lenore Weitzman’s research is used by many groups of feminists to trash
men … no matter what. It’s either ‘men are monsters,’ or ‘we don’t need
them.’”19 Even now, after Weitzman has recanted and the story has been
told many times, her figures are hardly ever challenged. If this book had
been written by someone at Harvard, after all, how could it be wrong?
It is probably impossible to overestimate how influential
Weitzman’s 73 percent figure was … A search of databases found
that over 175 newspaper and magazine stories have since cited
Weitzman’s numbers. Even this figure understates enormously the
extent to which her findings have invaded popular culture. Like a
virus out of control, Wetizman’s results have surfaced in an
unknown number of reports in which her figures are erroneously
attributed to other sources … When looking at academic sources,
however, we are able to get a more accurate count of how
widespread Weitzman’s influence was. There were citations in
348 social science articles, 250 law review articles, and 24
appeals cases. Her figures were characterized as “ranking among
the most cited demographic statistics of the 1980s.”20
It was precisely with Weitzman’s phony statistics in mind that Cathy
Young wrote a review of First Wives Club. This cinematic comedy, based
on a best-selling novel by Olivia Goldsmith, is “about three aging women
who are dumped by their husbands and set out to get even, using various
sneaky and illegal tactics to bring the men under their thumb and strip them
of their property.”21 It was a hit at the box office, so we must assume that it
made a lot of women feel good about themselves and reinforced group
solidarity. Moreover, it was warmly greeted by critics in such influential
publications as Time22 and the New York Times.23 “The movie’s feminism is
a dubious sort,” writes Young. “It is not about women making it on their
own but about women taking men’s money: ‘I don’t get mad, I get
everything,’ says one character.”24 In other words, this movie is about
revenge. It feeds the revenge fantasies not only of women whose ex-
husbands have mistreated them, moreover, but also of most other women.
They “know” from Weitzman and other sources of what passes for
conventional wisdom that the game of divorce is usually won by men. On
the picketing of this movie by advocates of fathers, Young observes that
“[s]ome may chuckle that these men don’t have a sense of humor, a charge
often made against feminists. But the men have a point. It’s only a movie,
but the attitudes it promotes – that personal problems between men and
women are political, that the man is always to blame and the woman is
always the victim – has dangerous consequences in real life.”25 Among
these consequences was Weitzman.
Even during the 1980s, a few academics realized that domestic violence
was often committed or even initiated by women. In Britain, Erin Pizzey
wrote not only about domestic violence against women in Scream Quietly,
or the Neighbours Will Hear26 and established the first shelter in London
for female victims but also about domestic violence against men in Prone to
Violence.27 In the United States, Suzanne Steinmetz wrote an article on
“The Battered Husband Syndrome” for Victimology.28 But no research, no
matter how scholarly, could be undertaken seriously before the first national
survey was conducted by Steinmetz, along with Murray Straus and Richard
Gelles. In Behind Closed Doors,29 they reported what they themselves
could hardly believe: that 3.8% of husbands beat their wives but 4.6% of
wives beat their husbands.30
This new evidence was hotly denied by many feminists, who managed
for years to suppress any debate about it in the public square. Steinmetz
received scathing attacks from academics, more on rhetorical than academic
grounds. She received a bomb threat at the University of Delaware and a
threatening phone call at home from a woman: “If you don’t stop talking
about battered men, something’s going to happen to your children and it
won’t be safe for you to go out.”31 No one ever did attack her or her
children. Years later, though, Steinmetz found out that some colleagues had
tried to ruin her career by urging women on her faculty to lobby against her
promotion and tenure.32 Ironically, given the compassionate and egalitarian
rhetoric of feminism, the wonder is not that a few of them have resorted to
intimidation in the name of women but that any of them have.
Steinmetz admitted that “wives are injured in greater numbers by their
husbands” but also noted that “the average violence scores show wives to
be slightly more likely to resort to violence than husbands.”33 This was
unacceptable to those who had a vested interest in domestic violence as a
woman’s problem and an industry based on services to battered women. But
wait. The threats continued.
In an attempt to try to keep me from speaking, I had thinly veiled
threats put on me. I was speaking at an American Civil Liberties
Union conference [which championed free speech] and they
received threats. They were told if they allowed me to speak, the
place would be bombed … I was told before giving an address at
a Canadian university I would have major problems by one group
of radical women. They wrote to the college president and said I
should be stopped from coming to speak … What happened to me
was nothing, trust me, compared to what Murray Straus has gone
through. He always says I had it worse, but I don’t think so …
He’s had women academics come up to him and almost
physically accost him in the hall because they’ve been so angry.34
Even though Murray Straus, one of her co-authors, had been the
president of academic associations and had received awards for research on
families, he was heckled, booed, and picketed and targeted by a telephone
campaign accusing him of misogyny, sexual harassment, and even beating
his former wife.
It is almost beyond belief that some critics can ignore or dismiss
these studies. Perhaps even more serious is the implied excusing
of assaults by women because they result from frustration and
anger at being dominated. This is parallel to the excuses men give
to justify hitting their wives, such as a woman’s being unfaithful
… In my opinion, [these] are not feminist critiques, but
justifications of violence by women in the guise of feminism.
This is the betrayal of the feminist ideal of a nonviolent world. In
addition, excusing violence by women and denying
overwhelming research evidence may have serious side effects. It
may undermine the credibility of feminist scholarship and
contribute to a backlash that can also undermine progress toward
the goal of equality between men and women.35
As for Richard Gelles, Steinmetz’s other co-author, he faced similar
hostility from professional colleagues: no longer being elected to office in
professional associations, no longer being asked to speak at conferences,
and so on.
The same thing happened to R.L. McNeely, an attorney and a professor
of social welfare at the University of Wisconsin at Milwaukee. He, too,
wrote on the topic of domestic violence against men and had his career
threatened by ideological adversaries as a result. McNeely observed that
these feminists “are not about the search for truth. What this is about is a
search for political power. That is power based upon a concept of a
defenseless group of people being victimized by a larger, stronger
aggressor. When people start recognizing that, indeed, domestic violence
seems to occur both ways, that undercuts the whole concept of weakness,
out of which comes power. It’s based on a concept of being an exclusive
victim. That’s why some people react so strongly. A lot of these people are
absolutely convinced that they are on the ‘correct’ side.”36
Americans set the precedent for censorship of politically incorrect
information in 1979. Published evidence from a survey conducted for the
Kentucky Commission on Women included statistics only on the abuse of
women.37 Someone suppressed the ones on abuse by women. How do we
know, then, that 38% of the women acknowledged attacking men without
physical provocation? Because some professors eventually managed to get
hold of the original computer files.38 It is unnecessary to assume that
everyone involved in this scandal was motivated directly by feminist
ideology. Some might have been motivated by fear of losing research
grants, academic tenure, publishing contracts, or even common courtesy in
public from colleagues. This story was not new, but the context must have
seemed new to anyone who had believed that only men would stoop so low.
Because Behind Closed Doors had raised more questions than it could
answer, and despite the pious denials and condescending dismissals, at least
a hundred projects on domestic violence against men were begun over the
next twenty-five years. Approximately half the researchers were women,
and most of these women were feminists who expected to refute Straus,
Gelles, and Steinmetz.
The statistics on domestic violence against men might surprise many
readers, just as they did the early researchers. Nevertheless, these statistics
were found by reputable social scientists throughout the 1980s and 1990s.
People working on the subject of family violence now had a
choice: they could expand the field to include male victims –
establishing that abused men were not the same men that were
abusing, and vice versa for women – or they could do what they
did: devote an extraordinary amount of energy to shouting the
data down. For feminists, the idea that men could be victimized
was nonsensical. It didn’t square with their fundamental analysis
of wife assault – that it was an extension of male political,
economic, and ideological dominance over women. If women
were so clearly subjugated in the public domain, how could there
be a different reality behind closed doors? Activists anticipated,
moreover, that the … data might be used to devalue female
victims, in the manner of male lawyers, judges, and politicians
saying, “See? She does it too”; case dismissed.39
The same thing was happening in Canada. In 1989, a study found that
39.1% of the women questioned had assaulted their husbands, and 16.2% of
those who had been assaulted defined these assaults as severe. In fact, 90%
of the women who had asssaulted their husbands said that they had not
acted in self-defense. “They had been furious or jealous, or they were high,
or frustrated. Rational or irrational, impulsive or controlling, they had hit,
kicked, thrown, and bitten. Fourteen percent of the men went to the
hospital.”40 Another Canadian study conducted that very year at the
University of Alberta found that 12% of husbands and 11% of wives were
victims of domestic violence. Its findings on women were published, of
course, but not those on men.41
The debate over domestic violence was reaching a crescendo by the mid-
1990s, especially after the arrest in 1994 of O.J. Simpson for the murder of
his wife and her friend. Journalists came up with staggering figures. But not
everyone fomented hysteria.
How many battered wives are too many?
That’s an easy one: in an ideal world, even one is too many.
But we live in a glaringly imperfect world, in which battered
wives are only one exhibit in a panorama of human misery
clamoring for our attention. So when O.J. Simpson’s history of
wife-beating came to light after his arrest, women’s advocacy
groups were quick to point out that what was really shocking was
how often this happens among ordinary families. Undoubtedly
many Americans were shocked to read in Time magazine that 4
million American women are assaulted by a “domestic partner”
each year. It must have been especially shocking to those who
read in Newsweek that the number of women beaten by
“husbands, ex-husbands and boyfriends” was 2 million a year.
This is terrible. Not because of the implication that either Time
or Newsweek is wrong by a factor of 2, but because the
divergence reflects society’s actual state of ignorance on such an
important and theoretically verifiable statistic.42
Even today, these numbers are cited at least in the context of informal
discussions.

According to John Fekete, quantitative studies, with their presumably


scientific basis, have helped to create the view that all men are violent.
“Specifically, it turns out that the numbers look more alarming if research
subjects check off micro-actions from a list of event-descriptions, rather
than describe their interpretation of their own experience.”43 He goes on to
show how the set of scales created by Straus and Gelles (the Conflict
Tactics Scales) have been modified and then misused by other researchers
in the field (such as Mary Koss and her colleagues who did the Sexual
Experiences Survey reported by Ms. in 1987).44 The scales are misused
when research subjects are not allowed to interpret their own experiences,
when these are defined as abuse rather than conflict, or when rape is placed
“on a continuum with normal male behaviour within the culture.”45
Among the serious effects of ideological takes on violence against
women is the inflation of definitions. As a result, all men are stereotyped as
violent. Even in 1979, Lenore Walker, a psychologist and author of The
Battered Woman, had extended the definition of “violence” to include other
forms of intimidation. “A battered woman,” she writes, “is a woman who is
repeatedly subjected to any forceful physical or psychological behavior by
a man in order to coerce her to do something he wants her to do without any
concern for her rights.”46 Walker writes that in one case, “it is clear that
there was a good deal of provocation. There is no doubt that she began to
assault Paul physically before he assaulted her. However, it is also clear
from the rest of her story that Paul had been battering her by ignoring her
and by working late, in order to move up the corporate ladder, for the entire
five years of their marriage.”47 Walker referred even to professional women
whose husbands do not accompany them to social events! “Those women
who attempt to have some kind of social life never know whether their
batterer will be charming company, leave the party, become inattentive or
bored, or verbally humiliate them.”48
In view of this definition, Walker concluded that no fewer than one out
of every two wives can be classified as a victim and thus should not be
considered responsible for her own behaviour, including, apparently,
premeditated murder. This definition is an integral part of Walker’s larger
theory of violence – a profoundly ideological one, by the way, which has
been used extensively and effectively by Catharine MacKinnon and other
feminists in their efforts to rewrite existing laws. According to Walker, who
identifies herself as a feminist,49 violence against women (the only kind of
violence that troubles her) is “the misuse of power by men who have been
socialized into believing they have the right to control the women in their
lives, even through violent means.”50 Walker admits that “[u]fortunately …
I tend to place all men in an especially negative light, instead of just those
men who do commit such crimes. Perhaps when more is known about
batterers, we will need to view them also as victims.”51 In the meantime,
however, the presupposition of her psychotherapeutic approach is that “the
man is a batterer and the woman is a battered woman.”52
Many women (and even a few men) have moved step by step from the
belief that every man is a potential abuser to the belief that every man is an
abuser and also from the belief that every man is a potential rapist to the
belief that every man is a rapist. In other words, all men are evil. At one
time, rape was defined as something that strangers sometimes did to girls or
women. Nowadays, rape is defined as something that husbands or
boyfriends routinely do to women or girlfriends. Here is the ideological
trump card par excellence. What better way could there be to make women
afraid of men and thus feel the need of feminist measures to protect
themselves? Ideologues are quite willing to foster panic. Ironically, that
strategy has not generated new stereotypes, which would have been bad
enough, but given new life to old ones: women are passive and nonviolent,
according to both misogynists and feminists, men aggressive and violent.
These stereotypes not only allow misogynists to excuse their own behaviour
but also allow feminists to avoid the disturbing fact that women are capable
of violence.
According to Sommers, “the idea that a high percentage of American
men are brutes is promoted in three illegitimate ways”:53 first, by
generalizing from high-risk populations; second, by classifying pushes and
shoves and slaps as “battery”; third, by referring to studies that do not even
exist.54 Fortunately, women as well as men have begun to question the use
of statistics to manipulate the political process. Sommers is among those
who have discussed the hoax about Super Bowl Sunday. Here is the story.
On Thursday, 27 January 1993, a coalition of women’s groups met in
Pasadena to hold a press conference. They told journalists that the number
of women battered during or after the Super Bowl game on Sunday would
be 40% higher than on a normal day. To support that figure was Sheila
Kuehl of the California Women’s Law Center, who cited a study that had
been produced three years earlier at Old Dominion University in Virginia.
Also present, to add authority, was Linda Mitchell of Fairness and Accuracy
in Reporting (fair). Next day, Lenore Walker told viewers of Good Morning
America that she had come to the same conclusion after monitoring police
reports on these occasions for ten years. On the show with Walker was
Laura Flanders, another representative of FAIR. On Saturday, Lynda Gorov
wrote up the story for a major newspaper.55 What was the point of all this?
Even though violence against women occurs at all times, Americans were
told, it increases dramatically when fostered by the brutality of football,
which is emblematic of masculine culture. Cheering for the home team,
therefore, was tantamount to cheering for local rapists.
Where did these statistics originate? Could any reputable scholar vouch
for their legitimacy? Were other interpretations possible? Ken Ringle, at the
Washington Post, was among the very few journalists who even bothered to
ask these questions – risky ones, in fact, because anyone could accuse him
of misogyny for trying to defend men. Ringle got the runaround, in fact,
when he tried to follow the story’s trail. Janet Katz, one author of the study
cited by Kuehl, told him that her findings had nothing to do with Walker’s.
On the contrary, she and her colleagues had found no correlation at all
between admissions to emergency rooms and the occurrence of football
games. So that was a blind alley. Gorov admitted to Ringle that she had
never actually seen the study and advised him to consult her source at FAIR.
Mitchell, at FAIR, told him to consult Walker. Her office told him to consult
psychologist Michael Lindsey, a leading authority on battered women. And
Lindsay admitted that he could see no basis for Walker’s conclusions. When
other reporters later on contacted Walker, who was clearly at the epicentre
of this controversy, she replied that her findings were not for “public
consumption” (even though she had personally announced them on national
television) but only for “guidance” among advocates in women’s groups. “It
would have been more honest for the feminists who initiated the
campaign,” writes Sommers, “to admit that there was no basis for saying
that football fans are more brutal to women than are chess players or
Democrats nor any basis for saying that there was a significant rise in
domestic violence on Super Bowl Sunday.”56
On 31 January, Ringle’s story was published in the Washington Post, and
Robert Lipsyte warned readers of the New York Times that the Super Bowl
had turned into an “Abuse Bowl.”57 On 2 February, Gorov’s newspaper
published what amounted to a retraction of her earlier story, along with a
withdrawal by Steven Rendell of support for FAIR.58 Later on, Mitchell
admitted to Ringle that she had known during the original press conference
that Kuehl was distorting the Old Dominion study. In one sense, the story
was over. In another sense, however, the story had taken on a life of its own.
Sommers observes that “despite Ken Ringle’s exposé, the Super Bowl
‘statistic’ will be with us for a while, doing its divisive work of generating
fear and resentment.”59
During an interview as president of the National Organization for
Women, Patricia Ireland once told Charlie Rose about a study by the March
of Dimes which showed that battery of pregnant women was the number
one cause of birth defects. Sommers observes that
to repudiate … victimology statistics is to open oneself to
recrimination even from some dedicated and sincere feminists.
“What is so wrong,” they say, “with exaggerating and overstating
when trying to cope with an epidemic of wife abuse? Women are
suffering. In casting doubt on activists’ claims, you are doing far
more harm than good.” To this, [the] response must be that even
well-meaning untruths inevitably undermine the good-faith efforts
to help the victims of real abuse and discrimination. The acts that
constitute severe domestic violence are crimes that shatter lives;
those who suffer must be cared for and those who cause their
suffering must be prevented from doing further harm. But in all
we do to help, the most loyal ally to compassion is truth …
Divisive falsehoods like these are fueling resentments that blight
male/female relations in this country. Finally, phony feminist
statistics make for bad social policy. If Ms. Ireland, Ms. Quindlen,
Ms. Pollitt and their sisters-in-arms are right that the average male
is a serious threat to women, then a massive make-over of
American society would indeed be called for. If, however, 2%–
3% of men are abusive, then we need to target that group and
leave the remaining 97%–98% of men alone.60
Yet another major hoax is repeated relentlessly by journalists, academics,
and politicians. This one involves at least two feminist icons. In The Beauty
Myth, Naomi Wolf claims that no fewer than 150,000 women die in the
United States every year from anorexia. In Revolution from Within,61 Gloria
Steinem repeats that claim. The point in both cases is to make an
ideological claim: that men cause this “holocaust” of women. But the claim
is preposterous. Sommers learned from the Centers for Disease Control that
101 American women died of anorexia in 1983, 67 in 1988, and 54 in 1991.
Tragic on moral grounds, yes, but not on emotional – and therefore political
– grounds that were even remotely comparable to a “holocaust.”
Caused by men? That claim, too, is highly questionable. Women
participate actively and eagerly in the culture that produces anorectic
standards of feminine beauty, after all, and female stars in Hollywood –
Calista Flockhart and Lara Flynn Boyle come to mind – react angrily when
told that they are too thin and thus set bad examples for girls and young
women. Besides, men have historically – except for a very brief interval in
the 1920s and once again since the 1960s – preferred buxom women over
thin ones for the obvious reason, at least in earlier centuries, that the former
look as if they are healthy enough to bear healthy children. (During the late
mediaeval period, it is true, fashionable women were portrayed by artists as
very thin. But so were fashionable men.) Finally, neither Wolf nor Steinem
bothers to note the parallel between young women who starve themselves to
look beautiful and young men who consume dangerous anabolic steroids –
side effects include organ damage and even death – to look athletic or
macho.
At any rate, Sommers challenged Wolf’s and Steinem’s figure in Who
Stole Feminism? That was enough for Flanders, who attacked her in FAIR’s
newsletter.62 Although Flanders admitted that the 150,000 American
women did not die of anorexia every year, she accused Sommers (and,
presumably, the Centers for Disease Control) of using “highly dubious”
figures all the same. Many who die of anorexia, she averred, are mistakenly
reported in the statistics for heart failure or suicide.
Ms. Flanders should have called the CDC’s National Center for
Health Statistics … to learn just how many women between 15
and 24 (the prime anorexia years) are dying of heart failure. For
1991 the figure is 19. As for suicide, the 1991 figure is 649. Of
these young women, how many are likely to have been
dangerously emaciated and have had doctors who mistakenly
reported the cause of death as suicide rather than anorexia? It
would be astonishing if the number were as much as ten percent
of the total. That would add about 70 fatalities to the official cdc
figure.63
Our point here is not that feminists are unique in faking research for
political ends. That is clearly untrue. Our point is only that journalists and
politicians – and all citizens – should be careful before accepting at face
value bizarre statistics that just happen to support their own political
positions. At the very least, we should all refer to statistics that both support
and do not support our positions, especially when controversies have
erupted over the statistics on both sides. The harm done by hiding these
controversies can never be repaired, after all, because every article or book
that repeats tendentious claims is reproduced countless times by publishers,
cited in countless footnotes, and so on.
The same crescendo occurred in Canada at the same time. This was
partly local fallout from the American story of O.J. Simpson and partly
fallout from the local one of Marc Lépine. In Moral Panic, John Fekete
observes that a problem exists even at the governmental level. Statistics
Canada is a highly respectable and even venerable institution that has a
direct impact on public opinion and thus both direct and indirect influence
on legislation. But when it comes to gender, Fekete argues, Statistics
Canada produces documentation that is sloppy at best and deceitful at
worst. It is guilty, in short, of succumbing to the tyranny of political
correctness. Fekete indicts the growing industry of dubious research that is
intended to promote panic and rage among women, one result being to
manipulate the political process. Politicians should be influenced by public
opinion, yes, but what if public opinion is based on ignorance? Not many
politicians have the moral integrity or even the intellectual curiosity to
question statistics gathered by academics, let alone by government officials.
A 1993 study by Statistics Canada had the cooperation of six federal
departments, as well as police officers, some academics – Fekete calls them
“advocacy experts” – along with activists from transition houses, sexual
assault crisis centres, and ethno-cultural and refugee services, as well as
feminists.64 “[T]his whole project was developed during the height of the
post-Lépine ‘war-against-women’ panic, and in a way that guaranteed that
the survey would belong to the clinical population of violence victims and
to its biofeminist advocates.”65 The survey investigated the extent of
violence only against women and sought information only from women. It
ignored the possibility that women themselves might perpetrate violence
either against men or against other women.
What is scandalous is that this study, which purports to provide
pioneering national information about relationship interaction in
Canada, is a single-sex survey. In my view, the decision to ask
only women about acts of violence perpetrated against them is
highly partisan. The inflammatory figure, which is this survey’s
claim to fame, is that 51% of Canadian women have experienced
at least one incident of violence since the age of 16 … [T]he
question that was one of the two main staples for generating the
survey’s physical-assault data is a yes/no question: “Now, I’m
going to ask you some questions about physical attacks you may
have had since the age of 16. By this I mean any use of force such
as being hit, slapped, kicked, or grabbed to being beaten, knifed
or shot.”66
According to the results, one third of the victims complained of threats
so severe that they feared for their lives. But, points out Fekete, “Statistics
Canada is misreporting its own data: the figures here refer to perpetrators,
not to victims. It is not that 34% of women fear for their lives; nor that 45%
of women feared for their lives in a past marriage. It is that 34% of those
partners who were complained about made the women fear for their lives,
including 45% of the allegedly violent partners in past marriages.”67 The
study not only misinterpreted its own data but actually double-counted
figures to get these data. In addition, Fekete challenges the basic premise
that misunderstanding in connection with casual fondling can be included
legitimately with intimidation in connection with the most shattering
transgressions. Women were asked if they had ever received unwanted
attention from male strangers, say, or if they had ever been made to feel
“uncomfortable” by men who commented on their beauty or “blew kisses”
at them. The implication was that there is no moral difference between the
expression of heterosexual interest in a woman, albeit unwanted, and rape
(a topic that we discuss in chapters 8 and 9).
Not all statistics used by politicians are produced by academic or
governmental bodies. Among the most notorious examples of statistical
engineering cited by Fekete is a study produced by an overtly partisan
group: the Canadian Panel on Violence against Women.68 This study –
funded by the government, it cost taxpayers $10 million – claimed that 98%
of Canadian women are sexually violated. This conclusion is self-defeating,
in a way, because it looks too much like the “electoral victories” of 98% in
totalitarian countries. Why not simply claim, as some feminists do, that all
women are sexually violated or even that all men subject all women to
sexual violation? These claims require no statistical “evidence.” They are
supposedly self-evident on ideological grounds. As David Thomas points
out, these claims involve “an elementary error of logic: All buttercups are
yellow flowers, but not all yellow flowers are buttercups. Similarly, all
rapists are men, but that does not mean that all men are rapists. This is, of
course, part of an attempt to induce guilt by association … The notion that
all men are “capable” of rape is either … absurdly prejudicial, or
meaningless.”69 The Canadian study was considered necessary to convince
women who prefer not to think of themselves as ideologues. (An interesting
analogy could be made with religious people who prefer to believe that
science “proves” their theory of creation.) But who is going to take this
problem seriously, especially since most of those concerned about it (for the
time being) are men? And men, unlike women, are supposedly incapable of
honest scholarship when their own interests are at stake.
In 1995, Earl Silverman got the data on men from a research assistant
and wrote it up himself. No one would publish it.70 In 1997 a Canadian
study about abused men was suppressed. It found that 46% of the women
questioned and only 18% of the men had resorted to violence. Only the data
on men, in this case, were published. Someone found out, asked to see the
original research, and was refused. “It was only when he exposed the
refusal in his next book, combined with another three more years of
pressure, that the 46 percent female violence was released and published.
By that time, Canadian policy giving government support for abused
women but not abused men had been entrenched. As were the
bureaucracies; as were the private funding sources like United Way.”71 In
1999, the United Way of Greater Toronto increased its grant to services for
abused women and children by $1 million, the annual total then reaching
$3.3 million. This mainstream benevolent organization gave not one cent
for abused men.
Grant Brown writes that systemic discrimination against men is the
direct result of these biased statistics.
[P]artner abuse is routinely portrayed and acted upon as though it
were almost exclusively about men abusing and victimizing
innocent women and, by extention [sic], their children – despite
the overwhelming sociological evidence that a significant amount
of abuse is also suffered by male partners. The prevailing
orientation to the problem is typically supported by little more
than speculative, ideological rationalizations of the sociological
evidence, if not outright suppression or denial of that evidence.
Genuinely gender-inclusive research is needed to test the validity
of this orientation, and to determine whether it has had a
beneficial or detrimental effect on the administration of justice.72
Brown explains that research on this topic can be flawed in at least two
important ways. In some cases, it is based on sources that are incomplete
and hard to analyze. In other cases, it is focused on the work of judges or
police officials but not prosecutors.
Some feminists make no pretense of relying on statistics, even when
statistics might be used to serve their cause. Andrea Dworkin, for instance,
claims that her own intuition or insight supersedes any other form of
evidence. Her argument is based on what she calls “experience,” something
that is ultimately, by definition, beyond the grasp of anyone who has not
had her experience, something that transcends, in other words, the need for
discussion or research.
APPENDIX FOURSilencing Men: The Trouble with
Political Correctness
Contrary to the protestations of those now called “politically correct” by
their adversaries, this term was once used by the former themselves without
the slightest trace of irony. The first to do so, according to William Safire,
were on the left.1 The notion of “correct ideas,” or “correct thinking,”
originated in 1963 with Chairman Mao. It gained massive popularity among
his followers in the Western world with the publication of his Little Red
Book of ideological platitudes and slogans. For dedicated communists,
Safire continues, correct thinking was “the disciplined inculcation of a party
line expressed in all forms of social and political intercourse.”2 To those on
both left and the right, “correct” came to mean anything that reflected the
group’s opinions, doctrinal orthodoxy, conventional wisdom, and so on. In
the late 1980s more people (though still a minority) began attacking
conformity on the left, especially at universities. The term “politically
correct” thus became an insult.
Political correctness operates on the right, too. During the war in Iraq,
for instance, many dissenters claimed that they had been “censored.” (This
was ad hoc behaviour by individuals rather than censorship per se, however,
which is established by law.) The most famous examples, not surprisingly,
were in the entertainment industry. Consider only two of the most notorious
examples. Bill Maher, host of Politically Incorrect, observed on the air that
terrorists who crash into office towers, unlike American soldiers sending
missiles from a distance, were not cowards, whatever else they were. Soon
after that attack on conventional wisdom, his show was cancelled. Singer
Natalie Maines, of the Dixie Chicks, observed that she was ashamed that
the president, who was about to invade Iraq, came from Texas. This led to
public demonstrations of anger and an “apology” from Maines. Given our
ideological topic in this book and its primary venue at the university,
however, we focus attention here on the left.

Advocates of political correctness seldom even pay lip service to freedom


of expression, except, when pressed, as some abstract and remote ideal. On
the contrary, they often explicitly deny the value of free speech. Consider
one debate over precisely this in the pages of a Canadian academic journal,
bearing in mind that precisely the same arguments would be used in the
United States and many other Western countries. Supreme Court justice
John Sopinka wrote an article in University Affairs to support freedom of
speech as an essential requirement for scholarly debate, one that should be
protected by the law.3 In the next issue, an academic reader protested
vehemently. With beguiling rhetoric, Allan Hutchinson chastised those,
such as Sopinka, who want to appropriate freedom of expression to serve
their own political interests – that is, according to Hutchinson, to maintain
the status quo.4 Hutchinson opined that freedom of expression is never
above partisan politics and must be kept that way. But much of his
argument was facile. Yes, the debate over free speech does have a political
dimension. It does not follow that this is the only dimension, however, or
even the most important one. In fact, it has intellectual and moral
dimensions as well. By “privileging” the political, to use deconstructive
jargon, Hutchinson not only “problematized” the latter but also trivialized
it.
Hutchinson accused Sopinka, and others like him, of refusing to
acknowledge the political implications of supporting free speech. He
believed that merely admitting his own “political agenda,” moreover,
legitimated his position. Any possibility of evaluating either position,
therefore, surely lies in our ability to examine both in terms of some
criterion other than politics. In fact, Hutchinson’s political position was no
more innocent than Sopinka’s. If Sopinka could be accused of using a moral
or intellectual argument to bypass a political one, after all, Hutchinson
could be accused of using a political argument to bypass a moral or
intellectual one. In any case, Hutchinson’s political point was shot through
with questionable moral and intellectual assumptions.
Supporters of political correctness usually rely on the conspiracy theory
of history. “The problem is not so much to do with who favours freedom of
expression,” Hutchinson wrote, “but who benefits most from elevating it
above other values. Put crudely, it is those who have the power to speak, not
those without it. Established interests – white, male, straight, etc. – have
more to gain from prioritizing free speech over equality; it serves to
preserve the status quo rather than to change it.”5Quite apart from any
political connotations, this cynical passage has obvious moral connotations.
Hutchinson was accusing those who oppose political correctness of doing
so for sinister motives. He was accusing them, in effect, of evil. Because he
chose to argue on political grounds rather than moral grounds, however, he
felt no need to say so directly, much less to back up this assertion. It was
enough, for him, merely to use a verbal weapon in the political struggle.
Hutchinson claimed that equality and free speech are merely “competing
values.” In any case, from his point of view, free speech is an illusion. It is
fostered by those who actually have the “power to speak” instead of those
who do not. But this is questionable for at least three reasons. For one thing,
precisely who are those with this “power to speak”? By now, it could easily
be argued that straight white men are the only citizens without it. Whether
political correctness is actually enforced by law and policies or not, after
all, it is enforced by public opinion and always has been. To argue that even
the most scholarly critique of a feminist claim can be taken seriously in the
current atmosphere as the focus of intellectual debate rather than
ideological ranting is, relying on the most charitable interpretation, to be
incredibly naive.
Moreover, the opposition between equality and free speech is inherently
false. Free speech ensures that theory and practice coincide. To eliminate it
in the name of “equality and dignity” is, as we learned during the Vietnam
War, like destroying a village in order to save it.
Finally, free speech is precisely what guarantees the “power to speak,”
and not only for those with “established interests.” No one is arguing for the
opposite of political correctness, after all, in which only those with
established interests may say what they want. By suggesting that some
people are, Hutchinson skewed the debate. At issue for his adversaries, to
judge by the arguments they put forward, is not whether free speech should
be confined to themselves, either directly or indirectly, but how to extend it
more effectively to include everyone. As one observer put it, the notion of
respecting minority points of view by protecting them from other points of
view does nothing except “suppress free expression of the kind of strong,
distinctive beliefs and values that people will stand up for. So-called respect
for opposing views readily devolves into a sterile, paralysing kind of
political correctness.”6 If free speech is deliberately restricted to the few, it
is meaningless in the context of a democracy, let alone a university.
Opportunism can work both ways. It is true that straight white men now
have the most to gain from free speech. At the moment, how could it be
otherwise? They (and religious people) are the only ones now threatened,
explicitly and directly, with the loss of it. On the other hand, it is true also
that those who classify themselves as victims of free speech have the most
to gain from denying it to others. Advocates of political correctness confuse
justice with a dubious combination of expediency and revenge. Their
position is based not only on opportunism, moreover, but also on cynicism.
Instead of acknowledging the fear that new ideas might not compete
successfully with older ones, even in the university, they argue conveniently
that new interests cannot compete with older ones. In doing so, they affirm
the belief that scholarship is ultimately nothing more than a clever way of
seeking class privileges (whether old or new) rather than seeking truth (no
matter how haltingly). Consequently, the voices of those who defend older
ideas, or “interests,” must be drowned out and freedom of speech
eliminated – which is to say, offered only to those who claim some unique
need for it.
Hutchinson accused Sopinka of hypocrisy, too: arguing for freedom of
expression but then denying it in unpalatable cases. To make the point, he
presented a syllogism. Sopinka, he wrote, had advocated constitutional
protection for freedom of expression; murder, rape and violence are forms
of expression; ergo, Sopinka should advocate constitutional protection for
these physical forms of expression no less diligently than for verbal ones.
But the syllogism is foolish. There is a difference, a big difference, between
murder, rape, or any other kind of violence and unkind words or even – and
this is really what matters in the debate over free speech in the university –
opposing ideas. At this point, Hutchinson revealed his own hypocrisy by
claiming to fight for those who need protection from unkind words. His
own words, however, could have been profoundly offensive to the victims
of murder, rape, and other forms of violence.
But something else is involved in this debate. It is often argued that
unkind words can lead to violence. And so they can. But banning them, too,
can lead to violence. One reason people resort to violence, after all, is
precisely their sense of having no legitimate outlet to express their fear,
frustration, or anger. For decades, the communist countries of Eastern
Europe did everything they could to oppose expressions of nationalism,
individualism, and everything else considered bourgeois, reactionary, or
antisocial. The results in, say, the former Yugoslavia, hardly justify their
efforts. What every democratic society must do, what every university
exists to do, is encourage people to think for themselves. Of course this
involves risk. But nothing worthwhile – not maturity, not democracy, not
scholarship – is without risk. Hutchinson used the rhetoric of equality to
undermine freedom of speech and, in doing so, transformed old inequalities
into new ones.
Less aggressive or sophisticated advocates of political correctness often
base their claim on what sounds irrefutable: the need for sensitivity. But
they, too, are hypocritical. On closer examination, they invariably argue for
selective sensitivity – that is, sensitivity to some groups of people but not
others. This is not sensitivity to others as a general moral principle. People
are always more sensitive to some people than to others. They are more
sensitive to those of their own kind, whether defined by race or sex or
anything else, than to those they consider threatening. But selective
sensitivity is a lamentable fact of life, not a worthy moral goal.
What goes around, as they say, comes around. There is a perfectly good
reason to use “politically correct” in a pejorative sense, especially when
applied ironically to the heirs of those who first used it in describing
themselves and to the leaders of our own time who purport to represent
diversity! It focuses attention, legitimately, on the belief that their own way
of thinking is correct and all other ways incorrect (or, among the more
cynical, that some ideas are expedient for promoting the cause and others
inexpedient). This belief in “our truth” versus “their truth” makes sense in
terms of divine revelation, it is true, but divine revelation is hardly an
authority that could or would ever be claimed by those who believe that
Western religions are really insidious “superstructures” designed to generate
“false consciousness” and thus maintain bourgeois or patriarchal hegemony.
The problem with those who insist on political correctness has nothing at
all to do with the causes that they promote. It has everything to do with the
self-righteous, anti-intellectual, and even totalitarian way that they go about
doing so (stifling debate by censoring free speech through laws or
behaviour codes) and the opportunistic use that they make of a double
standard (ignoring or even assaulting the feelings of those who are excluded
from their list of society’s official victims – which is to say, those who had
done the same thing to them).
The politically correct, among others, ostensibly have one main goal:
eradicating prejudice. And who could argue with that? There have indeed
been serious cases of prejudice against minorities in modern Western
societies (though no more than in other societies). Hindus in Britain
protested when Matchbox Toys produced a series of figures called Monster
in My Pocket, which included the following: werewolves, hobgoblins,
zombies, ogres, vampires, ghouls, witches, hunchbacks and two popular
Hindu deities: Ganesh and Kali.7 Muslims have long pointed to prejudice
directed against them in press coverage of Islamic fundamentalism and
terrorism. This problem was addressed directly by President Bush after 11
September 2001. In the 1970s, however, cartoons often showed Arab
sheiks, sinister with their exaggerated Semitic features, standing behind gas
pumps and leering. Arab stereotypes of oversexed degenerates, shrewd
scoundrels, bloated slave traders, and so forth had long been featured in
popular movies.8 The same problem can be found even in academic circles.
Jews have discovered, for example, that Christian feminists sometimes
succumb to traditional anti-Semitic polemic. In this case, Christians present
Jesus as someone who had come to liberate women from their enslavement
under the patriarchal laws of Judaism.9 The fact is that identity, whatever its
basis, is not always respected. The complexity of reality as minorities have
experienced it is not always acknowledged. Due to the imbalance of power,
moreover, it is seldom easy for members of minority communities (and
women in the past) to speak out. As a result, they feel “silenced.”
At the very least, an effort should be made to avoid language that
excludes whole groups of people. Linguistic history notwithstanding, it is
obvious to most people by now that the generic “he” no longer refers to
both men and women. Fortunately, the English language is easily adapted,
both grammatically and aesthetically, in most situations. Simply by using
the plural instead of the singular, for example, speakers and writers can
avoid constructions that are either clumsy (“he or she,” and “his/her”),
ungrammatical (“their” when referring to a single person), or
unpronounceable, legalistic, and, well, barbaric (“s/he”).
No doubt aware of this, some people nevertheless prefer more
pretentious solutions. They do not want merely to avoid inappropriate
language. They want to demonstrate their own rectitude. Sometimes,
therefore, they make a point of alternating between the generic “he” and the
generic “she.” Sometimes, they do not even bother with that self-conscious
declaration of their commitment to equality. In an article for the august and
venerable Journal of the American Academy of Religion, for example, Mark
Cladis uses the generic “she” throughout. “A reasonable person,” he writes,
“is someone who, among other things, desires to justify her beliefs when
confronted with sensible doubts or questions. She will ask herself…”10 In
this heavy-handed way, Cladis preaches as well as teaches. Quite apart from
presenting ideas or theories about the subject at hand, he treats his righteous
feminist readers to moral edification even as he exposes his ignorant sexist
readers – for their own good, presumably – to moral chastisement. After
reading the article, some readers might conclude that the subtext
establishing his own moral, political, and ideological credentials is more
important to Cladis than the essay itself. In another essay in the same issue,
James Wiggins, president of the Academy, indignantly and pretentiously
uses “sic” to correct the generic “he” in a quotation by Albert Einstein!11
Well, what is the solution to the problem of previously ignored groups?
To take revenge by silencing others? To claim the need for protection from
the pressures of public or academic debate? To ignore scholarship as an
excuse for promoting political expediency? Unfortunately, the desire to
control what others say, even if initiated with good intentions, has a
profoundly destructive impact on any free society. This brings us to some
egregious cases of prejudice against majorities. Does that sound
preposterous? If it does, our society is in big trouble. By definition, after all,
a democracy must allow the majority to dominate (though not persecute).
Discrimination against the majority, therefore, must not be dismissed as
irrelevant. It has serious moral and legal implications.
Participants in the interfaith memorial service for victims of a Swissair
disaster, for instance, represented several religions. Included were
Christians, Jews, and Muslims. The service was supposed to be ecumenical,
of course, but it was not. Jewish and Islamic but not Christian scriptures
were read. Agreeing to this, in fact, was a condition for the participation of
Christians at all.12
Political correctness is always linked closely with deconstruction, both
being tools used together by postmodernists. Deconstruction involves the
“destabilizing” or “subversion” of institutions, beliefs, and so on. Which
ones? Those that are politically incorrect. Which ones are politically
incorrect? Those that have been deconstructed. That the aim of
deconstruction is to destroy one thing and replace it with another, not
merely to add “diversity,” is made surprisingly clear. In an essay for the
New York Times Magazine, Bob Morris discusses a brochure depicting a
model family. On the surface, every member seems to be healthy, happy,
and wholesome. But Morris finds out that the truth is less attractive.
It all seemed pretty seamless. Model son played sweetly. Model
dad watched lovingly. Model mom remained upstairs in makeup.
For this they were earning a couple thousand dollars each. So
how would I unravel them? It turned out I didn’t have to. Because
as soon as I asked about their home life, model dad got testy.
Then, when I asked him how long he and model mom had been
married, he became belligerent. Why? Because they’re not
married. They don’t even live together. And of course it would be
very bad for their image were I to report such a thing. After
meeting model mom (who seemed to have almost nothing to say
to model dad) I left them in the Rockwellian world of art-directed
hugs and turkey, relieved to know that the model family is only a
model family when it’s paid to be one.13
At one level, Morris takes justifiable pleasure in the unmasking of self-
righteous hypocrisy. We all know that those who present themselves as
ideal types seldom live up to expectations. At another level, though, Morris
suggests that there is something wrong with having ideals in the first place.
For him, the paintings by Norman Rockwell that represent an ideal America
are not merely sentimental but dangerous. They give people the shocking
impression, he believes, that “traditional” families (which most people
understand as one in which both mother and father live with their children)
is better than other forms of family life. In fact, he suggests, it is worse.
Hence his relief at discovering the sinister reality that underlies the glossy
facade.
This way of thinking, however, is not just selectively cynical and self-
righteous but self-defeating as well. No society can exist unless it presents
people with some ideals to emulate. Of course no one ever attains the ideal
totally or perfectly. Is that any reason to abandon the ideal itself? According
to the more politically expedient postmodernists, it is indeed. They believe
in the legitimacy, even the necessity, of blurring the distinctions among fact,
opinion, and interpretation. “[It] is a measure of how far we have gone, or
how far we are, in the belief that any social reality is an arbitrary
construction that could just as easily have been any other social reality, and
that knowledge is only, or mainly, a form of power, and that power is
domination of the kind that pits the simple and unevolving dominator, with
his reality against a simple and unevolving dominatee, with hers.”14
Moreover, political correctness always involves some form of
opportunism. In their massive effort to bring women back into history,
politically correct feminists often feel free to turn historical figures into
modern feminists or proto-feminists. This is obviously the case in popular
culture, which has always treated history as a source to be ransacked for the
stories of people who can be transformed into heroic icons or at least
adjusted to suit the needs and tastes of later generations. The same is true,
though, of elite culture. Whether they call it revisionism or not, for
example, historians have always revised history in view not only of new
facts that come to light but of new theories or ideologies that come into
fashion. But few historians, until recently, did so intentionally. Nowadays,
some academics believe that doing so is an appropriate way of
“deconstructing” history, of giving a “voice” to marginalized groups. But
they do not always listen carefully to those being studied. As a result, they
fall into the same trap as their adversaries: reading into the past what they
think should have been there.
Consider the case of Carolyn Karcher, author of The First Woman in the
Republic: A Cultural Biography of Lydia Maria Child.15 In a review of this
book, Drew Gilpin Faust discusses the ahistorical result of politically
correct and deconstructive historiography.
The author demonstrates her ahistoricism [by observing] that
Child’s work seems to have a “startlingly modern ring.”
Throughout her book, Ms. Karcher views Child within the context
of her own 20th-century concerns and standards, rather than
offering a textured portrait of the way Child herself viewed her
world. Ms. Karcher hails her for variously “anticipating” the
20th-century historians Richard Slotkin, Richard Drinnon and
Sara Evans; “recent trends in feminist scholarship”; “the
revolutionary 20th-century educator Paulo Freire” and even
Freud.
Ms. Karcher is then discomforted when Child, quite naturally,
shows herself [to be] a daughter of her own age: demonstrating a
distressingly tenacious ethnocentrism; a “tinge of racism”; an
unfortunate paternalism; anti-Catholic, anti-French and anti-Irish
bias; and an inability, late in life, to comprehend the class and
labor conflicts that were emerging around her. Although Ms.
Karcher struggles to construct Child as a proponent of a “truly
egalitarian, multicultural society,” she is ultimately disappointed,
admitting that Child “would never succeed in formulating an ideal
of human brotherhood that did not involve the absorption of other
cultures into her own.”16
At least Karcher is able to admit defeat in this respect. Not everyone is
that honest. Faust’s concluding observation is extremely interesting:
“Making a historical case from present knowledge is an ethnocentrism
operating over time instead of over social or geographical space.”17
APPENDIX FIVERespectable Porn: The Debate over
Romance Novels
Romance novels present a problem for feminists. On the one hand, they are
formulaic books of little or no literary value. And worse, the formula
reinforces stereotypes of women. On the other hand, they are written both
by and for women.1Obviously, much hangs in the balance when their
cultural function is discussed. Why do women write them? Why do women
read them? So far, most feminists have condemned these novels as
anachronisms even as they have defended their authors and readers as
unwitting dupes of a patriarchal society that prevents women from
understanding their own oppression. More recently, though, feminists have
begun to defend both the books and their readers.
The romance genre, addressed to women, is often compared to one or
more genres addressed to men. These are usually said to include not only
science fiction, adventure, and war but also porn. Feminists have noted that
the female characters are either crudely stereotyped and “objectified” (as in
porn) or almost non-existent (in the other genres).2 Although these
productions clearly serve some need of the men who buy them, therefore,
they are not considered respectable. Neither were romance novels until very
recently, although they clearly serve some need of the women who buy
them. Apart from anything else, these books present women as victims who
are saved by strong men – that is, naive young women who end up happily
and safely married to powerful men. Why would any feminists approve of
that scenario? For several reasons, actually. One thing is certain: these
books have been reevaluated, reclassified, and sometimes rewritten as the
literature of female “empowerment.” The male characters are just as
stereotypical as ever, of course, but no one cares about them. To the extent
that male characters are stereotyped and “objectified” in the interest of
female ones (and female readers), though, these stories could be called
“respectable porn.”
Angela Miles has produced a most ingenious and elaborate defence. Far
from being embarrassed by romance novels, she uses them as evidence for
(among other things) the theory of comparative suffering so useful in
promoting feminist ideology. Fantasies of an ideal lover who is both strong
and sensitive are so popular among women, she claims, because women –
unlike men, presumably – are emotionally deprived. We can see that
women suffer more than men, she argues, because otherwise men would
produce romantic fantasies for themselves. Instead, they produce
emotionally empty pornographic fantasies. In what follows, we examine
romance novels and the debate that they have provoked in more detail,
bearing in mind this underlying assumption.

According to Sarah Bird, approximately “600,000 readers belong to


Harlequin’s book club and buy, sight unseen, month in, month out, every
book in their favourite series. Readers’ letters, focus groups, surveys, and
sales enable the editors to keep their fingers on the pulse of their audience.
This information in turn is passed along to writers as guidelines. Looking at
the these tip sheets after being absent for more than five years, I’m
convinced that if you want to know what is up with women in the land, you
could do worse than consult the rules of the romance-writing game.”3
Well, what precisely is up with women in the land of Harlequin? This is
what Miles tries to answer in “Confessions of a Harlequin Reader:
Romance and the Myth of Male Mothers.”4 Because feminists have
frowned on romance novels for allowing women to escape into reactionary
fantasies in which women are swept off their feet and rescued by strong
men and because literary critics look down on them for pandering to
unsophisticated low-brows who are satisfied with formulaic plots and
verbal clichés, Miles feels the need to spend her first four pages merely
explaining her desire to defend them in the first place. Some of her attempts
to do so are, to be charitable, naive. “Readers of westerns,” she avers, “are
not commonly supposed to live in expectation of a stage coach at the door
but Harlequin readers are presumed to believe in the Harlequin world and to
live in daily expectation of the hero’s arrival.”5 Not so fast. Readers or
viewers of westerns are not expected to believe in the literal reality of stage
coaches, to be sure, but they are often expected to believe in the
metaphorical and psychological reality that underlies the mentality of
gunslingers. It was for precisely this reason that many Americans were
dismayed when George W. Bush, from Texas, became president. It could
be, as Miles argues, that Harlequin readers “have as good a grasp on reality
as any other formulae readers,”6 but is that anything to celebrate? From
what she herself writes elsewhere in her article, we would say no.
Although Miles presents her discovery of Harlequin romances as a
“coming out” story, that genre is derived from a much older narrative genre
with deep roots in Western culture. Several terms used by Miles, including
one in the title itself, “confessions,” indicate a connection, consciously or
unconsciously made, with an earlier phase of this older genre. We are
referring to the Protestant conversion story. Like so many of the
testimonials by evangelicals, hers is marked by the characteristic movement
from confession of shame and guilt, to repentance, on to the “born again”
experience, and, finally, to “sharing.”
Like most women, I think, I read one or two Harlequins over the
years when nothing else was available. All I saw, at first, were
sexist, predictable, often poorly written stories with boorish
heroes and embarrassingly childish heroines. They have a rigid
formula which, unlike many other aspects, has remained
unchanged over the years … Imagine my surprise when I first
found myself actually enjoying a Harlequin. It was one summer
when I stayed at a friend’s cottage and it rained for days and days.
I lay on a comfortable sofa … After I returned to the city and the
pressures of thesis writing, I continued to read the occasional
Harlequin; but I sometimes chose to read them when other books
were available. At the time, I explained my pleasure in them by
the fact that I was very, very busy and tired and needed a break …
Gradually, I began to read more and more Harlequins, until one
day, when I found myself about to buy one, I began to suspect I
was hooked … As soon as I realized this, I “came out.” As a
feminist I know that the personal is political and that we must
struggle individually to change ourselves as well as collectively to
change society. Yet I didn’t want to lose the strange comfort I
found in Harlequins and I didn’t feel they were terribly
destructive or sinful. I could justify making Harlequins a non-
struggle area of my life only if I genuinely felt they weren’t so
bad. And if they weren’t so bad I had to be able to tell my friends
that I read them. In any case, skeletons in the closet leave you
awfully vulnerable, if not to blackmail then to terrible
embarrassment, and I wasn’t up to living with the risk. I didn’t
make a public announcement or send cards but I did drop it into
conversations whenever I could.7
Once Miles discovers the hidden key that unlocks the mystery of why
women like romance novels, she reveals it to other women with the zeal of
a missionary. They, too, can now indulge in their secret passion without
guilt or shame. Not only are these novels not politically anachronistic or
artistically worthless, according to Miles, they are also psychologically or
even spiritually redemptive. “When a reader knows the Harlequin formula,
she can identify the hero figure immediately, anticipate the pattern of
events, and is involuntarily caught up in an extremely active and demanding
psychological interaction with the text, one that has been called, without
irony or exaggeration, ‘the Harlequin experience.’”8 Just as religious
experience usually precedes theology (which is an attempt to explain the
ineffable experience in cognitive terms), this introduction precedes analysis
(which is her attempt to explain the subjective in objective terms). “My
experience as a feminist and Harlequin reader starkly raised the question
“What do they offer me?” I began reading Harlequins before they were
even slightly influenced by the values of the women’s movement … and as
a feminist I often found their message/story offensive. I had to suspend or
censor these judgement/feelings in order to enjoy the book. The fact that I
could do this suggested that there was another level of meaning for me.”9
The explanation offered by Miles is really very simple. The romance
novel is not as childish as it seems. In fact, it is really a roman à clef. Or, to
pursue the religious analogy in her title, it is a myth: a story that is told in
symbolic language and that reveals some truth about the human condition.
As such, it consists not of idiosyncratic individuals in complex situations
but of archetypal characters in idealized situations. Miles describes the
essential and archetypal attributes of the heroine, the “other man,” the
“other woman,” and the hero. A brief description of each should explain a
great deal about Miles and her political perspective, even if it does not
explain a great deal about the Harlequin romance itself.
The heroine is generally a waif-like creature. She might be an orphan,
penniless, far from home, or inherently vulnerable in some way. She has
some psychological problems, too. Very often, she is accident-prone.
Sometimes, she is just plain silly. She is almost always unsure of herself in
some basic way. For this very reason, feminists have attacked the genre.
Why, they argue, should women be infantilized? Why should heroines be
women who cannot make it on their own but depend, instead, on men? If
the heroine is ultimately looking for fulfilment in heterosexual love, though,
she gives in (to what Miles apparently considers a weakness) only at the last
moment.
It … has been suggested that the uppity, reactive, foot-stamping
behaviour of the heroine may give women readers pleasure
because they like to see heroines who can talk back to men and
give them a hard time. Readers like heroines who do not try to
please and impress men, who are, at least at first, indifferent to
male opinion. Certainly, the heroine is never looking for a man or
thinking of marriage. If she is not indifferent to men and
marriage, she has an absolute aversion. Early on she isn’t
interested enough to use feminine wiles; later she disdains their
use. One explanation put forward for this is that the heroine’s lack
of interest in the hero is required by a traditional code that forbids
“good” women to take an active part in initiating sexual
relationships. But when I first began to ponder the heroine’s
unvarying initial indifference or aversion to the hero, it seemed to
me that the heroine’s lack of initiative is important not primarily
because we are bound by an internalized patriarchal morality but
because it indicates genuine love (whatever that is).10
Miles claims to know precisely, however, what is meant by “genuine love.”
The heroine wants to be “loved for herself, warts, tantrums and all.”11 In
short, she yearns for the kind of unconditional love she had, or wanted, as a
child.
The “other man” is, of course, an inadequate man. He is the one not
chosen by the heroine. In fact, he is the foil against which the hero is
measured. He is the stereotypical wimp. “These ‘other men’ are weak,
childish, dependent, sullen, and needy. They whine and pout and constantly
demand attention and mothering from the heroine.”12 Not surprisingly, the
heroine rejects him in no uncertain terms. “Harlequins,” observes Miles,
“are about not having to mother men.”13 In fact, the heroine wants a man to
take care of her. There is a double standard here. Men who want someone to
take care of them are contemptible wimps, but women who want the same
thing are sympathetic heroines.
Corresponding to the “other man,” is the “other woman.” She is the
heroine’s rival for the hero’s love. Unlike the heroine, according to Miles,
she is aggressive and domineering. “In earlier Harlequins, these [characters]
are a whole species of extremely beautiful, manipulative women who
pretend to be all heart and warmth to men but don’t bother to hide their
coldness, indifference, and cunning from other women. Your quintessential
male-identified woman.”14 But in the Harlequin world, as in the real world,
things are changing. “In more recent Harlequins, the other woman is much
less likely to be a nasty, male-identified, woman-hating manipulator. She
may be kind and friendly, warm, generous, and gifted, but still breath-
takingly beautiful and a feared potential rival for the hero’s love.” Being up
to date and politically correct in a feminist age, we surmise, means that no
woman – not even the “other woman,” – may be portrayed in a negative
way. Though idealized, the new “other woman” remains a rival in relation
to the heroine. No longer “bad,” she is nevertheless envied and feared by
the heroine.
Of primary importance for Miles, though, is the hero. He, too, stands in
symbolic opposition to the “other man.” Not only does he not depend on the
heroine, he also remains indifferent to her until the very last page.
Moreover, he is often patronizing, boorish, arrogant, or even sinister. In
fact, he often bullies the heroine. On the other hand, he has many admirable
qualities. He is strong, for instance, and self-sufficient.
In view of all this, the archetypal romance novel is surely Gone with the
Wind, by Margaret Mitchell. After more than sixty years, the book remains
popular. (Even more popular, though, is the filmed version.)15 The story has
always appealed primarily to women. It can be seen, in fact, as the romance
novel’s direct prototype.16 Its major characters certainly correspond to the
types characteristic of this genre. Scarlett O’Hara is the sheltered but
determined heroine. Melanie Wilkes is the perfect but resented “other
woman.” Ashley Wilkes is the chivalrous but wimpy “other man.” And
what of Rhett Butler?
Consider what Helen Taylor says of him in Scarlett’s Women: Gone With
the Wind and Its Female Fans: “Swashbuckler and tough guy; entrepreneur
and war hero; enigmatic stranger and relaxing confidant; sexual wizard and
tender parent; wanderer and home-lover; iconoclast and visionary. Is it any
wonder he is the stuff female heterosexual fantasy is made of, or that so
many women find his final parting so profoundly tear-jerking?”17 Of
particular interest here is Taylor’s assertion that Rhett “must surely be the
twentieth-century prototype of the hero of postwar mass-produced romance
fiction, he who combines a restrained violence with gentle nurturant loving,
and who remains (until the end) a sexually magnetic enigma.”18 As the
characteristically idealized but ambiguous hero, in short, he is warm,
generous and protective, but also dark, aggressive, and vaguely sinister.19
Vaguely sinister? Even though Rhett is considered disreputable in elite
circles, readers or viewers are expected to sympathize with this honest and
straightforward man rather than the smug or outdated leaders of polite
society. Even though he has acquired considerable wealth through gambling
and piracy, moreover, viewers are expected to admire his enterprise and
ambition. All the same, as Taylor points out, they are expected also to be
thrilled by his more threatening characteristics, especially those
conventionally and stereotypically associated with maleness. Even his
physical appearance is big, muscular, predatory, and animalistic – unlike
Ashley, who is elegant, aesthetic, reserved, refined, sensitive, moralistic,
civilized – and thus associated stereotypically with femaleness. In the book,
Rhett “is associated with the forces of evil, mystery and male sexuality,
with his black eyes, hair, face and clothes and his wild stallion. His
darkness allies him with other legendary and fictional figures, too, from the
pirate and villain of melodrama to the swarthy Victorian hero and the
gangster. Attractive but sinister, sexually irrepressible but morally repulsive,
all these are connotations of the dark and inscrutable Rhett Butler.”20
Because these qualities are far less obvious in the movie than in the
book, very few female viewers have consciously thought of Rhett as
sinister. On the contrary, they have admired his virile and handsome
appearance, his sophisticated way with women, his shrewd approach to life
in general and pragmatic approach to politics in particular, his insight into
human nature, his gentleness with Bonnie, his appreciation of Melanie and
– most of all – his patient devotion to Scarlett. He understands her. He woos
her. He pampers her. And yet he, well, rapes her.
It is possible, at any rate, to interpret his behaviour in one scene with that
in mind. The most famous scene in the movie, the one featured on countless
posters and lobby-cards, the one that suggests a reason for the movie’s
extraordinary popularity among women, shows Rhett carrying Scarlett to
the bedroom upstairs – against her stated will. Although the women of
earlier generations seldom interpreted this as a rape scene, some do now.
The controversy is not exactly trivial. It has enormous symbolic, and thus
political, significance. It is notorious enough, in fact, to have been discussed
in a column of the New York Times: “Word for Word: A Scholarly Debate.”
The particular debate began after Christina Hoff Sommers told an
audience that “[m]any women continue to enjoy the sight of Rhett Butler
carrying Scarlett O’Hara up the stairs in a fate undreamt of in feminist
philosophy.”21 Incensed, Marilyn Friedman told another audience that the
behaviour of Sommers could be described as “treasonable to women.”22
Friedman declares that only someone ignorant of feminism could claim that
rape is “a fate undreamt of in feminist philosophy.” But Sommers said
precisely the reverse. She argued not that Scarlett’s fate was rape but that it
was something far more complex and ambiguous than rape. “I have read
quite a lot of what the gender [ideological] feminists write,” replied
Sommers. “And I have learned that they almost always interpret a text in a
way that puts the most humiliating construction on women’s experiences
with men. The gender [ideological] feminist … ‘subtext’ of almost
everything written about men and women in the patriarchy is rape,
prostitution, debasement.”23
Well, was it rape or not?24 Even Friedman admits that the case for rape is
debatable, at least theoretically. “By the time Butler gets to genital
penetration, O’Hara is sexually aroused.”25 Presumably, she becomes an
automaton; totally controlled by Rhett – or, better still, by ways of thinking
and feeling engrained in her mind by men in general – Scarlett cannot be
held responsible for behaviour that she herself later regrets. But Friedman
ignores the larger context of this scene. When Scarlett wakes up the next
morning, after all, she is happy with whatever fate had befallen her the
night before. Because this is so obvious in the movie, Friedman turns
instead to the book. “In her own words of recollection the next morning, as
written by Margaret Mitchell, O’Hara had been ‘humbled,’ ‘hurt’ and
‘used’ … brutally.’”26 But the words quoted have been taken out of context.
Friedman has forgotten, apparently, to quote the entire passage: “And now,
though she tried to make herself hate him, tried to be indignant, she could
not. He had humbled her, hurt her, used her brutally through a wild mad
night and she had gloried in it.”27 Ignoring this little technicality, Friedman
continues: “O’Hara, it seems to me, has a more credible understanding of
her own experience than does Sommers.”28 Actually, it is Sommers, not
Friedman, who finds Scarlett’s own understanding credible. And not only
Scarlett’s understanding, we might add, but that of all the women who, for
whatever reason, find this episode so delightful.
Friedman admits that “the narrow definition of rape” might not be
applicable. “However, I use the term ‘rape’ in a wider sense, in which it
refers to any very intimate sexual contact which is initiated forcibly or
against the will of the recipient. Perhaps … we should refer to this wider
notion as ‘sexual domination.’” In other words, as Sommers points out,
“Friedman insists that even when ‘no’ turns to ‘yes,’ a rape has occurred …
She now finds herself in the position of conceding to the macho male the
sexist thesis that women like the idea of being raped (in the ‘wider
sense’).”29
Friedman argues that “this scene arouses the sexual desire of some
men.”30 In other words, it is pornography. Actually, there is no evidence
whatsoever that men like this scene. In fact, the entire movie has never been
particularly popular among men. According to the evidence, it is and
always has been popular mainly among women. This is a problem that
Friedman never even addresses. Whether the scene actually depicts a rape
or something else, after all, is irrelevant. Whether the fictional Scarlett
actually enjoys it or not is irrelevant. Very relevant, though, is the fact that
millions of real women identify themselves strongly with Scarlett and
clearly do enjoy it. What this fantasy actually means, of course, is another
matter entirely. Both women and men need to find out what it means.
Ambivalence toward the hero in romance novels is nothing new. Helen
Taylor points out that these stories have a long history, one that goes back to
the eighteenth century. The hero of that tradition was not only handsome,
charming, and aristocratic or wealthy. He was also someone “with an
enigmatic, shady past history, a reputation for sexual excess and scandal,
exquisite taste and perfect self-control, a proud and determined ability to
keep his distance and appear cruel to the woman he eventually overwhelms
with passion.”31 One writer of romance novels echoes this. Of the hero’s
advances toward the heroine, she observes that “he overpowers her [so that]
she shouldn’t look as though she absolutely hates this.”32 The implications
of this ambivalence, though, have yet to be fully understood.
The debate over this famous, or infamous, scene from Gone with the
Wind highlights the current debate over sexual relations between men and
women. It says something about the ambivalence women have always felt
toward men. In everyday life, ordinary men can seldom, if ever, satisfy the
contradictory needs or desires of women. Therefore, women must choose
between, say, adventurous sailors and steady accountants. Men have always
been aware that women want to be considered attractive by men or, at the
very least, to be noticed by men. But men have recently become aware also
that openly acknowledging their sexual interest in women, openly enjoying
the beauty of a female body, is considered vulgar, disreputable, or even
oppressive by many women. The latter say that they find it degrading and
insulting rather than flattering, for example, when men whistle at them on
the street. Feminists are very explicit about it: wolf whistles, they say, are
sexist. This is the premise, in fact, on which countless situation comedies
and even more serious television programs are based. Moreover, it is the
basic premise of all romance novels. Heroines must be sensuous or even
sensual but not overtly sexual. They must remain chaste to the end – that is,
until the marriage ceremony. Readers accept sexual intercourse after
marriage, because (even if for no other reason) they accept the desirability
of children, but they do not want their escapist pleasure disturbed by frank
talk of sexual intercourse.33 Not surprisingly, male heterosexuality is now
referred to contemptuously, in some feminist and lesbian circles, as
“phallocentrism” or “phallocracy.”
What interests Miles most are the hero’s admirable qualities, not his
sinister ones. Unlike the “other man,” the hero offers the heroine protection,
security, and tenderness under the right circumstances. In short, according
to Miles he offers her the kind of love associated with mothers. The hero is
a mother! “True love, as unconditional love which comes unsought and
unearned, without the heroine actively seeking it and regardless of what she
does to antagonize the hero, is like our dream of mother-love. The hero’s
nurturing and domineering behaviour, two aspects of the childhood
experience of mothering, are presented as two constant and interacting
themes, often evoked with symbols of mother and child in scenes which
echo mother/child images, and involve explicit references to the male as
caretaker/mother and the female as a motherless child.”34
Miles devotes most of her essay to this ingenious but facile analogy. It is,
in fact, the heart of her argument. She does acknowledge a need to answer
“the complex question of why women would fantasize a mother figure as
male.”35 After twenty-seven pages, though, she admits that she can offer
only “initial observations” on this problem. According to Miles, “one
obvious reason [for arguing that the hero is a mother] may be that in a
patriarchy only men have enough social power to represent the powerful
mother figure. Paradoxically, female figures other than mythical ones do
not have the necessary power and resources to stand for the mother.”36 This
is obvious? Miles would have to provide some evidence for what would
otherwise seem, at the very least, contrived. What has “social power” to do
with symbolism? How, for example, would Miles explain the rise of
Christianity? The earliest Christians, after all, were a bunch of despised
sectarians, destitute peasants, and illiterate slaves. They had no social
power. Their god was an executed criminal, their symbol the cross on which
he had been tortured! By the late Middle Ages, on the other hand, Mary had
indeed become a powerful symbol of motherhood. So powerful that
devotion to her had almost eclipsed devotion to Christ. Besides, the social
power that supposedly enables men to represent mothers is the very kind of
power that Miles considers antithetical to “women’s consciousness.”
Undaunted, Miles provides another possible answer to the vexing
problem, this one based on warmed-over Freudianism. If the hero is male,
she avers, the psychological threat of fusion with Mother is mitigated. By
the same token, though, the threat of fusion with Father is augmented.
Incestuous feelings toward the latter are surely not so very much more
acceptable than incestuous or regressive feelings toward the former.
Besides, why should symbolic fantasies of marrying Father be experienced
as threatening? The whole point of a fantasy, after all, is precisely to
indulge in thoughts and feelings that would otherwise be condemned as
foolish or immoral.
Miles comments on her lesbian friends, finally, who read Harlequin
romances. For Miles this clearly shows that the novels are not merely about
love and sex between straight people. The implication is that lesbians would
be unable to find any value in books about straight love, in which case they
would be cut off from most of the world’s great literature. But this is utter
nonsense. Human identity transcends sexual identity. Gay people are not a
separate race or species. They are as capable as any others of seeing their
own humanity reflected in the fictional characters (no matter how
seemingly different from themselves) of straight authors. And they are as
capable as any others of creating these characters themselves. In books
valued by all people, gay authors – Somerset Maugham, E.M. Forster, and
Tennessee Williams, to name a few – have written movingly,
compassionately, insightfully, and convincingly about straight love.
According to Miles, romance novels commonly focus on themes such as
the ambivalent feelings of the heroine toward the “lover/mother,” her joy at
being noticed and despair at being unnoticed, her problem of “sibling”
rivalry for love and attention, her intense longing for security through
fusion, and so forth. Yet she points to hardly anything about her relationship
with an idealized mother that could not be said equally of her relationship
with an idealized father. “Certain types of activities, commonly shared by
mother and child, appear frequently enough in different Harlequins to earn
the status of themes. The hero and heroine shop for clothes for the heroine
together; he comforts her when she has bad dreams; he scolds her for
risking illness; he tucks her into bed and gives her medicine; he leads her by
the hand; restrains her physically from running away, having tantrums and
so on.”37
With the possible exception of shopping for clothes, these activities are
all associated with the ideal parent whether mother or father. Having quoted
a Harlequin passage in which the hero saves the heroine’s life, Miles
concludes as follows: “It is not incidental … that the hero has … like the
mother, actually given the heroine life.”38 The analogy is forced. It is true
that mothers alone gestate. And it is true that mothers alone are associated
also with activities that sustain new life. But fathers are associated with
saving or protecting new life from perils outside the womb and beyond the
home (in addition, of course, to providing the material resources that enable
mothers to nourish the young). It could be argued that very few real fathers
are as tender and loving as Rhett Butler, sure, but it could be argued as well
that very few real mothers are as tender and loving as Rhett – or Ellen
O’Hara or even Mammy.
Now consider the reality of parenting more closely. It is safe to say that
we would all like the kind of unconditional love under discussion here. But
those fortunate enough to receive it as children are precisely those least
likely to go on seeking it through fantasy as adults. If so many women are
addicted to romance novels, therefore, it would be logical to conclude that
they were not given enough love as children in real life. Because Miles
associates this kind of love only with mothers, though, it would be logical
to conclude in addition that the problem has been caused by a widespread
inadequacy of real mothers. For Miles, no doubt, this conclusion would be
unacceptable. But the same logic could be used to argue for the hero as
father. That women do, in fact, feel strongly about fathers can be seen not
only in the productions of popular culture (which often portray fathers
doing the very things described by Miles, albeit clumsily) but also in the
findings of psychiatrists (who note that girls seek a distinctive kind of love
and guidance from their fathers, which later enables them not only to
succeed in achieving personal goals but also in establishing healthy
heterosexual relationships) and even, ironically, in the works of some
feminists (who argue that children – presumably this includes girls – need
fathers who are fully integrated into the emotional structure of family life).
It could be argued that real fathers seldom express their love adequately, in
short, but not that daughters feel no powerful need for this love. On the
contrary, many feel the need precisely because their own fathers did not
express their love adequately. That would be a more attractive hypothesis to
Miles, but the same logic would refute her own hypothesis about mothers.
Miles has devoted a great deal of energy to legitimating the fantasies of
women. As we say, her theory is both cumbersome (relying heavily on the
misandry of ideological feminism) and counter-intuitive (denying the
obvious maleness of heroes). But she has proposed it for a reason. In her
introduction, she gives as her reason the need to explain the embarrassing
fact that many intelligent women like simplistic, stereotypical, and
standardized romance novels. (Others have tried to explain the equally
embarrassing problem of soap operas, which are produced primarily by and
for women.) Even in the introduction, though, she makes it clear that the
topic is of far more than scholarly interest to her. At stake is her identity as
a feminist. This “suggested that there was another level of meaning for me;
something less explicit that appealed to me and presumably to other
readers; something that could help to explain why this simple and
threadbare formula should so attract women, and how women, who know it
to be false, can lose themselves in it; in other words, something that could
begin to answer the question ‘What is the myth of romance for women?’”39
Not surprisingly, perhaps, the answers provided by Miles are both explicit
and implicit. Explicitly, she argues merely that the romantic fantasies of
women are superior to the pornographic ones of men. Underlying the entire
article, though, are two implicit arguments: that (female) homosexuality is
superior to heterosexuality, and that women are superior to men. We will
now examine each of these three arguments in more detail.

Miles argues explicitly that the romantic fantasies of women are superior to
the violent ones of men. First, she admits that Harlequin romances provide
women with an escape from reality but adds that women need to escape.
Okay, they do. Everyone does at one time or another. That is part of being
human. But Miles implies that men do not. Her way of thinking could be
expressed as a syllogism. Romance novels provide an escape from
emotional deprivation; romance novels are written by and for women alone;
ergo, emotional deprivation is suffered only by women – which is to say,
only women have a legitimate reason for escapist fantasies. If men do not
need an escape, though, why do they turn to their own forms of fantasy,
which include pornography, science fiction, westerns, stories about sports
and survival in the wilderness, and so on? Pornography itself, moreover,
consists of at least two genres: the kind that stimulates erotic fantasies and
the kind that stimulates violent ones. Because Miles fails to mention the
distinction, it could be assumed that she acknowledges none. In that case,
she would take the common position that erotic images, because they
objectify women, are no more innocent than violent ones. On the contrary,
she would say, both are inherently sexist. It is true that Harlequins do not
lead women to acts of violence (although even violent porn does not
necessarily lead men to acts of violence). All the same, they can lead to
serious social problems.
Taken at face value, they encourage women to expect the impossible
from men. Publicly, women demand gentleness and sensitivity from men. In
itself, that demand is unambiguous and at least theoretically possible for
most men to meet. But privately, if romance novels are any indication of
their fantasies, women long in addition for aggressiveness and challenge
from men. That presents men with a double message. Their ideal is
inherently ambiguous and thus very hard for most men to attain. Even if
boys were taught the emotional and relational skills women admire in the
Harlequin hero, after all, these skills would still conflict in the real world
directly with what boys are taught of the hero’s competitive and combative
skills. As it happens, boys are seldom taught the former and often taught the
latter. Hardly ever are they taught how these skills might be combined in a
healthy personality. The result of this confusion is a kind of intrasexual
polarization among men. At one end of the continuum is the inadequate
wimp. At the other end is the macho barbarian.
Not taken at face value, on the other hand, these novels encourage the
withdrawal of women from men. If Miles were correct, if the hero were a
mother, then the message to men would be that women need them either as
replacements for mothers or not at all. To paraphrase a familiar racist cliché,
“the only good Indian is a dead one,” Miles would have us believe that the
only good man is a woman – that is, a man who no longer exists as such.
Why should men not respond with anger to the charge that they are
inherently either inadequate or irrelevant? Women are dehumanized by men
in some ways, it is true, but men are dehumanized by women in others. One
kind of masculine pornography could be associated with violence, but
feminine pornography could be associated with self-righteousness. The
former might be even worse than the latter, but neither is any good.
Feminist separatism (on which Miles bases her argument) is, along with
male violence, directly involved in generating the kind of conditions that
would bring about the dissolution of our society – or any society. Just as
romance novels can lead to intrasexual polarization, then, they can lead also
to intersexual polarization.

The second argument, like the third, is implicit. Miles does not actually say
that female homosexuality is superior to heterosexuality, but no other
conclusion can be drawn from what she does say. Following Nancy
Chodorow and many other currently popular feminists, Miles argues that
women are erotically self-sufficient.40 The bond between women and men
is secondary; the bond between mother and child – especially, as Miles
argues, between mother and daughter – is primary. “The erotic power of the
hero,” she writes, “is achieved because he is the mother; he offers the
complete gratification of safe total, passive surrender.”41 If this new twist
on the old Freudian Elektra complex were correct, of course, then
heterosexual intimacy would be nothing more in this age of sperm banks
than a primitive way of conceiving children, preferably daughters.
Heterosexual love would be a luxury that many women could do without.
Their primary emotional needs would be served, presumably, by their
mothers and other women. Heterosexuality would be the “root cause” of
suffering for women, in fact, because “the emotional deprivation almost all
women suffer in a heterosexually structure[d] society where women are
care providers, rarely receivers, and where most women can expect no
mothering or nurture after early adolescence, all combine to explain why
the fantasy of mothering in the guise of a romantic hero is the predominant
form of escape for women.”42 Permeating this essay, then, is what amounts
to lesbian separatism. If the primary bonds for women are with other
women – mothers, daughters, friends, and presumably lovers – why should
women maintain contact with men at all? No wonder Miles refers to her
realization of the value in romance novels, a redemptive experience that
legitimated her identity as a reader of them, in terms of “coming out.” The
problem here is not homosexuality itself but the way in which Miles
chooses to legitimate it: by delegitimating heterosexuality – which is to say,
the kind of intimacy and interdependence that link women and men in
enduring relationships.
Discussing her coming out experience, she observes that “it got easier as
I developed arguments defending women’s romantic fantasies as harmless
(to others at least), human, and relatively innocent, especially when
compared to the pornographic fantasies of men.”43 If Miles refers here to
the kind of pornography that is based on sadomasochistic fantasies, we
would agree. But if she refers to erotica in general (on the assumption that
the mere enjoyment men find in looking at beautiful women is immoral),
we would have to disagree with her. The implication of this attitude is that
male heterosexuality as such is immoral.44
There is a parallel, as we have already indicated, between romance
novels and erotica. The former are less vulgar, to be sure, but can
nevertheless be defined with the latter as pornography. In the first place,
both genres exploit images of the opposite sex by using them as screens
onto which their own fantasies, representing their own needs, are
conveniently projected. Although it is now common for feminists to discuss
masculine pornography from the perspective of women, it is very
uncommon for anyone to discuss feminine pornography from the
perspective of men. How does Miles think men might feel about the way
they are presented in Harlequins? She never asks this question.
Nevertheless, the answer is not difficult to guess. Men would feel the same
way any other group of people feel about being stereotyped. In this case, as
we have said, men are stereotyped either as substandard (wimps) or
superhuman (heroes who are both macho and, paradoxically, nonmacho).
This would be true, moreover, even if Miles were correct in arguing that the
men in the latter category really appear to women as mothers in drag. In
that case, after all, the only men left, as such, would be those in the former
category.
Besides, romance novels really are about the manipulation of power.
Miles grudgingly admits that it is not quite unheard of for women to have
fantasies of power over men (in which case she disagrees with Marilyn
French and her colleagues).45 “Some of us do,” she says, “some of the
time.”46 Think of the sadomasochistic fantasies that please some women
just as they do some men. Nevertheless, she quickly exonerates Harlequin
novels from this patriarchal taint. “The popularity of Harlequin Romances,”
she argues, “suggests that most women are not primarily interested in and
do not gain satisfaction from power over others or the power to aggress.”47
But if readers do not fantasize about attaining power over men, how can we
explain the fact that heroines always do attain power over their heroes?
How can we explain the fact that so many female viewers applauded the
heroines in Thelma and Louise for attaining power over men? Unlike recent
movies, romance novels urge women to dream of attaining only emotional
power over men. Even so, it is indeed power over men. After all, the heroes
are so sick with love by the last page that their earlier indifference to the
heroines melts away like ice on a spring day. The heroines themselves do
not actively, or at least consciously, seek this hold over them, true. But
readers obviously hope and know that they will attain it; otherwise, they
would not read these formulaic books. To be sure, power is not an end in
itself. Heroines do not relish this emotional power for its own sake. It is a
means to another end. What they really want is “security” – that is,
emotional and physical safety, along with (if we take the hero’s social or
economic position seriously) wealth, pleasure, and status. Not only is power
over men the means to an end, though, but also men themselves are the
means to an end. They supply women with what Miles herself defines as
the goal of fantasy: “what is desirable but unattainable or non-existent.”48
It will not do, therefore, to eulogize women by declaring “that most
women’s erotic pleasure, desire, and potential does not find itself primarily
in phallic focused intercourse outside of intimacy, nurture, care, and
security; and most women’s sense of self and fulfilment requires a rich
world of interrelationship and interdependence.”49 No doubt, many women
want these very things (as do men). But if the erotic or quasi-mystical
experience of childbirth and nursing makes women so “interrelated” and
“interdependent,”50 how can they be so unrelated to and independent of
men? Miles makes it very clear, after all, that the autonomy of women is
innate and not merely some response to negative experiences with men.
And if the traumatizing experience of forming identity makes men so rooted
in “discontinuity,” why is there no equivalent to the lesbian separatist
movement among gay men? Ironically, then, the very assertion that only
women are truly integrated and connected to other people or other living
things is refuted by her own claim that the emotional lives of women are
self-contained, that their emotional needs are best satisfied by other women,
that they simply do not need men. Whatever reasons lesbians use to
legitimate separatism, the vaunted “permeable boundaries” that supposedly
enable women to feel at one with all living things of the natural order
cannot be counted among them – unless, of course, men are conveniently
excluded from the natural order.

The third argument, too – that women, as such, are superior to men – is
implicit. Unlike the second one, though, it is implicit not only in specific
statements made by Miles but also – and this is extremely important – in
her whole way of thinking. The comparisons made are highly moralistic. In
each case, one term is identified as superior to the other. The former is then
identified as good (which is the essence, as it were, of essentialism) and the
latter with evil (which indicates the presence of dualism, too). Two things
must be said about this way of thinking. In the first place, it is illogical. Just
because one thing is better in some way than another does not mean that it
is actually good; both, in fact, might be bad in other ways. For this reason, it
is possible to choose one course of action as “the lesser of two evils.”
Similarly, just because one thing is worse in some way than another does
not mean that it is actually evil; both, in fact, might be good in other ways.
But logic has little or nothing to do with this third and ultimate argument of
Miles. Dualism, on the other hand, has everything to do with it.
Without a trace of irony, she refers approvingly to Mary O’Brien, who
“has argued that women’s integrated experience of birth as a continuity of
mediated labour provides the material basis for a female consciousness,
which is more integrated and less dualistic than male consciousness rooted
in a discontinuous experience of reproduction through the alienation of their
seed.”51 Miles draws an almost inevitable conclusion from the similar
opinions not only of Chodorow but also of Dorothy Dinnerstein and Jane
Flax.52 They have written of a “continuous identification with the mother
which gives women the basis for a less separative, more relationally defined
and connected sense of self than men. Thus women’s experience of self and
the world is very different from the competitive and dualistic male sense
which has been called the ‘human condition’ and which shapes all
patriarchal cultures and values.”53 True, the origin of these patriarchal
cultures and values – what she obviously considers evil – is existential
rather than genetic. But that distinction is irrelevant, because the former is
as universal as the latter. Ironically, in any case, it does not occur to Miles
that making invidious ontological comparisons of this kind – identifying
“us” with what amounts to innate virtue and “them” with what amounts to
innate vice (even though neither virtue nor vice, by definition, can be
innate) – lies at the very heart of dualism!
Elsewhere, Miles agrees with Adrienne Rich, who has written that “to
accept and integrate and strengthen both the mother and the daughter in
ourselves is no easy matter because patriarchal attitudes have encouraged us
to split, to polarize, these images, and to project all unwanted guilt, anger,
shame, power, freedom, onto the ‘other’ woman.”54 Once again, it does not
occur to Miles (or Rich) that by projecting guilt, anger, shame, power, and
freedom onto men, instead of the “other woman,” they are reversing the
sexual hierarchy rather than moving beyond it. In fact, they are perpetuating
dualism, not breaking away from it. Implicit is the notion that men and
women may legitimately be considered, like blacks and whites in the days
before integrated schools, both separate (if women have no emotional or
sexual need for men) and unequal (if the fantasies of women are superior to
those of men).
Ostensibly, Miles has adopted an apologetic approach: defending women
who like romance novels. Actually, though, she has adopted a polemical
one: attacking men for making romance novels necessary, as it were, in the
first place. “Not only are Harlequin heroes grown up (rare birds in women’s
experience),” she writes, but in addition “they are sensitive and considerate
and take care of the heroine – something so unexpected that the heroine
frequently marvels about it.”55 When men write things like this about
women, they are denounced for sexism. But Miles has a very specific point
to make. As we say, she argues that the hero (male and good) is really a
woman and that the heroine’s rival (female and bad) is really a man! The
wimp (male and bad) is, of course, still a man. By overtly contradicting the
plain literary statements, Miles has managed to link femaleness with all that
is good and maleness with all that is evil. When men are good, it is because
they are really women (mothers). When women are bad, on the other hand,
it is because they are really men (male-identified women)! Nothing could
better illustrate the inherent misandric dualism in ideological forms of
feminism.
Miles draws heavily on the work of those feminists who make biological
or psychoanalytical claims for “interrelatedness” as a uniquely female
quality. Mary O’Brien, Carol Gilligan, Nancy Chodorow, and many others
discuss this notion in far more sophisticated but no less superficial ways
than Miles. To have any meaning, this word must refer not only to empathy
but also to responsibility. But what is responsibility? The authors we have
been discussing use it in the sense of taking responsibility for others. In that
future-oriented sense, it means willingness to act on their behalf. The same
word, on the other hand, can be used also in the sense of taking
responsibility for ourselves. In that past-oriented sense, it means willingness
to accept guilt for the destructive things we have done to others. Ideological
feminists claim that the former is a quality uniquely or innately female and
the latter a quality uniquely or innately male. It would be difficult indeed to
think of any ideological feminist who explicitly acknowledges that women
share the burden of guilt with men for any social problem and not much
easier to think of an egalitarian feminist who does. Even obvious examples
of complicity are generally explained away as things that women have been
“forced” to think or do by the men who dominate society. When women
support war, for example, it is only because they have been manipulated
cynically by the patriarchal institutions that promote violence and
nationalism. When men do so, of course, it is because their “impermeable
boundaries” inevitably lead them to love killing others.56 When men
support peace, on the other hand, it is only because they have been
influenced by feminists or protofeminists. When women do so, it is because
of some innate oneness with the “web of life” that leads them to love caring
for others.57
In a less dramatic way, Miles does the same thing. Why do so many
female readers see nothing peculiar about the “uppity, reactive, foot-
stamping behaviour” of their heroines? Because men have made them that
way! “Ann Snitow and others read the hero’s bullying and the heroine’s
infantilization as a part of the general patriarchal message that women are
not full people, are not to be taken seriously, are not responsible and are
necessarily dependent on men.”58 (Why this should be reflected in the
secret fantasies of women is not explained.) It is precisely this
unacknowledged but pervasive dualism of ideological feminists that
diminishes the credibility of their own claim to being uniquely
“interrelated” (and, by implication, superior to men). At any rate, Miles
herself can hardly claim to be an exemplar of this quality. Considering the
topic of this particular essay, for example, she fails even to consider the
possibility that romance novels send double messages to both women and
men (who seldom read them but often find out about them in one way or
another, especially when they see the cinematic versions with their
girlfriends or wives). As a result, the women who write and read romance
novels are morally implicated in the confusion and conflict between men
and women.
But even if Miles were correct, even if this “interrelatedness” were some
uniquely or innately female characteristic, that would still not make women
morally superior to men. There is nothing inherently good, after all, about
being interrelated or even interdependent. That is a fact of life for all living
beings, male and female. Relationships take on moral overtones only when
they are defined in terms of a larger philosophical or theological context. As
long as people are valued only for what they can provide or do and not for
what they are, words such as “nurture,” “care,” and even “love” can be used
only in the most superficial sense. Consider this matter in more detail.
It is very easy to love those who provide us with what we want, whether
we seek physical and emotional security or property, prestige, and pleasure.
It is not wrong to want any of these things. What is wrong, though, is to
pretend that there is some moral gulf that divides those who want the
former from those who want the latter – or women who use men from men
who use women. With regard to people, exploitation is defined by the act of
using others (sometimes by intimidation and sometimes by manipulation) to
serve our own needs or satisfy our own desires, not by the type of need or
desire. In short, Harlequin heroes are used by Harlequin heroines. When
men do that to women through fantasy, it is called “pornography.” And
when they do so in real life, it is called “objectification” or “exploitation.”
It is very hard, on the other hand, to love with the expectation of nothing
in return. Not even the gratitude and solicitude of children. That is the
specifically moral dimension of love. Romance novels are said to be about
fantasies of love. And love, in turn, is linked in these novels to marriage. It
is generally assumed that marriage, or the path toward it, begins with the
desire not only for physical intimacy but for emotional intimacy as well.
Unfortunately, it is seldom assumed – by men or women – that marriage
could or should lead to something deeper than either physical or emotional
intimacy. Considering love in a moral sense, therefore, there is no
significant difference between the readers of feminine pornography and
those of masculine (erotic) pornography.
We have made three main points. First, romance novels say something
disturbing about the fantasies women have of men, not something laudable
about the fantasies they have of other women. Second, when romance
novels are interpreted by ideological feminists, the result reveals more
about the latter than the former. Third, that an ideological mechanism, what
we call “comparative suffering,” allows these interpreters to justify not only
the unfair stereotypes of men explicitly presented in the novels (if women
alone are deprived, then they alone need compensatory fantasies) but also
their own polemical arguments about the superiority of women (if women
alone produce and consume these fantasies, they alone are interested in
caring or “nurturing”).
So far, however, we have discussed only traditional romance novels,
which appeal to women with positive but confused attitudes toward men.
They want men, to be sure, but they want men unlike any that they could
possibly meet in everyday life. Is that still true of more contemporary
romance novels? In a way, it is. The hero is still impossibly unattainable.
Otherwise, his value as a fantasy would be diminished and the genre would
disappear. Still, there has been a major change in the Harlequin world.
As it happens, one of the most lucrative markets in our time is for
romance novels that reflect specifically feminist (though not necessarily
ideological) perspectives. Those who write romance novels these days, in
other words, explicitly legitimate their work in terms of feminism. Kelli
Pryor makes this much perfectly clear in the opening line of her article on a
convention of the Romance Writers of America: “Think of a weekend with
Thelma and Louise – but without the guns.”59 This metaphor of combat is
very appropriate in view of that old proverb about the pen being mightier
than the sword. Listen to Pryor’s description of what she saw and heard at
the convention. “In a chandeliered hall with floral carpets, best-selling
author Susan Elizabeth Phillips … is wearing an elaborate open work-
embroidery blouse and describing the romance novel as an expression of
female empowerment: The heroine takes on a domineering hero and by the
end of the book she has turned him into a sensitive human being. ‘In other
words, she has turned him into a woman,’ Phillips says. The audience
cheers.”60 This is the kind of “empowerment” now being promoted among
women by romance novels. Once again, the only good man is a woman.
Miles might have distorted the meaning of traditional romance novels – the
ones, no doubt, that continue to embarrass her as a feminist – but she might
have some insight into contemporary ones. It could be that they no longer
have the function of escapist fantasies but have instead the function of
political fantasies. Our main point here, though, is that the dualistic
perspective on gender is no longer just the expression of academics. It is the
expression of a mass-market industry purveyed at the check-out stands of
countless supermarkets throughout the country.
Romance novels are not misandric – they do not promote hatred toward
men – which is why we did not discuss them in Spreading Misandry. We
discuss them here, especially in connection with our discussion of
pornography, to illustrate the double standard according to which
stereotyping and objectifying men is considered respectable, or at least
acceptable, but not stereotyping and objectifying women.
APPENDIX SIXBargaining at Beijing: United Nations
or United Women?
Among the many goals of the United Nations is improving the status of
women. To that end, it has called many conferences, established many
organizations or offices, and produced many documents. Being about
women, they are all gynocentric. In itself, that is perfectly legitimate. The
problem is that this gynocentrism has become more than a focus to be
adopted for specific practical purposes. It has become a worldview in its
own right, a particularistic worldview in conflict with the universalistic one
that is expressed in founding documents of the United Nations. Among
those promoting it are, of course, ideological feminists. They use the
rhetoric of gender, human rights, and equality. But they do so in ways that
give a tendentious meaning to each. “Gender” usually refers only to
women, as if it were never problematic for men. “Human rights” usually
refers only to women’s rights, as if these were never conflict with those of
men or even of children. “Equality” usually refers to a goal that only
women need to attain, as if special “corrective” programs for women were
never the cause of new problems for men, at least in Western countries. And
we are interested here only in two Western countries: the United States and
Canada.

In 1946, the United Nations created its Division for the Advancement of
Women. After being renamed, relocated, and restructured several times
since the 1970s, it is now part of the Department of Economic and Social
Affairs and located in New York. It works closely with the United Nations
Commission on the Status of Women, which has representatives from forty-
five countries on a four-year rotation. They meet annually to set global
standards on women’s rights, refer specific women’s problems to other
United Nations agencies, and make policy recommendations to improve the
status of women. In 1975, Mexico City was the venue for its first World
Conference on Women.
During its Decade for Women, 1976–1985, the United Nations
established many institutions to improve the status of women, including the
International Research and Training Institute for the Advancement of
Women and the United Nations Development Fund for Women. In 1979 the
General Assembly adopted the Convention on the Elimination of All Forms
of Discrimination against Women (abbreviated here as “the Convention”).
This Convention is the major document on sexual discrimination. Some
passages use cautious language, which suggests equality of opportunity.
Other passages permit affirmative action on a temporary basis. Still others
endorse equality of result. More about this document in a moment.
Two more world conferences on women were held during the 1980s:
those of Copenhagen and Nairobi. The most recent was held in 1995: that
of Beijing. Two major documents were drafted for this conference, then
debated and ratified: the Beijing Declaration1 (abbreviated here as “the
Declaration”) and the Beijing Platform for Action (“the Platform”).2 The
wording of both reflected a consensus of participating women. Those who
ratified them went back to their own countries with the goal of instituting
the recommendations.
Political bargaining is not as easy when the rights of all citizens must be
taken into account, though, as it is when only those of women need be taken
into account. Delegates have not always been successful in convincing their
governments to change. Periodically, therefore, the General Assembly
reviews their progress. In its report on the twenty-third special session, of
2000, it adopted “further actions and initiatives to implement the Beijing
Declaration and Platform for Action, annexed to the present resolution”
(abbreviated here as “the Annex”).3
Because many people understand the Convention of 1979 as a purely
political document, those who signed it being bound by few obligations and
therefore lacking clout, the United Nations introduced its Optional Protocol
in 2000.4 It contains procedures that allow “individual women, or groups of
women, to submit claims of violations of rights, as protected under the
Convention, to the Committee on the Elimination of Discrimination against
Women” if they have exhausted all remedies in their own countries. One
procedure allows the committee itself “to initiate inquiries into situations of
grave or systematic violations of women’s rights,” although countries may
make use of an opt-out clause.5 At one time there were few legal means of
enforcement by the United Nations itself, although there were once member
countries that changed their laws accordingly. Recently, though, the
International Court of Justice, an arm of the United Nations that is
popularly known as the World Court, created procedures to deal specifically
with member countries that do not measure up to their treaty obligations in
connection with women. To the extent that symbolism matters, countries
with bad report cards lose status in the international community.

With this historical background in mind, consider several themes found in


the Declaration, the Platform, and the Annex. First, human rights.
Among the most ubiquitous and seemingly harmless terms is “human
rights” (even though the people who use this term have no coherent
philosophy on which to support human rights). And what could possibly be
wrong with human rights? Not a thing. Not unless the term is used as a
euphemism for the rights of any specific group. The aim of some feminists
is to reinterpret human rights by giving primacy to the rights of women. We
say “primacy,” because women’s rights and human rights are not identical
and do not necessarily even converge. Human rights are universal; they
apply by definition to all human beings. Women’s rights, by definition,
apply only to women. And these sometimes conflict with those not only of
men and boys, or even children of either sex, but also with those of various
religious communities. More about that in due course.
As delegates at Beijing from around the world commented on two draft
documents that had been prepared earlier, the discussion of women’s needs
and problems was subtly transformed into a discussion of women’s rights.
According to Mary Glendon, a professor of law at Harvard who observed
the proceedings, this focus on women’s rights presented a serious challenge
to human rights as understood by another document of the United Nations:
the Universal Declaration of Human Rights (abbreviated here as the
“Universal Declaration”). Leading the onslaught on human rights, she
points out, were European and Canadian delegates. They attacked several
things that were supposedly protected by the Universal Declaration:
marriage (by article 16), the family (article 16), mothers and children
(article 25), and freedoms of thought, conscience, and religion (article 18).
The new mentality could be summed up in connection with several
presuppositions. First, claimed the Europeans and Canadians, people are
autonomous and self-sufficient; they and their rights exist apart from any
references to their families or communities. Second, rights are entitlements;
they have no corresponding responsibilities. Third, many new rights should
be added specifically for women; this would make them something other,
though, than human rights.
More disturbing still, according to Glendon, was that these delegations
actually tried to remove references in the drafts to human dignity. Why?
Possibly because human dignity would include the rights of both women
and men. “Recognition of inherent human dignity and of the equal and
inalienable rights,” according to the Universal Declaration’s preamble, is
intended for the protection “of all members of the human family.” Article 1
adds that “all human beings are born equal in human dignity.” This is
amplified in article 2, which says that human beings deserve “the rights and
freedoms set forth in this Declaration, without distinction of any kind, such
as race … sex … religion.” According to article 6, “everyone has the right
to recognition everywhere as a person before the law.” Article 7 says that
“all are equal before the law.” And article 12 says that “no one shall be
subjected to arbitrary interference with his privacy, family, home or
correspondence, nor to attacks upon his honour and reputation.”6
Some delegates at Beijing refused to allow direct quotations from the
Convention on the Rights of the Child, possibly because those rights could
be interpreted in a way that would conflict with the rights of women: the
right to abortion, say, or the right not to acknowledge a biological father in
any way. With that in mind, we suggest, they campaigned for inclusion of
the term “sexual rights” (presumably those of women) wherever possible.
The strategy of Beijing’s Western coalition (minus the Americans) was
to get new wording on women’s rights into the two documents that
emerged: the Declaration and the Platform. Once that was done, it would be
possible to proclaim international norms and therefore shame countries into
shaping up to the new reality. Incremental change, after all, has always been
their strategy of choice. But what about the Universal Declaration? From
one point of view, that document was written in “sexist” language and could
therefore be considered passé. From another point of view, these delegates
were merely trying to expand human rights by conferring new ones on
women. From yet another point of view, however, they were clearly trying
to change human rights. This would have been news to their own
governments. In fact, it was news. Bad news. After the Catholic contingent
gave a press release about what was going on, European legislatures began
to debate the changes proposed by their representatives in Beijing. This
provoked enough dismay at home to require last-minute changes in Beijing
(although the Canadian government was quiet, because these new proposals
were actually close to its current policy). But a great deal of damage had
already been done and not all of it could be undone.
Glendon adds that European and Canadian delegates wanted the rights of
girls to be independent, not related to those of their parents. In fact, they
tried to eliminate even “mother” from the draft – except, of course, in
connection with the right of women to reproductive autonomy. For these
delegates, after all, motherhood is a lifestyle choice, one that they will not
allow to define or even constrain women. In this postmodern age, they
referred not to “the family” but to “families.” Using the plural meant that
families headed by single women, or even by two women, would have the
same status as families headed by married women and their husbands. In
fact, says Glendon, these delegates tried to eliminate any recognition at all
of parental rights and duties.
The Canadian delegation, in line with political developments at home,
campaigned for rights based on sexual orientation. Even the Europeans
rejected that for some reason. Maybe the European Union, as distinct from
any particular European country, was divided on that topic. Canada, too,
was divided. But gay activists had already made a great deal of progress.
Only a few years later, they were campaigning for the legalization of gay
marriage.
Amartya Sen, an expert on development, observed that something else
was missing in the rhetoric coming from Europeans and Canadians: any
reference to the fact that educating women leads to the use of contraception,
which leads in turn to lower birthrates. Why would women want to gloss
over that? Possibly because it would deflect attention from the real interest
of both the Europeans and the Canadians: the replacement of human rights
by women’s reproductive rights and autonomy.
Not surprisingly, in view of all these implicitly ideological maneuvers,
European and Canadian delegates explained women’s poverty as the
inevitable result of inequality between men and women – that is, as the
inevitable result of male power over women. They made not one reference
to any other possible cause of poverty among women (and men): economic,
social, political, or whatever.
So much for the demands of Western feminists at Beijing. What about
delegates from other parts of the world? According to Glendon, they sat
silently in the face of all this pressure. They seldom spoke at negotiating
sessions. In the end, though, they signed on the dotted lines. She believes,
not without reason, that they had been intimidated. Many non-Western
feminists openly resent what they consider the newest form of Western
imperialism. They want to improve the condition of women but also to
remain Hindus, Muslims, Buddhists, and so on. The extent to which they
can reform their traditions without reducing them to window dressing is
another matter. The Western experience of reforming religion in conformity
with modernity has not been particularly or unambiguously successful in
that regard, because modernity itself is inherently secular. Some Jews and
Christians resort to compartmentalization; they isolate religion from the
secular world. Others retain only those aspects of religious tradition that can
be reconciled with modernity, at least metaphorically; they discard the rest
as primitive or embarrassing anachronisms. But if ideological feminism
were to prevail – like all political ideologies, it functions as a secular
religion and thus as a rival of traditional religions – that would make the
disappearance of distinctive religions, and thus of distinctive cultures as
well, almost a certainty.
In any case, the Europeans and Canadians at Beijing tried to eliminate all
references to religious ethics or spirituality. When they did refer to religion,
it was to religious intolerance or extremism. Never mind that article 18 of
the Universal Declaration strongly implies that religion is a positive feature
of human existence: “Everyone has the right to freedom of thought,
conscience and religion; this right includes freedom to change his religion
or belief.” So much, then, for all the jive talk about “diversity,” “pluralism,”
and “multiculturalism.”
The Declaration and the Platform might well represent the apogee of
interest-group influence. And both documents assume that influence will be
used to mobilize women in their own countries. “The active support and
participation of a broad and diverse range of other institutional actors
should be encouraged, including legislative bodies, academic and research
institutions, professional associations, trade unions, cooperatives, local
community groups, non-governmental organizations, including women’s
organizations and feminist groups, the media, religious groups, youth
organizations and cultural groups, as well as financial and non-profit
organizations.”7 These documents refer repeatedly to the need for networks
that encourage “the growing strength of the non-governmental sector,
particularly women’s organizations and feminist groups … [which have]
become a driving force for change … [and have] an important advocacy
role in advancing legislation or mechanisms to ensure the promotion of
women.”8 According to the Platform, the United Nations International
Research and Training Institute for the Advancement of Women “should
identify those types of research and research methodologies to be given
priority, strengthen national capacities to carry out women’s studies and
gender research, including that on the status of the girl child, and develop
networks of research institutions that can be mobilized for that purpose.”9
(In chapter 10 and appendix 11, we discuss women’s studies and gender
research in relation to ideological feminism.)
In both the Declaration and the Platform, euphemisms abound. One is the
word “gender” itself. For some reason, it is never defined.10 Nonetheless, it
is ubiquitous: “gender issues,” “gender focal points,” “gender equality,”
“gender sensitivity,” “gender balance,” “gender analysis,” “gender impact
analysis,” “gender perspectives,” or whatever. Despite occasional
references to the “equality of women and men,” this term is obviously
intended to disguise the fact that these documents are designed for women,
not men. Presumably, only men must change if we are to create a “full and
equal partnership”11 between the sexes, whether at home or in the
workplace. The corollary is that men are either personally guilty (for not
approving these measures) or vicariously guilty (for reaping the benefits of
their patriarchal ancestors). According to these documents, “equality” is
really about affirmative action – known as “mainstreaming of gender
perspectives,” “targets and goals,” or “special mechanisms” – to improve
the lives and increase the power of women. They reveal no interest
whatsoever in the possibility that results might go beyond sexual equality
and discriminate against men or boys.
The Annex uses similar rhetorical strategies. Readers, at least those who
count, have already been converted to the true faith of ideological
feminism, which is why no attempt is made even to acknowledge moral
ambiguity or complexity. Every section in the main body begins with a list
of “achievements” to date, in any case, and concludes with a list of
“obstacles” to be overcome. The former builds morale, and the latter
motivates continued efforts for the cause. Throughout the document,
moreover, words are used as mantras. Repeated over and over again, these
not only become self-legitimating but also discourage careful thought about
their implications.
Sometimes, it is true, the Annex refers explicitly to both women and
men: “Ensure universal and equal access for women and men throughout
the life-cycle, to social services related to health care.”12 The term “boys
and men,” too, appears here and there. On one occasion, the Annex says
that the problems of women “can only be addressed by working together
and in partnership with men towards the common goal of gender equality
around the world.”13 On another occasion, the Annex admits that
“customary practices and negative stereotyping of women and men still
persist”14 (although the perfunctory nature of that admission about men
becomes clear almost everywhere else).15 In a document that explicitly
focuses attention on women, however, why mention men at all? These
passages are intended to suggest some underlying inclusiveness. But that is
an illusion. They create a front for the underlying lack of any practical
interest whatsoever in the needs and problems of either boys or men.
References to the latter almost always have negative connotations, in
fact, referring to something that makes them evil or to something that they
owe to girls and women. “Research into and specialized studies on gender
roles are increasing,” advises the Annex, “in particular on men’s and boys’
roles, and all forms of violence against women, as well as on the situation
of and impact on children growing up in families where violence occurs.”16
Research has begun on boys and men, it is true, but the Annex does not
refer to that. It refers instead to the decades of research, some of it highly
questionable, on “violence against women.” Elsewhere, the Annex urges
readers to develop “policies and implement programmes, particularly for
men and boys, on changing stereotypical attitudes and behaviours
concerning gender roles and responsibilities to promote gender equality and
positive attitudes and behaviour.”17 It refrains from adding that women
might need to change their own “stereotypical attitudes and behaviours.” In
our own society, even to judge only on the basis of popular culture and
public opinion, women clearly hold negative stereotypes of men. And these,
as we show throughout this book, are becoming heavily institutionalized in
law.
Similarly, “gender perspective,” “gender balance,” “gender equality,”
and “gender-sensitive research” are almost always used in gynocentric ways
– which is to say, in connection with the needs and problems only of
women – even though the word “gender” should refer to the cultural
traditions associated with both sexes. “Develop and support the capacity of
universities, national research and training institutes and other relevant
research institutes,” advises the Annex, “to undertake gender-related and
policy-oriented research in order to inform policymakers and to promote
full implementation of the Platform for Action and the follow-up thereto.”18
It would be naive to imagine that those who wrote this Annex would be
open to any research not in conformity with feminism, especially
ideological forms of feminism. It calls for “engaged scholarship” –
information and analysis to support preconceived feminist views. As for
“political will and commitment,” which occurs over and over again
throughout the Annex, that is a euphemism for ideological resolve. The
only thing preventing progress, apparently, is political pressure from
unreformed misogynists. Nowhere does this Annex acknowledge the
possibility that anyone could disagree in good faith with its underlying
premises.
The most ludicrous word used in the Annex, however, is “herstory,”
which is defined right there as a “widely used term denoting the recounting
of events, both historical and contemporary, from a woman’s point of
view.”19 It is widely used, to be sure, but only as a polemical gesture among
feminists; no one actually claims that the etymology of “history” is sexist.
The feminists who use “herstory” are the same people, including those who
prepared a website for Canada’s National Action Committee for the Status
of Women, who use “womyn” or “wimyn” to avoid the linguistic
contamination of any word that includes “man” or “men.”20
The ubiquitous word “empowerment” is used almost exclusively in
connection with women. The implications are that only men hold power (or
that power can be defined only in connection with those forms of it that are
usually associated with men) and that only women lack power. As we argue
throughout this book, however, that notion of power is inadequate to
describe conditions even in our own “patriarchal,” or “phallocentric,”
society.
Several words represent what could be described as the feminist
colonization of virtue. Because the Annex is about women, not men,
“peace,” “justice,” and “development” are linked over and over again with
women. Comparable references to men, being both few and ambiguous,
underscore this link. The unavoidable implication is that only women want
these good things or that only women have the innate skills to produce and
sustain them. The Annex urges implementation of the Beijing Platform “to
ensure that commitments for gender equality, development and peace are
fully realized.”21 Elsewhere, we read the following passage: “Peace is
inextricably linked to equality between women and men and
development.”22 But why, precisely, is inequality between the sexes a cause
of war (unless one country attacks another at least partly to eliminate that
form of inequality, which is what Americans did in Taliban-ruled
Afghanistan)?
The same applies to “holistic,” a word used relentlessly, and other terms
associated with the traditional lore of non-Western societies. These societies
are allegedly oppressed by the men, but not the women (except in some
indirect sense) of our own society. For instance, the Annex urges readers to
take a “holistic approach to women’s physical and mental health throughout
the life cycle.”23 The implication is that only women know, value, or need
those things. Elsewhere, it advises readers to “protect the knowledge,
innovations, and practices of women in indigenous and local communities
relating to traditional medicines, biodiversity and indigenous
technologies.”24 On several occasions, it refers more explicitly to “women’s
knowledge.” There are “traditional” cultures that explicitly link women
with some forms of knowledge, but those societies also explicitly link men
with other forms. Are we to assume that outsiders have a moral
responsibility to protect only the former? Apparently so. Otherwise, the
United Nations would have created equally elaborate international
mechanisms to protect the latter. The United Nations has not done so,
despite local campaigns against “cultural genocide,” because of the link
made by feminists between specifically masculine traditions and
“patriarchy,” or “phallocracy.” That is something to be attacked, they
believe, not protected. As a result, feminists either consign these traditions
to the dustbin of history or open them up to women. The second approach
sounds more respectful and useful, and in some ways it is both. On the
other hand, it destroys the value of those traditions for the formation of
masculine identity, which would allow men to make distinctive
contributions, and thus undermines the foundations of these societies.
Some terms are deliberate obfuscations and are intended for readers who
do not count but might object if they understood them in the larger context
of this document. The Annex defends “freedom of religion” in one or two
passages, for instance, but makes it clear elsewhere that this defense applies
only to the extent that religious communities accept the principles being
promoted by the United Nations. If they reform themselves accordingly,
fine; otherwise, they must be discarded. This is an intrusion not merely into
the personal realm but also into the public, because traditional forms of
religion never confine their activities to the personal. Religion governs
attitudes toward family life, at the very least, which is a kind of bridge
between the private realm and the public.25
On the one hand, this Annex admits that in some “cultural, political and
social systems, various forms of the family exist and the rights, capabilities
and responsibilities of family members must be respected. Women’s social
and economic contributions to the welfare of the family and the social
significance of maternity and paternity continue to be inadequately
addressed. Motherhood and fatherhood and the role of parents and legal
guardians … are also acknowledged and must not be a basis for
discrimination.”26 But that statement is prefaced by one that compromises
its gender neutrality: “The inadequate support to women and insufficient
protection and support to their respective families affect society as a whole
and undermine efforts to achieve gender equality.”27 One implication here
is that families depend primarily on mothers; fathers are helpful at best and
expendable or even dangerous at worst. Another implication is that families
headed by single mothers or by lesbian couples are just as beneficial to
children as families headed by both mothers and fathers.
Finally, we come to “root causes.” This term appears on almost every
page of the Annex, three or four times on some pages. As many people
have pointed out in connection with anti-Americanism after September 11,
this is an ideological euphemism. Terrorism is caused by poverty and
tyranny, some argue, but those are caused in turn by American foreign
policy. Ergo, America is the “root cause” of terrorism. Something very
similar is at work in this Annex. It calls for “research to develop a better
understanding of the root causes of all forms of violence against women in
order to design programmes and take measures towards eliminating those
forms of violence”28 and for research on the “root causes, factors and trends
in violence against women, in particular trafficking.”29 These “root causes”
could not be poverty and tyranny, because the latter are treated throughout
the document as symptoms rather than causes of suffering for women.
“Inadequate understanding of the root causes of all forms of violence
against women and girls hinders efforts to eliminate violence against
women and girls.”30 Only three sentences later, readers are asked to
examine “sociocultural attitudes.” That is a euphemism for misogyny: a
male pathology that presumably crosses the boundaries of both space and
time. The real “root cause,” therefore, would be the power of men over
women. Or, to put it more bluntly, men.
The process of transforming human rights into women’s rights, too,
continues in the Annex. A massive but repetitive progress report, it uses the
rhetoric that is characteristic of all documents produced by the United
Nations and, indeed, of those produced by many feminist organizations.
Trying to have things both ways, it advises readers to collaborate for the
“promotion and protection of all human rights and fundamental freedoms of
women and girls, the dignity and worth of the human person and equal
rights for women and men.”31 Either women are not covered by human
rights (and therefore need specific rights as women), or the fundamental
freedoms of men and boys are unimportant.
Women have organized at both the national and the international levels to
replace equality of opportunity with equality of result. They have been very
successful in doing so at the United Nations and also in countries that have
come under the influence of its worldview, especially Europe and Canada
but increasingly the United States as well.
Given the gynocentrism of these documents, it is hardly surprising to
find that the United Nations has promoted affirmative action for women.
The Commission on the Status of Women commented in 1991 that article
4(1) of the Convention refers to positive action – that is, affirmative action
to create equality of result – “as a temporary measure necessary to permit
the implementation of equal rights”32 and to create equal representation of
men and women (also called “gender balance”) in political parties and
political life in general.33 Member countries were allowed to define
affirmative action. They were bound by few obligations, and no
mechanisms were set up for enforcement. Therefore, notes Anne Peters, the
Convention was seen by many as a purely political document.
The Annex explicitly endorses affirmative action in the sense of “equal
pay for work of equal value.”34 In addition, it endorses proportional
representation based on “the goal of 50/50 gender balance in all posts,
including at the Professional level and above in particular at the higher
levels in their secretariats, including in peace-keeping missions, peace
negotiations and in all activities.”35 It recommends that governments “[s]et
and encourage the use of explicit short- and long-term time-bound targets or
measurable goals, including, where appropriate, quotas, to promote
progress towards gender balances … on a basis of equality with men in all
areas and at all levels of public life, especially in decision- and policy-
making positions, in political parties and political activities, in all
government ministries and at key policy-making institutions, as well as in
local development bodies and authorities.”36 The Annex promotes new
“national machineries” to achieve gender balance and “to play an advocacy
role and to ensure equal access to all institutions and resources.”37

Gynocentrism, like androcentrism, relies on double standards. If the world


revolves around “us,” after all, then what happens to “them” is either
unimportant or justifiable as retribution. We permit ourselves to say or do,
therefore, what we would never permit others to say or do. The Annex is
littered with double standards. It calls for “strong national machineries … to
promote the advancement of women and mainstream a gender perspective
in policies and programmes in all areas.”38 For some reason, though, it fails
even to mention laws that force men, but not women, into combat. This
omission would be okay in a document that focuses on women, actually, if
conscription were nonetheless denounced in a document that focused on
men. Unfortunately, no such document exists. “Given the gap between male
and female life expectancy,” the Annex says elsewhere, “the number of
widows and older single women has increased considerably, often leading
to their social isolation and other social challenges.”39 Despite the
legitimate focus on women, it might have included an aside or at least a
footnote on the need for research to help men improve their health. Or it
could have mentioned that need in a document specifically on the needs and
problems of men. Once again, no such document exists. The social isolation
of women is more important, apparently, than the biological vulnerability of
men. The Annex urges readers “to examine the decline in enrolment rates
and the increase in the drop-out rates of girls and boys at the primary and
secondary education levels in some countries … and … design appropriate
national programmes to eliminate the root causes and support lifelong
learning for women and girls.”40 This reference is presumably to non-
Western countries, where the problem is serious. In many Western
countries, after all, the “decline in enrolment rates and the increase in the
drop-out rates” applies to boys, not girls. Why ignore that problem? Could
it be due to lack of interest in boys? Or the belief that boys do not deserve
any consideration?
The broad scope of these documents is striking: from the home to the
workplace, from the local to the national or international, from the private
to the governmental. Everywhere, they refer to testing or monitoring for
harm done to women. Nowhere, though, do they refer to testing or
monitoring for harm done to men or even children (except, of course, for
girls). Nowhere, in fact, do they refer to limits of any kind.

Although the current wave of feminism began as a political movement with


the limited goal of integrating women into the workplace and other areas of
public life, some feminists have turned it into an ideological movement
with a global mandate. How does its proselytizing mentality fit in with that
of the United Nations? After all, the latter is a fountainhead of rhetoric
about “diversity,” “pluralism,” “tolerance,” and “multiculturalism.” The
reason is not hard to find when you consider that it is the fountainhead also
of postcolonialism (or postmodernism in the industrialized world). What
postcolonialism (or postmodernism) seldom acknowledges are the support
that it provides to ideologies, by “deconstructing” other ways of thinking
and the fact that those ideologies function as secular religions. Like many
other religions, secular religions proselytize. Many Westerners once
believed that the spread of Christianity was a positive feature of their
colonial empires. More recently, many have come to believe that it was a
negative one. But secular religions have replaced Christian proselytism with
ideological proselytism. First Marxism and then feminism, both Western
ideologies. They have turned the United Nations, which began with the
limited goal of preventing wars, into the global headquarters of feminist
missionaries.
No one who takes seriously from an impartial point of view the
documents that we discuss here could imagine that they actually promote
diversity or even tolerance. They refer over and over again to the dignity of
“indigenous” cultures, but the fact is that they would utterly destroy those
cultures if implemented fully. And the destruction this time would be
complete, not partial, due to the political, economic, bureaucratic, and
technological resources available to feminists through the United Nations.
The new religion is implacably opposed to tolerance of anything that
conflicts with feminist ideology. It insists on one model for social change
(ironically, given postcolonial rhetoric, a Western one). With that in mind,
every aspect of daily life – education, marriage, reproduction, work,
entertainment, religion – would be forced into conformity with an
ideological vision of utopia.
If these documents were fully implemented here, in the United States
and Canada, the prognosis for democracy would be far from hopeful. The
required targets – they amount to quotas – are to be imposed in most
countries by government fiat, after all, not by majority opinion. But even in
democratic countries, ideologues have found ways to get around that thorny
problem. Instead of trying to convince the public and working through
elected representatives, they often bypass the legislatures and work instead,
behind closed doors – which is to say, through the courts and within the
bureaucracies. And this is happening today not only in Canada but also in
the United States. Many American feminists have lost hope that the
required number of states will ratify the Equal Rights Amendment
(although the campaign continues), but they have found hope in the United
Nations. Ratifying documents of the kind discussed here would do as much
or more to support ideological feminism than any constitutional
amendment. Better yet, very few Americans would even be aware of what
was happening. The revolution could be achieved quietly, in committee
chambers, and without resistance.
APPENDIX SEVEN
Paved with Entitlements: The Road to Caste
A website of the Canada’s federal government distinguishes between
equality of opportunity (known at this site as “formal equality”) and
equality of result (known as “substantive equality”). The former is defined
in connection with people “getting the exact same treatment as other
people.” The latter is defined as “full participation in society by everyone,
regardless of personal characteristics or group membership … [which]
requires challenging common stereotypes about group characteristics that
may underlie law or government action as well as ensuring that important
differences in life experience, as viewed by the equality seeker, are taken
into account.”1 This site makes it clear that fostering substantive equality is
Canada’s official method of ending systemic discrimination, in short, but
neglects to mention that formal equality had already been modified in
connection with pregnancy and other matters of interest specifically to
women. It attributes those modifications to substantive equality, which
makes it seem that formal equality is inherently misguided or even a sinister
product of patriarchy.
Of great importance here is the reference to “full participation,” which
sounds innocuous enough. Who would argue against that? But terms of
precisely that kind have been used over and over again to justify the
additional demand for equality of result. This prepares the way for the
government’s endorsement of “substantive equality,” which is defined as a
broader view. It recognizes “that patterns of disadvantage and oppression
exist in society and requires that law makers and government officials take
this into account in their actions. It examines the impact of law within its
surrounding social context to make sure that laws and policies promote full
participation in society by everyone, regardless of personal characteristics
or group membership.” The paragraph goes on to say that “[s]ubstantive
equality requires challenging common stereotypes about group
characteristics that may underlie law or government action as well as
ensuring that important differences in life experience, as viewed by the
equality seeker, are taken into account. The Supreme Court of Canada
recently affirmed its commitment to a substantive approach to equality in its
unanimous decision in Law v Canada.”2
This is modified equality of opportunity, so far, except that words such
as “promote” and “ameliorate” are more proactive. This suggests that the
term “substantive equality” is being introduced via the middle ground,
where there is a high degree of consensus. Here is an example with which
few would disagree. Citing the case of Eldridge v. British Columbia,3 the
site opines as follows: “If a Deaf patient cannot understand or communicate
effectively with his/her doctor s/he is simply not receiving the full and equal
benefit of free medical care. To ensure substantive equality for Deaf
patients, sign language interpretation must also be funded.”4 Not doing so
would provide merely formal equality, in other words, but doing so would
provide substantive equality. That would not follow from equality of
opportunity or even from a modified form of it.

Many people have commented on “identity politics” and the


institutionalization of group identities that are based on innate, or
biological, characteristics. Of particular interest here is sex: maleness and
femaleness. (Other examples would include ethnicity, race, or sexual
orientation). The groups in question have always existed, true, and most
(though not all, unfortunately) have been acknowledged respectfully in
democratic societies. But they have not always been given legal
encouragement. This new approach is called “diversity” (or
“multiculturalism” in connection with factors other than biology) and
justified in connection with “pluralism.” In fact, however, these words hide
a problem. To understand it, consider an analogy with one country that has
a much longer history of diversity than any Western one: India.
For most Westerners, “caste” is a dirty word because of its common
association with the hereditary, exclusive, and hierarchical assignment of
group status in India. That system has become notorious in modern times
for entrenched inequality and therefore injustice. It connotes both elite
Brahmins (think of an analogous elite, the “Boston Brahmins”) and
outcastes (so low that they are considered beyond, or beneath, the
hierarchy).
Caste in India was originally based on occupation and allowed some
mobility. By the fifth century A.D., however, the system had hardened; caste
membership had become fixed by birth. The system had also fragmented
into many groups, sometimes called “subcastes.” Among the many rules
governing caste were two of particular importance in maintaining
exclusivity: members may marry only within the caste and eat only among
those of their caste. Caste became “the primary subject of social
classification and knowledge.”5 Nonetheless, whole castes could still rise in
the hierarchy, and personal identity could still be described in connection
with overlapping criteria. In Castes of Mind, Nicholas Dirks describes that
system very fully. Indians recognized many forms of identity, which were
part of a complex … [and] constantly changing political world.
The references of social identity were not only heterogeneous;
they were also determined by context. Temple communities,
territorial groups, lineage segments, family units, royal retinues,
warrior subcastes, “little” [or minor] kings, occupational
reference groups, agricultural or trading associations,
devotionally conceived networks and sectarian communities, even
priestly cabals … Caste, or rather some of the things that seem
most easily to come under the name of caste, was just one
category among many others, one way of organizing and
representing identity … Regional, village, or residential
communities, kinship groups, factional parties, chiefly
contingents, political affiliations, and so on could both supersede
caste as a rubric for identity and reconstitute the ways caste was
organized.6
This system was still somewhat fluid until the late nineteenth century.
Rigidity intensified, Dirks explains, when the British introduced caste as an
administrative category for the census,7 although they did so on what were
believed to be empirical grounds: how Indians defined themselves. He adds
that “it was under the British that ‘caste’ became a single term capable of
expressing, organizing, and above all ‘systematizing’ India’s diverse forms
of social identity, community, and organization. This was achieved through
an identifiable (if contested) ideological canon as the result of a concrete
encounter with colonial modernity during two hundred years of British
domination. In short, colonialism made caste what it is today.”8
Elsewhere, he writes that caste was “made out to be far more – far more
pervasive, far more totalizing, and far more uniform – than it had even been
before … What we take now as caste is, in fact the precipitate of a history
that selected caste as the single and systematic category to name, and
thereby contain, the Indian social order.”9
Because caste became even more important than it already had been, it is
hardly surprising that many Indians were even more dissatisfied with their
assigned level than they had been. In fact, it created “extreme sensitivity” to
social status in general and social precedence in particular. This led to a
deluge of petitions in protest. And this, in turn, led to intense competition.
Castes began to organize politically to improve their status in the hierarchy,
which led to unprecedented caste conflict and many protests to the
government. As a result, notes Dirks, the British stopped using caste before
the census of 1931. But the organization of society based on fixed group
identities arranged in a hierarchy did not go away.
During the fight for independence, the outcastes (also known as
“untouchables,” “scheduled castes,” or “backward castes”) began to
mobilize for their own emancipation, as part of an anti-Brahmin
movement.10 One of its leaders was B.R. Ambedkar, who advocated
proportional representation and a form of affirmative action in the emerging
electoral bodies of late-colonial India. Though an untouchable, Ambedkar
was educated abroad – he got a PHD from Columbia – and after
independence became a founding father of India’s new constitution. He
believed that caste was the main impediment to equality and thus to social
justice. His argument, summarized by Dirks, was that their status could be
improved only by using the constitution to establish “reservations” – what
we know as affirmative action – at universities and in the civil service for
outcaste and tribal communities.11 But this meant that belonging to these
groups – by definition, the lowest – suddenly conferred opportunities and
benefits that were tempting enough to cause the envy and resentment of
groups that were actually lower in economic status. In other words, prestige
alone was no longer the only game in town. At stake also was economic
advancement. Reservations, or affirmative action, proved so attractive that
even groups with higher status than those eligible for government help still
wanted to qualify. Advocates argued for the inclusion of other backward
castes, which led to the Backward Classes Commission of 1953.
Although the category of backwardness was nebulous, continues Dirks,
the commission decided that 2,399 groups deserved help from the
government. This did not prevent a deluge of claims by other groups that
they, too, deserved the status of “backward.” Because of political agitation
and worry about entrenching caste, the report was eventually dropped.
Interest in it was revived before the election of 1977, however, by the Janata
Party. After coming to power, it appointed the Mandal Commission to study
the matter. By the time its report was ready, the Janata Party was out of
power. Returning to power in 1989, it once again took up its mandate to
reform the system by increasing the number of groups eligible for
reservations. Reforms announced in 1990 were accompanied by a flurry of
attempted suicides on the part of young people who had been declared
ineligible, by virtue of caste, for government help.12 They would not get
into universities or get government jobs, while those under them in the caste
hierarchy would. A furore led to the Janata Party’s defeat in yet another
election. By associating caste with reservations, Indian state governments
ensured that caste would become even more entrenched than ever. Caste
now conferred real benefits, after all, and who would want to give up
benefits?
Despite protests, reservations have come to stay in India. The system has
become deeply embedded in popular consciousness. So deeply embedded,
says Dirks, that there is “no simple way of wishing it away, no easy way to
imagine social forms that would transcend the languages of caste that have
become so inscribed in ritual, familial, communal, socioeconomic, political,
and public theaters of quotidian life.”13 The Supreme Court has ruled that
only 50% of civil-service positions may be reserved for specific groups, but
even this qualification is not fixed in stone. Because of a loophole, some
state governments have pushed the figure to 80%. (A bill to reserve 30% of
the seats in Parliament for women, however, has not yet succeeded.)
At first, the analogy between India and our societies – between a caste
and any group offered special status – seems very remote. India is not the
United States or Canada. A Hindu caste is much more rigidly defined, for
instance, than any group in our society except the Amish and the Hasidim
(who are not lobbying in Washington or Ottawa). Intermarriage, to take
only one example, has traditionally been (until recently) very uncommon in
India but very common here. In this sense, the interest groups under
discussion in this chapter are not equivalent to the castes of India.
Nevertheless, the analogy is worth examining more closely because of what
it reveals about the underlying assumptions of those who favour
affirmative-action programs – and also because of what it reveals about our
prospects for social harmony.
Gathering data makes it possible to establish social-engineering projects
such as affirmative action and pay equity, which makes it possible, in turn,
to institutionalize the rivalry of groups based for the most part on innate
characteristics: sex, race, ethnicity, and so on. The information supplied by
those belonging to preferred groups, after all, is rewarded. This could
indeed be understood as the making of a caste system.
Critics of proportional representation and affirmative action have noted
that identity politics can be especially fractious in countries with many
competing groups. But, you might ask, in the United States or Canada?
Well, why not? Consider the current emphasis on political identity
according to sex and skin colour. Or the current use of those very categories
on census forms. Or the link between data collected and government
policies. Or the fact that additional groups – gays, for instance, and
transsexuals – have lobbied for official status as victim classes, which might
well lead to demands for affirmative action. Many other groups, no doubt,
will do the same thing. And why not? The logic is inescapable.
Once groups are assigned “reservations” with better economic
opportunities, it is very hard to change the system.14 Established groups
will always struggle to retain their benefits, and new ones will always
struggle for their own – even though most calls for affirmative action are
called “temporary measures.” The system perpetuates itself and expands. It
becomes far more rigid than social structures based on class – which, not
being based on innate characteristics, provide at least some opportunities
for mobility.
Consider the case of Canada. On one page of a government website for
the Court Challenges Program,15 the key words for those who take their
causes to court in Canada are “a group which has experienced and/or is now
experiencing social, legal and/or economic disadvantage.”16 One important
factor is whether a group “already experiences disadvantage in society.”17
Elsewhere, we read: “Aboriginal women, same-sex couples, and
newcomers to Canada from developing countries already experience
disadvantage as groups in society.”18 In addition, the website refers to
groups that are currently “vulnerable to prejudice, or stereotyping,” groups
that are currently being “mistreated or having [their] needs/conditions
overlooked,” groups that are currently “being prevented from participating
fully in society,” and “minority communities within the broader society.”19
Sometimes, the site uses another abbreviated list, or formula. It refers to
“women, members of visible minorities, persons with disabilities, and
Aboriginal peoples. As well, employers must move towards a representative
workforce.”20
But not all these groups can claim to have been victims of discrimination
in Canada. Some have just immigrated. Others were elites in their original
societies and, it could be argued, discriminated against others. In any case,
Grant Brown points out that they have generally been better educated than
other Canadians:
With respect to visible minorities, note that Canadian immigration
law has for decades favoured relatively wealthy, well-educated,
and skilled applicants. Consequently, this group is not, on the
whole, disadvantaged relative to native-born Canadians by any
objective measure. There is, for example, no correlation between
designated-group membership and educational attainment in
Canada. Even as long ago as 1981, the national census showed
that Filipino-Canadians had the highest percentage of members
who had attained some post-secondary education (59%). They
were followed by Jews (53%), East Indians (46%), Koreans
(43%), Japanese and blacks (both 41%), Scandinavians (40%),
and Dutch (39%). On this scale, Chinese-Canadians were tied in
ninth place with Canadians of British ancestry (38%). Below
them ranked persons of German (37%), Polish (35%), Ukrainian
(32%), and French (29%) descent. Italian Canadians had the same
rate of attainment of post-secondary education as did aboriginal
Canadians (23%) – and yet are deemed to be advantaged
members of Canadian society. Data from Statistics Canada based
on the 1991 census show that 18% of Canada’s 1.9 million
visible-minority adults held a university degree, compared with
only 11% of other Canadians. The employment picture for visible
minorities in Canada is more mixed [although this differed by just
a few percentage points].21
Why confer special protection on visible minorities now? Because
government officials assume that their colour makes them liable to
discrimination in the present or future. But something similar could be said
about men. They were not victims of discrimination in the past – unless, of
course, you remember that young men have often been forced by law to risk
their lives in military combat – but they certainly are now (although
feminists try to legitimate discrimination as a necessary evil or the means to
some higher end). Denial leads to a moral quagmire. What would it mean in
moral terms, after all, if we were to say that historic forms of discrimination
were wrong but current ones are okay as remedial measures? Apart from
anything else, it would mean belief in the (secularized) Christian doctrines
of vicarious guilt and even vicarious atonement.22
In short, the United States and Canada could indeed develop versions of
the caste system. They have recognized precisely the same basis (though
not necessarily the same language) for identity (“us” versus “them”) and
precisely the same political strategies (“deconstruction” of the “dominant”
culture, affirmative-action programs, and so on) as the government of
modern India. As in India before the British, people have formed identity in
connection with many groups: religious, social, political, ethnic, linguistic,
and so forth. As in India, group conflicts have made it necessary for them to
seek solutions for urgent political problems with social and economic
aspects. And as in India, the process has led to severe problems: racial
tension in the United States and linguistic conflict in Canada. Like India,
but unlike the United States, Canada has tried to solve those problems in the
context of writing a constitution (although the United States has done
similar things in more indirect ways). Like India, the United States and
Canada officially require affirmative-action programs in connection with
federal contractors programs (although “reservations” are actually
embedded in India’s constitution and only supported by Canada’s Charter).
Like India, Canada has produced an official list of groups considered
worthy of these programs – a list that keeps growing. And like India’s
interest groups, American and Canadian ones have learned to use the
rhetoric of democracy, with its focus on rights, in ways that raise
fundamental questions about democracy itself.
By definition, democracies involve minorities and majorities. And
women are sometimes treated as if they were a minority. We have heard a
great deal about what rights a minority should have. And with good reason,
because every society is tempted to allow a tyranny of the majority. But
what rights should a majority have? And what happens if a majority is
consistently thwarted?
APPENDIX EIGHT
Here Come the Feds: Case Studies of Affirmative
Action and Pay Equity
When it comes to hiring professors, affirmative action is sponsored by
“federal contractors” programs in both the United States and Canada. In
Canada both the Federal Contractors Program and the Employment Equity
Act have been championed by the Canadian Association of University
Teachers (CAUT). Its explicit goal has been to hire women and members of
“visible minorities” in direct proportion to their numbers in the general
population.
One of the more problematic aspects of [Canadian] employment
equity concerns defining the categories “visible minority,”
“aboriginal …” and “disabled.” Given that human racial
classifications are highly disputable sociological constructs that
have no basis in objective biological fact, who is to count as a
visible minority, or an aboriginal? Where along the continuum
from (E.G.) Greece through Turkey and Iran to Pakistan does one
draw the line at becoming “visibly” non-white? What about
Latin-American descendants of the conquistadors – are they
disadvantaged or not? (Official answer: No.) What about wearing
a yarmulke, or other distinctive ethnic dress? (Official answer:
Arabs count as visible minorities but not Jews, however each
might dress.) How many of one’s grandparents or great-
grandparents have to be aboriginal, or otherwise non-white, for
one to qualify? (Official answer: only one, as far back in the
family tree as one cares to go.) Exactly how blind or feeble-
minded does one have to be to count as disabled for employment
equity purposes? (Official answer: we accept whatever you tell
us.) Given the mixed heritage and mixed health of a large
proportion of the … population, these are pressing questions.1
To that end, the government has intimidated universities by forcing them to
establish numerical “targets.” Failing to do so means trying to get along
without the federal grants on which almost all universities depend. But by
agreeing to comply, universities have abandoned some fundamental aspects
of both intellectual and moral integrity. Nonetheless, even these measures
have failed to satisfy CAUT and other advocates of both affirmative-action
programs and pay-equity programs. Consider a submission by CAUT to a
review of the Employment Equity Act.
It was clear that universities had still not met their “targets” under the
Federal Contractors Program. Rather than ask hard questions about its own
ideological presuppositions and methods, CAUT explained the failure
conveniently in connection with “the practical reality that enforcement of
the criteria and other requirements of the [Federal Contractors Program]
have [sic] been revealed to be problematic.”2 After all, no university had yet
been found guilty of any infraction and punished accordingly. Besides, the
submission observed, universities had found sinister ways of avoiding
punishment for not complying with the rules. One example would be
double counting a single employee who fits two classifications for
preferment. Clearly, more punitive action would be required. “We
recommend a review of the status of these groups [women and minorities]
and the development of stronger initiatives to make Canadian universities
inclusive.”3 By “initiatives,” they meant penalties. At issue was
enforcement. CAUT wanted to amend both the Federal Contractors Program
and the Employment Equity Act with that in mind. A tribunal would be
added to the Employment Equity Act, for instance, and this tribunal would
be accessible at every stage and not only as a last resort.4 Moreover, new
demands would have to be met.
CAUT recommended, although “demanded” would be a more accurate
word, “gender-based analysis” to establish precisely why universities had
failed to comply with the program (or, from our point of view, why the
program itself had actually made things worse). “The effect of such an
analysis,” said the submission, “is likely to reveal that the program has an
adverse effect on the representation (and hence participation) of women (for
example, women of colour, aboriginal women, women with disabilities).”5
Producing a gender-based analysis – that is, a feminist analysis – would be
in accordance with Canada’s official policy under the Equal Employment
Act of doing so for all federal programs, policies, and laws. And by
specifying the type of analysis, the findings would be predetermined. As
feminists have always said, research is inadequate for the needs of women
unless researchers are trained to ask the “right questions.” They must know
the answer, in other words, before beginning their research.
Notably absent from this list of the university’s (or the program’s)
victims were white women. Why? Because white women were already
being hired preferentially by universities; focusing on other women
provided a reason for continuing the ideological struggle for a feminist
utopia and, of course, for maintaining or even expanding the new
bureaucracies. Why expand? Because more and more groups are
demanding privileged treatment. If “they” got preferential treatment, after
all, why shouldn’t “we”? The logic, once set in motion, was hard to set
aside. “caut is aware that there is considerable concern among equity
committees within Canadian universities that lesbian[s], gays, bisexuals and
[the] transgendered are not presently included as designated groups under
the Employment Equity Act and fcp.”6

Pay equity has legal status under Canada’s Employment Equity Act, which
was passed in 1995. CAUT recommended also that the Federal Contractors
Program be enforced, ultimately, by the Canadian Human Rights
Commission’s Employment Equity Program.7 By removing pay equity from
the realm of ordinary legislation and placing it in that of human rights
legislation, endorsed not merely by Canada but also by the United Nations,
the stakes would be raised significantly. Failure to comply would lead not
merely to the loss of government funding but to much more serious
consequences. Moreover, the focus would shift from the complaints of
individuals to those of the groups considered Canada’s official victim
classes as defined in accordance with guidelines established by both the
Charter and the United Nations. “As the Employment Equity Act together
with the Canadian Human Rights Act constitute quasi-constitutional
fundamental rights legislation,” moreover, “the funding mechanism [for
pay-equity programs] must be directed through Parliament rather than
through the bureaucratic and limiting route of a Treasury Board submission
process.”8
Because Canada now officially rejects even modified formal equality
and officially endorses substantive equality, it is hardly surprising to find
the latter explicitly mentioned by caut: “The goal of the [Employment
Equality] Act must include emphasis on the achievement of substantive
equality, not just procedural equality. If this were achieved then the
emphasis on participation rates (numbers) would not permit an employer to
rely upon the global numbers as evidence of equality of participation and
opportunity for members of the designated groups.”9 But this idea took on a
new and ironic twist. “Increasing numbers,” added the submission, “can
lead to increased hostile environments where ignorance and inadequate
support structures, training, awareness building programs do not exist. [sic;
the text must have been intended to read as follows: Increasing numbers can
lead to increasingly hostile environments, where knowledge, adequate
support structures, training, and awareness-building programs do not exist.]
Equality of treatment, participation and opportunity goes [sic] far beyond
representation.” Even substantive equality, in short, was no longer good
enough! In this utopian and ideological world, every conceivable problem –
including the slightest sign of dissent, interpreted as a “chilly
environment”10 – would have to be eliminated by regulation.
Finally, it is worth noting that CAUT preferred to make changes behind
the scenes rather than through public debate. The submission referred, for
instance, to someone who was about to challenge the Federal Contractors
Program in court by means of another program that funds Charter
challenges. “While CAUT is not involved in this effort, we support the
comments made in the Application and look forward to the results of their
research.” But the very next sentence revealed an anti-democratic approach,
because CAUT added that “litigation could be averted by the adoption of
amendments to the program and the Act.” Litigation takes place in public;
arguments, both pro and con, are submitted for approval in court. An
amendment to the Federal Contractors Program would be made in private,
on the other hand, not in court. And not in Parliament. How convenient for
those who want to create a revolution but by generating as little fuss and
encountering as few objections as possible.

Listed on the website for Canada’s Pay Equity Review are many
organizations representing the interests of women, including departments or
agencies of both the federal government (such as Status of Women Canada)
and provincial governments (such as the Manitoba Women’s Advisory
Council and the Quebec Pay Equity Commission), as well as
nongovernmental organizations (such as the National Action Committee on
the Status of Women and the National Association of Women and the Law).
This website lists not a single organization representing the interests of
men. Is the assumption that men have none, that they deserve none, that all
other organizations represent men by default, or what? This state of affairs
reflects the fact that “gender,” though ostensibly a category that includes
both women and men, almost always refers exclusively to women; most
people assume that a “gender” problem is by definition a women’s problem.
(We discuss various aspects of this assumption in chapter 10 and appendix
11.)
Here is one example from the task force’s own website. The task force,
viewers read, will “undertake consultations with relevant individuals and
organizations, including but not limited to employer and employee
organizations, groups representing the interests of women workers and
experts in the pay equity field.”11 Why establish a task force? Because of a
gap in pay between women and men, which “increased to 30.1 percent in
1999 … A 1999 Statistics Canada report … indicates that although the
male-female wage gap has narrowed over the past few decades, a persistent
unexplainable male-female wage gap continues to exist. After accounting
for gender differences in work history and other factors, the study concludes
that approximately one half to three-quarters of the gender wage gap cannot
be explained. This unexplained portion of the gender wage gap is
commonly referred to as the pay equity wage gap.”12
Documents submitted to the task force “must demonstrate how the
proposed research paper will contribute to the overall objective of the Pay
Equity Review, which is to develop options which may ensure greater
clarity and effectiveness in the way pay equity is implemented in the
modern workplace.”13
According to the same website, various “options” are being proposed.
Among these is some sort of “oversight agency,” possibly one with
authority for public “education.” Who would set the tone? Feminists,
whether female or male, who are ideologically committed to the notion that
only the needs of women deserve to be taken seriously? If so, the agency’s
moral legitimacy would be questionable. And how would the word
“education” be interpreted? If this agency were to use its authority and
resources to convince the public that only women have needs and problems
worthy of consideration by the state, it would be interpreted as
indoctrination.
APPENDIX NINE
Dissing Dads: The Debate over Custody and Child
Support
For two reasons, we have focused most attention on problems underlying
the rhetoric of women: of those feminist groups, in particular, that directly
or indirectly put their own interests before the interests not only of men but
also of children. First, this is a book about men and the rhetoric of
ideological feminism about men. Fatherhood is a very significant feature of
manhood even for men who do not themselves become fathers, just as
motherhood is even for women who do not themselves become mothers.
Second, women threw down the gauntlet. Some men have responded in
kind, true, by refusing to acknowledge even the possibility that women
might have some legitimate problems with advocates of fathers. But some
women have responded, in turn, by refusing to acknowledge even the
possibility that men might have some legitimate problems with advocates of
mothers. Canada’s National Association of Women and the Law, for
instance, uses its web-site to complain of “criminal sanctions against
women who make ‘false allegations’”1 of violence or molestation. Can this
organization seriously believe that women should be allowed to make false
allegations – note the use of ironic quotation marks, as if these allegations
were self-evidently either trivial or nonexistent – with impunity? Our goal
is not to defend extreme positions taken by men, at any rate, but merely to
warn readers that fathers must be taken seriously in connection with the
needs of children and that fatherhood must be taken seriously in connection
with the needs of society. At the moment, that is not the case for either of
these needs.
Feminists in both the United States and Canada have reached a
consensus on custody and child support. They want exclusive control over
custody and as much money as they can get from the courts. By the turn of
the century, the debate had heated up. Professional legal organizations and
departments of justice were reviewing the controversies over custody and
child support. In this appendix, we will discuss the current debates in both
the United States and Canada. Representing the American scene are a report
of 2002 by the American Law Institute called “Principles of the Law of
Family Dissolution” and some feminist websites. Representing the
Canadian scene are a parliamentary report of 1998 called “For the Sake of
the Children,” a government report of 2002 called “Putting Children’s
Interests First,” and some feminist websites (responding to those reports).

In 2002 a professional organization called the American Law Institute


produced its revised “Principles of the Law of Family Dissolution.” On the
surface, this report seems fair enough. In other words, it does not seem to
belong with “dissing” documents. Below the surface, though, it does. The
document begins with a look at the various problems that are inherent in
any discussion of custody and goes on to propose a new legal system that
would prevent, or at least mitigate, those problems.2 One conflict is
between predictability and individuality. Guidelines and formulas are useful
to the extent that one size, as it were, fits all. Most people conform to one
classification or another, which reduces the likelihood of litigation and of
manipulative behaviour by one or both parents. The rules are simple and
easy to apply. The result is efficiency. On the other hand, not every family
fits conveniently into bureaucratic schemes. Outcomes are predictable for
them, to be sure, but they might not be appropriate to their particular
circumstances. Far better in these cases, therefore, to allow judges more
leeway in making their decisions. The result is flexibility.
Throughout the twentieth century, custody legislation focused on the best
interest of the child. That was the test, or standard, according to which all
considerations were measured. From the middle of the nineteenth century to
the last quarter of the twentieth, everyone assumed that it was in the best
interest of all children to live with their mothers. The principle affirmed,
therefore, was predictability. Once people stopped assuming that, however,
the test became very vague. The principle affirmed now was individuality.
Decisions could be based on almost anything. “Critics charge that the
unpredictability of results encourages parents to engage in strategic
behavior, take their chances in litigation, and hire expensive experts to
highlight each other’s shortcomings rather than work together to make the
best of the inevitable. The test is also condemned because of the room it
allows for those who apply it to express biases based on gender, race,
religion, unconventional behaviors and life choices, and economic
circumstances.”3 Other critics point out that the test now sets unrealistic
expectations. “The standard tells courts to do what is best for a child, as if
what is best can be determined and is within their power to achieve. In fact,
what is best for children depends upon values and norms upon which
reasonable people sometimes differ. Even when consensus exists, there are
substantial limits on the ability of courts to predict outcomes for children
and to compel individuals to act in ways most beneficial to children.”4
To solve these problems, most jurisdictions now try to make the test
more concrete than it has been by specifying precisely which factors should
be considered and which should not be. But this approach can be helpful
only if these factors are arranged according to priority. Some states
explicitly prefer one form of custody, therefore, over another. In Oregon, for
instance, joint custody is preferred over sole custody. Yet the institute
observes that these preferences are based on “factual and normative
assumptions about families and children” that are not made by all families
or communities.5 This “runs counter to the commitment this society avows
toward family diversity.”6 We wonder if that statement is accurate even in
this age of political correctness. Do most Americans truly believe that there
is no such thing as an ideal family and therefore of a best alternative in the
event of family dissolution? And would that be a truly legitimate
assumption even if most Americans were to make it?
Another conflict is between the principle of finality and that of
flexibility. At some point, parents must accept an arrangement and do the
best they can with it. This offers stability to children. On the other hand,
parents must be ready to adapt when circumstances change. At the moment,
finality trumps flexibility. “Once a decision is reached, it is expected to be
final; relitigation is considered a failure of adjudication and often is limited
by a strict modification standard.”7
As for the conflict between judicial supervision and private ordering,
priority has usually been given to the latter – that is, to the parents –
because of several assumptions. In ordinary circumstances, parents are the
most likely adults to love their children, this love inspires them to act
responsibly, and parental autonomy makes them more committed to the care
of their children than they would be if supervised by the state. These
assumptions are tested, of course, in connection with divorce.
Closely related is the conflict between biological and de facto parents.
So far, biological parents are given priority over de facto ones. In theory,
this reinforces parental commitment. In fact, though, many children are
cared for by other people: grandparents, stepparents, or parental partners
who function as co-parents. Giving rights to the latter might undermine the
commitment of society to parents, which is why children are removed only
from demonstrably unfit parents. But not doing so might undermine the
valuable and stable relationships that they have with children. “Yet states
have carved out an exception for one group of nonparents – grandparents –
who may be given rights sometimes without regard to their prior contact
with the child.”8 The prevailing priority still operates, because grandparents
are still biologically related to their grandchildren.
Finally, we come to conflict between the protection of children from
harm and the privacy of family life. Everyone wants to make sure that
children are not beaten or molested, but no one wants to create an Orwellian
dystopia run by the state. To avoid these problems a new system is
proposed. Its cornerstone would be a parenting plan – that is, “an
individualized and customized set of custodial and decision-making
arrangements for a child whose parents do not live together.”9 This plan
would be mandatory for any parent seeking either custody of or access to a
child. Ideally, it would be a joint plan. “A parenting plan is not simply a
recital of who ‘wins’ custody and who has to settle for visitation. The
assumption … is that each parent ordinarily will play an important ongoing
role in the child’s life… The parenting plan must also contain provisions
that respond to anticipated changes and can resolve future disputes as to
matters that may not have been anticipated.”10
Neither “custody” nor “visitation” would be a relevant word; both would
be replaced by “custodial responsibility,” which would refer to a wide range
of functions and would therefore be used in connection with both parents.
“Once planning for the child at divorce is viewed as a more dynamic and
complex process, terms that imply one form of custody over another are
inadequate.”11 This arrangement would be legitimated partly on the basis of
“diversity,” or not relying on one preferred model (even though diversity
itself is a preferred model, one that not all families or communities would
accept as legitimate). Even so, it would be better than the adversarial,
winner-takes-all, approach that is currently used.
The new system would prefer voluntary agreements, parenting plans,
rather than reliance on decisions imposed by the courts. The courts would
intervene only to resolve disputes or to prevent domestic violence. In some
cases, the courts might facilitate negotiations between the parents by
requiring them to attend parenting classes, or they might provide them with
information about mediators (but they would not require mutually hostile
parents to engage in face-to-face mediations).
The system would rely on “structured yet individualized”12 decision-
making principles. “The principal rule for allocating custodial responsibility
when parents do not otherwise agree is that custodial time between parents
approximate the share of caretaking each parent performed for the child
before the parents separated. By focusing on how the child was cared for
previously, the past caretaking rule anchors the determination of the child’s
best interests not in generalizations about what post-divorce arrangements
work best for children, but in the individual history of each family.”13
This sounds fair on the surface. But it all depends on how we understand
caring. According to the proposed system, providing financial support is not
a form of caring. If one parent works full time (presumably the father) and
the other stays home, then the former must do his full-time job and do half
of all the childcare if he is to have a chance of being considered the primary
caretaker in the event of divorce. Even if the mother works part-time, the
cards are still stacked against a father who works full-time. The same
argument could be made for mothers who work full-time and fathers who
stay at home or for fathers who work part-time while mothers work full-
time, of course, but these arrangements are far more rare than the others.
The fact is that women as a class would come out ahead with this “principal
rule.” Because most mothers would be the primary caregivers according to
the system’s definition, that would almost always make them the custodial
parents – even though the term “custody” would be dropped.
A lack of sincerity is obvious in the double-talk that follows: “This does
not mean that caretaking arrangements are expected to remain the same
after the divorce. What it means is that a parent who has been the primary
caretaker of the child should remain so, and that parents who had co-equal
roles before their separation should also retain those roles afterwards, if
possible.”14 What does that mean? If the second sentence is taken seriously,
then it does mean that caretaking arrangements are expected to remain the
same. Besides, what was done before divorce might or might not indicate
the best that could be done in new circumstances.
Moreover, according to the proposed system, “unless circumstances exist
warranting access limitations … each parent should be allocated an amount
of custodial responsibility that will enable the parent to maintain a
relationship with the child, even if this level of responsibility is not
supported by the parent’s past level of involvement in the child’s care. In
the case of a parent who has contributed in other ways to the child’s
welfare, such as by providing financial support, the amount of
responsibility to be allocated should not go below a certain presumptive
amount of time.”15 But that ignores the intrinsic merits of a father’s
relationship with his children, allowing only a patronizing concession to the
fact that he should have some contact – the amount of contact is not
specified, but “should not go below” refers only to a minimum – if his main
contribution is financial. This is very different from the assumption of
shared parenting and maintains the proverbial notion that fathers are
nothing more than ambulatory wallets.
The new system would allow exceptions for several additional reasons:
the preferences of older children, keeping siblings together, earlier
arrangements that might harm the child due to “a gross disparity in the
quality of the emotional attachments between the child and each parent,”16
and so on. But look at these exceptions more carefully. The preferences of
older children could favour fathers, as could the quality of emotional
attachment, true, but either consideration could easily be countered by the
need to keep siblings together. In any case, how could anyone ever establish
“emotional quality”? Instead of protecting children, this approach might
merely encourage one parent to turn children emotionally against the other.
The new system appears to stand for fairness. It would prohibit
consideration of race, ethnicity, sex, and sexual orientation. It would limit
consideration of religion and sexual conduct in connection with possible
harm to the child. It would allow consideration of economic circumstances
only in connection with practical arrangements. On the other hand, it stacks
the cards in women’s favour by elevating emotional care over financial
care. More important, it fails to acknowledge that fathers are especially
important for helping their sons and daughters to achieve healthy sexual
identities. (More about that in Transcending Misandry.)
It gets worse. The new system would allow for the inclusion of someone
who has paid for child support without being the legal parent, lived with a
child for two years and believed that he is the biological father, lived with a
child since its birth on the basis of a co-parenting agreement with the legal
parent or parents, and so on. But when a man has lived for two years with a
woman and her children by another man (whether he knows the situation or
not), he is required by law to provide child support in the event of
separation or divorce. Once again, is he a real parent or merely a wallet?
The new inclusiveness might apply to a grandparent, stepparent, or the
nonmarital partner of a legal parent; these de facto parents have “lived with
the child and … regularly performed at least half of the caretaking functions
… with the consent of at least one of the child’s parents and without
expectation of financial compensation.”17 Here, again, the amount of care –
and that is defined in exclusively emotional terms – trumps all other
considerations. The criterion, however, is more explicit than in other
circumstances: it must be half the amount of care.
We do agree with one aspect of the new system. Once cases come before
the courts, it would provide safeguards at every step of the process against
child abuse or domestic violence. No criterion would take precedence over
safety. That is as it should be.
Because women have become accustomed to sole custody – and most
feminists now consider motherhood an essential feature of female identity –
many women dislike the idea of joint parenting. To protest joint-parenting
legislation in Michigan, Gloria Woods, president of that state’s branch of
NOW, wrote and published on the Internet an article called “‘Father’s
Rights’ Groups: Beware Their Real Agenda.”18 Knowing that women today
win sole custody in most cases, and that they benefit economically from
child-support payments, mothers are aware of the high stakes and therefore
support the status quo. Woods argues that enforced joint custody is useless
for parents who cannot work together, because this arrangement places the
children in psychological war zones. Instead of demanding that parents,
including mothers, either act responsibly or pay the consequences, she
implies that fathers are more responsible than mothers for creating
psychological war zones. Worse, she argues, violent fathers might place
their children in what amounts to physical war zones (even though the
evidence does not indicate that fathers are more likely than mothers to
assault their children).
These feminists rely on two additional arguments. One goes like this:
advocates of fathers’ rights ignore “the diverse, complicated needs of
divorced families,” which can have “serious, unintended consequences on
child support.”19 That argument is nothing if not vague. Besides, it can
work both ways. Maybe feminists, given their own preoccupation with the
rights of adult women, are just as guilty of ignoring all these complications.
Another argument goes like this: everything would be fine “if only fathers
would share the parental responsibility.”20 But why on earth would they do
so when so much feminist rhetoric tells men that fathers are either assistant
mothers at best (and thus of no real importance in family life) or potential
molesters at worst? In other words, they are either unnecessary luxuries
(because women can do anything that men can do) or dangerous
liabilities.21
Ideological feminists have collected or produced social-scientific studies
to back up their position on what is best for children. “Joining Michigan
NOW in opposing this [joint parenting] legislation,” says Woods with pride,
“are: antiviolence/women’s shelter groups, the bar association, child
psychologists, social workers, family law experts, judges, lawyers, and even
the Family Forum.”22 But these are the very same groups that have vested
interests in the child-support industry. The statistical war is far from over.
On the contrary, it is just heating up.
Similar points of view advocating the interests of mothers and children
have shown up on Canadian websites. These are often more sophisticated
than those of their counterparts advocating the interests of fathers and
children but not more honest or fair. Many are overtly hostile to fathers, in
fact, and some resort to outright lies.

In Canada, fathers have a better chance, at least in theory, to make radical


changes in the legal system, partly because the laws governing marriage
and divorce are federal, not provincial (although provincial governments
usually amend their own legislation on closely related matters accordingly).
Advocates of both mothers and fathers have lobbied for changes to the
Divorce Act. In late 2002 the federal government recommended some
changes and caused a furore in doing so. But the story begins several years
earlier.
In a report of 1998, For the Sake of the Children, an all-party
parliamentary committee examined shared parenting and decided to
recommend it. The terms “custody” and “access” would be replaced by the
term “shared parenting,” and the “tender-years doctrine” (which had almost
automatically given custody to mothers) by decisions based on individual
cases. The basic criteria would include not only “the best interest of the
child” but also the following: the stability of family relationships, the
“ability and willingness of each applicant to provide the child with guidance
and education, the necessaries of life and any special needs of the child,”
“the child’s cultural ties and religious affiliation,” “the importance and
benefit to the child of shared parenting,” “both parents’ active involvement
in his or her life after separation,” and so forth.23 The report recommended
better programs to prevent divorce in the first place or to improve the
process of divorce from the perspective of children, including better
conflict-resolution mechanisms. It stated explicitly that “there shall be no
preference in favour of either parent solely on the basis of that parent’s
gender.”24 Cases that involved proven violence would be treated differently
to account for this important variable. In addition, it recommended
improving the guidelines and formula to fix the amount of child support by
considering the effect of taxes, the income of each parent, and so on. In
addition, the following measures would be included: “recognition of the
expenses incurred by support payors while caring for their children;
recognition of the additional expenses incurred by a parent following a
relocation of the other parent with the children; parental contributions to the
financial support of adult children attending post-secondary institutions; the
ability of parties to contract out of the Federal Child Support Guidelines;
[and] the impact of the Guidelines on the income of parties receiving public
assistance.”25
These changes would be accompanied by a unified family-court system
across the country and the accreditation of family mediators, social
workers, and psychologists who work in shared-parenting assessments.
Among those testifying to the parliamentary committee were lawyers
claiming that some of their colleagues “make a practice of escalating the
fight between divorcing parents. These practices include encouraging their
clients to make false claims of abuse and encouraging women to invoke
violence as a way to ensure an advantage in parenting and property
disputes.”26 Still others noted that charges of violence are entered in the
affidavits of lawyers for ex-wives, even though these charges have never
been verified by professional agencies. Finally, some people testified that
family courts operate in secrecy, without transcripts and due process, let
alone standards of proof that would be demanded in criminal and civil law.
Clearly, they said, the system was corrupt.
Men, mainly fathers, presented their own arguments to the parliamentary
committee. They referred to “gender bias in the courts, unethical practices
by lawyers, flaws in the legal system, false allegations of abuse, parental
alienation, and inadequate enforcement of access orders and agreements.”27
As for gender bias, fathers noted that the “tender age” doctrine in common
law once applied only up to the age of seven but now applies to all of
childhood and even beyond. No social-science evidence indicates that
mothers are innately superior to fathers. Besides, the pattern of mothers
staying at home with their children is usually the result of agreement
between both parents. Why use that against fathers when the marriage
breaks down?
Individual women, local and national women’s groups, social service
agencies, and women’s shelters testified as well. Their comments, in fact,
were included in the report. First and foremost, they opposed shared
parenting. Why oppose it when so many married women want their
husbands to become more involved in family life? Some said that they
feared domestic violence, which they equated with the violence of men
against women and children. They quoted a study conducted by Statistics
Canada, the Violence against Women Survey, which claimed that 29% of
Canadian women experience violence in their marriages or common-law
relationships.28 These women made several additional claims. Women are
the primary caregivers for children during marriage and should continue in
that capacity after divorce, they claimed, because the moment of divorce is
an inappropriate time to assess gender equality. Men want shared parenting
only to exercise control over their former wives, they claimed, or to
decrease their financial obligations in child support. Fathers often renege on
their parenting commitments, they claimed, disappointing the children.
The report was ignored not only by Justice Minister Anne McLellan but
also by her successor Martin Cauchon. Meanwhile, behind the scenes,
feminists had already taken action.29 In late 2002, after much dithering, the
Liberal Party presented a bill in Parliament30 that ostensibly would reform
the Divorce Act in accordance with recommendations from the
parliamentary committee but actually would preserve women’s control
(although no politician would ever admit to caving into pressure from a
lobby group of any kind).
One change was highly publicized: the use of “parenting order” and
“contact order” instead of “custody” and “access.” Fathers had lobbied hard
to replace “custody” and “access” with the language of “shared parenting.”
Since “parenting order” and “contact order” mean the same thing as
“custody” and “access,” they have denounced the change as nothing more
than window dressing.
Another change was deliberately suppressed. By this time, though,
critics were no longer asleep at the wheel. Advocates of strengthening the
relationships between fathers and children noticed that one passage of the
old Divorce Act was now absent. The repealed passage, section 16(10), had
required judges to give children “maximum contact” with both parents
(except, of course, for parents likely to indulge in violence or
molestation).31 This change “was not mentioned in the Justice Department’s
news releases or media briefings when the contentious Divorce Act
amendments were introduced.”32 Virginia McRae, a lawyer for the
Department of Justice, offered an official explanation for the “de-emphasis”
on contact with both parents. “We did not want people to get bogged down
on the quantity of time a child spends with a parent. It really is about the
nature of the ongoing, continuing beneficial relationship between parents
and children, and to focus on a ‘maximum’ gave people something more to
fight about. It’s about what the needs of the children are.”33 Are we to
believe that this furtive move, which happened to coincide precisely with
the demands of a powerful group that lobbied specifically to eliminate the
notion of “maximum contact,” was motivated merely by the urge to prevent
unnecessary squabbling? The amount of time parents spend with their
children really is important, after all, despite all the jive talk about “quality
time,” especially when one parent is denied much or even any time by the
other. Besides, as we have already shown, the amount of time is directly
related to the amount of money that changes hands. Senator Anne Cools
was characteristically blunt in her appraisal of McRae’s attempt at political
damage control: “It’s an attempt to shift back to the earlier position … of
‘mother gets all.’”34 And she was not the only critic. “It’s going to
perpetuate the gender bias that already exists in the court system;” said Jay
Hill of the Canadian Alliance Party; “that’s my great fear.”35
In 2002 the Department of Justice produced a new report, this one called
Putting Children’s Interests First.36 Some feminists were clearly involved
in its production, even though other feminists denounced it. Despite the
title, in fact, we find evidence that this report did place the interests of
women above the interests of children by discouraging fathers from being
actively involved in parenting and indirectly discouraging men from
marrying or having children in the first place. This report was presented to
Parliament as part of the government’s mandatory review of child support.
The apologetic for the formula continued. As Alar Soever points out, “no
fewer than seven reasons [were] given why the costs relating to access time
should not be recognized. Conversely, not one positive attribute of
recognising these costs, such as affording the children a comparable
standard of living in both their homes, is even mentioned.”37
According to Putting Children’s Interests First, says Soever, “the paying
parent’s costs related to access are offset by the paying [sic: he must mean
the receiving] parent’s direct and hidden costs” and “the guidelines already
recognize that a paying parent will spend time with the children.”38 When
Soever wrote about this problem to Virginia McRae, co-chair of the Family
Law Committee, she explained that the “hidden costs” were “diminished
career advancement opportunities and reduced ability to earn overtime
pay.”39 The irony was not lost on Soever, who noted that the receiving
parent (usually the woman) has already argued in the divorce settlement
against the paying parent’s desire for greater access to the children. Besides,
the hidden cost of diminished career opportunities falls under the category
of spousal support in the Divorce Act, not child support.40
At the end of the day, then, it is the children of separation or divorce who
are most harmed by the child-support Formula (which has now become, by
fiat, the domestic-support formula). It financially rewards fathers who pay
their mandatory child support, says Soever, but ignores their children and
financially punishes fathers who are actively involved with them. Never
mind. A new government came in. All bets are off. Irwin Cotler, the
minister of justice, has declared that the Divorce Act will not be revised
until the Supreme Court has ruled on gay marriage (assuming that divorcing
gay couples would have to be given due consideration).
Even as we were finalizing this book, in 2004, one case was being
prepared to challenge the constitutionality of Canada’s laws governing
custody and child support.41 Gerald Chipeur is the lawyer for three
unrelated plaintiffs: a mother married to a man with children of his own, a
divorced father with joint custody, and a boy who was separated – against
his will – from his father after his parents divorced. Chipeur argues
primarily that current divorce and custody laws violate section 15 of the
Charter, which guarantees equal rights to all Canadians. Current laws make
it much easier for mothers than fathers to gain custody; mothers are ten
times as likely as fathers to be awarded sole custody. This amounts to
systemic discrimination against fathers. And because fathers are men, by
definition, this contradicts the Charter’s guarantee of freedom from
discrimination by sex. Moreover, he argues, current laws allow courts to
withdraw the right of fathers to communicate and interact with their
children, which violates their freedom of association. Losing legal status as
a parent is tantamount, moreover, to being stigmatized as an unfit parent.
And the result, finally, “can be emotionally as painful as any other loss of a
child, such as the experience of a death of a child or a missing child.”42
But this case is not about the rights only of fathers. It is about the rights
of children, too, as defined by the United Nations in its Convention on the
Rights of the Child – a document signed by Canada. “The child is subjected
to the same cruel treatment when deprived of the full benefit of a child-
parent relationship.”43 The suit argues that custody should not be awarded
in an adversarial context and that children should have some say in the
matter. Some fundamental legal problems, moreover, should be solved,
including the use of “hearsay and unsworn evidence from people such as
child psychologists and the over-reliance on independent child assessors
who vary widely in skill, personal preferences, prejudices and
sensitivities.”44 This suit claims that the law should “require a showing of
harm or likelihood of harm to a child before a court may deprive a parent of
equal custody of the child.”45
Despite the real problems faced by fathers as a result of divorce and child-
support legislation since the 1980s, feminist groups complain that this very
body of legislation has either already harmed women or will do so. It is
worth reviewing their comments for what they reveal about both the overt
and the covert aims of these groups (in connection with changes proposed
in 2001 and 2002).
One Canadian website, produced by the National Association for
Women and the Law, resorts to the very attack that feminists have rightly
deplored when used against women: “This Committee was swayed by the
emotional – at times hysterical – presentations from the ‘fathers’ rights’
lobby.”46 The author, Pamela Cross, blames all proposed changes on upstart
fathers.
Men’s rights lobby groups rose up in protest against these new
guidelines. Fathers who were resistant to paying decent levels of
support for their children insisted that many of them wanted to be
custodial rather than access dads, thus eliminating the need for
them to pay support. Many more fathers claimed that they were
routinely being denied access to their children by vengeful mums
who were out to take them for as much money as possible.47
These men’s groups found a sympathetic audience in the Senate,
which stated it would only lend its support to the new child
support legislation if then-Minster of Justice Alan Rock would
establish a joint House of Commons/Senate committee to look at
custody and access. Thus the Special Joint Committee on Child
Custody and Access was created as a direct byproduct of men’s
rights opposition to the new child support guidelines introduced
by the federal government in 1997… Unfortunately, the
committee’s anti-woman perspective was apparent throughout
this process. Hearings were dominated by men’s and
grandparent’s rights activists whose comments always focussed
on the alleged pro-woman bias in the law. Organizations working
with women – especially anti-violence organizations – attempted
to ensure that women’s voices and experiences were heard by the
Joint Committee. Unfortunately, they were treated unfairly in the
process. Heckling by men’s groups was not stopped by the
committee members, and in many cases, feminist presenters were
physically intimidated and threatened by men’s groups.48
Everything was just fine and dandy, thank you very much, until selfish
fathers joined selfless mothers among the lobby groups in Ottawa. If it is
true that feminists were heckled or even intimidated, then Cross justly
rebukes the men’s groups in response. To be honest, however, she would
have to admit that women have been running the show for a long time and
deliberately used their influence to silence men, or that the lobbying of
women, unlike that of men (or grandparents), was supported by tax dollars.
Since Cross admits nothing of the kind, we must conclude that she is part of
the problem rather than its solution. And children, of course, are the chief
victims of self-interest and self-righteousness on the part of adults whether
male or female.
So much for the tone. Two arguments appear over and over and over
again on this website (and other feminist sources). One is that the men
involved have no interest in either being fair to their former wives or taking
care of their children; they want only to control them. The other is that these
men are violent; giving them joint custody or even merely visiting rights
puts women and children at risk. Neither argument is supported on these
sites by authoritative sources or by documentation that would lead visitors
to them. (This is true even of a page aimed specifically at journalists and
lawyers, which primes them with fragmentary and undocumented statistics
on everything from time spent by fathers with their children to the violence
unleashed by fathers.)49 Even if the statistics were presented in full and
documented, however, they would still be contentious. Some can be
interpreted in various ways, for instance, and others are contradicted by
other statistics.
These trump cards are based on ideological claims about men in general,
claims that have been accepted as fact by many people – including many
men – merely because of their constant repetition. The most obvious ones
are that men (unlike women) are innately unsuited to child care and that
men (unlike women) are innately given to controlling or abusing others.
The implications of these claims extend far beyond the immediate source of
conflict, divorce and custody, calling into question the whole idea of a
society in which men and women can live together peacefully and
effectively in families. We will examine those in due course. For the time
being, listen to what feminists are saying about proposals for legislative
change.
These proposals are based partly on the idea that divorced women need
economic security and partly on the idea that children need contact with
their fathers. It is worth noting here that, ideological rants notwithstanding,
none of these proposed legislative changes has ever ignored the fact that
exceptions require special treatment. No legislative change has ever ignored
the fact that demonstrably violent men, for instance, should not have the
same rights as other men. At stake here, therefore, is not what the
legislation says about individual men but what it says – or, from the
perspective of some feminist sites, what it fails to say – about all men. The
belief that violence by men is the rule, not the exception, underlies these
sites, one could argue, not the welfare of children. If women claim to be
acting responsibly in the name of children by accusing men of bad faith,
after all, why should men not claim to be acting responsibly in the name of
children by accusing women of bad faith?
Now, consider a site set up in 2001 by the Ontario Women’s Network on
Custody and Access, consisting of representatives from seven presumably
mainstream organizations.50 Its aim is “to respond to federal law reform
initiatives on the Divorce Act and family law legislation.”51 This mission
statement is expanded elsewhere at the site. “The Network is insisting that
any changes to the federal Divorce Act take into account women’s ongoing
inequality in the family and in society, particularly as it pertains to their role
as the primary care-givers of children, their experiences of woman abuse
perpetuated by their partners, and their limited access to the legal system.
Any reforms … must also include an explicit recognition of violence
against women and its impact on women’s autonomy and the security of
themselves and their children.”52 Many others, including Cross, have
repeated that mantra: “Women have a right to live independently and to
enjoy their autonomy.”53
Everywhere you turn at this site, you encounter preposterous double
standards, deliberate obfuscations, and even outright lies. To take only one
example for the moment, the site rails passionately against “the emotional
and anti-woman backlash of the well-financed minority of men who claim
to speak for the rights of fathers.”54 That one fragment of a sentence
contains enough material for an extensive analysis. As for the charge of
emotionalism, there is some truth in it. Some fathers find themselves in
outrageously unfair positions. Why would anyone expect them not to
respond emotionally? But if women can claim to be both emotional and
objective – and feminist academics claim precisely that – why should the
same not be true of men? (We are not convinced that either claim is well-
founded, actually, but that is another matter.) As for the charge of an “anti-
woman backlash,” it is true also in some cases. Some sites do indeed refer
to “feminazis” and promote misogyny. But we have found few sites
advocating fairness to fathers that display more misogyny than this site and
others like it display misandry. And finally, what about this “well-financed
minority”? The fact is that advocacy groups for women are infinitely better
financed (and better organized) than those for men. Much of the money
used by women’s groups comes from the government – which is to say,
from taxpayers both female and male. Classified with visible minorities, for
instance, women benefit from the Court Challenges Program. When they go
to court over discrimination against female citizens, the government pays
them to challenge its own laws. When men go to court over discrimination
against male citizens, they pay their own way.55 Moreover, women’s groups
are heavily funded by government agencies such as Status of Women
Canada and its provincial equivalents. Even with the cutbacks that come to
all government projects now and then, women’s groups still retain access to
tax dollars and influence that no men’s group even dreams about. Groups
representing grandparents, too, receive no government funding. In addition,
of course, women solicit donations from members of their own
organizations.
One page at this site focuses attention on inequality within the family.
Women, visitors are told, do most or all of the housework without pay.
When they do work for pay, they suffer from “systemic racial and sexual
discrimination” and therefore earn only 72% of what men do. Once
divorced, 60% live in poverty – and up to 80% when they have children
under seven. “Despite changes in the law, many men still refuse to pay child
support and spousal support, and welfare rates are too low to meet the
actual shelter and basic needs of women and their children.”56 (Note the
site’s reference to “women and their children,” by the way, as if they belong
to women exclusively.) These claims are tendentious, to say the least. The
first claim is by no means uncontested.57 As for the oft-quoted global figure
of 72%, it does sound very disturbing, true, unless you remember two
things. First, it includes all the women who choose either not to work or to
work part-time, rather than full-time, and it includes older women with
inadequate education or training. Second, the wage gap narrows
considerably among younger women and men.
But economic equality is not the only, or even the primary, problem
discussed at this site. “One striking example of the impact of this inequality
is woman abuse: poverty reduces a woman’s capacity to leave an abusive
spouse, and a controlling man will use his social and economic power to
maintain his dominant position in the family. As the United Nations has
recognized, ‘violence against women is a manifestation of the historically
unequal power relations between men and women.’”58 On another page at
this site, we read that “custody has become such a hot topic for many men
because it is about money and power, as well as about who is looking after
the children,”59 as if precisely the same thing were not true of many
women. Poverty does indeed reduce a woman’s ability to leave an abusive
man, but the same thing applies to a man, especially in a society that would
expect him to maintain two households.
Refraining from any mention of the fact that some women abuse men
and others children (or both), the site claims that men abuse women
precisely because men have more money or power of any other kind than
women. Once again, this reduction to “power relations” indicates a classic
ideological claim: that men abuse women merely because they can – that is,
because they are men. The experience of daily life should be enough to
teach everyone that people (of both sexes) abuse others (of both sexes) for a
very wide range of reasons, some of which have nothing to do with either
economic or physical power. One example of unequal power relations
between men and women, of course, can be seen in the way that women
have come to dominate all current discussions of the family and society,
including this one. At another website, Cross warns readers: “Do not think
this does not matter to you. Whether or not you will ever have to deal with
custody and access law yourself, almost without question someone you
know and care about will, and the anticipated proposals for changes to the
Divorce Act will have significant implications for her.”60
In appendix 7, we discuss the ideological slant characteristic of the
United Nations. It is no accident that that this site and many other feminist
sites – another example is that of the National Association of Women and
the Law61 – refer to that organization. It refers also, not coincidentally, to
section 15 of the Charter and legal cases germane to it. “The Supreme Court
wrote,” notes the site in connection with Willick v. Willick,62 “that the
Divorce Act must be interpreted in a way that is ‘sensitive to equality of
result as between the spouses.’” And, who would oppose equality? In this
case, though, “equality” is a misleading word. As we keep saying, the term
“equality of result” expresses a particular interpretation of equality, one that
is preferred by those who believe that their political interests are not served
by modified equality of opportunity. The result is not even an interpretation
of equality, in fact, but a perversion of it. Equality of result does not require
equal treatment under the law. On the contrary, it requires preferential
treatment (presumably in order to achieve equality in the future). Similarly,
in connection with B.C. Government and Service Employees’ Union v. B.C.
Public Service Employees’ Relations Commission,63 also known as the
Meiorin case, this site adds another quotation from the Supreme Court:
“Interpreting human rights primarily in terms of formal equality [that is,
equality of opportunity] undermines its promise of substantive equality and
prevents consideration of the effects of systemic discrimination.”64
Ironically but not coincidentally, the very call for preferential treatment of
women (implicit in equality of result) is nothing other than a call for
systemic discrimination in favour of women.
Finally, this section exhibits open hostility toward any encroachment of
fathers into family life after divorce – and, by implication, before divorce or
even in the absence of divorce. “Mandatory shared parenting, and
mandatory mediation are examples of what the government MUST NOT DO.”
No proposed or enacted legislation ever “mandated” shared parenting (also
known as “joint custody”). What has been proposed is the presumption of
shared parenting unless it can be shown that children are in danger of
physical harm or some other severe harm. (Some websites comment on
other forms of harm.) But the reference here is only to “violence against
women,” as if that could be discussed adequately in isolation from violence
of any other kind. “It is in the children’s best interests that women’s
security, liberty and dignity be respected and promoted by laws and policies
in Canada.”65 To be sure, although that in itself says nothing about the
security, liberty and dignity of children. Overlooked is the possibility that it
would also be in the best interests of children – especially of boys – to
respect and promote, in addition, the security, liberty, and dignity of men.
Another page at the same site is organized more specifically around “the
best interests of the child.” The main goal is to reject any form of shared
parenting that might be established by law reformers. In a diatribe, the site
informs visitors that men seldom take their share of the responsibility for
childcare either during or after marriage. “Even when there are joint
custody orders, or agreements between parents to ‘share parenting,’
children usually continue to live with their mothers, and it is women who
take care of their day-to-day needs and support them financially.”66 In that
case, though, why would it make any difference what the law says?
On yet another page, visitors read that “many men become ‘disappearing
fathers.’ They do not fulfill their parental responsibilities, including the task
of taking the minimal amount of time agreed to visit their children, and
begrudging or disregarding the financial support they have to pay to meet
their share of the child’s needs.”67 Well, some divorced or separated fathers
do follow that pattern. But given the circumstances – included are self-
righteous and hostile former partners (who might well encourage the
children to become equally hostile); police officers, social workers,
psychologists, and even judges carefully “reeducated” to have immediate
sympathy for mothers but not fathers; indifferent bureaucrats; politically
correct legislators; and avaricious or corrupt collection agencies – it is
surely a wonder that so many do not.
It would take a major research project to find out precisely why many
fathers move heaven and earth, at great emotional expense, to retain contact
with their children. That research will not be done as long as social
scientists are satisfied that ideological feminists already have an answer to
the claim that is seldom even made – which is to say, that most fathers in
crisis have nothing better to do with their time and energy than seek
revenge against their former wives or girlfriends (thus demonstrating,
conveniently for ideologues, that the world revolves around women). Like
mothers – and like all human beings – fathers are probably motivated by
conflicting urges. Even those fathers and mothers who do want to punish
former spouses, after all, might nevertheless also want sincerely to stand by
their children. If we as individuals cannot tolerate or even acknowledge
ambivalence and ambiguity, which are characteristic and universal features
of human existence, then we have lapsed into terminal cynicism. What,
then, can be said of a whole society that has institutionalized cynicism in
the law?
Elsewhere at this site we read about the importance of “embracing
diversity,” which means that a “white, middle-class standard must not be
used to determine what kinds of parenting are appropriate or to evaluate
‘parenting plans’ of all families.”68 Yes, but that flies in the face of what
this site demands: a single feminist standard. Very few of the women who
created this site would even consider the possibility that fathers have
parenting skills or styles that, though very different from their own, might
nevertheless be “interpreted in a manner that is respectful of the diverse
realities of families in Canada.”69
On the contrary, they acknowledge not a single distinctive or necessary
thing that fathers might be able to contribute to family life. They show
nothing but contempt, in other words, for fathers who fail to accept the
superiority of mothers (and, in effect, leave parenting to them). They imply
on every page that fathers want only to exploit their children in order to
harass or attack the mothers. “The standard must take into account the
specific Aboriginal, as well as diverse racial, ethnoculural communities,
and immigrant experiences” in relation to parenting.70 Are we to believe
that these women would accept cultural practices that do not measure up to
the standard of feminism (let alone ideological feminism)? Anyone who
does believe that is naive to the max. After all, many are cultures that
feminists either have condemned or would have to condemn as patriarchal.
The site includes that passage in order to add the respectability conferred by
political correctness. When it comes to custody and child support, diversity
is the very last thing that the folks who created this site would tolerate. For
good measure in connection with “diversity,” the site warns against
continuing “discrimination on the basis of … sexual orientation in custody
and access cases.”71 Given its exclusive concern for women, this warning
probably refers mainly to lesbians (but with the understanding that some
gay men, especially those most likely to want children within the context of
gay relationships, find it politically expedient to adopt feminism in one
form or another).
Another page at the same site is about parenting after separation.
“Claims by Father’s Rights groups that men receive unfair treatment by the
courts in custody decisions are simply untrue. Courts often award custody
to women because they recognize that the mother was the primary caregiver
when the relationship was intact. In such cases, they recognize that children
will suffer the least upset in a separation if they remain in the care of the
parent who has been the primary caregiver.”72 This passage begins with a
facile observation: claims that men receive unfair treatment are “simply
untrue.” In other words, no father has ever been shafted by the system.
Almost as facile is what follows. It is true that women are usually the
primary caregivers, but at least one reason for that is the a priori message to
men in our society, including the one conveyed effectively at this site, that
fathers have no necessary or even significant function in family life. That
being the case, why be surprised when fathers leave childcare to mothers?
One part of the solution to this problem would be to give men (and boys)
a different message by taking them seriously, in law, as parents or potential
parents. Another part of the solution would be to acknowledge that fathers
and mothers characteristically provide children with different kinds of
primary care. And even if young children do not suffer by being left with
their mothers, older children might. And even younger ones might not in
the long run. To deny that possibility, once again, is to deny the need of
children for fathers in any situation, not merely in one of separation or
divorce. That is a very radical claim, one that is supported with evidence
neither at this site nor anywhere else. It is a belief, an assumption, an
ideological claim, that few visitors are likely to question.
Elsewhere at this site, we learn that “when men do apply for custody of
the children, they often get it despite the fact that they had not exercised
their fair share of parental responsibilities during the relationship.”73
Actually, this accusation is disingenuous. Fathers usually get custody in
these cases, after all, only because the mothers are even less responsible
than they are. If this accusation were true, though, it would still disregard
the fact that custody is not about the past – a reward, say, for services
rendered – but about the present and future. Separation or divorce is a
radical change in the lives of all concerned: children, mothers, and fathers.
What fathers once did or did not do, for a wide range of reasons, is not
necessarily what they would do in these new circumstances. If they can
adjust to so many other changes when required to do so – and most of these
men, by far, do find ways of carrying on with their lives – why assume that
they either cannot or will not adjust to this one? Here again is the old
stereotype that only women are fit to become parents (as long as they are
supplied with money either by the fathers or by the state). Even male
gorillas have been known to care effectively for their infants, especially
when the females are either dead or reject their infants for one reason or
another; the task is not one that these animals have learned from infancy,
but it is one that they can do and will do.74
According to this site, moreover, the principle of “maximum contact”
between both parents and their children, enacted in the Divorce Act, was a
step in the wrong direction. Why oppose that? Because it was accompanied
by the “friendly parent rule,” these feminists claim, which gave custody to
the parent most likely to grant visitation rights to the other parent. “Mothers
who seek to protect their children from abusive or controlling fathers are
often labeled ‘unfriendly,’ and they may lose custody of the children
because the courts find them ‘uncooperative.’”75
Visitors read elsewhere that “[m]aximum contact with both parents is
supposed to be in the best interest of children, but it often is not. When a
father is violent, abusive or controlling it is not in the best interest of the
child to have extensive contacts with him.”76 The ante has been upped.
Fathers are demonized for being not only violent and “abusive” but also
“controlling.” Psychological control, in fact, is the rhetorical counterpart to
physical violence. The implication is that only men like to control others.
Presumably, women never do so unless they are either insane or somehow
driven to it by men. In fact, as anyone should realize from the experience of
daily life, women can be just as controlling, manipulative, and domineering
as men. As those who have read the politically “controversial” studies of
domestic violence should know, moreover, women can be just as violent
toward children as men are. You can argue forever about the precise
statistics on female violence toward children, either as mothers or as
babysitters, but it is clear by now that it makes no sense to assume either the
innate “nurturance” of mothers or the innate violence of fathers. Law
reform – joint custody – has been designed to take precisely this ambiguity
into account, presuming that both parents truly care about their children
unless one (or both) of them clearly does not. That is the equivalent of
presuming that people on trial are innocent unless proven guilty. This site,
on the other hand, would have us succumb to cynicism – selective
cynicism, of course, in that only men would fall collectively under
suspicion.
But wait. More accusations. “In addition, the maximum contact rule is
regularly used by vindictive men to harass ex-partners, by allowing them to
take mothers back to court for any allegation of access denial. Father’s
Rights groups say that unfair denial of access by mothers is a big problem,
but it actually happens in a very small percentage of cases.”77 Without
documentation, of course, visitors to the site have no way of checking either
contention. Besides, arguments of this kind, based on politically motivated
generalizations, are self-defeating. Reality is more complex than advocates
of any position like to admit. Precisely the same kind of argument, after all,
has been made by women’s-rights groups. They complain about fathers who
fail to show up for visits with their children. It could be argued that this,
too, actually happens in a very small percentage of cases. When it does,
moreover, the explanation could be either circumstances beyond their
control or overt hostility from their wives and even from the children living
with their mothers.
Visitors to the site are told that joint custody is acceptable in theory but
that “problems appear when the courts impose joint custody on parents
against their will.” What can that possibly mean? No court would ever
award joint custody to a father (or mother) who wants nothing to do with
parenthood. The site’s deceptively simple statement must refer, therefore, to
cases in which the court gives joint custody against the will of mothers.
Which problems appear? One might be that “women are often left with the
burden of physical and financial responsibility for their children.” But you
can hardly blame the courts for the failure of fathers to honour the legal
obligations assigned by it. And besides, the burden of physical and financial
responsibility is what these mothers would have under sole custody – which
is presumably what this site advocates. “And in the process,” the section
adds, “they will lose the autonomy necessary to raise their children.”78
But why should any parent (except a widow or widower) have that kind
of autonomy in the first place? Since when is the autonomy of either parent
“necessary” for children? The section continues with what amounts to an
answer. “Joint custody can also significantly lower child support awards,
and women often end up living in poverty.” This argument would make
more sense, morally, if sole custody (or “60%” custody) by mothers – the
solution advocated by this very site – did not leave so many fathers living in
poverty after duly making their child-support payments. “Finally,” this
section warns, “joint custody is a tool that can be used by violent or
manipulative men to continue to exercise control over their children and ex-
partners for many years after separation or divorce.”79 Once again, what is
sauce for the gander should be sauce for the goose as well. If joint custody
allows that kind of behaviour by men to continue, it allows the same kind of
behaviour by women to continue. No one has ever claimed that joint
custody is a solution to human stupidity, malice, spite, selfishness, or
neuroticism – traits that are obviously shared by both men and women. It is
merely the lesser of two evils (assuming the absence of violence):
maintaining the relationships of children with both parents, though not
under the ideal conditions of a happy marriage, or severing their
relationships with either mothers or fathers.
In a section on “mandatory shared parenting,” the site mentions similar
approaches in other countries and concludes that “more women have to deal
with husbands who try to control the way they raise the children but don’t
actually share in the caregiving work. More children are placed in the care
of abusive and violent fathers, and more parents spend more time in courts
litigating the meaning of the different clauses in their parenting plans.
Shared parenting can work: but it must never be imposed on parents, and it
[must] not be allowed in cases of woman abuse or child abuse.”80 Since no
documentation is provided, once again, no one can check the international
statistics. The rest of these claims can be questioned more easily.
Some fathers, having been awarded joint custody, do try to “control” the
way their children are brought up. So do some mothers. In fact, so does
everyone at one time or another. We all need to have some control over the
world around us. And we all want at least some control over whatever is
most important to us. The site refers to total or exclusive control, of course,
and implies that only men want it. Some do. So do some women (something
made clear inadvertently, as we will show, by this very site). That is what
can happen in cases of separation or divorce. These are bad situations. No
legal system can ever change that, but any legal system can try to mitigate
the damage. As for fathers who fail to share in the “caregiving” work, that
might depend on precisely what care is thought to entail. If we assume that
it can be defined in exclusively emotional terms, we are being not only
naive but also ahistorical.
At all times, most fathers have cared for their children as “providers.”
Not so long ago, that involved introducing sons to the exciting but
hazardous outside world, instilling self-discipline, teaching them trades, and
teaching them how to compete with others or setting them up in businesses.
Nowadays, single mothers try to do all those things with help from the state
instead of husbands. But not even the most successful single mother can
teach her sons how to be healthy men. And not even the most successful
single mother, alone, can teach her daughters how to experience men in
healthy ways. Not all fathers live up to the ideal, of course, but neither do
all mothers.
We do not need to discuss the standard charge of violence yet again, but
we might need to reiterate one thing. The Special Committee on Custody
and Access did not recommend that “shared parenting become
mandatory.”81 It recommended only that shared parenting be presumed in
the absence of compelling reasons for a different arrangement.
Many of these arguments are rehashed yet again in the section on
“parental responsibility,” the term proposed to replace “joint custody” or
“shared parenting” (although all three are very similar). This approach has
already been tried in Britain, Australia, and the state of Maine. “Reports
indicate,” visitors learn without being given any reference to the research,
“that the reforms in the UK and in Australia have not been successful. No
report has yet been done on the Maine model.”82 But successful for whom?
For children? For fathers? For men? For mothers? For women? For society?
For the short term? For the long term? If the goal in each case was to give
mothers what amounts to exclusive ownership of children or to give women
ultimate control over family life, of course, then this solution probably has
failed. But questions about motivation and underlying ideological
assumptions are not what anyone responsible for this site would want to
discuss.
“Like joint custody,” this section continues, “its success will depend on
the good will of the parents involved. Women already complain that there is
no mechanism to enforce or monitor fathers who do not exercise scheduled
access and disappoint their children.”83 Yes, but every plan depends on the
good will of the parents involved. How could it be otherwise except in a
totalitarian state? And men already complain that there is no mechanism to
enforce or monitor mothers who find excuses to prevent children from
seeing their fathers. This passage, like many others, indicates a strong urge
to control children, to control men, and therefore to control society as a
whole. It is hard to avoid the conclusion that the problem for these women
with “parental responsibility” is not so much that it might prove harmful to
children as that it would prevent them from having exclusive control over
children.
That becomes even more obvious in the passage’s conclusion: “As with
mediation, there may [that is, might] be no public record, no right of appeal
and no constitutional guarantees. Like mediation, it’s a service that would
likely be privatized, without national standards.”84 Of course, no one at this
site ever complains about the lack of accountability, from the perspective of
fathers, in the family-court system, with its psychologists and social
workers and bureaucrats working behind the scenes. Besides, the same
problems could just as easily affect fathers. And what “constitutional
guarantees” are we talking about? Some fundamental “right” of women to
have exclusive control over family life? It would take some fancy foot-
work, to say the least, for feminists to interpret section 15 of the Charter –
which guarantees sexual equality – in that way.
Like almost every other page at the site, this one concludes with the
shibboleth of violence. The usual trump card. “In family law disputes,
women are often fighting for the safety of themselves and their children,
while some men are fighting to maintain power and control.”85 But the
same argument could be used in reverse. And this kind of comparison, the
best of one with the worst of another, is not legitimate. The bad news is that
some men and some women really are interested primarily in themselves
and their need for control, revenge, identity, political virtue, or whatever.
The good news, on the other hand, is that some women and some men
really are interested primarily in their children. No system is ever going to
change human nature, once again, not even that of a totalitarian state.
People are complex beings with ambivalent attitudes and contradictory
needs. All any system can do is try to treat every litigated case individually
and not on the basis of preconceived ideas, whether cultural stereotypes or
ideological beliefs, about what men or women in general are all about. Will
that always work out for the benefit of children? No, but the alternative, the
one implied but never actually stated on this web-site, would be infinitely
more dangerous.
At the site’s page on women’s access to justice, visitors learn that men
often manipulate the family-law system in order “to punish the women and
children who leave them … as a way to continue holding power and control
over their former wives and girlfriends.”86 Some men do, no doubt. But are
we to believe that women are somehow above using the system for the
same reasons? The only people who have seldom or never come across
vindictive women are infants (and even some children are abused by their
mothers). Stalking is probably more characteristic of abusive men than it is
of abusive women. But the latter have much more effective ways of
harassing their former partners. More effective, because they are perfectly
legal. Besides, stalking is already illegal, not only in the context of
separation or divorce, by the way, but in any context. No alteration to the
Divorce Act will change that.
In another section, the site lists all the ways in which abusive men
misuse contacts with their children. They ask for information about the
doings of their former partners, say nasty things about them, threaten to
withhold child-support payments, try to gain sympathy, and so on. This is
indeed an ugly side of human nature, partly because it puts children in an
extremely difficult position. As usual, though, visitors to the site are
implicitly asked to believe that women refrain from doing and saying
precisely the same things. No one who has lived in this world for more than
a few years (except feminist ideologues) could honestly claim to believe
that.
In the following section, this site explains how abusive men can misuse
contacts with their children. It is because the law allows them to do so,
apparently, or even encourages them to do so. “Family Courts often do not
believe women or their children when they say they are abused or exposed
to violence. Most family lawyers are not adequately trained to work with or
represent the interests of abused women and their children in court.”87 Once
upon a time, this was true. Not only is it no longer true, on the other hand,
but the reverse is probably true. Beginning in the 1980s and picking up
steam in the 1990s, federal and provincial governments established
extensive “reeducation” programs (either mandated or demanded by public
pressure) for police officers, social workers, emergency-room physicians,
lawyers, judges, legislators, and so on. Men may now be forced out of their
homes on the mere say-so of women – that is, without evidence.
This site laments that law reformers recommend “only taking into
account incidents of ‘proven’ violence when determining custody: in many
cases women cannot prove violence enacted against them because of
insufficient evidence.”88 Women and children, according to this site, need
access to a “legal system that recognizes woman abuse and children’s
exposure to violence, and believes women and children when they say that
they are abused/exposed to violence.”89 In that case, what they really need
is something other than a democracy in which all citizens are treated
equally under the law and no citizen may be arrested, tried, or convicted, on
the basis of an unsubstantiated accusation. Otherwise, we might as well
return to the Salem of 1692. If insisting on evidence and due process
indicates a survival of patriarchy, in short, then even that would be
preferable to the current status quo in which “women don’t lie” has become
an article of faith in politically correct circles – that is, the circles that run
our legal and other bureaucracies. But once again, no system is perfect.
People must choose, now as always, between a system that allows a
relatively few guilty people to go free, possibly to strike again, and one that
allows many innocent people to be destroyed. By refusing to acknowledge a
massive cultural change in the latter direction, at any rate, this site indulges
in outright dishonesty. Visitors read that women need access also to a “legal
system that holds abusive men accountable for their actions,”90 for instance,
as if that were not already the case and were not part of any reformed
version of the Divorce Act.
Every section of this site concludes with instructions under the headings
“Act Now!” or “What You Can Do!” One page includes a sample letter
addressed to the minister of justice. The writer expects “that any changes to
the federal Divorce Act will acknowledge the prevalence of violence
against women and put provisions in place to ensure that child custody and
access arrangements protect women and children from exposure to violence
and abuse on the part of former partners. These provisions are entirely in
keeping with the federal government’s national and international
commitments to end violence against women, including its support of the
United Nations Declaration on the Elimination of Violence against
Women.”91 Note the word “prevalence,” as in “prevail.” Violence against
women not only occurs often, according to this letter (which conveniently
forgets about all other forms of violence, including domestic violence, that
targets men), it is the prevailing pattern. It is the norm of a society still
languishing under the tyranny of patriarchy. It is the major factor to be
considered in any revision to the Divorce Act. And just in case the minister
is not convinced by the questionable statistics that underlie this statement,
he – it was a he, by the way, Martin Cauchon – is intimidated by the threat
of exposure to ridicule or contempt by the world community. The letter
continues with a demand for “gender-based analysis,” a euphemism for
feminist analysis. This too, after all, is mandated by documents of the
United Nations – the Beijing Platform is mentioned – that have been signed
by Canada. (At its site, too, the National Association of Women and the
Law refers to Beijing.)92 The letter then asks for the minister to “hold a
consultation with equality-seeking women’s organizations that work on the
issue of violence against women and are familiar with how family law,
including its impact on child custody and access arrangements affects
women.”93 “Equality” has become a peculiar word, as we have already
observed, denoting one thing but connoting the opposite.
The worldview of this website is a separatist one. It is based on the
notion of female “autonomy,” understood not in the relative sense of
psychology or sociology (because no human being can ever be, or should
ever be, completely autonomous) but in the political sense of ideological
feminism. What the latter requires, ultimately, is a utopia in which women
have as little as possible to do with men (except for a few gay men, perhaps,
or a few converts to ideological feminism). This would mean not only
complete maternal autonomy (exclusive jurisdiction over children) but also
complete reproductive autonomy (a project that has been the goal of
agitation for several decades by groups such as the Feminist International
Network of Resistance to Reproductive and Genetic Engineering).
In this political and ideological context, the urgent demand for a legal
system that presumes or even mandates custody by mothers alone makes
sense. What better way to build a feminist utopia, after all, than to create a
male generation reared from infancy to young manhood on the edifying
feminist doctrines of their mothers and untainted by the corrupt patriarchal
doctrines of their fathers – and a female generation, reared from infancy to
young womanhood on the same basis, that wants and needs little or no
contact with men? This is surely one reason for the site’s explicit rejection
of proposals for mandatory mediation and parenting programs.
As for the former, we read on one page that “[e]ven in the absence of
violence, many women who enter into mediation compromise too much,
sometimes jeopardizing their own and their children’s welfare.”94 To be
sure. But so do many men. Some believe – not surprisingly, given what
society tells them – that they cannot be as effective at parenting as women.
Others are afraid of conflict. Still others worry about the effect of conflict
on their children.
And as for the latter, we read that “[f]orcing parents to take parenting
classes assumes that divorce/separation is bad for children.”95 So divorce is
good for children? Because “[s]tudies show that children are often stressed
and anxious when living in a home where their father hurts their mother.
When their mothers leave the abusive relationship, they are able to heal,
and feel safe and secure. Mediation, parenting plans, and parenting classes
only work when no abuse or power imbalance is present, and where parents
have shared the responsibility and care for their children during the
marriage relationship.”96 Well, children are indeed stressed in those
circumstances, although we have no reason to assume that most children do
live in those circumstances. But children are stressed also by the crisis of
divorce or separation, unfortunately, especially if that means separation
from one of the parents – and particularly, though not only, for boys
separated from their fathers. A breakup is sometimes the lesser of two evils,
yes, but that does not make it good for children. The best solution for them
would be for both parents to remain with their children and conduct
themselves like adults with each other. But that would require more
maturity than most adults can be expected to attain and also – this is
important – more maturity than our self-oriented society is willing even to
recommend.97
The ultimate good as defined at this website is not to repair marriages
(because the only reason that they need repair in the first place, apparently,
is due to the wicked ways of men) or to learn new parenting skills (because
the only parents who need new ones, supposedly, are fathers) or even to
establish working relationships for practical purposes (because that would
require women to remain in contact with men) but to limit or end the
presence of men in families. This is implied, not stated. We cannot prove
that our interpretation is correct, of course, because we cannot get into the
minds of those who established these sites. But we are interested in the
effects of what they write, not their inner motivations or whether these have
been conveyed adequately or inadequately. Visitors to this site or similar
ones are likely, we believe, to draw the same conclusion that we have
drawn. Some will like the message of separatism, and others (including
many feminists) will not. But not very many – certainly no one who is
familiar with the literature of ideological feminism – will fail to see it.
Our approach here has been, admittedly, impressionistic. It would
require a full-scale research project to gather a large enough sample of
websites for inspection. Someone in the social sciences should do this
research.
APPENDIX TEN
Gynotopia: Feminism at Academic Conferences
In Dinotopia,1 by James Gurney, a professor and his son find themselves on
a lost island where humans coexist peacefully with dinosaurs. But
Dinotopia is truly neither a lost paradise nor even a longed-for utopia.
Conflict does arise; otherwise, there could be no story. This fantasy is
delightful, in any case, because readers (or viewers of the television series)
know that real dinosaurs once prevailed over all other forms of life; had any
humans been around sixty-five million years ago, they would surely have
been prey for at least some of those powerful beasts. A similar fantasy is
played out every year, at least in theory, in the context of academic
conferences. On the surface, a kind of politically correct harmony reigns.
Everyone knows, however, that this is illusory; beneath the surface, one
species prevails – the one that uses postmodern rhetoric to disguise or
legitimate ideological claims. Advocates of several ideologies have done
this successfully in the past. At the moment, those of ideological feminism
are most successful.
Even a cursory examination of papers presented at annual conferences of
the Modern Language Association during the last decade of the twentieth
century makes it clear that gynocentrism prevailed. (The same could be said
of many other academic organizations, let alone the many feminist
academic and nonacademic organizations.) Not everything said or done at
the conferences discussed here was either directly or indirectly about
women, of course, but so many things were – papers at almost every panel
– that visitors from another planet might well have called this world a
“gynotopia.”
During the 1990s, gender was among the most common topics, along
with race, postcolonialism, canon, and so on.2 By “gender,” presenters
almost always referred to the distinctive problems of women as represented
in literature – problems due almost invariably to the oppressive “social
constructions” created by men. The word “gender,” in short, almost always
indicated a specifically feminist approach. Only a few papers, on the other
hand, referred to the distinctive problems of men as represented in
literature. Even papers that did, however, often adopted feminist
approaches. So did those on the problems of gay men and women, for that
matter, although feminism in that context was known as “queer theory.” As
a result, these conferences were profoundly gynocentric (and, to some
extent depending on content, misandric as well).
Feminist theory, queer theory, and postcolonial theory – sometimes
combined as “cultural studies” – are all products of postmodernism. Most
of the papers presented at these conferences are easily identifiable as
postmodern from their titles and subtitles alone – that is, from their use, or
overuse, of deconstructive jargon. Code words – “intertextuality,”
“strategies,” “voices,” “construction” – for instance, appear over and over
again. Because postmodernists claim that there is no such thing as truth
(except, presumably, for the truth of what they themselves are saying), their
chosen titles acknowledge only shifting “discourses” about it. But some
words clarify their intentions. They refer over and over again to “contested
sites” of “resistance,” “subversion,” and “transgression.” These words
strongly suggest political motivations. The titles listed below are littered,
moreover, with words indicating that the authors’ goals can be attained
merely by focusing on one (politically expedient) aspect or even one
perception of an amorphous reality rather than some other one: re-
presenting, re-forming, re-formulating, re-positioning, re-situating, re-
locating, re-inventing, re-negotiating, re-thinking, re-imagining, re-
inscribing, re-stating, re-figuring, re-assessing, re-articulating, re-
constructing, re-visiting, re-considering, re-conceptualizing, re-
contextualizing, re-drawing (boundaries), and so on.
We turn now to two conferences, one held at the beginning of the decade
and one held at the end. The conference of 1990 included several papers
about men in literature.3 These papers do not necessarily represent the
perspective of men, certainly not that of straight men. Indeed, they usually
represent the deconstructive perspective of feminists and queer theorists.
Here is the list: Gender and Genre (“As I Am a Man”: The Structure and
Stakes of Masculinity in “The Thorn”); Margins of Masculinity: Discourses
of Male Subjectivity in Nineteenth-Century Anglo-America (Bachelor-
hood, Reverie, and the Odor of Male Solitude; The Detective as Pervert;
Marginally Criminal: Male Subjectivity in Sister Carrie); After Atwood:
Feminist Utopias in the 1980s (Nonessentialist Versions of Male Violence);
Showing the Boys How: Staël Rewrites Masculinity (Suicide as Self-
Construction; “Let’s Do It after the High Roman Fashion”: Staël’s Critique
of Revolutionary Heroism; What’s Wrong with Mr. Right? The Melancholy
Face of Patriarchy in Corinne); The Turn of the Century in the Twentieth
Century II: Feminist Perspectives – Feminist Reform Meets Modernist
Form (Real Womanhood versus Conventional Manhood: Marie Stopes
Backstage); The “Voice” of David Mamet: Plays and Screenplays (Phallus
in Wonderland: Machismo and Business in American Buffalo and
Glengarry Glen Ross); The Fiction of Dorothy L. Sayers: A Symposium on
the Centenary of Lord Peter Wimsey (Lord Peter Wimsey: A Member of the
Neighboring Sex); Wang Wen-Hsing: Postmodernism and the
Contemporary Chinese Text (Male Happiness: Wang Wen-hsing); Shaping
Masculinities: Victorian Writers, Artists, and Their Careers (The
PreRaphaelite Brotherhood and the Problematic of Manliness; Muscular
Aestheticism: Pater’s Discipline; Policing Swinburne’s Desire: Reshaping
the Male Writer’s Masculinity); Men in Women’s Places: Exploring
Masculinity in Hollywood Film (John Wayne, the Western, and the Ideal of
the Family on the Land; Masculinity in Crisis: The Dialectic of Female
Power and Male Hysteria in Play Misty for Me; Hometown as Male
Domestic Space in It’s a Wonderful Life; “Don’t Ever Rub Another Man’s
Rhubarb”: The Homoerotics and Homophobia of Batman); The Fiction of
Masculinity: Images of Men in Modern Literature (The Ideal Friend: Gay
Representatives of the Heterosexual Male; Man among Men: David
Mamet’s Homosocial Order; Tang Ao in America: Male Subject Positions
in Maxine Hong Kingston’s China Men; Unveiling the Prick: The
(De)Construction of (Western) Masculinity in David Henry Wang’s M.
Butterfly); Humor of the American Family (Playing House: The “New”
Masculinity in 1980s Situation Comedy); Spectacular Bodies (The Castrato,
Spectacle, and Gender in the Eighteenth Century); Composition, Context,
and Gender (Composition Theory and the Myth of the Self-Made Man:
Authentic Voice and the Rhetoric of Masculinity); Gender and Generation
in Frances Burney’s Novels (Relating Families: Brotherly Love, Brotherly
Hatred in Frances Burney’s Fiction); 1980s Chicano Literature: A
Cornucopia of Prizes (Women and Men: Villanueva’s Ultraviolet Sky); The
Ties That Bound: Homophobia and Relations among Males in Early
America (Sodomy in the New World; The Prurient Origins of the American
Self; New English Sodom; The Sodomitical Tourist); The Concept of the
Male Child in Children’s Literature (The Image of the Male Child in
Literature: Or, Why I’ve Stopped Teaching C.S. Lewis’s The Lion, the
Witch and the Wardrobe; Growing Up Male in the Nuclear Wasteland:
Danger Quotient, Fiskadoro, Riddley Walker, and the Failure of the
Campbellian Monomyth; Generic Archetypes? Universality and Maleness
in LeGuin’s Earthsea Trilogy; Reluctant Lords and Lame Princes:
Engendering the Male Child in Nineteenth-Century Juvenile Fiction).
The same conference included eighty-eight papers about women (but
also, albeit indirectly in some cases, about men) in literature. Once again,
the dominant perspective is the deconstructive one of ideological feminism
and queer theory. Here is the list: Gender and Genre (Mourning,
Masochism, and Mothers: Felicia Hemans on the Origins of Poetry); Dante,
Petrarca, Boccaccio: Intertextual Perspectives (Tamed Amazons and Tearful
Virgins: Narrative Strategies and Feminine Authority in Boccaccio’s
Teseida); “New Behns, New Durfeys Yet Remain in Store”: New Views of
Restoration and Early Eighteenth-Century Drama (Woman’s Wit: Some
Successful Female Tricksters in Restoration Comedy); Emily Dickinson in
the New Century: Publication, Critical Reception, Influence (“Vinnie’s
Garden”: Emily Dickinson and the Women’s Nature Poetry Tradition,
1880–1925); Black Chicago Renaissance: Old and New (Women and
Agency in Marita Bonner’s Frye Street and Environs); Netherlandic
Language and Literature (Van Deyssel’s Een liefde: Art, Passion and the
Construction of Sexuality); Sexual-Textual Poetics: Mary Wroth and the
Sidney Family Men (In My Father’s House: Mary Wroth and Robert
Sidney; “All Arcadia on Fire”: Mary Wroth Reads Philip Sidney; The
Sidney Family Romance: Mary Wroth and William Herbert); Theorizing
“Third World” Literature (The Problematics of the Western Feminist Model
in Israeli Literature); Le Déshabillé dans la Recherche de Proust (The Art of
Undress(ing): The Déshabillé in Proust’s Recherche; Discursive Sexuality:
Veiling and Undressing in Proust; Elaborate Négligée: Reading Proust with
Blanchot); Chicano Folk Drama: Issues and Approaches (The Defiant
Voice: Feminist Rhetoric in the Luxican-Chicago Pastorela; Pastoras and
Matachines: A Feminist Look at Chicano Folk Drama); Thinking through
the Body: Cultural Differences and Women’s Bodies (Writing the (Lesbian)
Body; Between Western Feminist Theory and Third World Women’s
Literature: Reexamining the Mother-Daughter Relationship in Wansuh
Park’s Mother Roots; A Question of Power: The Psychotic Body in a Work
by Bessie Head; The Dead Feminine Bodies of Frankenstein); After
Atwood: Feminist Utopias in the 1980s (Renewed Subversions: Gender and
Power in Recent Feminist Utopias; Nonessentialist Versions of Male
Violence; Wordplay and Revolution); Problems of Affirmation in Cultural
Theory I (Critical Theory and the New Mestiza: A Deconstructuralism for
the Nineties); Toward a Political Pedagogy in Hispanic Literatures and
Cultures: A Workshop (Strategies for Teaching the Other “Other”: The
Black Woman in Latin America; Strategies for Feminist Team Teaching of
Hispanic Women Writers; Strategies for Teaching us Hispanic Women
Writers; Strategies for Teaching a Feminist Political Latin American
Culture Course); Fictions of Feminine Compliance (Pudeur among the
Pigeons and Other Rousseauistic Fictions; Slaves, Masters, and the Sexual
Contract: Prévost’s Histoire d’une Grecque moderne; Fictions of Feminine
Compliance in Kant’s Third Critique; Beyond the Heart of Women:
Postrevolutionary Sentiment); Revolting Acts: Gay Performance in the
Sixties (“Pop Comes from the Outside”: Absorption, Theatricality, and
Gender in Sixties Performance; Gay Vanguardism; The Critic as
Performance Artist: Susan Sontag’s Writing and Gay Subcultures); Issues
of Sexuality and Subjectivity in Old French Literature I (The Feminization
of Law in the Advocacie nostre dame sainte Marie; Sex Change and
Subjectivity in La mutacion de fortune; To Speak or Not to Speak: Silence,
Sexuality, and the Representation of Subjectivity); Perceptions of
Otherness: Gender, Sex, Race, Religion, Nation I (Wilhelm von Humboldt
and the Difference between the Sexes; Taking a Woman’s Word for It: The
Memoirs of the Jewish Salonière, Henri-ette Herz); The “New Woman” as
Poet: American Women’s Poetry, 1910–1930 (“You Are Not Male or
Female”: Moore’s “Octopus” and the American Sublime; “We Women Who
Write Poetry”: The Plural Subject in Amy Lowell and Louise Bogan;
Women’s Poetry in The Masses; The Repulsive Woman as Poet: Djuna
Barnes and the Politics of Sexual Deviance); Margaret Oliphant: Gendered
and Subversive Strategies in Her Fiction (Victorian Seamstresses, Victorian
Goddesses: Images of Aggrandized Womanhood in Margaret Oliphant’s
Fiction; Scandalous Women and Changing Mores: Margaret Oliphant’s The
Sorceress; Independent Women in Margaret Oliphant’s Fiction: Gentle,
Gendered Subversion); Renegotiating Marxism and Pragmatism (Ideology:
Or, Feminist Discourse, Practically Speaking); Doris Lessing: Feminist
Critical Contexts (The Riddle of Doris Lessing’s Feminism; New Sites of
Power: Lessing’s Antiessentialism); Third World Literature and the Biblical
Call for Justice (Unbinding Literary Feet: Twentieth-Century Chinese
Women Writers); Unread Texts (Femmes sauvages, femmes civilisées:
Marie de l’Incarnation entre la clôture et les bois; The Heroine at War:
Gender Deviation and Self-Division in the Mémoires of Madame de la
Guette); Social Theory and Social Fiction I (Women and Marriage in Gyp
and James); Medieval and Renaissance Italian Literature (Gender and
Cultural Literacy in the Improvisation of the Sixteenth-Century Commedia
del l’Arte); Representing Modernist Texts: Editing as Interpretation (H.D.:
Text, Canon, and Gender); Feminist Composition, Feminine Composition
(Composition, Gender, and the Uses of Texts; What Is Feminine
Composition, and Why Should We Teach It; How Composition Anthologies
En-gender Subjectivity: Or, “Once More to the Lake”); “All Generations
Shall Call Me Blessed”: Female Saints in Medieval England (Crystis Wyfe:
Saint Faith in England; Ourse, “Maide of Noble Fame”: Saint Ursula in
Middle English History and Hagiography; Torture as Appropriation: Saints
and Their Public in Middle English Hagiography); The Turn of the Century
in the Twentieth Century II: Feminist Perspectives – Feminist Reform
Meets Modernist Form (Real Womanhood versus Conventional Manhood:
Marie Stopes Backstage; “My Buried Life”: The Lady in T.S. Eliot’s
“Portrait”; Voyaging Out: Modernist Primitivism and the Discourse on the
New Woman; Rewriting the Domestic Novel as Political Critique); Editing
H.D.: Female Texts and the Meaning of Silence (H.D. and Richard
Aldington: In and out of Silence; Another Life Relived: The Challenges of
Editing the H.D.-Pearson Correspondence; Gender Politics in Editing
H.D.); The Figure of the Preacher in Twentieth-Century American
Literature (A Woman in the Pulpit: Gender and the Structures of Power in
Elmer Gantry); John Milton: A General Session (Saying No to Freud:
Milton’s A Mask and Sexual Assault); Joyce & His Life (Joyce and Women:
Challenge and Discovery); Women’s Studies Programs in the Rocky
Mountain Region (The Women’s Studies Program at the University of
Wyoming; Women’s Studies at Wichita State University); Romance Epic I
(Women and Their Sexuality in Ami et Amile: An Occasion to
Deconstruct?); Women’s Studies, Cultural Studies (Reading against the
Grain: 2,600 Years of Women Writing in India; I Won’t Always Be a
Penniless Subaltern; A Cultural Agenda for the Next Millennium;
Metathesis: Reading the Future, Future Reading; Going Public: Latin
American Feminism in the 1980s; Othering: Heterogeneity and Discourse);
Lesbianism, Heterosexuality, and Feminist Theory (Mapping the Frontier of
the Black Hole: Toward a Black Feminist Theory; The Lesbian Phallus: Or,
Does Heterosexuality Exist? Perverse Desire, the Lure of the Mannish
Lesbian); Sexual Encounters and Dramatic Performance (Anxieties of
Intimacy in Twelfth Night and Other Plays; Restoration Shakespeare, the
Male Gaze, and the Woman Actor; Rehearsing Sexual Encounters); The
Material Book in the Seventeenth Century (Isabella Whitney and the
Female Legacy); Victorian Science and Literature (Sex and the Science of
Political Economy in the Edinburgh Review); Afro-Hispanic Literature and
Contemporary Critical Theories (Feminist Criticism and Black (Fe)Male
Hispanic Texts); The Discipline of History and Its Discontents in Narratives
of Late Eighteenth- and Early Nineteenth-Century England (The Discipline
of History: Genre Theory and Female Paranoia in Northanger Abbey); The
Fiction of Dorothy L. Sayers: A Symposium on the Centenary of Lord Peter
Wimsey (Lord Peter Wimsey: A Member of the Neighboring Sex); Jean
Genet’s Un captif amoureux (Writing Gender in Resistance: Jean Genet and
Leia Khalid); Cultural Criticism on Henry James (Degeneration and
Feminism: Cultural Determinations Shaping Character in Henry James’s
The Bostonians); John Milton: Construction of the Self and Problems of
Agency (When God Proposes: Agency, Marriage, and Gender in
Tetrachordon; Eve in Eden and Other Beauty Spots); Voices of Silence
(Behind the Arras: Editing Renaissance Letters; Editing the Letters of Lady
Anne Southwell; Problems in Editing Margaret Cavendish); Feminine
Voices in Hispanic Literatures; New Approaches to Literature and
Socialization in Eighteenth-Century Germany (Die fehlende Mutter:
Sozialpsychologische Überlegungen zur Ödipus-Problematik in der
Literatur des 18. Jahrhunderts; Unterdrückung oder vernachlässige
Aufsicht? Väter und Töchter bei Lessing und im Sturm und Drang; The
Mystery of Mignon: Object Relations, Abandonment, Abuse, and Narrative
Structure); Historical Determinations in Renaissance Texts (Gender, Power,
and the Female Reader: Boccaccio’s Decameron and Marguerite de
Navarre’s Heptameron); Wang Wen-hsing: Postmodernism and the
Contemporary Chinese Text (Working on Chia-pien (Family Matters):
Presenting Some Problems and Solutions); Anne More Donne: Reading Her
Present Absences in the Verse of John Donne (Woman as Mortal
Sacrament: Ambivalent Mourning in the Sonnet on Anne’s Death);
Autobiographical Writing: The Question of the Canon (Autobiography as
Suicide: Women and the Forms of Confession); Heroism at Home:
Women’s Struggles in Domestic Life in Early Twentieth-Century American
Fiction (Charlotte Perkins Gilman’s Paradoxical Domesticity;
Reconstructing a Home: The Emergence of an African American Female
Identity; Dorothy Canfield’s Domestic Novels); Margaret Atwood in
International Contexts (The Moral Geography of The Handmaid’s Tale –
and Uncle Tom’s Cabin and Nineteen Eighty-Four); Mark Twain’s Female
Coterie: New Perspectives in Twain Biography (“I Am Woman’s Rights:
Olivia Langdon Clemens and Her Feminist Circle); Women’s Responses to
Shakespeare Today: Gender, Race, and Colonialism (Miranda’s Canadian
Metamorphoses: A Study in Postcolonial Resistance; Contemporary Indian
Uses of Shakespeare: Issues of Gender and Race); Reading Valle-Inclán: In
a Feminine Mode? (Mari Gaila: Un personaje androgino de Valle-Inclán;
Translating Valle-Inclán’s Salida in an English (Sub)Version of La lampara
maravillosa); Shaping Female Subjectivity in Hispanic Narrative (Woman
as Subject: Violation and Volition in Cervantes and Zayas; Bearing
Motherhood: Issues of Maternity and Degradation in the Novels of Emilia
Pardo Bazán; The Shape of Things to Come: The Female Nude and
Narrative Voice in Vargas Llosa’s Elogio de la madrastra; “La nena
terrible”: Directions of Desire in the Stories of Sivina Ocampo); Women’s
Studies, Cultural Studies Workshop I (Crisscrossing: A Theory of Black
Feminist Dialogics; Rehistoricizing the 1920s: Gender, Race, and
Modernism; Epistemological Intersections for Women’s Studies and
Cultural Studies); Comparative Approaches to Ethnic Literature
(Representing Women: Critical Approaches to Ethnic Literature; Feminist
Concepts of “Eros and Power” among Asian American Writers); The
Embodied Voice: Feminine Figures of Song (Music and Maternal Voice in
Purgatorio 19; Ophelia Sings the Blues; The Poet’s Song and the
Prostitute’s Cry; Her Mother’s Voice: Madonna’s “Like a Prayer”); The
1590 Faerie Queene: Four Hundredth Anniversary of the First Publication
(Spenser’s Women’s Book); The Uses of Popular Culture in the Study of
Literature (Inscribing the Female in the American Dream: Updike’s S and
Popular Culture); Crises on the Left: Dominance, Competition, and
Uncertainty in Contemporary Italy (Sputiamo se Hegel: Feminism,
Autonomy, Dialectics); Representations of Women in the Eighteenth
Century (La mujer prudente en Ramón de la Cruz; An Enlightenment
Premiere: Feminism and Innovation in the Theater of María Rosa Gálvez);
Eve, Ham, and Their Colonial Contexts: Race and Gender in the
Seventeenth Century (“What Strange New Courses”: Aphra Behn’s
Abdelezar and the Reconstruction of Difference); The Turn of the Century
in the Twentieth Century III: Enculturation and Canon in Modern Literature
(Pornography and the Professional Author: The Sexuality of Modernism);
American Literature and Social Resistance (The Goods of Historical
Change: The Place of Black Feminist Criticism “In Theory”); Disruptive
Discourse of Southern Women Writers (“A Good Mother Is Hard to Find”:
Flannery O’Connor’s Rhetoric of Violence and Suffering; The Politics of
Finding a Voice in Walker’s The Color Purple); H Is for Hero(ine): The
New Woman Detectives (Sisters in the City: V.I. and Lotty in Paretsky’s
Chicago; More than Murder: Moral Agency in Lesbian Detective Fiction;
Probing the Territory: P.D. James and Liza Cody as Social Critics; Murders
Academic: The Professor as Detective and Detected); Psychoanalytical
Approaches to Jane Austen (Sexual Identity in Mansfield Park: A Freudian
Approach; Maternal Empathy in Pride and Prejudice: From the Perspective
of Object-Relations Theory; Kohut, Emma, and Humiliation); Women in
Ethnic Writing (Authorizing Female Voice and Experience: Ghosts and
Spirits in Kingston’s The Woman Warrior and Allende’s The House of the
Spirits; Marxism, Feminism, Ethnicity: Questions of Definition and
Difference in Kingston’s Tripmaster Monkey and Amy Tan’s Joy Luck
Club; Confirming the Place of the Other: Ethnicity and Gender in Paula
Gunn Allen’s The Woman Who Owned the Shadows and Paule Marshall’s
Brown Girl, Brown Stones; The Unbearable Looking Glass: An Approach
to Reading Contemporary Black American Women Writers); Aesthetics and
Politics: South Africa (Sex and Politics: Challenge to Racism in Nadine
Gordimer’s Occasion for Loving and A Sport of Nature); Rebellion,
Reform, Rereading: Female Authority in Early Modern England
(Constructions of the Woman Reader in Mary Wroth’s The Countess of
Mount-gomerie’s Urania; Gender and the Subject of Sovereignty: Elizabeth
Cary’s Edward II; Margaret Cavendish and the Science of Reform);
Witchcraft and Sexology (The Second Sarah and Further Wonders of the
Invisible World; The Misgovernment of Woman’s Tongue: Gender,
Language, and Authority in the Worlds of Ann Hibbens and Anne
Hutchinson; Revolutionary Virtue and the Federal Family: Or, Good Sex
Makes Good Politics); Materializing Culture I: Commodifications,
Conversation, Combat (Between Public Culture and Private Lives:
Women’s Reading Groups and the Making of the Middle Classes; The
Militarization of Feminism); Early Women Writers in English: Integrating
the Curriculum; Gender and Power in Yeats (Kathleen’s Cracked Looking
Glass: Yeats, Gender, and National Identity; Among the Dragon Rings:
Concentric Structure in “A Woman Young and Old”; Looking for Georgie;
Crazy Jane and the Irish Episcopate: The Politics of Sexuality in the Late
Yeats); Teaching with and against the Norton (Pope and Feminist
Pedagogy); Toward a Theory of the Mystic’s Autobiography (A Genre of
Their Own: The Autohagiographies of Medieval Women Mystics;
Autobiography as Cultural Text: The Book of Margery Kempe); Catalan
Language and Literature (Gender in Exile: Forms of Allegory in Mercé
Rodoreda’s “The Salamander”); Gender, Politics, and Literature (Freud,
Race, and Gender; The Violence of Gender; Sexual Politics: Twenty Years
Later); Screening of Hamlet Comes to Mizoram, arranged in conjunction
with the special session Women’s Responses to Shakespeare Today:
Gender, Race, and Colonialism; New Directions in French Studies: The
Impact of Feminism (The Power of the Repressed Feminine: Nathalie
Sarraute and Autobiography; Women Writers and History; The New French
Feminism: Ten Years Later); Medieval Literature (Lamprecht and the
Perfect Woman); Popular Culture and the Arts (“Wild Beasts” and
“Excellent Friends”: Romance, Class, and the Popular Female Warrior);
Joyce Cary’s Women (A Feminist Looks at Joyce Cary; The Eclipse of
Romance in The Moonlight; A Woman’s World, A Fearful Joy, and the
Human Condition; Art and Reality: The Women in Cary’s Life);
Melancholia and the Question of Feminine Subjectivity (Kristeva’s Mother
and the Gender of Depression; The Tears of Narcissus: Modern Theory,
Early Modern Texts; Melancholia and Jouissance: Reopening the Case of
the Missing Penis); Spenser, Milton, and Pornography (Gross Feeders and
Flowing Cups: Is Naked Ministering Pornographic in Book 5 of Paradise
Lost?; Discourse and Intercourse: The Ludlow Mask as Intellectual
Pornography; Areopagitica, Censorship, and Pornography; At What Cost
Heroism? The Female Body in Book 2 of The Faerie Queene); Women in
the Theater of Judgment: Gender and the Law in Shakespeare and Webster
(“It Shall Teach All Ladies the Right Path to Rectifie Their Issue”: Bas-
tardy Law in Webster’s The Devil’s Law-Case; Right Recourse: Female
Inheritance and Shakespeare’s Henry V; The Authorizing (M)Other:
Witchcraft, Gender, and Inheritance in Shakespeare’s First Tetralogy);
Barrio, Ghetto, Chinatown, and Urban Rez (Barrios and Cities in Chicana
Writing and Selected Readings); Learning and Teaching a Foreign
Language: Contributions from Left Field (Desire and Language: Selon
Lacan and Kristeva); The Rhetoric of Ethnic Criticism: Ducking the Issues
of Controversial Texts (Unrecognized Feminist Subversion in Hurston’s
Seraph on the Suwanee); Contemporary Austrian Women Writers (Wiener
Frauenverlag: Stimmen aus der Tiefe; Women Writers and the Austrian
Past; Das Erbe der Töchter: Vergangenheitsbewaltigung und
Selbsterfahrung in Elisabeth Reicharts Prosa); In Celebration I: Twenty
Years of the Women’s Caucus; Problems in Cultural Studies I: Nonelite
Women (Poet and Politica? The Role of the Poet in a Pluralist Society;
Chicanas Writing across Borders; From Literacy of Differentiation to
Feminist Literacy); The Three Asian Nobel Prize Winners: Tagore,
Kawabata, and Mahfuz (Gender Construction in the Fiction of Naguib
Mahfuz); Relations between Old English Poetry and Prose (Anxieties of
Female Governance: Reading Social Formations in Prose and Poetry);
Historicizing the New Censorship (Sexwork, Power, and the Law); Laura
Riding at Ninety: Most Modernist or Postmodernist (The Plotting of the
Truth: Women, Language, and Laura Riding’s Renunciation of Poetry);
Subject and Subjection in Renaissance Rhetoric (Sexual-Textual Politics in
Puttenham’s Arte of English Poesie); The Flesh Made Word: Figuring
Women’s Bodies in Victorian Fiction (Interiority in Fictions of the Fall;
Moralizing Hunger; Majestic Bodies: Figuring the Mythic in Oliphant’s
Fiction); La Sonrisa Vertical and Approaches to Literary Erotica by Spanish
Women (Whose Masochism, Whose Submission? Critical Nurturing and
the Disappearing Subject in Almudena Grande’s Las edades de Lulú;
Detecting the Erotic in Mercedes Abad’s Ligeros libertinajes sabaticos);
Women’s Studies, Cultural Studies Workshop II (Postmodernity, Feminism,
Theory, Cultural Critique; The Edges That Blur: Women’s Studies, Cultural
Studies, and the Politics of Analogy; Who’s Calling Whom Subaltern? us
Academics and Third World Women: Is Ethical Research Possible?);
Winnicott in Literary Studies (J.D. Salinger and the Myth of Maternal
Return); Women and the Divine (Whose Eyes Are Watching God? The
Theology of Zora Neale Hurston; Women’s Prophecy, Women’s Prayer:
Barrett Browning, Dickinson, Rossetti, and God; The Road to Rome:
Muriel Spark and the “Nevertheless Principle”); Postcolonial Subjectivity II
(Female Subjectivity and Bodily Consciousness: A Reading of Rawiri’s
G’Amérakano-Au carrefour and Fureurs et cris de femmes; Representations
of the Self in A. Djebar’s L’amour, la fantasia); The Slavic Challenge to
Poststructuralist Theory (Sexual Revolutions: Blok and Yeats); Eroticism,
Asceticism in Golden Age Poetry (The Magdalenic Figure in
Representative Poetic Texts); Sexual Encounters and Dramatic Theory
(Getting Desire: Sexuality, Representation, and Williams’s Streetcar;
Lesbian Sexual Encounters; Abject Relations: (En)Gendering Pain in The
Conduct of Life); Attitudes toward Change in Contemporary English
(Women, Men, and Speaking Strategies); Tactical Shakespeare: Resistance
and The Economy of the Early Modern Subject (The English History Play
and the Problem of Female Resistance; Erotic Resistances in Shakespearean
Drama: Boundaries, Apertures, Matrices; Early Modern Characters and
Postmodern Subjects: Counterhegemonic Discourse in The Comedy of
Errors and The Winter’s Tale); Africa in the Romantic Imagination:
Rethinking Exoticism (Wordsworth’s “White-Robed Negro”: Race and
Gender in 1802; “Black” Rage and White Women: Charlotte Brontë’s
African Juvenilia); Why Cultural Studies? Reexaminations, Theoretical
Questions, Alternative Models (Feminist Literary Criticism and Cultural
Studies); A Sense of Distinction: Taste in Seventeenth-Century France
(Gender and the Politics of Taste); Italian Women Writers: The Revision of
the Canon (Double Marginality: Matilde Serao and the Betrayal of the
Canon; Narrative Voice and the Female Experience: Redefining Images in
the Regional Worlds of Grazia Deledda and Maria Messina; “L’invasione
smisurata”: The Themes of Neurological Disease and Madness in Elsa
Morante’s Novels; “Caring Voices” in Clara Sereni’s Narrative: A World of
“Differences”); In Celebration II: Twenty Years of Feminist Publishing –
The Book(s) That Changed My Life; Louise Erdrich’s Fiction: Marginality,
Centrality, Madness, and Mothers (Marginality in Love Medicine; Fleur,
“The Funnel of Our History”: The Centrality of Women in Louise Erdrich’s
Chippewa Landscape; Madness and Myth: Constituting the Constitutive
Subject, the Representation of Native American Experience and Women as
Other; Adoptive Mothers and Throwaway Children in the Novels of Louise
Erdrich); Teaching Literature and Other Arts: Reflections on Recent
Theoretical Issues (Gender Issues in Teaching Literature and Other Arts);
Art, Power, and Politics in the Modern South (The Spunky Little Woman:
You Can’t Be One in the South If You’re White); Reiseliteratur und
utopische Perspektiven (Sisters and Pilgrims: Women as Religious
Travelers and Exiles, 1600–1750); Women’s Studies, Cultural Studies (An
Account of the Struggle at Rutgers; Crossing (Out) the Disciplines;
Women’s Studies, Gay Studies, Transitional Cultural Studies; Women’s
Studies, Cultural Studies: Some Problems); The Family as Fictional
Construct in Children’s Literature (The Politics of Representation: The
Family as Ideological Construct in the Fiction of Arthur Ransome;
Changing Faces: Pictures of Women in Fairy Tales; Performing Family);
Renaissance Heroic Fictions: Text and Theory (Pillars of Virtue, Yokes of
Oppression: The Ambivalent Foundation and Function of Philogynist
Discourse in Ariosto’s Orlando furioso); Exoticism and Colonialism (Vis-à-
vis the Other: German Women Writers Describe the Orient); Materializing
Culture III: Poetry, Politics, History (Women/Woman: Modern Poetry,
Gender, Ideologies, and Feminist Cultural Studies); Avant-Gardes: Past and
Present, Theory and/versus Practice (Women, the Avant-Garde, and
Contemporary Writing Practice); Dorothy Richardson, Dissenting Feminist
(The Foreword to Pilgrimage as a Feminist Manifesto; Dorothy
Richardson’s Theory of Gender Difference; The Woman behind
Pilgrimage); Emily Dickinson, 1890–1990: Rereading Her “Letter” after
One Hundred Years (Containing the Phallus: Overturning the “Worm” in
Poem 1,670 and Beyond; “Who Goes to Dine Must Take His Feast”:
Toward a Feminist Code of Language Exchange); Language in
Contemporary Art (The Image, the Word, and the Unmarked Woman);
Property, Propriety, and Virtue in British Literature, 1770–1820 (Bankrupt
Heroines: The Economics of Self-Effacement in Frances Burney’s Evelina
and Camilla; Sermons and Strictures: Conduct-Book Propriety and Middle-
Class Women; Mansfield Park, Hannah More, and the Evangelical
Redefinition of Virtue); Scott and His Contemporaries: Formations of
Cultural Identity (Folk Voices and Female Enthusiasts: Scott, Hogg, and the
Culture of Calvinism); The Gay Nineties I: Bodies as Texts (Unmediated
Lust: The Impossibility of Lesbian Desire); Graduate Students: Beginning
Professionals, Beginning Pedagogy (Writing and the Politics of Difference;
Undergraduate Resistance to Feminist Concerns); Sexualities and Textual
Markers (Play)Wrights of Passage: Women and Games-Playing on the
Stage; Sight and Sexuality in La última niebla); Female Autobiography:
Tradition and Innovation (Writing “Femystic” Space: In the Margins of the
Castillo interior; Toward a Poetics of Martyrdom: Luisa de Carvajal y
Mendoza’s Escritos autogiográficos; Elementos autobiográficos en una
comedia desconocida de Sor Juana, La Segunda Celestina); Sexual
Encounters and the Dramatic Text (A Transcendental Infidelity: Kleist,
Lacan, and Amphitryon; Sex, Class, and Stage Space in Miss Julie); Chaos
Theory and Cultural Analysis (Gender, Chaos, and Science: Subtexts in
Complex Dynamics); Continuing the Quest: The Poetry and Prose of James
Wright (Women and James Wright); English Romantic Women Writers
(Mary Robinson and the Poetic Marketplace of the 1790s; Felicia Hemans
and the Effacement of Women; What We Say, Not What We Do:
Frankenstein and the Woman Writer’s Predicament); Habeas Corpus
Feminae: Theories of Women’s Representation in Literature and Law
(“Home-Rebels and House-Traitors”: Gender, Class, and Petty Treason in
Early Modern England; Criminalized Bodies, Sexualized Crimes: Legal and
Literary Representations of Women in Twentieth-Century America; Typist,
Housewife, Mother, Spy: The Role(s) of Ethel Rosenberg in Legal
Documents and Postmodern Literature); Staging Alternative Shakespeares:
Histories and Hypotheses (Straw Lances – Performance as Weapon: Or,
Untaming the Shrew; “She’s Good, Being Gone”: Or, Everything I’ve Got
Belongs to You; The Wayward Sisters Go on Tour); Women Writers on
World War II: Shifting Frontiers in Global War (“Too Naked and
Uncivilized”: Women and Jews in World War II Fiction by British Women;
Scrambling the Language of Authority: Revolutionary Humor on the
Homefronts; Underground Lives: Women’s Personal Narratives; Violence
in Female Bildung: Hisako Matsubara and Ella Leffland); Contemporary
Spanish Theater, 1985–90 (New Works by Women Playwrights); Women’s
Studies, Cultural Studies Workshop III (Always Take Measurements, Miss
Kingsley, and Always Take Them from the Adult Male; Plantocratic
Paradigms and Otherness: Jane Austen and Mary Wollstonecraft; Kalpana
Dutt and the Discourse of Indian Nationalist “Terrorists”; Translating
Gender); From Novel to Film: The Problematics of Transforming
Multicultural Texts (Traducing Race, Gender, and Class Identity: The
Hollywoodization of The Color Purple); The James-Hawthorne
Relationship (James’s Portrait of Female Skepticism); Kafka’s Rhetoric I
(The Erotic Couple in “The Castle”: Women as Connectors); Spectacular
Bodies (The Spectacle of Sensibility: Bodily Diagnostics in Diderot’s La
religieuse); Problems in Cultural Studies II: American Minorities (“When
Boys Collide”: Gender Negotiations in African American Cultural Studies);
The Uses of Popular Culture in Gender and Ethnic Studies (Gender
Differences in Reading Popular Narratives; Victorian Underwear and
Representations of the Female Body); New Directions in French Studies:
Literature and Film (Eric Rohmer: Gender, Culture, Camsea); Body
(Politics): Theory and Representation (The (Body) Politics of Feminist
Theory; Metonymy and Androgyny: The Figure of Woman in Renaissance
Rhetoric); Beowulf (The Body of the Mother in Beowulf); Edith Wharton:
Issues of Class, Race, and Ethnicity (In Nettie’s Kitchen: Edith Wharton
and Working-Class Women; Class and Gender in The Custom of the
Country; Anti-Semitism, Misogyny, and the Anxiety of Authorship); In
Celebration III: Navigating into the Feminist Future(s) (Institutional
Constraints to a Radical Vision; … or Hang Separately?; The Black Studies
Movement and the Ladies; Roads to and from Eressos); In Celebration IV:
Twenty Years Together – The Commission on the Status of Women, the
Women’s Caucus, the Gay and Lesbian Caucus, and the Division on
Women’s Studies in Language and Literature; Feminist Theories and Old
French Studies: Problematic Intersection (Reading the Female Body:
Essentialism and Historical Differences; Scopophilia and Linguaphilia:
Film Theory, Psychoanalytic Theory, and Erec et Enide; Medieval Studies
and the Ideology of Gender: The Women Trouvères); Composition,
Context, and Gender (The Feminization of Composition; Composition
Theory and the Myth of the Self-Made Man: Authentic Voice and the
Rhetoric of Masculinity; Academic Preparation, Academic Discourse, and
the Doctrine of Separate Spheres); On Teaching Swift (Swift among the
Feminists: An Approach to Teaching); Gender and Generation in Frances
Burney’s Novels (“Oh Dear Resemblance of Thy Murdered Mother”:
Female Authorship in Evelina; Family Circles, Female Circles in The
Wanderer); Chaucer and Rape (Chaucer and the Discourse of Misogyny;
Rape as Literary Transgression; Chaucer, Chaucerians, Rape, and
Indifference); Radical Heterogeneities: Theory, Gender, and Language (For
a Postmodern Solution to the Impasses of Feminist Theory; Feminism, Gay
Theory, and Male Subjectivity; “Normative” Feminism and Experimental
Writing by Women); Testing the Limits of Liberty: Nonfiction Writings of
Early American Women (The Captivity Narrative as Female Text; From
Anxiety to Authority: Bathsheba Bowers’s An Alarm Sounded (1709);
Signing the Republican Daughter: The Letters of Eliza Southgate, 1783–
1809; “Ambitious to Be Free”: Self-Empowerment in Silvia Dubois’s
Biography of the Slav Who Whipt Her Mistres and Gand Her Fredom);
Vietnam and the Postmodern Moment (“Rambo’s a Pussy”: Seduction,
Rape, and Subjectivity in Vietnam Films); American Indian Literatures: Old
Traditions and New Forms (Modern and Traditional Women’s Issues in the
Poetry of Luci Tapahonso); Tennyson and Women (Suppressing Suicide:
Tennyson’s Elaine – Text/Image; Emily Tennyson’s Deathbed: Another
View of Tennyson and Women; Gender and Sexual Relationships in the
Great Beyond); Virginia Woolf and Humor (Patriarchy through the Looking
Glass: Or, Woolf’s Reflections on the Lords of Misrule; The Sense of
Humor in Jacob’s Room; Carnivalesque Comedy in Between the Acts;
Potsherds from a Woolfen Archaeology: Potshots at the Patriarchs);
Surrealism and the Other (The Lesbian Other: Surrealism as Disguise); The
Return of the Suppressed: Other Voices in the Hebrew Bible (Adultery in
the House of David; Poetic Silence: En-gendered Suffering in the Book of
Job; Zipporah and the Struggle for Deliverance; Out of My Sight: The
Buried Woman in Biblical Narrative); Portuguese Literature: Poetry and
Drama (Sabina Freire: First “Modern” Female Character in Portuguese
Drama? What Does Woman Want? Cantigas de Amigo as Strategies of
Containment); Feminism, History, and Cultural Studies (“Savage” Mothers:
Feminism, Race, and the Enlightenment; Literature, History, and the
Organization of Knowledge); Feminist Theory and Linguistic Theory in the
1990s (Escaping the Prison-House of Silence: Women, Power, and
Cognitive Linguistics; When Hetero- Becomes Homoglossia: Language and
Gender in the Short Fiction of Margaret Atwood; When “He” Means “She”:
Verbal Cross-Dressing in Women-Identified Writers); Encyclopedias as a
Literary Genre (The “Poetry” and Feminist Ethics of Anna Jameson’s
Sacred and Legendary Art); Investing (in) the Body: Postmodernity,
Practice, and Social Theory (Circulating Femininity on the Free Market:
Helen Gurley Brown’s Sex and the Single Girl); Reading Diseases: Literary
Texts and Medical Contexts (Female Masochism, Feminist Aesthetics:
Elfriede Jelinek’s “Lust”; Classical Heroines in Modern Eastern European
Texts: The Western Reader Responds (Bitov’s “Penelope”: Women’s Space
in the Male-Centered Narrative; The Archetypal Alien: Göncz’s Hungarian
Medea; Wolf’s Cassandra: Myth as Medium against the “Male Reality
Principle”); 1980s Chicano Literature: A Cornucopia of Prizes (Women and
Men: Villanueva’s Ultraviolet Sky; The Female Voice in Rios); Social
Theory and Social Fiction II: The Inscription of Gender (Utopian Socialism
and the Feminine Origins of the Social Novel; Flora Tristan’s Ways of
Knowing; Reading Women: The Novel’s Place in Hysteria’s Text); Women
in Russian Literature (The Feminine Subject in Russian Poetry:
Lisnianskaya and Petrovykh; Whimsey and the Daughters of Echo: Marko
Vovchok and Political Writing); Gender and Politics in Recent Film and
Television (Gender and Genre: The Politics of Representation); Reinventing
Gender (A Diva’s Confessions: Homosexuality and the Art of Personality;
Ghostly Instructors: Women’s Visions of Yeats, Yeats’s Visions of Women;
Otto Weininger and the Modernist Woman); Feminism and Postcolonial
English Literatures (Caught in the Act: Sexuality, Liberation, and
Entrapment in the Fiction of Nadine Gordimer; Politics, Gender, and
Growing into Womanhood: Jamaica Kincaid, Zee Edgel, and Michelle
Cliff; Thresholds of Difference: Feminism, Decolonization, and Native
Women’s Writing in Canada; Literacy and Orature: A Tension in Black
South African Women’s Writing); Race, Gender, and Fictional Form in
American Literature, 1880–1925 (Rape, Racial Violence, and Black Female
Heroism in Pauline E. Hopkins’s Contending Forces); Literature and
Politics in the Era of the English Revolution (Class, Gender, and Literacy:
Some English Printers and Readers of the 1650s); Patterns of Male and
Female Discourse in Early Iberian Literature (Patterns of Male and Female
Discourse in the Traditional Romancero; “Amigo fals e desleal”: Discursive
Strategies in the Cantigas de Amigo; Mediadoras del deseo en el Corbacho:
El discurso feminino segun el predicador; The Language of Love in
Montemayor’s Diana); Women Writing Letters across the Genres in
Sixteenth- and Early Seventeenth-Century France (From Writing to Its
Absence: Epistolary Silence and the Closure of Happiness in L’astrée;
Duplicité narrative chez Hélisenne de Crenne: Des Angoysses douloureuses
aux Epistres familieres et inventives; Le roman familial comme alibi à la
production de l’écriture chez Marie de l’Incarnation; Functions of Tragic
and Comic Love Letters in Marguerite de Navarre and Several Seventeenth-
Century Comedies); Women of Color (Letting Go of the Thread: The
Lesson of Gloria Naylor’s The Women of Brewster Place; The Black
Woman as Urban Exotic: Exportation and Exploitation of Afro-American
Beauty; City as Circe: The Locus of Endless Desiring in Gwen Brooks’s
and Toni Morrison’s Works); Colonial Baroque Culture: The Arising
Consciousness of Spanish American Identity (Feminine Portraiture and the
Baroque: The Challenge of Sor Juana); Conceptos medievales en la
empresa de Indias (Silent Women in the Chronicles of New Spain);
Noncanonical Pedagogies: Gender and Class; Gender, Reading, and Writing
in Late Medieval England (Female Literacy and Early Middle English
Religious Writing; “Bokes to Hem Assigned”: The Gendering of Literacy in
Late Medieval England; “Book-Mad” Women and Margery Kempe);
Exploring Race (The Women in the Works, Life, and Career of Phillis
Wheatley); Issues in Gender, Race, Ethnicity, and Class in the Two-Year
College (Transforming the Curriculum to Include the Scholarship on
Women: A Multicollege Plan; Integrating Women into Humanities Courses;
Teaching Issues of Class, Race, and Gender in an Introductory English
Course: Triumphs and Pitfalls); American Dramatic Realism (Feminism
and Dramatic Realism: Possibilities and Limitations); Feminism, Theory,
and Cultural Criticism: Transforming the Scholarly Journal (The Advent of
Theory and the Transformation of Journal Editing; The Politics of History:
Publishing Dialogically; The Politics of Independent Journal Publication;
Radical Paradoxes: Networking and the Fate of Scholarly Publishing); Iris
Murdoch’s Fiction: The New Directions (The Changes in Murdoch’s
Women); Hedda at One Hundred: Hedda Gabler, 1890–1990 (Hedda
Gabler, Sex, and Class in Early Modern Drama); Women’s Studies,
Cultural Studies Workshop IV (Christina Serad and the Politics of Cultural
Critique; Alice Walker: Writing beyond the Blues; Can the Subaltern Speak
in English? Studying Middle Eastern Women); The Tropicalization of North
American Discourse (In the Heat of the Night: The Tropicalization of
Language and Women in Palm Latitudes); Reading the Bible: Cultural
Perspectives in Seventeenth-Century England and America (“Fair
Idolatresses”: Idolatry and Gender in Milton’s Republican Discourse); The
Dark Side of Enlightenment (Unenlightened Bodies: Rationality and
Gender in Philosophical Medicine); German Baroque Literature (“Dirnen-
Barock”: Das misogyne Frauenbild im Barock-roman und seine sozialen
Grundlagen in der gesellschaftlichen Wirklichkeit); Chicana and Chicano
Literature in the 1990s: A Forum of Position Papers (The Woman Question
and Noncanonical Texts; New Directions in Chicana Writing); Advances in
Slavic Philology (Women’s Studies and Slavic Philology); Cultural Studies
and Hispanism (Gender and Ideology in Caribbean Narrative); Gender,
Writing, and Violence in the Recent Texts of the French New Novelists
(Sadism and the Nouveau Roman; Figuring Violence: Postmodern
Meanings of Robbe-Grillet’s Metalepsis; La violence et la subversion
féminine dans “Manne” d’Hélène Cixous); In Celebration V:
Troublemakers in the 1990s – Feminist Interventions in Politics and Culture
(Christa Wolf’s Cassandra and Accident: A Model for Women’s
Troublemaking in the 1990s; Feminism Here and There: Academic Politics
and Political Art, 1990; Fracturing Meanings: Making Space for a Poem);
Problems of Affirmation in Cultural Theory II (Affirmation and Agency in
Ecofeminist Dialogics); Christopher Marlowe Workshop: Marlowe’s
History – Textual, Personal, National (Dido Queen of Carthage and the
Discourses of Rulership and Romance); Dickens and the Everyday II: The
Body and the Domestic (Bleak House and the Body; Gender Difference and
the Everyday: Dickens’s and Eliot’s Responses to Mary Barton); For Whom
the Bell Tolls II: Literary Aspects (“Something in It for You”: Female
Relationships in For Whom the Bell Tolls); Indian Influence in Eighteenth-
Century English Literature (Women Good and Bad: Ethnopolitical
Dynamics and the Language of Gendering in Dryden’s Aureng-Zebe);
Joyce’s Alternative Semiologies (“He Read the Meaning of Her Movements
in Her Frank Uplifted Eyes”: Semerotics – Or, Feminine Body Language
and Masculine Desire in Portrait; “In the Beginning Was the Gest … for the
End Is with Woman”: The Language of Gesture and the Language of
Women); New Directions in Irish American Literature (Responses to
Oppression in Irish American Fiction by Women); The Texts of Southern
Food (Agrarianism, Female Style; Black Women, White Women: The
Dining Room Door Swings Both Ways; Sweeping the Kitchen: Revelation
and Revolution in Contemporary Southern Women’s Writing);
Transcendentalists and Society (Theodore Parker’s “American Church”:
Race, Gender, Class, and the Logic of Intuition; Theodore Parker and
Women); Virginia Woolf and the Tradition of the Essay (Virginia Woolf’s
Essay Form: Paradigm for a Feminist Poetics; Virginia Woolf’s “Truths” as
Sleight of Hand; A Voice of One’s Own: Implications of Impersonality in
the Essays of Virginia Woolf and Alice Walker; Between Writing and Life:
Woolf and de Beauvoir’s Uses of the Essay); Feminine Voices in
Francophone Literature; Gender, Race, and “Othering” in the Narrative Arts
(The Necessary Subversion of Ana Lydia Vega); In Search of a Liberated
Female Character (Concha Méndez: A Feminist Voice among the Vanguard;
La mujer nueva latinoamericana en Yo Vendo unos ojos negros de Alicia
Yánez Cossío; Writing the Subject: Female Protagonists in Narratives by
Diamela Eltit, Paulina Mutta, and Reina Roffé; Poetics of Hope: Gioconda
Belli’s Línea de fuego); La representación del cuerpo humano en las
novelas de Galdós (Writing of the Feminine Body in Galdós); The Gay
Nineties II: Politics, Texts, Strategies (Women’s Studies, Gay Studies,
Transnational Cultural Studies); Toward a Definition of Sand’s Feminism
(Consuelo: The Fictions of Feminism; The Limits of Sand’s Feminism:
Marriage in the Novels of Her Maturity (1857–76); Un idéal mythique de la
femme; Textual Feminism in George Sand’s Early Fiction; Women Writing
Men: Female Authors and Male Protagonists (Ich war verkleidet als Poet …
Ich bin Poetin! The Masquerade of Gender in Else Lasker-Schüler’s Prose;
Bild (zer)störung: Zu Brigitte Burmeester, Anders oder Vom Aufenthalt in
der Fremde; Karin Struck’s Indictment of the Addictive Society; Women
Writing Men: Christa Wolf’s Kein Ort Nigends – Kleist as a New Male
Identity); Women’s Spiritual Narrative (Kristeva on Jeanne Guyon; The
“Devout Soliloquies” of Elizabeth Singer Rowe; Dorothy Day’s Conversion
Narratives).

The annual conference of 20004 included thirty-three papers about men in


literature. These papers do not necessarily, once again, represent the
perspective of men. On the contrary, they usually represent the
deconstructive perspective of feminists and queer theorists. Here is the list:
Region and Transnation (Rural Spaces and Differences among White Men);
Recent Trends in Latin American Theater (The Impotence/Importance of
the Male Intellectual in Mexican Theater Written by Women); Re-forming
Southern Literature, Reforming the South (Race, Masculinity, and the
South: Lessons from Thomas Dixon and D.W. Griffith to The Klansman,
O.J. Simpson’s First Movie); Eros and Pain in the Middle Ages (Cutting
and Eros: Castration, Knighthood, and Composite Genders); Queer
Approaches to the Spanish Comedia (The Unmasculine Activities
Committee and the Golden Age Stage); Classy Writing: George Gissing and
the Complexities of the Late-Victorian English Class System (Money and
Manhood: Gissing’s Redefinition of Lower-Middle-Class Man); The
Family in Medieval Courtly Romance (Fathers and Sons in the Chevalier as
deus espees); Realists and the Romance of Street Credentials (Violating the
Ultimate Taboo: White Men’s Property, White Women, and Street
Credentials in Richard Wright’s Native Son); Violent Desires: Sexuality and
Literature in World Wars I and II (Peg Legs and Roses: Sex and the
Wounded Soldier in Henry Green’s Back); Women, Writing, Community:
The Language of Reform (Foreign Bodies: Representations of the Male
Other in George Sand’s Fiction; Language and Gender: Sex as Work/Labor
in the Discourse of Male Bonding); Sex, Pornography, Marriage (Viagra
Vice: Philip Roth’s The Human Stain and J.M. Coetzee’s Disgrace);
Resisting Gender (The Illogics of Masculine Identification in Christopher
Lee’s Transvideos); Feeling Things: Race, Sex, and the Politics of Objects
(The Faux Father’s Compass: Living History, Reenacting Objects);
Masculinity Studies and Feminist Theory: Backlash and Advances
(Masculinities and Superordinate Studies; Queer Theory and Masculine
Reempowerment; Stiffed and Punch Drunk: W(h)ither Masculinity;
Reenfleshing the Bright Boys; or, How Male Bodies Matter to Feminist
Theory); Queering the Family (Daddy’s Boys; Papadada: Reinventing the
Paternal); Comparative United States Literatures I: Turn-of-the-Century
Sexualities (The Clubfoot and the Peg Leg: The Male Body in the
Postbellum American South); Incorporations: Child-Adolescent Issues
(Re)Forming Disability (Fathers and Sons: Family Incorporations of
Disability); Feminist Ethics and Epistemologies/Éthiques et épistémologies
féministes (Make Room for Daddy? Do “Masculinities” Have a Place in
Feminist Epistemology?); Language, Literature, and Politics in the
Twentieth-Century United States (Dismantling Booker T.: Or, What
Happened to My Modernism and My Black Maleness When I Took a Job at
Duke); The Function of the Courtroom at the Present Time: Law and
Literature, 1837–1910 (A National Trial: The Expert Witness, the Common
Man, and Mid-Century Stagings of Masculinity); Ethnographic Fictions
(Dangerous Languor: Medical Ethnography and the Exotic Male in
Confessions of a Thug); Native Sons, Cultural Kings: Harry Belafonte and
Performances of Citizenship (Madmen in the Kitchen: Harry Belafonte and
Elvis Presley in the Contact Zones of the 1950s; Calypso Harry and the
Performance of Black Manhood; James Baldwin on Film: The Black Male
Matinee Idol as Artist and Activist, 1955–85); Australia and Sport:
Physicality, Image, and Text (Running Addiction and Masculinity in David
Foster’s “Eye of the Bull”); Presenting the Environment: Film, tv, and
Popular Culture (Jungle Jims: Extreme Sports, Eroticism, and Nature as
Personal Trainer for Men in Disney’s George of the Jungle and Tarzan);
New Approaches to Hawthorne (The Man behind the Veil: Hawthorne and
the Writing of Masculinity; The Homosocial Homosexual in The Blithedale
Romance); Democracy, Citizenship, and the State in American Literary
Studies (Bo-Zhoo, Brudders: The Politics of Fraternity in Nick of the
Woods); Ethnic Communities and Urban Spaces (“If the City Was a Man”:
Founders and Fathers, Cities and Sons in John Edgar Wideman’s
Philadelphia Fire).
The same conference included (once again) eighty-eight papers about
women (but also, albeit indirectly in some cases, about men) in literature.
Here is the list: Feminism against Time (Why Feminism Is Not a
Historicism (and It’s a Good Thing Too); Third World Women’s Time
against Western Time; Refusing History); The Other Britain I: Late
Victorian and Early Modernist Orientalism (Female Orientalist Fantasy:
E.M. Hull’s The Shiek and D.H. Lawrence’s The Plumed Serpent); The
Ethics of Postcolonial Writing (Violence, Love, and the Fictional
Imagination: The Ethics of Reading Incest in Arudhati Roy’s The God of
Small Things; Locational Hand-Wringing: The Ethics of Postcolonial
Feminisms); Genres, Genes, and Geography in Feminist Perspective (The
Gendering of Public Spaces in Early Modern Drama; Language, Genetics,
and Geography: The Case of “African Eve”); Epic I: Epic Sexualities (A
Tragic Fall from a Trojan Horse: Sex and the Perilous Cliché; Sex and Epic
Epiphany: Desiring the Goddess in Sidney, Spenser, and Cervantes); Sex:
Alternative Positions (Through the Courtesan’s Eyes: Liane de Pougy’s
Idylle Saphique; “Sugar Daddies” and “Chicken Hawks”: The Homosexual
as Pedophile in Nineteenth-Century French Prose Poetry); Italian and
Italian American Women Wringing (Amelia Rosselli e la poesia della
differenza: La Libellula; Stories of Sicilian Girls: Italian and Italian
American Women’s Mythological Visitations; Obsession: Francesca
Mazzucato’s Hot Line; Fulfillments of Rimbaudian Prophecies? From
European Feminists to Italian American Poete); Body and Violence (The
Victim’s Body: Reading Violent Narratives in Contemporary Brazilian
Women’s Fiction); Writing from Prison I: International Perspectives
(Gender and Representation in Two Women’s Prison Memoirs from El
Salvador); Narrative Contaminations I: Sexuality and Contamination
(Eroticizing German Fascism in France: Sartre, Doubrovsky, Genet;
Contaminating the Scene: Lesbian Litter in an Otherwise Beautiful
Landscape); Pluralizing Early American Literature: New World Experience
through a Comparatist Lens (Anxious Spirits and Deviant Bodies:
Witchcraft and Treason in the Late Seventeenth Century); Commercial
Seductions: Popular Women Writers and the Literary Market of the 1920s
(Loose Women and Frivolous Publics: The Serialization of Gentlemen
Prefer Blondes in Harper’s Bazaar; “An Unwonted Coquetry”: The
Commercial Seductions of Jessie Fauset’s The Chinaberry Tree; Zona
Gale’s Serious Popular Fiction); African Prison Literature (From the Womb
of the Prison: A Rereading of Saadawi’s Woman at Point Zero); Images of
Teachers and Teaching (The Lady Professor); Female Modernists and Film
Culture (Visualizing National Culture: Dorothy Richardson and the Politics
of Close Up; hd’s Distractions; Nancy Cunard in Black and White); The
Other Britain II: Passing in Britain, 1880–1930 (Crazy Women Drivers: The
Borderline Woman in Great War Fiction); Disrupting the Center:
Contemporary British and Irish Women Poets (Disturbances of the Other:
Conflicts between Class and Gender Power in the Poetry of Carol Ann
Duffy); Mapping Trajectories of British Slave Narratives (“Me Know No
Law, Me Know No Sin”: Who Speaks for the Morality of Slave Women?);
Marriage and Modernity (White Turkeys, White Zombies, White Weddings:
The Personal Erotics of Laboring under Modernity; Properties of Marriage;
Love and Political Commerce in the 1910s); Rethinking Resistance in
Early-Twentieth-Century Working-Class Literature (Maternity and (the)
Work: Edith Summers Kelly’s Weeds); Cervantes’s Women: Bodies That
Materialize (Speaking in Tones: Cervantes’s Translator Transila; Redressing
Dorotea; The Body in Pieces: Imagining the Female Body in Cervantes’s
Novelas ejemplares); Recent Trends in Latin American Theater (Marx,
Villa, Martín Luis Guzmán: Fantasmas y fantoches en entre villa y una
mujer desnuda de Sabina Berman; The Impotence/Importance of the Male
Intellectual in Mexican Theater Written by Women); Uwe Timm and the
Ethnographic Gaze (Dangerous Liaisons: The Sexual Politics of
Colonialism in Uwe Timm’s Morenga); Nineteenth-Century Literary
Onomastics (“Not Much of an Explanation”: Victorian Onomastics and the
(Mis)Naming of the Middle-Class Woman in Gaskell’s Wives and
Daughters); Online Discourse: Theoretical Perspectives (Cyborg Feminist
Networks and Productions); Signed Language and Literature (Gender
Linguistics in American Sign Language); The Vicissitudes of Narcissism
(School Subjects: Gender and Narcissistic Entitlement in the Classroom);
The Powers of Horror: Trauma and Testimony (Talking Heads: Orpheus
and Medusa in Contemporary Women’s Posttraumatic Poetry); Figuring the
Morisco in Golden Age Spain (Jarifa’s Choice: The Representation of
Moorish Women in Golden Age Spanish Literature); Pietism Reconsidered
(Women’s Religious Speech in Halle and Herrnhut: The Sermons of Anna
Nitschmann); Representing the Seventeenth Century in Anthologies,
Syllabi, and Curricula (Representing Gender in the Seventeenth Century);
Functions of Victorian Culture at the Present Time I: A Roundtable
(Exhibiting Victorian Women); Textualizing the Self: The Genres of Early
America (Where the Literary Meets the Didactic: Early American Women’s
Travel Narratives); Women’s Reading Practices in England, 1580–1700
(Reading and Gender in Early Modern England; How Can We Know What
Women Read in Early Modern England?; Women Reading Shakespeare in
Early Modern England); Gender and Genre: The Picaresque in
Contemporary Women’s Narrative (The Ironies of Discourse in the
Feminine Picaresque; The Pícara and the Flâneur: Modes of Transformation
in Angela Carter’s Nights at the Circus; The Pícara in Brief(s): Underwear
as Narrative Manipulation in Two Contemporary Picaresque Novels by
Women); Whose Standards? II (Who’s the Reader? Who’s the Writer?
Electronic Versions of Early Women’s Texts); Shifting the Image, Shifting
the Story: Traditions, Allusions, and Intertexts in Margaret Atwood’s Works
(Feminist Inter-textuality: Atwood Uses Bluebeard’s Key); Eros and Pain in
the Middle Ages (Sadism and Submission in Fin Amors: Perverse
Punishments for Unwilling Women; Sweet Suffering Transformed: Eros
and Pain in the Works of Christine de Pisan; Cutting and Eros: Castration,
Knighthood, and Composite Genders); Pirandello’s World: A Psychological
Perspective I (As He Desired Her: A Girardian Reading of Pirandello’s
Obsession with Martas Abba); Epic II: Epic Historiographies (Meddling
Women and Biblical Histories in Renaissance Florence); Feminism in Time
(Feminism out of Time; Found Footage: Feminist Histories Lost in Time;
Nationalist Time and the Politics of Everyday Space); Historicizing Queer
Subcultures (“What’s That Smell?” Queer Dyke Subcultures Now and
Then); Theorizing Multiculturalism and Children’s Literature (Wetbacks,
Funny Boys, and Herb Women: Multicultural Gender in Children’s
Literature); Red, White, and “Blue”? Contemporary American
Independents (“Bitches’ll Fuck Your Shit Up”: Indie Films, Hip-Hop, and
Women); Fictions of Peace: The “Great War” of Jane Addams, Zona Gale,
and Dorothy Canfield Fisher (Playing with the Big Boys: Jane Addams and
William James; “Knowing Nothing of Nations”: The Feminist Pacifism of
Zona Gale and the Women’s Peace Party); “Hispanic” Women, Politics, and
Social Justice: Historical and Cultural Perspectives (Gestiones para el
nuevo milenio: Movimientos femininos, organizaciones feministas, y la
política en Argentina; Re-presentaciones de la represión: Pedagogía y lucha
armada; “Una historia para comprender lo que nos pasó”: Biografía, justicia
política-social, y la mujer en Hispano-américa; Mujeres de abril:
Representaciones de mujeres combatientes en la República Dominica);
Formal Session of the South Asian Literary Association (At a Loss for
Words: Reading the Silence in Women Writers’ Partition Narratives;
Abducted Bodies, Partitioned Souls: Women’s Lives in Amrita Pritam,
Urvashi Butalia, and Veena Das; The Gendered Rape of the National Body
and the Partition Fiction of Attia Hosain, Suraiya Qasim, and Bapsi
Sidhwa); The Family in Medieval Courtly Romance (Family Relationship
in Chrétien’s Romances; Mother-Child Relationships in the Roman
d’Enéas); African Cinema (Woubi Cheri: Negotiating Subjectivity, Gender,
and Power); Women, Labor, and Radical Literature in East Asia (Chinese
Empress as Exemplar: The Dramatic Portrayal of Wu Zetian and the
Cultural Revolutionary Struggle for Women’s and Laborer’s Rights; To
Write or Not to Write: Narrative Permutation and Political Allegiance in
Ding Ling’s Miss Sophia’s Diary and Sophia’s Diary, II; Diverging
Discourses in Two Korean Comfort Women Plays); National Identity in the
Italian Ottocento (The Rhetoric of the “Virtuous Woman” during the
Risorgimento and Postunitary Era); After Oxford: Reassessing the
Somerville Novelists (The Costs of Culture: Dorothy Sayers, Margaret
Kennedy, and the Gender of Snobbery; Writing the Feminist Home Front:
Great War Fictions of Vera Brittain and Winifred Holtby; An Intellectual
Tradition: The Influence of the Somerville Novelists on Contemporary
British Women Writers); Brain Work: Representations of Postindustrial
Labor in American Literature (The Gendering of Postindustrial Labor from
Riesman to Coupland); Psychoanalysis and the Victorians: Critical Legacies
and Their Discontents (Fantasies of Female Symbolic Reproduction in
Bleak House); Realists and the Romance of Street Credentials (Violating
the Ultimate Taboo: White Men’s Property, White Women, and Street
Credentials in Richard Wright’s Native Son); There and Back Again:
Gender, Discourse, and Transatlantic Circulations to 1750 (Anne Bradstreet
and the Circulation of Poetic Authority; Specimen Muse; An Amerindian
Princess in Paris: Imagining Paraguaçu in Colonial Brazil); Violent Desires:
Sexuality and Literature in World Wars I and II (Captive Sexuality:
Women’s Holocaust Narratives; Peg Legs and Roses: Sex and the Wounded
Soldier in Henry Green’s Back; Depraved and Corrupted: Sexuality and
Censorship after the Great War); Mothers’ Memoirs (Mothers of Suicides;
Did Your Mama Take Them Dreadful Drugs? Responding to Blame through
the Memoir of “Disabled” Motherhood; “A Mother’s Love”: The Burden of
Devotion in Recent Memoirs of Mental Disability); Social and Moral
Responsibility (“Knowledge for What?” Academic Feminism and
Distributive Justice; The Ethical Responsibilities of Feminist Educators in a
Globalizing Economy; What’s Wrong with Building the Discourse of
Solidarity in Academia? Reflections on Teaching and Testimonio);
“Nothing Else Is”: John Donne in the History of Sexuality (“Uritur et
Loquitur”: Donne, Catullus, and “Desire of More”; “Nothing Else Is” – and
That’s the Problem: Donne, Cixous, and the History of Failure; Glimpsing
Nothing: Reading between the Lines in the Book of the Flesh); Academic
Careers and the Family (The Two-Career Job Search? A Veteran’s
Perspective); The Transgressive Impulse in Doris Lessing, Margaret
Atwood, and Mary Shelley (Mary Shelley and Literary Women’s History;
Stuck in the Ice: Apocalypse and Transgression in Shelley, Atwood, and
Lessing; Transgressive Spaces: Postcolonial Scenes in Lessing’s “Old Chief
Mshlanga” and Atwood’s “Death by Landscape”); Victorian Writing,
Victorian Art (Following the Threat: Women, Needlework, and Publication
in the Arts and Crafts Movement); Women, Writing, Community: The
Language of Reform (“It May Be That Female Petitioners Can Lawfully Be
Heard”: Constituting Women Reformers during the United States Indian
Removal Debates, 1830–31; “The Blessed Education into a Tolerant Spirit
Goes Swiftly On”: Frances Willard and the Maintenance of the Women’s
Reform Community, 1887–92; “The Tragedy of Women’s Emancipation”:
Emma Goldman’s Critique of First Wave Feminism, 1905–20); Foreign
Bodies: Representations of the Male Other in George Sand’s Fiction;
Presqu’il, Presque Femme: Hybrid Identities in Sand’s Tamaris; L’altérité
de l’artiste improvisateur dans quelques romans de George Sand); Mixed
Subjects: Women Read Latin America (Women, Guerillas, and Love:
Understanding War in Central America; After Exile: Writing the Latin
American Diaspora; Easy Women: Sex and Gender in Modern Mexican
Fiction; The Fence and the River: Culture and Politics at the United States-
Mexico Border); Manifesto Writing and Cultural Critique (A Challenge to
Death: Women’s Manifesto for Peace in the Face of War); Language and
Gender (We Don’t Speak the Same as We Did Five Years Ago: Diachronic
Analysis of Japanese Women’s Language Use; Negotiating Religion: The
Construction of Gender in Personal Ads; Sex as Work/Labor in the
Discourse of Male Bonding); Romantic-Era Science II: Sex and Gender
(Romantic Science and the Perversification of Sexual Pleasure; Dissecting
for Metaphor: Joanna Southcott, or, Poetry on the Brain; Peacock, Mary
Somerville, and the Woman of Science); Functions of Victorian Culture at
the Present Time II (“Nurs’d Up amongst the Scenes I have Described”:
Political Resonances in the Poetry of Working-Class Women); Comparative
Cultural Studies and post-1989 Central European Culture (Petrarchan
Patriarchal: Allegorical Femininity in Hungarian “Postmodernist”
Literature and Film); Open Forum: Part-Time and Non-Tenure-Track
Faculty Members (Discourse of Victimization); Sex, Pornography, Marriage
(The Discourse of Intimacy and the Crisis of Marriage; Pornography,
Erotica, and Repression); Theoretical Approaches to Teaching Tudor and
Stuart Women Writers (Teaching the Writings of Early Modern Women
from and with a Theoretical Perspective; Theory in the Teaching of Early
Modern Women Writers; Early Modern Women Writing Race); Refiguring
the Latino and Latina Studies Canon: Genres, Population, Approaches
(Chicana Ecofeminism: Gloria Anzaldúa and Judy Baca); Edith Wharton as
Transnational (Wharton’s In Morocco: Feminism and Orientalism);
Feminist Philanthropy and Women’s Foundations (Women Philanthropists:
Myths and Reality; Encouraging Responsive Philanthropy; Are Women the
Philanthropic Leaders of the Future?); John Milton: A General Session I
(The Troublesome Helpmate, or, How Pandora Got Her Box); Movies as
Paradigmatic Narratives (Visual Pleasure and Narratological
Cinefeminism); Resisting Gender (Constructing the Transgender Subject:
Sexuality, Gender, and the Female-Bodied Man in Diane Wood
Middlebrook’s Suits Me and Jackie Kay’s Trumpet; Genetic Counter-
memory and the Genealogy of the Transsexual); Virginia Woolf on
Religious Texts and Traditions (Virginia Woolf’s “Reoccupation” of
Christian Territory; Mrs. Ramsay’s Last Supper: To the Lighthouse and the
Passion of the Female Christ); Beauty: Now and Then (The Female Artist
as Hercules: Angelica Kauffman’s Revisionary Aesthetics); Romancing
Women: “Gender and Popular Literature in Medieval and Early Modern
Europe (Retrieving the Female Voice in European “Women’s Song”;
Textual Sex and Sexual Tests: The “Doncella Guerrera” in Iberian
Romance; Romancing the News: Mme de Scudéry as Journalist); Jewish
Cultural Studies and the Question of Religion (Queer Theory and the
Invention of Religion); Late Nineteenth-Century American Brotherhoods
(Female “Body Snatching Will Out”: The American Protective
Association’s Tales of “Convent Horrors”); Lesbian Disidentifications
(“I’m Not a Lesbian, I Just Loved Thelma”: Djuna Barnes’s Lesbian
Disavowal; Against Melancholy: Women Disidentifying Women; “In the
Hard and Painful Life”: Queer Disidentification and Lesbian Ambivalence);
Modernity in Reflux: Modernism, Feminism, and Failed Fictions of
Progress (Mothers: Eugenic Feminism and Charlotte Perkins Gilman’s
Regeneration Narratives; Past Time as Pastime? Sapphic Modernity and the
Abandonment of Feminism; Female Peristalsis; Backlash of Fitness
Landscape? Feminism and Multiple Modernities); Resituating Glasgow
(Black Labor and the New Southern Woman); Contexts of Early Modern
German Literature (Reading the Visual Context of Sociability in G.P.
Harsdörffer’s Frauenzimmer Gesprächspiele); Performance and Culture in
Contemporary Latin America (Performing Motherhood in Argentina and
Mexico: Griselda Gambaro and Hugo Argüelles; Sex in the City: Striptease
and the Performance of Style in Cortázar and Peri-Rossi); Medieval
Spanish Language and Literature (Medieval Medical Views of Women in
the Lapidario of Alfonso X); Topics in Earlier German Literature (Female
Pain, Female Eroticism: The Eroticization of the Female Body in Pain in
Hartman von Aue’s Courtly Epics); Medical Knowledge and Cultural Study
(Generative Debt: Liberal Politics and the Placenta; Reading Abortion:
Medicine and Politics in an Age of Revolution); Ma(Donna): The Image of
Italian American Women in Literature, Film, and Television (Rescuing the
Fallen Woman: The Issue of Female Representation in Martin Scorsese’s
Cinema; Anything but Italian: Madonna’s Synthetic Ethnicity; Italian
American Women as Comic Foils: Exploding the Stereotype in My Cousin
Vinny, Moonstruck, and Married to the Mob; Transgressive Italian
American Women in Carole Maso’s Ghost Dance, Nancy Savoca’s
Household Saints, and David Chase’s The Sopranos); Feeling Things: Race,
Sex, and the Politics of Objects (Bad Sex Objects; Object and Home Erotics
in Dickinson and Gilman); Grief and Gender in Early Modern England (“I
Might Againe Have Been the Sepulcure”: Paternal and Maternal Mourning
in Early Modern England; Ghost Stories in The Winter’s Tale: Grief in
Leones, Aggression in Hermione; Mamillius); Masculinity Studies and
Feminist Theory: Backlash and Advances (Masculinities and Superordinate
Studies; Queer Theory and Masculine Reempowerment; Stiffed and Punch
Drunk: W(h)ither Masculinity; Reenfleshing the Bright Boys, or, How Male
Bodies Matter to Feminist Theory); Race and the Subject of Marriage in
Late-Nineteenth- and Twentieth-Century America (Captive Wives);
Construing Halperin: Acts, Identities, and the History of Sexuality
(Theorizing Desire: Acts and Identities in Pre- and Early Modernity;
Against Forgetfulness: David Halperin, “pseudo-Foucauldian Doctrine,”
and the Practice of Lesbian and Gay History; Friendship, Love, and the
Discursive Prehistory of Homosexuality); Constituting Ethnic Americans
(Radical Black Femininity: The Idealization of Social Progress); Queering
the Family (Tardy Epithalamia: Queer Love, the Family, and the Poetry of
Marriage); New Perspectives on the Heptaméron (Her Story: Social and
Sexual Structures of Desire in Heptaméron 12); Liberté, Egalité, Fraternité:
Human Rights and Nineteenth-Century French Literature (“Les droits de
l’homme” in 1848: Women of Color and Emancipation); Women in the
Colonial Latin American Inquisition (Santa Rose de Lima and the
Inquisition; Witches in the Tribunal de la Inquisicion de Cartagena de
Indias; And for the Defense, Sor Juana Summons the Inquisition); Re-
inventing the Peabody Sisters (Desire, Transgression, and Sophia
Hawthorne’s Notes in England and Italy; Subtle, Shifting, and Subverted
Power: Mary Peabody Mann’s Innovative Model for the True Woman;
Declaration and Deference: Elizabeth Palmer Peabody, Mary Peabody
Mann, and Their Complex Rhetoric of Mediation; Elizabeth Palmer
Peabody’s Problematic Feminism and the Feminization of
Transcendentalism); Rethinking Violence, Agency, and Aesthetics:
Feminist and Cross-Cultural Perspectives (Documenting Rape Warfare:
Feminist Criticism and Translational Epistemologies; The Aesthetics of
Romance and the Ethics of Ethnic Violence in Postcolonial Film; “Handing
Back Shame”: Survivor Discourse and Political Agency in Sapphire’s
Push); Madness, Melancholia, and Mourning: Austrian States of Mind
(Inspired Insanity: Women and Madness in Contemporary Austrian
Literature); Annual Meeting of the American Boccaccio Association (The
Ideology of Love in Corbaccio); Racialization, Dangerous Bodies, and the
(En)Gendering of Space/Place (Writing on the Social Body: Dresses and
Body Ornamentation in Contemporary Chicana Art); The Brown Women
Writers Project Online: “New” Texts, New Questions (Searching for
Women’s Work: Literary and Cultural Analysis of Online Texts; Medieval
Women’s Manuscripts: Authorship and Encoding Challenges; The Role of
the WWP in the Development of Literary Encoding in the 1990s; Mary
Carleton’s Conditional Moods: A Discourse Analysis of a WWO Text); The
Other Britain III: Modernist Migrations and Topographies – People, Places,
and Spaces in the British Imaginary (“Inconsequent Lives”: Anglo-Indian
Fictions of Female Voyaging and Domesticity); Transgressive Sexualities in
the Postcolony (Patricia Powell’s A Small Gathering of Bones and The
Pagoda: Articulating Transgressive Sexualities through the Disjunctures of
the Caribbean Diaspora; Nasty “Colored Girls”: The Revenge of the Native
Woman Informant; “There Are No Lesbians Here”: Political Definitions in
the Age of Human Rights Activisms); Comparative United States
Literatures I: Turn-of-the-Century Sexualities (Wired Love: Sex, Media,
and American Modernity); Boswell’s London Journal 1762–1763, 1950–
2000: New Approaches (“An I Not Then a Man?” Importance and
Authorial Anxiety in Boswell’s London Journal); Political Trollope (Social
Issues and Political Contexts: Domestic Violence and Trollope’s The Prime
Minister); Ta(i)lling the Dog: Power, Politics, and Play in the Works of
David Mamet (The Politics of the Deal: The Prisoner’s Dilemma, Logical
Paradox, and the Lacanian Gaze in David Mamet’s Oleanna; David Mamet,
Film-acher: Assault on/with Narrative); W. H. Auden’s Musical
Collaborations (Queer Identities and Musical Collaborations); In Their Own
Words: Understanding Chinese and Indian Rhetoric from Within (The
Problem of Global Feminism: An enthymematic Perspective on Post-Mao
Chinese Women’s Writing); Teaching Boccaccio’s Decameron (Women in
the Decameron; Anatomizing Boccaccio’s Sexual Festivity); The Arts of
Joyce (Whorehouse/Playhouse: The Brothel as the Setting for “Circe”);
Feminist Ethics and Epistemologies/Éthiques et épistémologies féministes
(Fémininité et négativité dans la pensée contemporaine; From “Femme
Juive” to “JuiFemme”: What Do French Jewish Women Writers Know?;
Make Room for Daddy? Do “Masculinities” Have a Place in Feminist
Epistemology?); Public Spectacles (War with Words: Nineteenth-Century
Literary Women in Public); Foreign Languages, Foreign Cultures (Cultural
Studies and Sexual Ideologies); Comparative Turns of Centuries (“The
Rational Spiritual Part”: Gender and Transformation in Late-Century Music
Dramas of Dryden and Purcell); Feminism on Time (Feminist Futures?
Telling Time in Feminist Theory; International Feminism: Timekeeping for
the Nation?); Writing from Prison (Temporality as Queer History: Genet
and the Time of Capital); History and Future of Rhetorics outside the
Paradigm (Rhetoric as a Feminist Project); How We Feel about Bodies: A
Roundtable Discussion (Feeling Differently: Conjugal Reorientation and
the Victorian Honeymoon; Much Butter, Fewer Eggs: Mary Chesnut’s
Infertility; Gender, Not Sex – and Not Sexuality, Either); Reading Women I:
Nineteenth-Century Women and the Social Work of Reading ((Im)Proper
Reading for Women: Mary Elizabeth Braddon’s Belgravia Magazine and
the Defense of the Sensation Novel; Reading Mothers, Reading Daughters;
Social Reading, Social Work, and the Social Function of Art in Louisa May
Alcott’s “May Flowers”); Interarts Excursions: Italian Poets on Painting in
the Twentieth Century (Women, Futurism, and Visual Writing); Irish Gothic
and Modernity (The Female Collaborator: Property and Authorship in
Stoker’s Dracula and Yeats’s A Vision); Poe’s Unseemly Passions (Poe in
Bed: Sex, Biographical Speculation, and Tales of Dying Women); Music,
Gender, and Representation (Moll Cutpurse and the Understanding Public:
The Dreams of a Roaring Girl; The Importance of Being Greek: Classical
Affect and Gender Anxiety in Eighteenth-Century British Musical
Aesthetics; “That Blood Can’t Be Contained”: (Re)Constructing Body,
Genre, and Lyric in Black Feminist Hip-Hop); The Invisible Canon:
Forgotten Names, Marginalized Texts (La sabiduría de la mujer en la obra
de Nemesio R. Canales; Queer Family as Edge: Erica López’s Flaming
Iguanas: An Illustrated All-Girl Road Novel Thing); Opera and Sexuality,
Revisited (Balloons and Guillotines: Ethics of Mutilation in Poulenc’s
Operas; Rescuing Vere from Melville; Forster, Britten, and Billy Budd;
Romancing the Opera); Acts of Reading and Print Culture in Early Modern
Spain (Eve’s Apple: Early Modern Hispanic Women Writers on Storytelling
and Knowledge); Music and Gender in Twentieth-Century French
Literature (Nancy Huston: Music and Feminine Identity; Siren of the Opera,
or, Gender Afloat; Vinteuil, Music, and Musical Aesthetics); Women
Collecting Poetry in Mid-Seventeenth Century England: The hm904
Miscellany and Open Business Meeting; Family, Gender, and Politics in the
Works of Simone de Beauvoir (A Mother-Daughter Link: Four Critics Look
at Une mort très douce; Gender Instability in Le sang des autres and Tous
les hommes son mortels; Beau-voir’s Fosca: Faustian Overreacher or
Product of the Medieval Italian Republics; Le jeu de “je” ou “elle” dans Les
belles images); Volatile Values (Gender, Sexuality, and the Literary Market
in Spain at the End of the Millennium); Gender and Language Learning
(Effects of Gender Differences on Students’ Motivation in Foreign
Language Learning; Gender and Language-Learner Socialization;
Language Learning and Gender Differences in Pronunciation); American
Picturesques: Visual Culture in the Nineteenth-Century United States
(Tourists and Settlers: Gendered Uses of the Picturesque in Antebellum
Travel Sketches); On the Uses of Perversity (Economics, Sexuality, and the
Perverse Desires of the Nineteenth-Century Novel); The Nineteenth-
Century French Heroine Revisited: Amazons, Dandies, and Hysterics
(Heroines à Cheval: The Amazon in Indiana, Les lys dans la vallée, and
Dominique; Le dandysme par procuration dans Illusions perdues; Folie à
Deux: Hysterical Contagion in Thérèse Raquin); Brilliance and Schlock I:
Brilliance in Twentieth-Century United States Drama (Race and Sexuality
in the Modern American Mystery Play); Reading Women II: Twentieth-
Century Women and the Production of the Self as Reader (Hall of Mirrors:
The Woman Reading and/in Radclyffe Hall’s The Well of Loneliness;
Diverting the Reader: Seriously Reading the Dumb Blonde Seriously
Reading; “One of Those People like Anne Sexton or Sylvia Plath”: The
Pathologized Woman Reader as Literary and Cultural Icon); Teaching
America Abroad (Fast Food, Fast Cars, and Fast Women: Confronting
Clichés of America in Turkey); Film and History (Historicizing Ida Lupino:
A Female Production Code in 1950s Hollywood); New Perspectives in
Twentieth-Century English Literature (Unnatural Passions: Sex and
Spirituality in Women’s Writing); Comic Scapegoating: Laugher, Identity,
and Community in Late-Twentieth-Century American Novels (Sticky
Evidence: Masculinity as Scapegoat in Portnoy’s Complaint); Victorian
Freaks! (The Bear Woman and the Lady: Julia Pastrana and the Politics of
Spectacle); Images of Maternity in Elsa Morante, Natalia Ginzburg, and
Dacia Maraini (The Tigress in the Show: Motherhood in Elsa Morante;
Matrophobia and Maternal Ambivalence in Ginzburg’s Daughters; The
Pregnant Nun: Suor Attanasia and the Metaphor of Arrested Maternity in
Dacia Maraini); Modernity, Gender, Aesthetics: Pardo Bazán beyond
Naturalism (Transgendered and Transgenred; Incipient Modernism in Pardo
Bazán’s Short Fiction; Thoroughly Modern Men: Crime, Sex, and
Adventure in La gota de sangre and La aventura de Isidro); Cervantes and
Cultural Studies (El Quijote y la construcción cultural de masculinidades en
la España aurisecular); El Teatro español des Siglo de Oro y las Indias
(Seeds of An American Baroque Aesthetic: Gender, Ethnicity, Sustenance,
and Theology in Sor Juana’s Version of the Conquest; “En Distintas
Cuadras”: Engendering the Americas in Sor Juana’s Los empeños de una
casa); Cognition and Ideology (Define Cognition: Be Sure to Distinguish
Ontological Problems from Both Epistemological Concerns and Feminist-
Materialist Accounts of Ideology); Public Appearances: Modernist Women
and Social Space (“Street Haunting”: Shopping and Public Selving in Mrs.
Dalloway; “Among the Furnitures”: Laura Riding’s Leisure Time; “In
These Secluded Districts”: The Case for Privacy in the Work of hd);
Revisions or New Visions? Contextualizing New Woman Literature of the
Fin de Siècle (Re-viewing the Pats: New Woman Writing and the Victorian
Women’s Novel; Painting the New Woman; Progress, Development, and
Individualism in New Woman Fiction of the Fin de Siècle); The Tran-
substantiation of Rhetoric in the Discipline of English Studies (Oratory and
the Construction of Gender in Postbellum America); American Humor in
the Twenty-First Century (Ludicrous Courtship in Rose Terry Cooke’s
Short Stories: “I Am What I Seem to Men. Need I Be Any More?”);
Brilliance and Schlock II: Schlock in Nineteenth- and Twentieth-Century
United States Theater (The First “Miss California”: Ramona Pageants and
the Romance of the American Southwest); Genre in Children’s Literature
(The Journey Within and Without: The Female Bildungsroman in
Children’s Literature); John Milton: A General Session II (“To Set a Foot
Forward with Manly Confidence”: Milton and the Gender of Liberty); The
“New Negro” away from Harlem (Southern Sisters of the New Negro
Renaissance); André Gide’s Politics (André Gide: From a Politics of
Sexuality to a Politics of Commitment); Pressure Points: Spanish Women
Writers and the Canon, 1898–1939 (Women Writers Imagine a New
Political Order, 1923–31; Couples, Creativity, and the Suppression of
Women’s Writing: The Case of Concha Méndez; Women Playwrights in the
Early Decades of the Twentieth Century); Modern Women Writers Editing
Sociology (Figuring Beatrice Webb and the “Serious Artist”; Refusing
Middle Age); Reading and Writing Margaret Cavendish in the Context of
Print Culture (Gender and the Monumental Book in Cavendish’s Poems and
Fancies); “The Words Continue Their Journey”: Atwood’s Language, Style,
and Form (Historian or Hysteric? Revising the History of the Canadian
Frontier in Margaret Atwood’s Journals of Susanna Moodie); Edith
Wharton and Mass Culture (Misreading The House of Mirth: Middle-Class
Readers and Upwardly Mobile Desire); Images of Byron (The Female
Gaze: Some Women’s Portraits of Byron); Mark Twain’s Literary
Daughters and Sisters (Mark Twain’s Debt to Women’s Humor Tradition;
Mutual Influences: Mark Twain’s Correspondence with Nineteenth-Century
Women Writers); The Imprisonment of American Culture (Women’s
Prisons, Women’s Lives); Gender and Sexuality in the Cultures of Medieval
Iberia (Cultural Assimilation and Gender in Minhat Yehuda, Sone hanashim
(The Gift of Yehuda, Enemy of Women); Engendering Trouble in the Libro
de buen amor; “Dones que feyan d’homens”: The Construction of Gender
in the Writing of Medieval Catalan History); Pirandello’s World: A
Psychological Perspective II (Women on the Verge: Tozzi, Pirandello, and
Sexual Sympathy); Simone de Beauvoir and the World around Her
(Courtesans, Libertines, and Demimondaines in Le deuxième sexe; Women
Intellectuals and the Canon: Recent Readings of Simone de Beauvoir and
Hannah Arendt); Lord Jim at One Hundred (Dreams of Grandeur, Fears of
Engulfment: Gender and Landscape in Conrad’s Lord Jim); Dickinson and
the Victorians (Finding Herself Alone: Emily Dickinson, Victorian Women
Novelists, and the Female Subject); Feminism, Policy, and Politics in the
New Millennium; Rhetoric, Technical Communication, and Theory
(Situated Knowledges, Embodied Information: Haraway’s Cyborg Rhetoric
in Feminist Technical Communication Research); Your Tax Dollars at Work
(for and against You): Public Policy and Gay and Lesbian Studies (Public
Policy and Gay and Lesbian Studies; They Didn’t Ask, So We Didn’t Tell:
Public Policy and the Construction of Federal Homosexuality; Mass Media
and Queer Studies; The Impact of Homophobic Media Coverage on Queer
Subjectivity); Cronicas: Tales from the Academy – A Workshop (Why Do
Women Enter the “Network” So Late, If Ever?); Dreams and
Sitings/Citings in Courtly Literature (The Female Gaze and the
Spec(tac)ular Male; Female Citings/Sitings in the Dream in Medieval
French Narrative; Charles d’Orléans’s Dream of Freedom from Women and
Grief); East German Women in United Germany: Ten Years Later
(“Geboren in frauenbewegter östlicher Nachwendezeit”: Looking Back at
Eight Years of Weibblick; Changing and Maintaining Identity: An East
German’s Quest for Answers); Les françaises: Etat des lieux / The Status of
French Women Today: An Assessment (The Debate over Feminine
Terminology; Women in the Media in France; Réussité scolaire et insertion
professionnelle des femmes en France); The Mother-Daughter Syndrome
(The Triad of the Mother, the Daughter, and Poland in Maria Kunuwiz’s
The Stranger; Exploring and Exploding the Discourse on Motherhood and
Creativity: Kristeva and Drakulic’s “Marble Stein”).
APPENDIX ELEVEN
A Front by Any Other Name: Ideology, Gender
Studies, and Women’s Studies
We have come a long way since the days of Shakespeare, who observed,
“That which we call a rose, By any other name would smell as sweet.”1
What must have been heard as common sense to most people in the
seventeenth century, however, is clearly no such thing to most people in our
time. What we now call a “rose,” for instance, might not actually smell
sweet. Although the powerful have probably always used euphemisms to
disguise their intentions, doing so has become more widely known and
more widely accepted than ever. And we can think of at least three reasons.
For one thing, consider the influence of advertising, a necessary feature
of commerce in every market economy. No longer considered an art, it is
taught systematically on the basis of psychological research. Something
very similar has happened in the world of politics – and not only, to judge
from the euphemisms and slogans of communist countries, in market
economies. Elected officials often prefer to follow rather than lead. To do
that, they must rely on opinion polls. And to do that successfully, they must
say what people want to hear, even if that means distorting the truth.
Finally, academics – those with ideological goals – have actively sought
and effectively promoted ways of legitimating all this, even though many of
them disapprove of advertising, in particular, as the capitalist way of
creating “false consciousness.” What was once derided as “groupthink,” in
short, is now acclaimed as “sensitivity” (or satirized by dissidents as
political correctness).
In Spreading Misandry, we introduced the word “front” with regard to
ideological feminists (the term originated among Marxists and is used also
in organized crime). The ideological rhetoric of feminism is not palatable to
all women, so a front is required – that is, rhetoric that really is considered
respectable and can therefore be used to conceal ideas and goals that would
otherwise be considered unacceptable. “Ideologues routinely use
fashionable rhetoric but without following through on its inner logic …
[T]hey fill old wineskins with new wine. The words are familiar to almost
everyone, yes, but not the implications or interpretations intended by this or
that ideologue.”2 Some apparently innocent phenomenon or institution is
used, in other words, to disguise what would otherwise seem much more
disturbing or even sinister.
One front, popular not only among ideologues but also among politicians
of all stripes and advertisers of all products, is language. We suggest that
the term “gender studies” originated as a euphemism for “women’s
studies.” It has come to include “gay studies” and “queer theory.” It
functions as a front for ideologies – that is, for feminism and its gay
derivative. A study with statistical significance would be an enormous
research project in itself, because so many colleges and universities teach
either gender studies or women’s studies. But, as a quick glance at
academic sites on the Internet will reveal to anyone, the following examples
are by no means eccentric.
Consider the Center for Gender Studies at University of Chicago. Its
website lists forty-six graduate and undergraduate courses offered in 2002–
2003. Visitors to this site learn that the center coordinates courses and
activities on gender and sexuality. Many courses are, at least ostensibly,
about both women and men. Many others are specifically about women or
gay people. Not one, however, is specifically about men (although that
varies from year to year, at least three – out of almost fifty – having been
offered at one time or another). Even when the word “gender” does include
men, moreover, it often refers specifically to gay men, bisexual men, and so
on. Given the prevalence of courses on feminist or gay theory (along with
Marxist, postmodern, and postcolonial theory), the focus of this program is
clearly “to locate knowledge in previously suppressed or understudied
places and modes of thought.”3 In other words, profs and students interested
in the needs and problems of straight white men need not apply.
The website for “gender studies” at Indiana University, Bloomington,
starts off inclusively enough. The program, for graduates and
undergraduates, offers twenty-two “exciting, interdisciplinary and rigorous
courses that concentrate on the position of women and men across many
cultures. Masculinity and femininity, often referred to as gender, have
evolved throughout history and are still evolving.”4Most courses are, at
least ostensibly, about both women and men – that is, both femininity and
masculinity. One is clearly not: Women, Gender, and Culture. Not even one
course is specifically about men. But this tally is deceptive.
For one thing, two additional courses are specifically about feminism:
Two Centuries of Feminist Thought and International Feminist Debates. In
fact, almost every course description refers directly to feminism. Many of
the courses listed could be on either women or men, true, depending on
demand in any particular year. But when the topics of previous years are
listed, the focus is on women: Topics in the Study of Gender; Survey of
Contemporary Research in Gender Studies: The Social and Behavioral
Sciences (which in earlier years included topics such as “Women, Sexuality
and Health: Research Issues and Policy Implications”; “Feminist Social
Science”; and “Feminism: Histories, Theories, and Methods”); and Themes
in the Study of Gender (such as “Victorian Women and Gender”; “Gender
and Sports Journalism”; “Sex Discrimination and the Law”; “Native
American Women and Welfare Policies”; “Women’s Health Issues”;
“Women Composers”; and “Gender and Military Service”).
The teacher of that last course is possibly, though not necessarily,
interested in men. The teacher of another course, Sexual Politics, probably
is: “Why,” asks the course description, “are men expected to be soldiers but
women are not (in most societies)?” On the other hand, consider this
description of the course on Gender, Sexuality, and Popular Culture: topics
include “gender and the power of the image; sex and spectatorship;
melodrama, film noire and ‘the women’s film’; rock music women;
Madonna and MTV; race, age and representation; as well as violence,
masculinity and pornography.” Men are not only placed last on the list but
also linked with two inarguably negative topics.
The University of Southern California offers seventy-five courses to its
students in gender studies. Some of the courses are cross-listed from other
programs or departments. Many are, at least ostensibly, about both women
and men. No fewer than twenty-three, though, are specifically about
women: Racial and Ethnic Women in America; Woman, Nature, Culture:
The Behavioral Ecology of Women; Overcoming Prejudice (on “the most
effective strategies and techniques for minorities, women, gays and
lesbians, and others subjected to stigma”);5 Women in Antiquity; Women
and Global Issues; Women in Judaism; Women in the European Middle
Ages; Women, Religion and Sexuality; French Women Writers; Women in
Society; Women Writers in Europe and America; Women and Gender in
China: Past and Present; Women in Contemporary Literature and the Arts;
Women in Music; Women’s Literature in Germany; Women in English
Literature before 1800; Women In English and American Literature after
1800; Women’s Spaces in History: ‘Hussies,’ ‘Harems,’ and ‘Housewives’;
Women in International Development; Images of Women in Contemporary
Culture; Studies in Women’s and Family History; and Woman [sic] as
Writers in World Literature. In addition, eight courses are specifically about
feminism: Introduction to Feminist Theory and the Women’s and Men’s
Movements (which nonetheless considers only “men’s roles in the feminist
movement”);6 Gender Studies and the Community: Internship (including
“men’s roles in the feminist movement”); Ecofeminism; Special Topics:
Seminar in Selected Topics Relating to Gender and Feminism; Feminist
Theory; Studies in Gender and Feminism; and Studies in Feminist Theory
and Art History.
Only one course is specifically about men: Men and Masculinity. The
obsequious description of that course is very revealing.
Why a course about masculinity? After all, academia is infused
with de facto male biases. Much of the subject matter, theoretical
constructs and thematic foci were constructed in a time when men
controlled education and women often had scarce access to it.
Ironically, the answer to this question can be found in women’s
studies.
In the generations since feminist examinations of gender
began, the mining of the social terrain yielded veins of strata,
patterns of formation and rich resources that construct social
architectures favoring men. Still, these excavations also unearthed
a series of conflicts within the production and performance of
masculinities. This course will explore social class, race and
ethnicity, sexual orientation and age. The course also looks at the
antecedents of today’s men’s movements. Particular scrutiny will
be given to the costs of rigid definitions of masculinity as well as
the costs of the power and privilege men exercise over women.7
Clearly, an apology is considered necessary for this course even to be
offered. At any rate, it assumes the legitimacy of studying men through the
eyes of women – that is, of feminism. In fact, its legitimacy as a course is
predicated on the extent to which it builds on (read: does not challenge)
feminism. Otherwise, how could we explain the reference to “social
architectures” favouring men without any direct reference to those
favouring women? Although this description acknowledges the costs –
presumably psychological – of the “power and privilege men exercise over
women,” therefore, the implication is that these are of no moral importance.
For some reason, the description of another course, Introduction to Feminist
Theory and the Women’s and Men’s Movements, mentions only the roles of
men in feminism. Go figure.
Finally, consider “gender studies” at Northwestern University. The
introduction to its website begins by noting a recent change of name from
the “women’s studies program” to the more inclusive “gender studies
program.” This change “recognizes the ways in which the field of women’s
studies has outstripped its original designation and … implies a greatly
expanded reach for our program.”8 In other words, women’s studies has
expanded to include several other fields: specifically, “queer studies” and
“critical race studies.” This mission statement makes it clear that the new
field “is properly building on the strong foundations established by over
twenty years of women’s studies scholarship.”9
Northwestern, which offers eight courses on gender, has been more
careful than other universities to use the word “gender” consistently – that
is, to make sure that all references to it include both women and men.
Nonetheless, many course descriptions make it clear that only women are of
interest. Topics in Gender Studies: Gender and Health, for instance, does so
immediately. The word “gender” in its title notwithstanding, it begins with
the following questions:
How do the biological category “female” and the cultural
category “woman” affect patterns of health and disease for both
individuals and populations? How do different cultural
constructions of gender, sex, and sexuality shape public policies
concerning the inequitable distribution of health and disease
within the United States, Africa, Japan, South America, and
Europe? How do the intersections of gender, biology, sexuality,
class, race, and racism produce health inequities. What is the
contribution of anthropologists to improving women’s health
worldwide? To address these questions, this course explores case
studies of breast cancer, sexual and reproductive health, mental
health, violence, substance abuse, physician-patient interactions,
infectious diseases, and access to health resources. Special health
issues in the lesbian community in the usa are also discussed.10
These questions are not without merit. But many questions are unasked.
Why is so little research being done to find out why women live so much
longer than men in our society? What measures might be considered to
reduce this gap in longevity? And why are men so much more reluctant
than women to consult physicians? So much for the alleged inclusiveness of
“gender.”
The bias at Northwestern is not so much toward feminism itself,
however, as to the larger context of political movements such as
environmentalism, antiglobalization, postcolonialism, and so forth. Without
actually saying so, every course description implies that women are both
the primary victims of social or political injustice and the primary creators
of social and political justice. Consider the course on Gender Studies for a
Small Planet: “What does it mean to understand cross-cultural,
transnational, and international processes through the lens of gender and
sexuality? Conversely, why are contemporary gender, class, and
ethnic/racial identities inextricably bound to these transnational
processes[?] Organized around the theme of commodification, this course
examines how production, marketing, and consumption of key products
(textiles/clothing, tourism, service industries, and world music) link regions
and peoples in relations of domination, mutual benefit, solidarity, and
resistance.”11
Despite its rhetorical questions, this description is characteristic not of
the academic environment – that is, one in which the answers are not
obvious from the getgo – but of a political movement. Hence the rhetoric of
“domination,” “solidarity,” and “resistance.” Here is part of the outline for
Topics in Gender Studies: Gender and Representation: “We will further
examine the issue of representation in relation to cultural hegemony, gender
and class hierarchies and postcoloniality: how has ‘the Other’ (in terms of
race, class, ethnicity, sexuality) been represented, what are the implications
of representing ‘the Other’? What happens when members of groups who
have been represented as ‘Other’ represent themselves?”12 Significantly,
some questions remain unasked: What happens when they turn the tables?
In this case, what happens when women represent men as the “Other”?
What happens to men when popular culture represents them as the new and
only legitimate “Other” (which is what we discussed in Spreading
Misandry)? Nothing on the web-site indicates that these questions would
ever be taken seriously as topics for scholarly research.
The Canadian situation is very similar. In the Status of Women
Supplement for 2001, sent out with the CAUT Bulletin, Edith Zorychta
defines women’s studies in connection with a focus on “gender.”13
According to her, this field “provides a scholarly critique of the
conventional ideas of what it means to be human and a woman, a critique
that is of interest to all scholars and students, male and female.”14 Once
again, the word “gender” should refer to both femininity and masculinity.
The fact that it seldom does in these circles, that “gender studies” has
become a euphemism for “women’s studies,” reveals a widespread belief
that gender creates problems only for women or that only women have
distinctive needs and problems. Zorychta claims that just about all students
– male students, too, presumably – now take courses in women’s studies
(surely a claim that would require statistical evidence). And these courses
should be of interest to both women and men, she claims, because they
involve “the study of constructions of masculinity.”15 Unfortunately, she
does not tell us how we can learn anything about men if the perspective
applied is that of women – what could be called the “female gaze.”16 Thus,
even though academics sometimes pay lip service to the goal of women and
men exploring “gender” together, the fact remains that “gender studies” is a
field that caters primarily to women. Which is why most departments that
teach courses on gender are actually called “women’s studies,” not “gender
studies.”
In short, the experts in “gender studies” (let alone women’s studies) see
no need to study or teach anything about men except the ways in which
they create problems for women or sexual minorities. Men appear primarily
as evidence to support theories such as social constructionism (according to
which all social roles are socially constructed and therefore can be
deconstructed to facilitate social change). This should lead to the suspicion
that something other than scholarship is involved.
APPENDIX TWELVE
What’s Sauce for the Goose: Double Standards in
a Government Report
On 30 May 2003 a highly revealing story broke in Canada, but it was not a
distinctively Canadian story. Americans who consider themselves immune
to the political and ideological forces involved in this story are deluding
themselves. When it comes to feminist ideology, as we say, the United
States and Canada are not separate societies. When it comes to feminist
ideology, in fact, their cultural unity applies even to Quebec. What happens
in one country could easily happen in the other – and often does, albeit in
slightly different form or to a slightly different extent. Which is why
American feminists not only influence Canadian legislation but sometimes
intervene directly (by invitation) in the legal or legislative process. More
about that later. Here is the story.
It began in 1999. Status of Women Canada, a federal agency,
commissioned research on the dangers faced by feminists in their struggle
on behalf of women in general and schoolgirls in particular. The title and
(redundant) subtitle of the original call for proposals make its political
orientation – ideological feminism under the guise of postmodernism – very
clear: “Where Have All the Women Gone? Changing Shifts in Policy
Discourses.”1 Among those who responded with a proposal were Pierrette
Bouchard, Isabelle Boily, and Marie-Claude Proulx. “How specifically,”
they asked, “was it possible to develop in discourse and thinking, over a
period of less than ten years, such unprecedented opposition to girls’
achievement at school?”2 Even at this early stage, the basic premise –
widespread and increasing misogyny – had already been established on
political grounds; research was required only to provide a suitably political
explanation and back it up with evidence. What the question calls
“unprecedented opposition to girls’ achievement,” after all, could have been
much less tendentiously called an unprecedented concern for boys’
achievement. Why assume from the get-go that concern for boys is
synonymous with lack of it for girls or even active opposition to them?
At any rate, three authors – Pierrette Bouchard and her two research
assistants, Isabelle Boily and Marie-Claude Proulx – were given a grant,
from the pockets of taxpayers, to find out why women were once again
under attack. Their report was called “School Success by Gender: A
Catalyst for the Masculinist Discourse.” Even though Bouchard is a
professor of education at the University of Laval, therefore, her specifically
academic credentials did not take her very far; she was being paid by a
government agency with an overtly political (and covertly ideological)
mission, not an academic institution or a neutral government agency.3
Interviewed for the National Post, Bouchard defended herself as follows:
“I have a feminist perspective, but just because I am a feminist, does not
mean that I am incapable of seeing that boys are having certain difficulties.
Nor do I put all men in the same basket. Not all men are like those I
identified in the report.”4 Unfortunately, the report does not support that
statement.
For one thing, nowhere does the report actually acknowledge that
schoolboys have any problems. Not once, not ever, not even in the most
perfunctory or condescending way. Bouchard acknowledges every claim to
that effect, sure. But on every occasion, without a single exception, she
trivializes or even ridicules it, often resorting to the age-old strategy of
manipulating men by shaming those who see themselves as helpless or
victimized.5 If the problem that a claim represents is real at all, in other
words, it is not worth taking seriously; only the problems of schoolgirls are
worth taking seriously. And yet evidence indicates that schoolboys do have
problems that are worth taking seriously in the interest not only of the boys
themselves but also of society as a whole. This is the conclusion drawn by
Jon Bradley, at any rate, of McGill University’s Department of Education.
The proportion of male teachers in elementary and secondary schools (of
the English sector in Quebec) is very low, he points out, and getting even
lower. The dropout rate for boys, on the other hand, is higher than that for
girls and getting even higher. “Boys do not suddenly decide to drop out in
Grade 9; there is not some mysterious gene that kicks in and ‘rebellion’ and
‘stupidity’ strike. Rather, boys are gradually turned off school and the
pursuit of learning through a long process that commences in pre-
kindergarten and moves up throughout the whole school system. This
model demands female learning styles, female-selected books and a
classroom environment that might do wonders for girls but is academically
killing the boys.6 Bouchard’s lack of even the most basic generosity toward
boys, let alone compassion for them, is ironic in view of the fact that she
calls repeatedly for “egalitarian” approaches to education and even for
“equality of opportunity” (by which, to judge from the fact that her
recommendations to the government – more programs for girls alone, more
research on them alone, more money spent on them alone – amount to an
exclusive focus on girls).
Although Bouchard does not claim that all men are misogynists,
moreover, she does indeed claim, albeit implicitly, something very similar:
that all men are misogynists except those who adopt feminism – that is,
those who agree with her own brand of feminism. The only good man, for
her, is a male feminist. In Spreading Misandry we classified male feminists
as “honorary women,” because the price that they pay for becoming
feminists – ideological feminists – is to deny the value of anything
distinctive in men, including themselves. They maintain their self-respect as
individuals in spite of the fact that they are men, not because of it. Being
unlike “those others,” they expect to gain respect from women (and enmity
from men, which confirms their original assumption).
One of the recommendations of this report is that those who express
opinions dubbed “masculinist” – by the way, this word is hardly ever used
by men (except, perhaps, for those who call themselves “male feminists”)
and is therefore not some perverse counterpart to “feminist” – should be
prosecuted under Canada’s legislation against expressions of hate directed
toward “identifiable groups.” In other words, Bouchard wants to silence
those who disagree with her (which is precisely, of course, what once
happened to women). She claims that this “masculinist discourse” is
tantamount to the promotion of hatred toward women. Although she never
actually defines “masculinist,” she clearly refers to any position that
challenges or even questions a feminist one. Opposing this or that aspect of
feminism, she implies, is the same as opposing women. Opposing women is
the same as hating women. And hating women is the same as hating Jews,
say, or gay people. This turns all of her adversaries into Nazis.
Why all of them? It is true that Bouchard makes her recommendation in
connection specifically with hostile websites on the Internet. You might
assume, therefore, that she wants the government to prosecute only male
rednecks, those who do indeed use websites to incite hatred against women
(although she says nothing whatsoever about female rednecks – zillions of
them – who use their own websites to incite hatred against men). But wait.
Appended to the report is a hit list that names not only male (and some
female) individuals, including academics, who have written books or
articles that challenge ideological feminist positions but also organizations
that promote the interests of boys or men: boys with problems at school or
at home, divorced men, fathers (including those without custody), and
therapeutic support groups of various kinds. (It does not, of course, include
individual men or men’s organizations that support feminism.)
This report presents us with the startling fact that we still live in a time
of hostility between the sexes. And in war, according to conventional
wisdom (which we reject), all is permitted. Or, according to the more
sophisticated version, ends can justify means. Bouchard unwittingly
illustrates the reason why some people, especially in the United States, have
always opposed censorship – that is, legislation that bans obscenity and
even legislation that bans literary or other expressions of hatred. They do
not approve of obscenity or hatred, but they do realize what can happen
when unpopular forms of expression are criminalized. Who decides, after
all, where to draw the line between what may be expressed and what may
not be expressed? The fact that a respectable academic, hired by a
government agency, could recommend to any government in 2003 that only
one political point of view be accepted as legitimate – that one ideology be
installed, in effect, as the country’s official philosophy – should be a wake-
up call to anyone who believes that the phenomenon described in Spreading
Misandry is, or even was, superficial.
Bouchard’s report contains so many examples of the feminist double
standard – attacking men for doing precisely what feminists have always
done – that we can provide only a summary of the more obvious ones here.
“A more detailed look at the groups behind the media discourse reveals
an extensive network using the Internet to become established and
entrenched and express its ideas. We have found a discourse of hate, often
violent and unchecked, directed at women and feminists. Far from being an
isolated case, this second level of discourse, which could be called
‘underground’ discourse, focusses on the same issues as the public
discourse, specifically fathers’ rights, but without any of the restraint shown
in the public discourse.”7 And feminists have not made similar use of the
Internet – even showcasing the violent screed of Valerie Solanas and her
Society for Cutting Up Men – for their own purposes?
“[T]he … authors of these articles tended to lump several male issues
together.”8And feminists have not done so? It would make no sense for
feminists to do otherwise, because one thing that binds all feminists
together is the belief that all their problems, specifically as women, are the
result of patriarchy (and, for some, of something innate in maleness itself).
“Masculinists are also attacking traditionally female employment
sectors, including health care and education, claiming that there are not
enough men in those sectors to serve as role models to understand male
issues. Their solution is to obtain jobs for men by hiring them in these
sectors.”9 And feminists do not make precisely the same claim: that women
need “role models,” or “mentors,” and must therefore be hired
preferentially in “male dominated” sectors?
“In this section,” according to the report, “we discuss the arguments on
which masculinists based their advocacy discourse and how they try to
convince the public, through the media, that the women’s movement has
made men victims of a new social system dominated by feminist values.”
Elsewhere, the authors complain that “masculinist groups know how to
derive maximum benefit from media coverage.”10 And feminists do not use
“the media” in their own attempts at “advocacy discourse”? They do not
know how to derive maximum benefit from media coverage – even when
they present mistaken statistics to the press?
“[M]asculinists are choosing to use political language and jump at any
opportunity to have their views published. Hey et al. … report that there
could be no movement in favour of boys before in Britain ‘because earlier
work had failed to construct a political language – and an activism – around
equity beyond competing claims about oppression.’”11 And feminists have
not jumped at every chance to publish their views? They have not
developed a “political” language in order to promote those views?
Elsewhere, we read about the “masculinist groups that are increasingly
forming national and international networks and feeding journalists
information related to recurring events, such as the release of marks on
national tests (here or abroad) and Suicide Prevention Week, or current
events, such as cases of spousal violence or spousal murders involving child
custody and fathers’ rights.”12 And feminists do not feed journalists stories
that promote their causes – and even feed them phony statistics
occasionally?
“But even worse than ‘women’ are feminists whom masculinists
ruthlessly attack. In particular, they denounce the ‘plot’ that feminists,
working in complicity with governments, judges, police officers and the
media, have supposedly hatched against fathers and men accused of
violence.”13 And feminists have not attacked men as the authors of a
prehistoric plot to overthrow a paradisal society under the benign aegis of a
Great Goddess and replace it with the oppression of patriarchy?14
We will discuss this topic in a separate book, tentatively called “Beyond
the Fall of Man.” For the time being, consider the work of two well-known
feminist academics: Marija Gimbutas and Gerda Lerner, along with several
“documentaries” widely shown on television that were produced by the
explicitly feminist wing of Canada’s National Film Board.15 All these
productions are explicitly based on the conspiracy theory of history.
Here are more examples of a double standard. “[The president of the
Groupe d’entraide aux pères et de soutien à l’enfant] … speaking as though
he represented all men, stated, ‘We are the feminists of the 1990s. We are
the ones who are calling for gender equality.”16 And the authors –
Bouchard, Boily, and Proulx – do not claim to speak as though they
represent all women? If not, how could they advise the government to
pursue a policy intended to benefit all women?
“These comments [advocating single-sex schools] reveal a narrow,
traditional view of gender relations in which girls are temptresses and boys
subject to their sexual impulses.”17 And feminists have not used this
strategy, arguing that boys are governed by their biological impulses (to be
either destructive or “aggressive”) and girls by their cultural conditioning
(to be either submissive or “nurturing”)? They certainly do, according to the
study done by Frederick Mathews for Health Canada.
It is not uncommon to hear male students express resentment
toward high school anti-violence curricula that presumes [sic]
them to be abusers, harassers, rapists and sexual assaulters in
waiting. Indeed, it is difficult to feel part of a collective social
movement against violence when one’s own experiences are
dismissed, excluded or minimized. It is evident from even a
casual review of this material that much of it contains biased
stereotypes and unchallenged assumptions about “male anger,”
“male aggression” and “male sexuality.” All too often, these
writers take as a starting point a caricature of the worst
imaginable elements of “masculinity” and assume it applies to all
male persons … If we want males to engage in true dialogue, then
we have to be open to hearing their criticisms, their experiences,
their pain.”18
“[A]mong other things [concern over the fate of boys in schools]
translates into the creation of ‘affirmative action’ programs.”19 And women
have not advocated affirmative action, relentlessly, for their own purposes?
Elsewhere, the authors add that masculinists
argue in particular for gender-based intervention (thereby denying
any diversity within each gender group), a return to single-sex
classes or schools, and the creation of new programs, or the
improvement of existing ones, in order to meet boys’ needs as
they see them. They want to increase the number of male teachers
in order to promote male identification. These solutions also
promote a return to traditional male values and the establishment
of quotas for admission to certain programs. The same criticism
levelled at the way the problem is identified can be made of the
solutions proposed. Why treat boys and girls differently, or
separate them, if one third of them at the most are having
problems at school while three fifths [?] are successful?20
And feminists have not advocated precisely the same measures for girls
(although feminists, at least those in Canada, usually prefer the euphemism
of “targets” instead of “quotas”)? Why treat the sexes differently? Because,
according to the standard feminist reply, the two are “differently situated.”
Besides, since when is one-third a trivial measure? If one-third of all girls
or women were having difficulty, or even one-quarter, all hell would break
loose.
“Therapy groups are interested in personal growth. Much of the
masculinist intervention scene involves their peer counselling activities,
‘12–step’ of this or that, healing groups, and ideas from the mythopoetic
movement of Robert Bly.”21 And feminists have not exploited, even
invented, the mania for pop psychology? Oprah Winfrey is not the role
model for millions of women? They did not glorify Princess Diana as a
royal guru of self-help therapy?
“Other sites maintained by men’s groups display direct threats to
feminists and their allies, and contain vicious comments.” Elsewhere, the
authors complain about a website that names Martin Dufresne,
“specifically, encourages people to harass him, and gives out his personal
contact information.”22 And feminists do not name names? This very report
includes a hit list of both individuals and groups. Although it does not urge
readers to intimidate them directly, it does urge the government to take
action against them.
Discussing men’s groups that write about home life, the report also states
that “[i]n this way men become the experts on analyzing the situation in the
private domain.” And feminists do not claim to be experts on both the
private domain (traditionally associated with women) and the public one
(traditionally associated with men)? Given the report’s hostility to any
claims of “traditional” society, we find it surprising, to say the least, that
they do indeed want to preserve expertise in the domestic domain for
women – even as they claim greater expertise than men in the public
domain (because feminism is primarily about the deconstruction of
patriarchy and thus relies on insights that originate with women). Not
surprisingly, we read on the next page that when “they [masculinists]
compare themselves to their female counterparts, they usually fail to
provide relevant data about women’s real situation.”23 And feminists are in
the habit of providing relevant – and correct – information about men’s real
situation? In that case, why is the “information” about men in this report so
dubious?
“Masculinists claim that there is far more research on breast cancer than
on prostate cancer (and therefore conclude that this is another example of
discrimination against men) because society allocates more resources to
breast cancer. In making this claim they turn cancer into a gendered illness
by reducing it to only two of its dimensions.” And feminists have not turned
some illnesses – heart disease, for one – into “gendered diseases”? The
passage continues as follows: “The reasons given by masculinists for men’s
shorter life expectancy are the stress, demands and responsibilities
associated with their role, factors that take their toll on men from their
earliest years. In their view, the past will inevitably be repeated in the
future. If we apply that hypothesis to the status of elderly women, it would
appear that a great many of them have experienced extremely trying times
during their lives.” Actually, it would do nothing of the kind. Because the
number of elderly women in relation to that of elderly men is so high, it
would appear that these women have not experienced extremely trying
times. The report recommends that “a network of experts in fields targeted
by masculinists should be formed to react to the misinformation campaign,
especially since the trigger events for this discourse are known.”24 Okay,
but how about a network of experts in fields targeted by feminists? The
trigger events – an obvious one being 6 December, a day set aside every
year in Canada to commemorate the women killed by Marc Lépine – are
certainly well known.
“The publication of gendered data must always be supported by analyses
that provide the context, since without it the data only fuel the masculinist
discourses.”25 Sure, but disaggregation works – or should work – both
ways. If so, it would certainly cause problems for feminists, whose work is
usually based on the premise that women are first and foremost a class, an
oppressed class, not merely parts of other classes.
“This network [monitoring expressions of hate against women] could
also be responsible for gaining a better understanding of how masculinist
groups are influencing policy makers, in order to make them aware of the
limitations and shortcomings of these discourses.”26 Yes, but the same
network should be responsible for gaining a better understanding of how
feminist groups – including those of Bouchard and her colleagues – are
influencing policymakers.
APPENDIX THIRTEEN
Take That! Comparative Victimology
One case study should illustrate the atmosphere in which the ideological
“discourse” on domestic violence, discussed in chapter 2, took place. We
refer to an issue of Victimology from the 1980s that was devoted
specifically to that problem.1Almost every argument used by two debaters,
who were reacting to an article by a third, is used to this day by ideological
feminists. In this respect, nothing has changed over the past twenty years.
The original article was written by Peter Neidig, who was director of
Behavioral Science Associates. He presented a view of domestic violence
based on his clinical experience as a family counsellor and identified
several assumptions that he considered not only unwarranted but also
counterproductive. His explicit aim was to promote professional “dialogue”
about domestic violence. Ellen Pence, of the Domestic Abuse Intervention
Project in Duluth, and Jeffrey Edleson, coordinator of research and
evaluation for the Domestic Abuse Project in Minneapolis, responded to his
article. Both were extremely hostile to Neidig and resorted to personal
attacks on his moral integrity. Clearly, dialogue was out of the question then
(and probably still is). These people were not able to “hear” each other any
more than Protestants and Catholics in Ireland were able to do so,
Anglophones and Fran-cophones in Quebec, or Israelis and Palestinians in
the Middle East. For Pence and Edleson, Neidig was not merely mistaken.
He was sinister. He was the enemy.2
Neidig described current research as “highly politicized in that those
providing the services are activists, deeply committed to a particular
analysis of the causes and means for redressing the social inequities
presumed to lie at the root of spouse abuse.”3 Most research focused
attention, he claimed, solely on one half of the troubled relationship:
researchers blamed only the men involved and even studied only the men.
“The typical research publications report the results of interview and/or
assessment data on women. This has led to an understanding of the abusive
relationship which is by definition biased and incomplete, and is at least
subject to limitations which occur when one attempts, no matter how
sincerely, to reconstruct from a one-sided account [what are] essentially
transactional phenomena.”4 More-over, the reports used were almost
entirely anecdotal; there were very few empirical studies.
The main purpose of Neidig’s paper was to discuss what he identified as
four underlying assumptions of researchers. “One of our own biases,” he
wrote, “is that individuals working in this field should attempt to articulate
as clearly as possible, both to themselves and to their clients, the principles
which guide their interventions.”5 This consideration was not merely
academic; it had very practical implications for evaluating treatment
programs, since we need to know which are value-based and which
empirically based. The latter are not completely objective, he admitted, but
they are at least relatively objective.
His differentiation exposed a raw nerve. In this field more than most,
researchers often have very heavy emotional investments at stake. “It seems
to us inescapable that therapists working in the field of spouse abuse will
adopt positions influenced largely by moral and political considerations.”6
These certainly influence the ways in which problems are conceptualized,
strategies developed, solutions defined, and so on. As Perry London pointed
out elsewhere,7 the extent to which therapists are confronted with moral
problems depends on the significance of the problems with which they
choose to involve themselves. He found it hard to imagine more significant
and more value laden ones than those involved in the treatment of domestic
violence.8
At any rate, Neidig identified four assumptions that should be
challenged. The first, which was adopted by the National Coalition against
Domestic Violence, is that the highest priority should be given to the
establishment of shelters for women and children, even though these had
already multiplied in the previous few years. “There can be little doubt,”
Neidig wrote, “that shelters do and should continue to play a vitally
important role in a comprehensive response to spouse abuse.”9 They play
not one role, however, but several. They have a symbolic function, for
instance, their mere existence making it clear to the entire community that
something is radically wrong. “Although there has been some question
about whether the continuation of sexual inequality contributes to spouse
abuse … or whether the recent increase in power realized by women
through the accomplishments of the feminist movement increases the
likelihood of wife abuse … we have taken the position that violence is most
likely to persist when the wife possesses significantly less power and fewer
resources than her husband.”10 But the most obvious function of the shelters
is providing emergency refuge. Most women stay only temporarily and then
return to their husbands. Nevertheless, Neidig claimed, a major aim of those
running the shelters is to promote separation of husband and wife. “It would
seem that this is the primary function as it is conceptualized by those in the
shelter movement. In fact, anything less than a total and permanent
termination of the marriage seems to be viewed as a failure.”11
The second common assumption challenged by Neidig is that marriage
and family therapies do more harm than good. Some experts believe that
marriage counselling, or any other therapy based on participation by both
husband and wife, is ineffective at best and dangerous at worst. Although he
maintained that therapies of this kind are potentially useful and should not
be abandoned out of hand, he admitted that they can sometimes be
dangerous. As Lenore Walker had pointed out on Nightline, for example,
professional therapists often have such a high commitment to preserving the
family unit that they will try to avoid a breakup even when that is the best
solution. As D. Adams and I. Penn had pointed out, moreover, husbands
might seek revenge if their wives divulge the intimate details of their
married lives.12
Other experts accuse male therapists of being ideologically and
politically dangerous, of harbouring sexist notions of female inferiority or
innate female masochism and promoting patriarchy merely by supporting
institutions such as marriage and the family. Walker and others have
consequently claimed that only women should treat women, and Zak
Mettger has consequently argued that only women should treat violent
men.13
Still other experts, wrote Neidig, attack marriage or family counselling
for giving the impression that women as well as men are involved in
generating violence or that abuse is an interactional problem. This
impression, they believe, would allow abusive men to imagine that the guilt
is not entirely their own. Behind this attack is the third common assumption
identified by Neidig: that spousal abuse is always the man’s fault, that the
source of all conflict resides within him alone. He is the only one, therefore,
who should change. Ideologues believe that the primary cause of any man’s
violent behaviour is the internalization of sexist notions prevalent in society
– the belief that women are inferior to men, say, or that hitting women is
acceptable. Many psychologists, on the other hand, believe that the primary
cause is a man’s inability to deal with his own psychopathological
problems: impulsiveness, low self-esteem, poor communication, poor stress
management, and so on. Neidig identified two reasons why treatment
programs for violent men almost always make this assumption.
First, they need to reject the idea of blaming the victim by suggesting
that abused wives somehow “ask for it.”14 As long as this approach is
taken, domestic violence can be seen as a rare phenomenon that results
from a neurotic relationship and be given over to psychiatrists who would
uncover the “real” meaning.
Second, most of the research on domestic violence has been based solely
on interviews with victimized women. “At the risk of belaboring the
obvious,” wrote Neidig, “spouse abuse is by definition an interpersonal
transaction. It is violence that occurs in the context of an ongoing
relationship (marriage). The behaviour of each individual within a marriage
is dependent upon the behaviour of the other and each behavior can be
thought of as both a cause and an effect depending on how the interactional
sequence is ‘punctuated.’” Because sympathy should be with the victim, it
might be difficult to acknowledge that every abusive event is experienced
and interpreted in two ways. “It would seem reasonable to assume,” wrote
Neidig, “that women, in their effort to organize, understand and
communicate their experiences in an abusive situation would tend to
‘punctuate’ the sequence of events in such a way as to introduce a bias into
the narration. Again, regardless of how sincere the interviewer and the
subject are, the portrayal would at best be incomplete.” Neidig noted that
there were striking linguistic similarities in reports from abused women and
that after a while the interviewers could finish sentences for them. “It of
course has enormous therapeutic significance whether these
characterizations are a valid description of the violence sequence itself or
are rather a valid description of one way of experiencing or punctuating the
violence sequence.”15
Finally, the fourth common assumption – and the most important –
identified by Neidig is the obvious but almost always ignored fact that
“from a political standpoint, it makes much more sense to define the issue
rather narrowly and to present it in terms of ‘victims and villains.’ To talk
about domestic violence which includes child abuse (which is frequently
engaged in by mothers), or to belabor the fact that women act violently
toward men about as frequently as men act violently toward women … is to
dull the sharp focus required for an effective political movement. However,
what might be a good basis for a political strategy is not necessarily a good
basis for therapeutic intervention.” The assumption that the causes of
domestic violence reside only in the husband’s mind has had several
negative effects on treatment programs. If the actors are assigned “fixed
roles variously labelled as the ‘victim and the batterer’ or the ‘victim and
the perpetrator,’” the former might be tempted to seek revenge and the latter
might be tempted to identify themselves with the label assigned to them.16
Neidig’s own bias
when conceptualizing spouse abuse is to define it as a relationship
issue with both parties participating (although not necessarily
participating equally) in the violence sequence. We tend to reject
labels “abuser” and “victim,” believing that neither partner has an
exclusive right to either term. In fact, it seems perfectly
reasonable although incomplete, that both parties could punctuate
the sequence in such a way as to feel victimized. We define
abusiveness as learned behavior which is frequently a desperate
but ineffective (in the long run) way of effecting behavior change.
In our analysis … violence does not occur instantaneously or
unpredictably, but rather it is an interpersonal behavior pattern
which couples can learn to control once they learn to discriminate
certain “cues” and acquire relevant skills.17
Nevertheless, it is often assumed that changes in a man’s attitude lead to
changes in his behaviour. Neidig claimed that this was an assumption of
Emerge, a men’s counselling group in Boston, and of virtually every other
therapy program designed for abusive men. Following the work of Russell
Dobash and Rebecca Dobash, most therapy programs assumed that
domestic violence would not be eliminated either until the patriarchal
structure of the family and the conditions that kept women subordinate were
destroyed or, following the work of Andrew McCormack, until the belief by
individual men in male supremacy was corrected.18 But Neidig found more
evidence to support the reverse argument: that changes in a man’s
behaviour lead to changes in his attitude. He referred to the work not only
of Albert Bandura, E.G. Blanchard, and R. Ritter but also of Leon
Festinger. ”Our own experience suggests that a skill building approach
which attempts primarily to change behaviours results in a marked
reduction of violent episodes and significant change as reflected in pre- and
post-program administrations of measures of locus of control and marital
adjustment.”19
Neidig was more interested in the cause of change than in the
chronology of change, which led to his interest in the ideology of these
men’s groups.
The basic premise of their approach is that men are socialized to
adopt the attitude that abuse is an acceptable and normal male
behaviour engaged in to maintain dominance over females. It is
this attitude which must be changed in order to eliminate
violence. There are three conditions (attitudes) “that lead directly
to woman abuse”: a man must believe that he has the right to beat
a woman, believe that it is a legitimate way of solving problems,
and believe that he needs to maintain his dominant position vis-à-
vis a woman … If it is true that abusive men do in fact subscribe
to these attitudes, then one would be inclined to agree with the
men’s collectives that the process of eliminating violence is going
to be slow going and that the prognosis would have to be
considered guarded at best.20
But in fact, Neidig observed, research had failed to support these
assumptions.
Measures of dogmatism and rigidity (The D Scale), attitudes
toward self (The Coopersmith Self-Esteem Inventory), attitudes
towards others (The Generalized Expectations of Others
Questionnaire) have all failed to discriminate [between men and
women] or at best have resulted only in statistically significant
differences with little or no practical, predictive application. Only
those measures which are more closely related to behavior as
opposed to attitudinal variables seem to be very promising
(measures of stress, assertiveness, and marital adjustment). The
one measure on which both males and females engaged in
domestic violence consistently differ from non-violent controls is
that of the locus of control. Thus, if the presumed differences in
attitudes exist, we have failed thus far to detect them, and in our
review of the literature we can find no reports of anyone else
having empirically verified these attitude differences.
Additionally, in screening something over one hundred couples
who have engaged in domestic violence for our spouse abuse
rehabilitation program … we have yet to encounter a single
individual who believes that “he has a right to beat a woman.”
That is not to say that we have not heard a vast array of excuses,
denials, rationalizations and other defensive maneuvers. However,
at least as we interpret it, the extent of the defensiveness supports
the view that abusive males generally ascribe [sic] to the
prevailing norm which defines violence against family members
as unacceptable. These men continue to engage in abusive
behavior not because they believe it is right but because they lack
the skills to do otherwise and are subsequently able to avoid
responsibility, maintain a sense of being victimized, and
neutralize the inhibiting effect of disapproval by self and others
through the extensive use of various defense mechanisms.21
In other words, precisely because they know that beating women is not
morally acceptable, they must find excuses to justify their behaviour.
In their response to Neidig, both Pence and Edleson challenged his claim
that “shelters serve as a resource for effecting a permanent break from the
spouse … anything less than a total and permanent termination of the
marriage seems to be viewed as a failure.”22 This approach, according to
Neidig, left many questions that participants in the shelter movement could
not answer.
The unpredictability and seemingly self-defeating behaviour of
many battered wives “has produced both cynicism and frustration
among the professionals dealing with them” … An indirect
measure of how distressing it may be when women choose to
employ the shelter as a temporary refuge rather than as a means to
establish their independence from the marriage is suggested by
the number of theoretical explanations offered for this
[phenomenon]. Learned helplessness … exchange theory …
attribution theory … locus of control … and the “complex pushes
and pulls of numerous forces” … have all been cited in the
literature.23
For Neidig, the explanation was much simpler: the goal of those seeking
help (temporary refuge) is often inconsistent with those of the people who
run shelters (permanent independence).
Although Neidig immediately went on to say that this inconsistency
“does not diminish in any way the value of shelters,” he had probably
oversimplified the matter. In the first place, as Pence observed, the gulf
between those who find refuge in the shelters and those who run them can
easily be exaggerated. The latter are very often drawn from the ranks of the
former and are not merely professionals acting on the basis of abstract
ideological positions. Furthermore,
it is important to acknowledge that we are in the business of
rescuing. Neidig says that we set up shelters to rescue women
from their marriages. We say that we rescue women from
violence. We live in a society which decorates policemen, firemen
and concerned citizens for rescuing people from burning
buildings or raging floods. But when women rescue other women
from life-threatening violent situations at the hands of their
husbands or lovers, suddenly rescuing is equated to home
wrecking. To separate is also not a negative term to those in the
battered women’s movement. The function of battering is to
dominate and control. We offer women a space, separate and safe.
We offer a space separate from violence, from threats, from
intimidation, a separate place of self-definition … Not all shelters
measure success in the same ways, but none of those people
contributing to this response knew of a single shelter which
ensured success in terms of a permanent break in the marriage.
Shelters are in the business of helping women end violence
against them, not ending marriages.24
Edleson objected also to the way that Neidig had polarized those who
work in the field of domestic violence.25 “He seems to classify the
thousands of practitioners and hundreds of researchers in this area of work
into two groups: family therapists and ‘others.’” But no position, wrote
Edleson, was common to everyone in either category. Neidig had
succumbed to reductionism. Multiplicity had been reduced to duality. There
were those, such as Dobash and Dobash, who took an ideological and
activist approach. There were also those, such as Neidig, who saw violence
as one element among others. And there were those, such as Edleson
himself, who took a “social learning” approach and tried to resocialize
violent men. Moreover, there were those who combined all three
approaches. “The important point here is that Neidig presents this widely
divergent group of researchers and practitioners as one group united in its
opposition to family therapy. It is a misrepresentation of the field to do so.
This area of clinical practice and research is, contrary to what Neidig states,
full of greatly varied and hotly contested issues.”26
But Edleson overstated his case in the opposite direction. Are there
really no general assumptions to link those working in the field? Is every
women’s shelter and every men’s therapy group unique in its approach? If
so, how could we even refer to a women’s shelter “movement” or a men’s
therapy “movement”? How could we explain the fact that many of the
men’s groups explicitly acknowledge their ideological debt to pioneering
efforts such as Emerge?27 Having recognized that Neidig ignored the
diversity in this field, we should still be able to recognize that some
generalizations are necessary for us to say anything at all. The fact that
Neidig had tried to identify trends, moreover, does not imply that he had
been consciously or unconsciously trying to distort reality.
Edleson made an effort to downplay the influence of the ideologues who
really do see marriage and the family as inherently oppressive for women.
A few individual shelter staff members may seek to permanently
separate every battered woman from her male partner. It is a gross
misinterpretation to attribute such goals to all of the thousands of
shelter workers in the United States. The major goals of most
shelters in this country are to provide safe refuges to the victims
of family violence and to help insure that such violence ends or
that, at a minimum, the victims need no longer to be subjected to
such violence. In many cases, this may mean helping a woman
fight for a legal separation and divorce. In other cases – probably
the majority – it means helping the woman bring community
pressure to bear on the man in order to persuade him to end his
violent behaviour. In any event, the goal of most interventions in
families where violence occurs is to bring about the permanent
cessation of violence.28 His point is well taken. Even if shelter
workers believed that divorce is preferable to reconciliation, after
all, they would not necessarily foist their opinions on women who
come to them seeking temporary refuge. And even if Neidig had
been correct in arguing that most shelter workers are predisposed
on ideological grounds to breaking up marriages that could be
saved, Pence and Edleson would be correct in replying that he
was predisposed on professional grounds to saving marriages that
should be ended. Although he had noted that shelters perform
several other extremely useful functions, he had also given the
impression that their value is severely limited by the ideological
convictions of those who run them.
If Pence and Edleson were correct in observing an underlying hostility
toward the shelters, then Neidig was justly rebuked. But they, no less than
he, contributed to the polarization. Both Pence and Edelson consistently
chose to interpret his words in the worst possible light. Occasionally, they
even ignored evidence to the contrary. Pence referred, for example, to
Neidig’s claim that “prior to 1970, there was almost no literature to be
found on the subject [of domestic violence] ‘except for psychiatrically
oriented discussions on sadomasochistic marital relationships.’”29 On the
contrary, she argued, “a review of history books would certainly yield a
more consistent reference to this historical practice used by men against
their wives. In fact, literally hundreds of references to the function of ‘wife
beating’ as a link between the institution of marriage and property laws in
Western civilization can be easily documented.”30 Neidig had referred only,
of course, to the social science literature. Consider the line immediately
preceding the one quoted by Pence: “The development of the ‘field’ of
spouse abuse has occurred rapidly.”31 By accusing Neidig of ignoring
history itself, Pence tried to establish an image of him as someone who
deliberately distorted truth. Moreover, the facts contained in history books
do not prove her claim that wife beating has been “part of a systematic use
of violence against women to maintain male privilege and status.”32 That
was her interpretation of history.
Pence accused Neidig of hypocrisy, too, arguing that he had denied the
need for political analysis but was himself “political” (which is to say,
politically opportunistic).
Mr. Neidig states that the current literature is politicized in that
those providing services to battered women and batterers are
“activists.” Since battering is seen by many activists not as a
transactional phenomenon as Mr. Neidig maintains, but as an “act
of power and dominance,” it is reasonable to assume that much of
the literature would have some suggestion of “political analysis.”
It is political for Mr. Neidig to choose phrases such as “violent
couples,” “abusive relationships,” “spouse abuse” and “domestic
conflict” rather than to name the person using the violence as the
assailant or batterer.33
Yes, but it was surely just as politically opportunistic to do what she did in
her own essay. By using labels such as “batterer,” for example, she reduced
the husband from a human being, albeit a seriously flawed and dangerous
one, to a demon like an enemy in wartime. The Americans did not fight
against the Japanese or the Vietnamese, after all; they fought against “Japs”
and “Gooks.” Dehumanizing an enemy might be practical, but is it morally
acceptable? Pence added that “it is political to ignore that the gender of the
person injured is almost always female.” It is surely just as politically
expedient, though, to ignore studies of domestic violence in which the
injured party is male.34 Pence would have known about them, even in 1984,
had she not been blinded by her own ideology.
Pence argued that Neidig was cynical for suggesting that men were
stereotyped for reasons of political expediency.35 But what if the problem
goes much deeper than that? Far from being too cynical, Neidig might have
been too naive. People who insist on discussing domestic violence in
dualistic terms, after all, are not necessarily opportunists. They might
sincerely believe that domestic violence is, apart from anything else, a
symbolic statement about the relation between men and women in general
and, indeed, about history itself. In that case, women are the paradigmatic
innocent victims and men the paradigmatic evil oppressors. To question this
belief, as Neidig did, is not merely to challenge a political strategy but to
challenge the identity of those feminists who define themselves in
opposition to men (or of male feminists, for that matter, who define
themselves in opposition to “those other” men.) If women are implicated in
any way with evil, then they are not really so very different from men.
According to Pence, Neidig had argued that “many of those working on
the issue of battering have been duped by reading too many anecdotal
accounts of battering by women who tend to ‘punctuate the event’ in an
understandably biased way. The age-old woman hating declaration rears its
ugly head: women are not physically and sexually oppressed in this
country; women lie.”36 But Neidig had said nothing of the kind. He had
never suggested, either directly or indirectly, that they lie, at least not more
often than men do. What he had claimed was merely that women (like all
human beings at all times and in all places) interpret reality. Pence herself
was clearly adept at interpreting things, reading into Neidig’s words what
she, as a feminist, believed he must have had in mind. With her, in fact, it
was the age-old polarization of ideology that had reared its ugly head.
Those who believe that they can provide effective therapies for violent
men, assuming that the latter are seriously disturbed and not normal, want
every piece of information they can find. But those who believe, as Pence
did, that domestic violence can be explained in ideological and moralistic
terms have less interest in therapy (except insofar as it is necessary for a
woman’s safety). The model is crime, then, not biology. Pence argued that
violent husbands should be locked up like any other criminals. Arrest with
no treatment of any kind, she believed, had proven to be at least a short-
term deterrent. Likewise, Edleson wrote that “violence by a man against his
wife is a crime and the perpetrator of this violence should be treated as
such. To speak of ‘transactions’ is to ignore that a crime has been
committed by one person against another. Such a position seems to
perpetuate long held beliefs and social norms … that somehow violence by
a man towards his spouse is exempt from current laws concerning
interpersonal violence.”37 Like Neidig, however, Edleson worked as a
therapist with men convicted of domestic violence. He surely believed that
this criminal behaviour was linked in some way with psychopathology.
Otherwise, the treatment he offered could have been reduced to lessons in
morality or sociological analysis.
Besides, Neidig had never suggested, either directly or indirectly, that
wife beaters should be considered innocent and protected from the law. The
topic under discussion by Neidig had been neither morality nor legality,
after all, but therapy. Domestic violence does involve crime, and
incarceration might be necessary. But what about a long-term solution? To
prevent violence, it would be necessary to understand what causes it.
Because Pence believed in a gynocentric ideology, however, the possibility
that she could ever understand men was extremely remote.
But – and this is very important – it was not enough for Pence to observe
that men afflict women. She was convinced that they want to do so, that
doing so seems to men an end in itself. According to her, “the battered
women’s movement has always asserted that assailants choose to batter –
that they are very much in control of the target, the timing, the extent of
injuries and the psychological terrorism accompanying the assault.”38 But if
men are so much in control, why are so many who engage in these activities
either drunk or stoned at the time?39 Pence did not ask this question, but
from her perspective only one answer would have been possible: that they
deliberately choose to become drunk or stoned in order to have a
convenient excuse for their behaviour. But if they are so convinced by the
cultural norms of our society that attacking women is perfectly acceptable
behaviour, why would they need this excuse in the first place? That
question presupposes complexity and ambiguity in the attitudes toward
women of both society in general and men in particular. Are men really so
preoccupied with women that they would drink themselves into oblivion or
become addicted to drugs merely to provide themselves with a cover for
experiencing the secret joy of assaulting women – even though, according
to the very people who take this position, men are openly encouraged to do
so? Pence believed that these men are evil, not sick. And because their
behaviour is not idiosyncratic but actively promoted by patriarchal
institutions, she believed that all men are evil unless they repent and convert
to feminism. She believed that they deserve punishment, consequently, not
therapy.
Concerning the treatment groups designed for violent men, as
exemplified by Emerge, Neidig wrote that “the concept of attitude change
has been the hallmark.” “The basic premise of their approach,” according to
Neidig, “is that men are socialized to adopt the attitude that abuse is an
acceptable and normal male behaviour engaged in to maintain dominance
over females. It is this attitude which must be changed in order to eliminate
violence.”40 Although it is obvious that boys and men are socialized in
many ways to be violent – standard examples are what they see at the
movies or on television, what kind of toys are sold to them, and what they
know of their potential role as soldiers – it is by no means obvious that they
are socialized to be violent in order to persecute women. That is a
gynocentric and ideological assumption that Neidig correctly questioned.
As for Emerge, Edleson dismissed its influence by arguing that “this is
another example of Neidig’s gross over-generalizations about a diverse
group of practitioners and researchers.” It is true that there are many
programs, that these are organized by many agencies, and that they are
based on many approaches. “To hypothesize that a unitary set of
assumptions are held by an entire field made up of such diverse elements is,
to say the least, a superficial treatment of the subject.”41 Yes, but to ignore
widely held assumptions on the grounds that they are not actually universal
must lead to an equally superficial treatment of any topic.
Instead of dealing with the problem identified by Neidig, Edleson went
on to criticize his second assumption: that a psychological (as distinct from
a philosophical) “attitude change must precede behaviour change.”42 On
this matter, Neidig had probably erred. Edleson pointed out that “contrary to
what Neidig has stated … the first goal of most programs for men who
batter is to take steps to help the men change their violent behaviour.”43
This would indeed be more consistent with the primary aim of closely allied
women’s shelters: providing safety.
Both Pence and Edleson attacked Neidig for suggesting that a man’s use
of violence against a woman is “interpersonal” or “transactional,” that both
the male and female “shared responsibility.”44 The real question for both
Pence and Edleson, as it still is for ideological feminists, was, Who is to
blame? For Pence and Edleson, Neidig seemed to suggest not only that
husbands are somehow innocent when hitting their wives but also that
wives are somehow guilty for being hit. Neidig did write about
“responsibility,” but this word can be used in connection with both moral
agency and causality. No one can legitimately be held morally responsible
for the act of another. Moral responsibility is governed by at least three
factors: freedom of choice, motivation, and knowledge of the consequences.
A husband is morally responsible for hitting his wife, to be sure, if he is free
to refrain from doing so, if he consciously intends to injure her, and if he
knows what could happen to her (and himself) if he does. He is not morally
responsible to the extent that he is pathologically deranged,45 morally
incompetent, or mentally incompetent. A wife, on the other hand, could be
held morally responsible for the violence of her husband only if she
somehow forced him to strike her, a most unlikely scenario. But the
situation is more complicated than that. If a husband does something evil
for which he alone is morally responsible, why must we assume that his
wife is a paragon of virtue? Even though a wife cannot be legitimately held
morally responsible for the behaviour of her husband, she surely can be
legitimately held morally responsible for her own behaviour. If her husband
hits her, he alone is guilty for that. But if she has humiliated him or shamed
him in some other way, then she is guilty for that. Unless we assume that
wives are incapable of malice, greed, manipulation, hypocrisy, selfishness,
or any other human failing – and this is contrary to the observation of
everyday life by virtually everyone – it makes no sense to rule out this
possibility. That would create a false dichotomy. Thus, it is at least possible
that the acrimonious debate in Victimology was caused by ideological
thinking on the part of Pence (projecting a generalized dichotomy between
good and evil onto women and men respectively) and not by sexist
perversity on the part of Neidig.
It is worth pausing here, briefly, to note a double standard that was, and
is, common in our society. When men hurt women, it is sometimes said, no
account whatever need be taken of mitigating circumstances; no matter how
provocative the woman’s behaviour, she is an innocent victim. Apparently,
though, the reverse does not hold. This was made clear in one segment of
the ABC program 20/20, aired in March 1993.46 When Jean Harris went to
prison for shooting her lover, Herman Tarnower, she received widespread
support as “a woman wronged.” Tarnower, you see, was an unpleasant
fellow. Moreover, he had thrown her aside for another woman. According
to Harris’s supporters, her behaviour was morally, though not legally,
acceptable. Shortly after Harris’s release from prison, Barbara Walters
reminded viewers that “hundreds of [women had] rallied to her defense,
repeatedly petitioning the governor of New York for her release.” In fact,
Walters noted, Harris had told her parole board that “Tarnower could have
prevented this if he had just been a little different that night.”47 In other
words, the (male) victim deserved to be killed.
At any rate, Pence went on to dismiss Neidig’s finding that the attitude
of abusive men toward women might not be a crucial factor in domestic
violence. “It is not surprising,” she wrote, “that Neidig’s tests on batterers
would show no appreciable difference in negative attitudes towards women
by batterers compared to the general population. We live in a culture which
is hostile and negative toward women. Few would agree that batterers can
be singled out as having any kind of monopoly on woman hating.”48 This,
too, was an ideological assumption on her part. To be sure, this culture is
hostile and negative to women in many ways. But in other ways, it has
placed women on the proverbial pedestal. And in still other ways, as we
discussed in Spreading Misandry, it is hostile and negative to men as well.
Pence believed, on the other hand, that women have a monopoly on
suffering (and, by implication, on innocence).
Feminists have clearly learned a great deal about the needs and problems
of women. But it could be argued also that they have concealed the fact that
men have their own needs and problems. This has led at one extreme to a
gynocentric ideology, in which the universe revolves around women. On
that basis, it is easy to assume that men, too, must be gynocentric. If men
hurt women, it must be because they hate women. And if they hate women,
it must be because their universe revolves around revulsion for women. It
never occurred to Pence that men might have needs and problems having
little or nothing to do with women. Given her ideological perspective, it is
not surprising that Pence discounted any evidence that contradicted her own
beliefs. That is because ideology, like religion, is self-validating.
Pence concluded by pointing out that above all else, Mr. Neidig’s
article is a precious piece of male privilege. Through casual
observation, he presumes to define the assumptions and politics
of essentially a women’s movement which is constantly growing
and changing. Under the guise of professional neutrality and
scientific rigor, he pretends fiction to be truth. The poverty of his
arguments are [sic] a measure of his lack of responsibility to his
readers and battered women; calling it an invitation to dialogue in
an international journal committed to improving the problems
facing victims of crime is evidence of his privilege.”49
The same arguments, however, could have been used against Pence herself.
The moral authority of her movement, too, confers privilege. She believed
that disagreement is tantamount to misogyny, after all, which amounted to
an implicit form of intimidation. Neidig had presumed to define the
assumptions and politics of the women’s shelter movement (but more
specifically those of the men’s collectives associated with it), to be sure, but
Pence presumed to define the assumptions and politics of all men
throughout history! There is no evidence whatsoever to indicate that Neidig
had been irresponsible toward either his professional readers or battered
women. He had suggested ways of treating more effectively the men who
batter them. Ideological compromise would be a small price to pay for any
improvement in the situation, especially for a movement that, according to
Pence, is constantly growing and changing. Given her implicit belief that
men are evil and women good, it is difficult to feel sympathy for her
complaint about this or that oversimplified belief held by Neidig. In fact, it
is her belief that looks like speculative fiction, not Neidig’s belief that
domestic violence is a complex problem requiring an attempt to move
beyond self-righteousness.
In that spirit, Neidig had called for dialogue rather than monologue. “As
is often the case when treatment efforts are applied to a recently discovered
condition, good intentions and the desire to be of help have outdistanced
our thorough understanding of the problem and how it may most effectively
be ameliorated. This situation is inevitable given our current state of
ignorance and does not suggest that intervention efforts should cease.
Rather, an attitude of modesty and the avoidance of doctrinaire positions
should prevail. At this point, we have more to fear from an unwarranted
sense of unanimity and closure than we do from open dialogue and
disagreement.”50 Edleson responded as follows:
Neidig has done a disservice to those practitioners and researchers
he has stereotyped. He has distorted the positions of many and
generalized the positions of few to an entire group. He has
attributed certain beliefs to all of the many perspectives
represented when there is often great disagreement among the
groups. Far from creating open dialogue, he has attacked those
who legitimately question the placement of preserving
relationships before physical safety and the cessation of violence.
Neidig’s allusion to family therapists as the white knights fighting
the misled is only self-aggrandizing fantasy. His article reflects
the opposite of the “modesty and the avoidance of doctrinaire
positions” that he calls for in his conclusion. Let us hope that the
rich and varied debate that has marked this field from the start
continues on a more scholarly level than that represented in the
work by Neidig.51
The fact is, however, that Edleson was in no position to accuse Neidig of
attacking those who disagree with him. His response to Neidig’s article
hardly welcomed scholarly inquiry. On the contrary, it was one of
contemptuous dismissal. The aim of both Pence and Edleson was simply to
attack Neidig, not to take his challenge seriously. Instead of trying to
answer the questions he raised, they attacked his scholarly and moral
integrity. As a result, the level of discussion never moved beyond
defensiveness and self-righteousness. If dialogue between men and women
is ever to take place, let alone reconciliation, we will have to discard the
model of two competing monologues.
By definition, dialogue is a conversation. In the context of everyday life
and in literature, it is usually conversation between two people. In other
contexts however, it is conversation between two communities that are
divided by conflict but interested in reconciliation as well or, at the very
least, negotiation. The aim is not to erase differences, to convert the other,
but to build mutual respect in spite of differences. Unlike debate, dialogue
assumes the continuing presence of two voices, not one. It assumes at least
the possibility of reconciliation, not the necessity of submission by one side
to the other. Although, as Pence and Edleson showed, Neidig had not
always “heard” what was being done by others in the field, they themselves
did not always “hear” what he was saying. And Pence was either unable or
unwilling even to listen. Patricia Pearson sums up the larger gender debate
as follows:
By the late 1980s, activists and scholars within the battered
women’s movement had grown markedly more militant about the
inherent distinctions between men and women … If women were
inherently blameless, it followed with mounting conviction that
men were inherently blameworthy, to the point where any
investigation of their motives was denounced as providing them
with “an excuse.” Childhood abuse wasn’t relevant, because it
was an excuse. So were individual pathologies, marital dynamics,
and personal circumstances until the whole field of inquiry was
blocked. In Canada, the final report of a multimillion-dollar
government panel on violence against women, which canvassed
experts from across the nation for several years, concluded in
1993: “If [a man] abuses his wife, it is because he has the
privilege and the means to do so.” Ten million dollars to cough up
a cliché. Those who advise policy makers in the United States had
their views summed up in Ms magazine’s 1994 special issue on
wife beating: “Researchers are now beginning to examine the
batterers,” wrote Ann Jones. “It’s the same old crap. Nobody
wants to admit that men do this because they like to. What began
as a nuanced discussion of one of the most volatile arenas of
human relating had been reduced to a bigoted creed. Men are evil.
Women are good. Domestic violence is wife beating, and any man
who finds himself at the receiving end of a woman’s fist is a liar
or a freak.”52
Notes

INTRODUCTION

1 At the age of 20, Canadian dropout rates were much higher for men
than for women. This gender difference remained at the age of 22:
15% for men and only 8% for women (“Youth in Transition Survey:
Education and Labour Market Pathways of Young Adults,” [dated]
2002, Statistics Canada: The Daily, [visited] 16 June 2004,
<http://www.statcanca/Daily/English/today/d04061b.htm>: 3. The
American dropout rate in 2001 for those 16 to 24 years old was 12.2%
for men and 9.3% for women (“Dropout Rates,” [dated] 2003,
National Center for Education Statistics, [visited] 16 June 2004,
<http://nces.ed.gov/fastfacts/display/asp?id=15>: 1.
2 Consider these American sex ratios based on the census of 2000: 3
males for every female between the ages of 10 and 14 commit suicide;
5 males for every female between 15 and 19; and 7 males for every
female between 20 and 24 (“Resources for Researchers and Program
Evaluators,” [undated], National Strategy for Suicide Prevention,
[visited] 16 March 2004,
<http://www.mentalhealth.samhsa.gov/suicideprevention/colltoaction.a
sp>: 3). In Canada, the suicide rate for young men has been increasing
more rapidly than the rate for other age groups and more than the rate
for young women (Antoon A. Leenaars, and others, Suicide in Canada
[Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1998], 38). In the United States,
suicide “was the 8th leading cause of death for males and 19th leading
cause of death for females … More men than women die by suicide.
The gender ratio is 4:1; 73% of all suicide deaths are white males”
(“Suicide Facts,” [updated] 23 December 2003, National Institute of
Mental Health, [visited] 12 March 2004,
<http://www.nimh.nih.gov/research/suifact.cfm>: 1). “From their
pattern of ebb and flow, Canada’s suicide rates can be seen to shadow
those of its neighbour to the south, but since the 1970s Canadian rates
have surpassed those of the United States … [although] their rates are
not far apart.”(Leenaars and others, 37). For more details on suicide,
see chapter 6, note 52.
3 Canadian Bar Association, Task Force on Gender Equality in the
Legal Profession, Touchstones for Change: Equality, Diversity, and
Accountability: The Report on Gender Equality in the Legal
Profession (Ottawa: Canadian Bar Association, 1993) 270–1.

CHAPTER ONE

1 Ellen Bass and Laura Davis, The Courage to Heal: A Guide for
Women Survivors of Child Sexual Abuse (New York: Harper and Row,
1988) 21.
2 Carol Tavris, “Pursued by Fashionable Furies,” review of Hystories,
by Elaine Showalter, New York Times Book Review, 4 May 1997: 28.
3 Mary deYoung, “The Devil Goes to Day Care: McMartin and the
Making of a Moral Panic,” Journal of American Culture 20.1 (spring
1997): 19.
4 DeYoung 21.
5 N. Brozan; quoted in deYoung 23.
6 Carol Milstone, “Sybil Minds,” Saturday Night, September 1997: 35–
42.
7 Elizabeth Gleick, “All in the Head,” review of Memory Wars, by
Frederick Crews, and Hystories: Hysterical Epidemics and Modern
Culture, by Elaine Showalter, Time (Canadian edition), 7 July 1997:
44–6.
8 Milstone 38.
9 Milstone 40.
10 Judith Levine, Harmful to Minors: The Perils of Protecting Children
from Sex (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2002).
11 Kevin Cullen, “More than 80 Percent of Victims Since 1950 Were
Male, Report Says,” [dated] 28 February 2004, Boston Globe, [visited]
9 March 2004,
<http://www.boston.com/blobe/spotlight/abuse/stories5/022804_victi
ms.htm>.
12 According to a study completed in 2004, 4,392 clergymen (almost all
of them priests) were accused of abusing 10,667 people. Even though
pedophilia is often said to have been rampant among the clergy, no
more than 4% of Catholic priests, most of them multiple offenders,
were involved, according to this study. Commissioned by the National
Review Board of American Bishops, it was released on 27 February
2004. Agostino Bono, “John Jay Study Reveals Extent of Abuse
Problem,” [undated], American Catholic.org, [visited] 9 March 2004,
<http://www.americancatholic.org/default.asp>.
13 Elaine Showalter, Hystories: Hysterical Epidemics and Modern
Culture (New York: Columbia University Press, 1997) 12; Stephen
Rae, “John Mack,” New York Times Magazine 20 March 1994: 30–3.
Parallels between stories of sexual molestation and alien abductions
have been noted by Thomas M. Disch in The Dreams Our Stuff Is
Made Of: How Science Fiction Conquered the World (New York: Free
Press 1998).
14 Rae 33–4.
15 Carl Sagan; quoted in Rae 33.
16 “Are We Alone?” 48 Hours, CBS, WCAX-TV, Burlington,VT, 20 April
1994.
17 At first Freud took seriously the idea that some of his patients had
actually been the victims of incest. Later he changed his mind and
argued that most cases of incest occur only in the imagination and not
in real life. This is one reason for current feminist hostility to Freud.
18 Tavris 28. The author does acknowledge that some symptoms can look
like hysteria but nonetheless have organic causes.
19 DeYoung 23.
20 Richard M. Gardner, Sex Abuse Hysteria: The Salem Witch Trials
Revisited (Cresskill, NJ: Creative Therapeutics, 1991).
21 Levine 20–44.
22 See Bass and Davis.
23 Showalter; quoted in Gleick 43.
24 DeYoung 23.
25 Gleick 45.
26 Frederick Crews is not so moderate. In The Memory Wars (New York:
New York Review of Books, 1995) this lapsed Freudian and his
colleagues attack the credulity fostered by psychiatry. Had it not been
for Freudian “demonology,” he argues, its “hyperactive young
successor” would never have occurred. In the last analysis, millions of
people were perfectly prepared to believe the most bizarre and
shocking stories that had no basis in fact. Where, he asks, is the
evidence backing up psychoanalytical theory? “But if Freud was a
charlatan, psychoanalysis pure babble, and repression nonexistent,“
writes Gleick, “then Crews must dismiss the more interesting
questions: What do our society’s obsessions with child abuse, or
satanic rituals, or aliens, really mean?” (Gleick 46).
27 DeYoung 22. In Canada, the situation is even worse. Canadian officials
have still not acknowledged the enormity of professional complicity in
a witch hunt. The Saskatchewan government said on 8 January 2004
that “it would not apologize to 12 people who were falsely accused of
sadistically abusing foster children and were found to have been
victims of malicious prosecution” (Gerry Klein, “Saskatchewan Not
Sorry for Malicious Prosecution,” National Post, 9 January 2004: A-1).
28 Gardner 127–40.
29 There were already a few critics by the early 1990s. See Eleanor
Goldstein, Confabulations: Creating False Memories, Destroying
Families (Boca Raton, FL: Sirs, 1992); Richard Ofshe and Ethan
Watters, Making Monsters: False Memories, Psychotherapy, and
Sexual Hysteria (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1994). By the late
1990s, there were many works on this topic. Here are a few examples:
Debbi Nathan and Michael Snedecker, Satan’s Silence: Ritual Abuse
and the Making of a Modern American Witch-Hunt (New York: Basic
Books, 1995); Arlys N. McDonald, Repressed Memories: Can You
Trust Them? (Ada, MI: Revell, 1995); Claudette Wassil-Grimm,
Diagnosis for Disaster: The Devastating Truth about False Memory
Syndrome and Its Impact on American Families (New York: Overlook
Press, 1995); Andrew Meacham, Selling Serenity: Life among the
Recovery Stars (Boca Raton, FL: Sirs, 1996); Robert Baker, Childhood
Sexual Abuse and False Memory Syndrome (Amherst, NY: Prometheus
Books, 1996); Ronald L. Stephens, Hypnotism and False Memories:
How False Memories Are Created (Freeport, PA: Ziotech International,
1996); Moira Johnston, Spectral Evidence, The Ramon Case: Incest,
Memory and Truth on Trial in Napa Valley (Boston: Houghton Mifflin,
1997); C. Brooks Brenneis, Transferring the Present to the Past
(Independence, MO: International Universities Press, 1997); Harrison
G. Pope, Psychology Astray: Fallacies in Studies of “Repressed
Memory” and Childhood Trauma (Boca Raton, FL: Sirs, 1997); Dean
Tong, Ashes to Ashes … Families to Dust: False Accusations of
Childhood Abuse, A Roadmap for Survivors (Tampa, FL: Family
Rights, 1997).
30 Steven Reiner, “Devilish Deeds,” Prime-Time Live, ABC, WVNY-TV,
Burlington,VT, 7 January 1993.
31 Elizabeth Loftus and Katherine Ketcham, The Myth of Repressed
Memories: False Memories and the Accusations of Sexual Abuse
(New York: St Martin’s Press, 1996).
32 Jill Neimark, “The Diva of Disclosure,” Psychology Today 29.1
(January-February 1996) 78; quoting Loftus.
33 Michael D. Yapko, Suggestions of Abuse: True and False Memories of
Childhood Sexual Trauma (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1994).
34 Mark Pendergrast, Victims of Memory: Incest Accusations and
Shattered Lives (Hinesburg,VT: Upper Access, 1995). A review by
Ann Diamond noted the atmosphere in which Pendergrast’s book had
appeared: “This is explosive material, all the more so because of the
number of women who now testify to having experienced flashbacks
and memories of abuse in early childhood. Who, after all, would doubt
what, for so many, is now incontrovertible fact? Incest is everywhere.
Faced with so many survivors’ stories, most of us feel like passive
spectators at a massive tragedy that is engulfing what we used to call
‘Western civilization.’” (Ann Diamond, “Exhaustive Look at Victims
of Memory: Father Accused of Abuse Looks into Mystery,” Montreal
Gazette, 1 April 1995: H-3).
35 Lawrence Wright, Remembering Satan: A Case of Recovered Memory
and the Shattering of an American Family (New York: Knopf, 1994).
36 John Goddard, “How Satanic-Abuse Charges Wrecked Family,” review
of Remembering Satan, by Lawrence Wright, Montreal Gazette, 25
June 1994: H-2.
37 This argument has been made also by Judith Levine. Despite cross-
cultural variation, adult notions of sexuality include the recognition
that children must be physically and emotionally mature enough to
engage in sexual behaviour, the outcome of which might be
pregnancy. See Suzanne G. Frayser, Varieties of Sexual Experience:
An Anthropological Perspective on Human Sexuality (New Haven, CT:
HRAF Press, 1985).
38 As Levine puts it, “dire assessments of a morally anarchic world are
not new. But they tend to crop up in times of social transformation,
when the economy trembles or when social institutions crumble and
many people feel they’re losing control of their jobs, their futures, or
their children’s lives. At times like these, the child-molesting monster
can be counted on to creep from the rubble” (Levine 29).
39 Historians can agree on one thing: that modernity not only ushered in
unprecedented levels of both change and stress but did so with
unprecedented and increasing rapidity. For our purposes here, we will
say that modernity began with the Industrial Revolution in the
nineteenth century, though slightly earlier in Britain, and continued
into the twentieth. (During that period of approximately 150 years, it
spawned new revolutions such as the ones associated with electricity
and electronics). Stress intensified occasionally due to specific crises.
Of interest here are not the ones brought on by external threats, such as
wars, but the ones brought on by internal threats. Stress intensified in
the 1930s, for instance, when economic and social structures seemed
to be on the verge of collapse due to the Great Depression.
As Levine points out, stress at this deep level often took the form
of anxiety about children. But not necessarily – or not directly – about
the most obvious perils, the ones that parents themselves inflicted on
their own children. At the beginning of this period, for instance, the
poor sent their young children to work in mills or mines. Parents
worried about what would happen to them without protection from the
sexual depravity of adult men who worked there. During the
Depression, even middle-class parents worried about the safety of
their children. What would happen to them with millions of
unemployed men, possibly predators, loitering on the streets? More
recently, even rich parents had to worry about the safety of their
children. What would happen to them at the hands of workers,
especially male workers, in daycare centres? (We discuss the historical
background in appendix 2.)
40 Jeffrey Victor; quoted in deYoung 22.
41 According to Gleick, the hysteria spread quickly to Britain and Europe
(“All in the Head,” Time, 7 July 1997: 44–6).
42 John Demos, Entertaining Satan: Witchcraft and the Culture of Early
New England. Rev. ed. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004).
43 This taboo is found in all cultures, although anthropologists still do not
agree on why that should be the case.
44 This molestation is widely condemned, of course, but concepts of
childhood and permissible ages for sexual activity vary widely from
one society to another.
45 The locus classicus for this theory is Susan Brownmiller’s Against Our
Will: Men, Women and Rape (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1975).
More recently, this approach was taken by Bernard Lefkowitz in Our
Guys: The Glen Ridge Rape and the Secret Life of the Perfect Suburb
(Berkeley: University of California Press, 1997).
46 Tavris 28.
47 DeYoung 24.
48 Gleick 46.
49 Neimark 49.

CHAPTER TWO

1 Barbara Ehrenreich, “Feminism Confronts Bobbittry,” Time, 24


January 1994: 52 (her emphasis).
2 Warren Farrell, Women Can’t Hear What Men Don’t Say: Destroying
Myths, Creating Love (New York: Jeremy Tarcher/Putnam, 1999) 126.
3 Alan Dershowitz, Lenore Walker, Lisa Kemler, Jeff Greenfield,
Charles Sykes, and Lynn Tipper, interviewed by Ted Koppel on
Nightline, ABC, WVNY-TV, Burlington,VT, 4 February 1994;
4 Alan Dershowtiz, Nightline.
5 Lenore E.A. Walker, The Battered Woman (New York: Harper and
Row, 1979) xi.
6 Lenore E.A. Walker, Nightline.
7 Lisa Kemler, Nightline.
8 Jeff Greenfield, Nightline.
9 Greenfield, Nightline.
10 Charles Sykes, Nightline.
11 Lynn Tepper, Nightline.
12 Tepper, Nightline.
13 This solution would mean, at the very least, taking steps to make
dialing 911 an effective measure: ensuring that police intervene
quickly to stop domestic violence (but with a responsibility to take
seriously both the woman’s and the man’s account of any conflict),
making shelters available to women and men who need them, and so
forth. But no one pointed out that the ultimate solution would be to
prevent domestic violence in the first place. That would require far
more than legal or social reform. It would require genuine dialogue
between men and women (which we will discuss in Transcending
Misandry). In this case, it would have required something other than
the ranting of Lorena’s supporters. Even more problematic than the
verdict itself, in other words, was public sentiment both before and
after it was announced.
On the problem of police intervention in cases of domestic
violence, see Grant Brown, “Gender as a Factor in the Response of the
Law-Enforcement System to Violence against Partners,” 20–2,
unpublished manuscript; for more information on this Canadian study,
contact the author at [email protected]. Brown refers to earlier
studies as well. “In one major partner-abuse survey in the U.S. in 1985,
when women called police about abusive husbands, the husbands were
arrested or threatened with arrest over 50% of the time; when men
called police about abusive wives, the wives were never arrested or
threatened with arrest” (Brown 22; referring to Richard J. Gelles and
Murray A. Straus, Intimate Violence [New York: Simon and Schuster,
1988] 262).
14 A few similar cases did occur, however. On the night of 20 September
1992, for example, Aurelia Macias took a pair of scissors and cut off
the testicles of her husband, Jaime Macias. The latter, she contended,
had tried earlier that evening to force her to have sex with him. Like
Lorena, moreover, she was acquitted; the jury found her not guilty of
mayhem and assault with a deadly weapon and could not even agree
on the lesser charge of battery. According to Claudia Marshall, who
spoke for the jury, Macias had been “verbally and emotionally abused
throughout the marriage” and was probably in mortal fear on the night
in question. The fact that Jaime, like John Bobbitt, had been fast
asleep at the time made no difference to these jurors (“Woman
Acquitted in Castration Case,” Montreal Gazette, 19 March 1994: C-
11). A closer parallel to the case of Lorena Bobbitt could hardly be
imagined. And Macias took the law into her own hands before
learning about Lorena. Moreover, as the prosecution pointed out, “the
defense had decided to employ the battered-wife defense after seeing
its effectiveness in the case of Lorena L. Bobbitt.” (“Woman Acquitted
of Charges in Castration,” New York Times, 20 March 1994: 27).
15 Susan Estrich, interviewed on Now, NBC, WPTZ, Plattsburgh, NY, 22
December 1993.
16 Jamie Lee Evans, interviewed on Now.
17 Clay Cogalis thought “the prior abuse made it easier to believe that
someone could snap after four years of being, you know, terribly
abused, and then … savagely raped.”
18 Evans.
19 Ehrenreich 52.
20 Ehrenreich 52.
21 Wolf had already done a great deal of whining about the beauty myth
allegedly foisted on women by men (Naomi Wolf, The Beauty Myth:
How Images of Beauty Are Used against Women [New York: Morrow,
1991]).
22 Ehrenreich 52.
23 Ehrenreich 52.
24 “The Men’s Issues Page” and “Men and Domestic Violence Index”
[undated], World Wide Web Virtual Library, [visited] 22 September
2002, <http://www.vix.com/men/index.html.>
25 See Molly Dragiewicz’s bibliography called “Gender Asymmetry in
Domestic Violence,” [dated] 5 September 2002, George Mason
University, [visited] 22 September 2002,
<http://mason.gmu.edu/~mdragiew/gender%20asymmetry%20dv.html
>.

CHAPTER THREE

1 Anita Hill Speaking Truth to Power (New York: Doubleday, 1997)


345.
2 Clarence Thomas, “Eloquent Lies, [dated] March 2001, Yale Alumni
Magazine, [visited] 8 March 2004,
<http://www.yalealumnimagazine.com/issues/01_03/quotes.html>: 7;
Thomas uttered these famous lines at the Senate confirmation hearing
in October 1991.
3 Jean Bethke Elshtain, “Trial by Fury,” New Republic 209 (6
September 1993): 35.
4 We cannot find the origin of that expression, but we did find on the
Internet that it is in common use among American blacks, women,
gays, and Arabs. See Julianne Malveaux, Sex, Lies, and Stereotypes:
Perspectives of a Mad Economist (Los Angeles: Pines Ones, 1994), for
instance, or Kim Ficera, Sex, Lies, and Stereotypes (New York:
Kensington Books, 2003). In any case, things really have changed in
popular culture. By the late 1990s, Ally McBeal had begun to foster a
much more tolerant attitude toward workplace flirtations, albeit in the
context of situation comedy. Almost all the characters have had affairs
with each other, and this is not presented as something sinister.
Moreover, workplace romances are often “explored” on NYPD Blue.
By 2002, detectives Connie McDowell and Andy Sipowicz were
moving toward some sort of “relationship” going beyond work. In this
case, a woman takes the initiative. She is not presented, however, as a
sexual predator. The same is true of two lawyer shows that began with
the new century: Philly and The Associates. On Philly, Kathleen
Maguire and Judge Jack Ripley fall in love with each other. Although
their relationship poses potential problems in court, no attempt is made
to paint Ripley as a sexual predator and Kathleen as a victim of sexual
harassment. On The Associates, a Canadian show, everyone flirts with
everyone else no matter what ranks are involved. On all these shows,
and many more, it is taken for granted that men and women who work
together, no matter what their positions in the corporate or bureaucratic
hierarchy, are often attracted to each other – and that there is nothing
wrong with this in normal circumstances.
5 Linda Bloodworth-Thomason, “The Strange Case of Clarence and
Anita,” Designing Women, CBS, WCAX-TV, Burlington,VT, 4 November
1991.
6 Elshtain 32.
7 Elshtain 36.
8 Hill claims in Speaking Truth to Power that she left the University of
Oklahoma because of harassment, partly motivated by racism,
including threats on her life. Politicians outside the university tried to
sabotage an endowed professorship that was to be established in her
name, for example, and even to close the law school as a way of
getting rid of her. According to Hill, the chair was intended to
encourage public debate. But that argument could work both ways.
Giving an endowed chair to someone with such a high political profile
would inevitably pose a problem for any university committed to
scholarship unencumbered by political or ideological affiliations. Was
this chair reserved for Hill and her successors, who support one point
of view? Or would critics be welcome as well? By this time, Hill was
travelling around the world and earning as much as $30,000 for public
appearances.
9 Hill has gained some enemies, yes, but this happens to every
significant figure in academic, legal, and political circles. “No one can
claim that Anita Hill is an unsung heroine,” writes Katie Roiphe. “It
makes sense that teenagers get caught up in the Anita Hill fury; they
are particularly susceptible to feeling uncomfortable about sexuality,
and sexual harassment offers an ideology that explains
‘uncomfortable’ in political terms. The idea of sexual harassment
displaces adolescent uneasiness onto the environment, onto professors,
onto older men” (The Morning After: Sex, Fear, and Feminism
[Boston: Little Brown, 1993] 92).
10 Joe Klein; quoted on Edge, PBS, WETK, Burlington,VT, 6 November
1991.
11 Nancy Gibbs, “Office Crimes,” Time, 21 October 1991: 30.
Considering the confusion, why be surprised that Playboy came up
with a cartoon about the much more serious crime of rape. A bunch of
prostitutes listen to one of their number, who has just received a
telephone call: “That guy who said he was a Peruvian diplomat used a
phony credit card? My God, girls, we’ve been raped” (Charles
Rodriguez, cartoon, Playboy, April 1995: 146).
12 There was much discussion about this in connection with Michael
Crichton’s novel and the movie version of it. In Disclosure, as we will
show, the male protagonist is sexually harassed by his female boss. No
one in the movie suggests that he quit his job, so why suggest that Hill
should have left her job?
13 No constitution can guarantee that, because happiness is a state of mind
and not a legally definable opportunity or a physically quantifiable
commodity.
14 It is true that women have developed some distinctive characteristics
but not necessarily true that these are “better” than those of men.
Moreover, they are usually characteristics that have been carefully
fostered by the very society feminists condemn as patriarchal. Women
whose self-esteem is undermined when their distinctive contributions
are ignored or trivialized by men should expect men to feel precisely
the same way when women do that to them. At stake for men is not
merely their power (to which their claim is no stronger than that of
women), by the way, but their identity (for which their need is no
weaker than that of women). It seems unlikely that any improvement
in relations between men and women will be possible until that
problem – and masculine identity is a problem and has been for
centuries – is addressed. And men might have as much difficulty as
women in doing so (though for quite different reasons).
15 Elshtain 32.
16 Elshtain 32–3.
17 Elshtain 33–4.
18 Elshtain 34 (our emphasis).
19 John Cloud, “Sex and the Law,” Time, 23 March 1998: 49.
20 Jane Mayer and Jill Abramson, Strange Justice (Boston: Houghton
Mifflin, 1994).
21 Hill 345, 346.
22 Hill 346, 352.
23 Hill 352, 347.
24 Hill 348, 349, 350.
25 Hill 349–50.
26 Hill 353.
27 Elshtain 34.
28 Mako Nonaka, “Letters,” Time, 25 May 1998: 11.
29 Wendy Kaminer, “Below the Beltway,” review of Scorpion Tongues,
by Gail Collins, No Island of Sanity, by Vincent Bugliosi, and Spin
Cycle, by Howard Kurtz, in the New York Times Book Review, 22
March 1998: 14.
30 June Prentice, ”Letters,” Time, 25 May 1998: 11.
31 Michael Crichton, Disclosure (New York: Knopf, 1994).
32 Eve McBride, “Sex in the Workplace Might Be Something from the
Past,” Montreal Gazette, 2 June 1994: A-2.
33 Holly Doan, during a discussion of Disclosure and Oleanna with
reviewer Geoff Pevere (who agreed with her), Canada AM, CTV, CFCF-
TV, Montreal, 21 December 1994.
34 Ian Katz, “Male Student Seeks Cash after Lecture by Lesbian,”
Montreal Gazette, 9 March 1995: B-10.
35 Katz B-10.
36 To some extent, the discussion of Prevette’s and Dearinge’s behaviour
was based on reason. There were those who argued, for example, that
these kissing incidents were trivial. Their point was not that sexual
harassment is trivial, to be sure, but that the uproar over these
incidents trivialized it. The real problem, they argued, was much more
serious. They were referring to little boys who show little girls
pictures in Playboy, for example, and dare the girls to show how they
measure up. “From younger and younger ages,” writes Dorothy
Nixon, “yes, even in elementary school, insecure boys who are very
often being outperformed by girls at school, are learning that sex is a
weapon – a weapon handed to them on a velvet cushion by the culture.
The pendulum has not swung too far on this issue; it’s never too early
to educate children about the meaning of respect and self-respect”
(“Sexual Harassment: Playing Field Still Not Level,” Montreal
Gazette, 13 October 1996: A-8).
37 Donna Laframboise, “Rules Trivialize Sexual Harassment and Hurt
Girls,” Montreal Gazette, 7 October 1996: B-3. The title of this article
might not have been chosen by Laframboise herself. She actively
opposes the kind of double standard it reflects. After all, the boys in
this case got hurt, being singled out for national attention as proto-
criminals, not the girls.
38 Another show of this kind is Ally McBeal, which is about the sex lives
of male and female lawyers in Boston. Interestingly, it is much more
popular among women, than men.
39 People often assume that heterosexuality can be taken for granted, that
most men and most women will always get together in one way or
another. In fact, this is an oversimplification. Nature itself brings men
and women together, sure, but only for brief liaisons. So a major
cultural project of all human societies has always been to keep them
together on a more enduring basis. That is necessary for several
reasons. Some division of labour, whether fair from our perspective or
unfair, has provided for the benefit of both children and society as a
whole.
40 John Leo, “Harassment’s Murky Edges,” U.S. News and World Report,
21 October 1991: 26.
CHAPTER FOUR

1 Erin Graham; quoted in Brian Bergman and others, “Sisterhood of


Fear and Fury: Intimations That ‘Marc Was Not Alone,’” Maclean’s,
18 December 1989: 18.
2 Helen Morrison; quoted in Bergman 18–19.
3 Among the more notorious were the shootings at Columbine High
School in Littleton, Colorado (20 April 1999), where fifteen were
killed; Springfield, Oregon (21 May 1998), where two were killed;
Fayetteville, Tennessee (19 May 1998), where one was killed;
Jonesboro, Arkansas (24 March 1998), where five were killed;
Pomona, California (28 April 1998), where two were killed; Pearl
Mississippi (1 October 1997), where nine were killed; and Moses
Lake, Washington (2 February 1996), where two were killed. At other
schools, students opened fire but did not succeed in killing anyone:
West Paducah, Kentucky; Conyers, Georgia; and Richmond, Virginia.
Something similar occurred at W.R. Myers Public High School in
Taber, Alberta.
4 Barry Came and others, “Montreal Massacre,” Maclean’s, 18
December 1989:, 14.
5 Greg Weston and Jack Aubry, “The Making of a Mass-Killer,”
Montreal Gazette, 11 February 1990: A-4, A-5.
6 Greg Weston and Jack Aubry, “The Making of a Massacre,” Montreal
Gazette, 10 February 1990: B-4.
7 Weston and Aubry, “Mass-Killer”: A-5.
8 Jean Bélanger; quoted in Weston and Aubry, “Massacre”: B-4.
9 Weston and Aubry, “Massacre”: B-4.
10 Weston and Aubry, “Massacre”: B-1.
11 Andrew McIntosh, “Couple’s Evening to Celebrate Turns into
Nightmare,” Montreal Gazette, 7 December 1989, A-3.
12 Weston and Aubry, “Mass-Killer”: A-4.
13 Morrison; quoted in Bergman 18–19.
14 Eriksen; quoted in Bergman 18.
15 Graham; quoted in Bergman 18.
16 Jennifer Bankier, “Vigil Saddens and Reminds Us Inequities Persist,”
CAUT Bulletin, November 1995: 7.
17 The urge to blame “ordinary” members of alien groups resurfaced
more recently in the wake of Daniel Goldhagen’s book Hitler’s Willing
Executioners: Ordinary Germans and the Holocaust (New York:
Knopf, 1996). According to Goldhagen, mass murder in Germany was
produced not by obviously insane or obviously evil people but by
“ordinary Germans” (although he never defines “ordinary” in a way
that accounts for factors such as class, education, region, and so on).
The direct implication is that we may condemn all Germans (or at
least those of that time) as murderers.
18 Bankier 7.
19 Larry Finkelman; quoted in Graham Good, “White Males Don’t Share
Lépine’s Guilt,” CAUT Bulletin, 2 March 1996: 2.
20 Edward Renner, Christine Alksnis, and Laura Park, “Sexual Injustice,”
Montreal Gazette, 23 June 1997: B-3.
21 According to a study by the National Coalition of Anti-Violence
Programs, gay men and women in four out of six American cities are
more often victims of domestic violence than they are of anti-gay
violence, although they are much less likely than straight people to
report it (Vicki Haddock, “Gay Domestic Violence,” Montreal
Gazette, 23 October 1996: F-10).
22 F.L. Morton and Rainer Knopff, The Charter Revolution and the Court
Party (Peterborough, ON: Broadview Press, 2000) 184.
23 Graham Good, “Letters,” CAUT Bulletin, 2 March 1996: 2.
24 Bergman 18.
25 Rosemary Gartner; quoted in Bergman 18.
26 Bergman 19.
27 Brian Gable, [untitled cartoon] Globe and Mail, 9 December 1989: D-6.
28 Morrison; quoted in Bergman 19.
29 Bergman 18.
30 See Heidi Rathjen and Charles Montpetit, December 6: From the
Montreal Massacre to Gun Control, The Inside Story (Toronto:
McLelland and Stewart, 1999). Nathalie Provost was one of the
female students. Having survived three shots, she said that “there are
guys who are feeling very bad about what happened. They keep
thinking that they were guilty of something, and it’s not true. There is
only one criminal in all of this, and he’s already dead. Everybody else
did everything they could.” This attitude was unusual, to say the least.
“A girl defending the guys? Many people had trouble understanding
that one: in the media and on the street, there were plenty of ignorant
people who blamed the male students for not having protected their
classmates. With comfortable hindsight, anyone could rewrite the
scene and have the guys overpower the attacker. But the truth is, it was
perfectly normal to have felt helpless in this situation” (Rathjen and
Montpetit 21 [their emphasis]). Blaming or not blaming individual
male students was one thing, though, and blaming or not blaming the
collectivity of male citizens was something else.
31 It was a moment of masculine heroism, at least among the first-class
passengers, who paid honourably in death for their privileges in life.
Ironically, this movie ignored the quiet heroism of a real woman on
board, Mrs Isidore Strauss, who refused to be separated from her
husband of many years.
32 This is true not only in the United States, where all eighteen-year-old
boys must register for the draft, but also in countries such as Canada,
which are heavily influenced by American popular culture.
33 Aside from Rathjen and Montpetit, cited above, see Gabrielle
MercierLeblond and Robert De Coster, Les Interventions
psychosociales: La Tragédie du 6 décembre 1989 a l’École
polytechnique de Montréal (Quebec: Groupe de travail De Coster,
1991); The Montreal Massacre, ed. Marie Chalouh and Louise Malette
(Charlottetown: Gynergy Books, 1991); Wendy Hui Kyong Chun,
“Unbearable Witness: Toward a Politics of Listening, Differences, 11.1
(spring 1999): 112–49; Julie Brickman, “Female Lives, Feminist
Deaths: The Relationship of the Montreal Massacre to Dissociation,
Incest, and Violence against Women,” Canadian Psychology 33.2
(April 1992): 128–43; Daniel Sansfacon and others, “Rapports de sexe
et violence contre les femmes: Essai de réconstruction sociale du sens
de la tragédie de la polytechnique,” Revue Sexologique 2.2 (autumn
1994): 107–28; Illah Patricia Wilson, “Metanarrative and Media:
Retrospective on the Montreal Massacre,” master’s thesis, McMaster
University, 1992; Pauline Fahmy, Les évènements de Polytechnique:
Analyses et propositions d’actions (Ottawa: Institut canadien de
recherches sur les femmes, 1994); Maureen Bradley, Reframing the
Montreal Massacre: A Media Interrogation [videorecording]
(Vancouver: Mediawise, 1995).
34 Pascoe; quoted in Bergman 18.
35 Gartner; quoted in Bergman 19.
36 Except, of course, when economic support from fathers is required by
mothers or when political support is required from male voters and
public officials.
37 Civil religion is known also as “public religion.” Though never
identified closely or directly with any traditional religious institution,
it is based on the forms of traditional religion. In this part of the world,
that usually means Judaism or Christianity. Like traditional religion,
civil religion consists of formalized behaviour associated with special
days, sites, rituals, parades, books, and so on, that give symbolic
expression to communal worldviews. Even communities associated
with traditional religions often have civil religions that transcend
denominational boundaries. The civil religion of diaspora Jews
focuses not on Torah, which is considered irrelevant by secular Jews,
but on the Nazi nightmare and the Israeli dream.
38 The correct title is Minister of Justice and Attorney General of Canada,
who works for the Department of Justice (also known as Justice
Canada).
39 This ministry is the wishful thinking of a utopian. There is no such
ministry. Not yet, anyway. The closest equivalent so far is British
Columbia’s Ministry of Community, Aboriginal and Women’s
Services.
40 Christie Blatchford, “Half Mast, Double Standard: Homage to
Montreal Victims Outweighs That Paid to Fallen Soldiers of Three
Wars,” National Post, 7 December 2001: A-1.
41 “Remember Them Well,” editorial in Montreal Gazette, 11 November
2001: A-16 (our emphasis).
42 Consider a book by someone who can hardly be called a militant
feminist: Tanya Melich, The Republican War against Women: An
Insider’s Report from Behind the Lines (New York: Bantam, 1996).
43 Canada, House of Commons, Standing Committee on Health and
Welfare, Social Affairs, Seniors, and the Status of Women, The War
against Women: A Report of the Standing Committee on Health and
Welfare, Social Affairs, Seniors, and the Status of Women (Hull, QC:
Supply and Services Canada, 1991).
44 Until recently, we would have assumed that their assailants were
almost always other men. In chapter 9, however, we discuss recent
studies that indicate a quite different state of affairs.
45 Not everyone who approved of the report did so because of a
gynocentric perspective, but that did not necessarily prevent them
from endorsing it.
46 This is not the first use of military rhetoric. The Feminist International
Network of Resistance to Reproductive and Genetic Engineering, for
example, used this rhetoric explicitly in its manifesto: “For us women,
for nature, and for the exploited peoples of the world, this is a
declaration of war” (from the “Resolution from the FINRRAGE
Conference, 3–8 July 1985, Vällinge, Sweden; quoted in Made to
Order: The Myth of Reproductive and Genetic Progress [New York:
Pergamon Press, 1987] 211).
47 Andrea Dworkin, “Terror, Torture, and Resistance,” [dated] 1991,
Canadian Mental Health Association, [visited]
<www.nostatusquo.com/aclu/dworkin/TerrorTortureandResistance.ht
ml>:7 September 2002
<www.nostatusquo.com/aclu/dworkin/TerrorTortureandResistance.ht
ml>:7 (keynote speech delivered at the Canadian Mental Health
Association’s “Women and Mental Health Conference – Women in a
Violent Society,” held in Banff, Alberta, May 1991); cited in “Kill
Wife Beaters Who Go Free, Feminist-Rights Activist Urges,”
Montreal Gazette, 13 June 1991: A-7; first published in Canadian
Woman Studies/Les Cahiers de la femme, 12.1 (fall 1991): 37–42.
48 “For Women Only! The Lioness Method of Rape Prevention,” [dated]
August 2002, National Firearms Association, [visited] 19 September
2002, <www.nfa.ca>.
49 Vigilantism continues to exist in virtually every nation, of course, but
usually by default rather than by design. No state, no matter how
inadequate by alien standards, can afford to tolerate the idea of citizens
taking the law into their own hands.
50 “Battered Woman Acquitted of Killing,” Montreal Gazette, 25 June
1991: A-8.
51 Many people believe that revenge is an acceptable basis for legal or
even moral discourse. Everyone feels the desire for revenge now and
then. It is perfectly comprehensible in situations of this kind. But that
does not make it acceptable. In moral terms, after all, revenge and
justice are not synonymous. Even in strictly legal terms, it is the need
to keep dangerous people off the streets (possibly to rehabilitate them)
and the need to deter others from crime, not the desire for personal or
collective revenge, that society acknowledges. Locking up those who
threaten society is considered their just reward.
The assumption that justice and revenge really are synonymous is
becoming increasingly prevalent at every level of society. In one
article, a professor of law and philosophy argued that the time had
come to question the traditional primacy given to love and
reconciliation, to rethink our traditional avoidance of revenge and
hatred (Jeffrie G. Murphy, “Getting Even: The Role of the Victim,”
Social Philosophy and Policy 7.2 [spring 1990]: 209-25). This way of
thinking has long been prevalent among ideologues, who rely on the
post-modern belief that nothing can have any intrinsic value and who
believe that ends such as the elimination of crime can justify even an
unedifying means, such as revenge by victims. Do we really want to
live in a society that institutionalizes revenge even as a principle of
law? Do Canadians, in particular, really want to retain capital
punishment after all? (Ironically, capital punishment was abolished at
least partly because, at that time, it was considered ineffective as a
deterrent.) Once ideological thinking is endorsed by society, especially
by the state that represents it, all other ways of thinking are threatened,
including those on which the collective notion of justice is based.
52 Any attempt to redefine the mandate of this government study would
have resulted in fierce opposition from those who believe that women
have no responsibility whatsoever for the polarization between men
and women (let alone for the rate of violence against women). Yes, it
is true that victims cannot legitimately be held morally responsible for
the actions of their victimizers. But one factor complicates this
discussion. Just as not all victims are women, not all women are
victims. Apart from the innocent bystanders in this conflict are those
actively involved in fostering hostility. They take control of their own
destiny – and are thus not passive victims – by deliberately promoting
the kind of polarization between men and women that perpetuates
conflict. They are not innocent victims. They know what they are
doing. They know that they are advocating misandry. In doing so, they
are either almost incredibly naive (not realizing that hatred is a very
powerful force and cannot be contained easily once it has been let
loose) or almost incredibly cynical (believing that more female victims
of men will at least provide additional evidence for their theory and
thus ultimately advance their cause). Consequently, they must take
some responsibility for their own behaviour. This does not mitigate the
guilt of men who respond to women with violence, whether provoked
or unprovoked. Individual men must pay for their own crimes. But
should individual women be encouraged to imagine that they or those
they permit to speak in their name can unleash powerful and
dangerous forces without accepting some responsibility for the likely
consequences?
53 The word “propaganda” is no longer very useful, though, because it is
now invariably defined subjectively. It has come to mean promoting a
way of thinking that “we” dislike. Using the same methods to promote
a way of thinking that “we” do like is hardly ever called “propaganda”
(except by the Vatican, which uses the word in the earlier sense of
“propagating” the faith).
54 Helen Branswell, “Canadian Men’s Suicide Rate Soaring,” Montreal
Gazette, 27 March 1991: B-1.
55 Pierrette Venne; quoted in Branswell B-1.
CHAPTER FIVE

1 Catharine A. MacKinnon, “Making Sex Equality Real,” in Righting


the Balance: Canada’s New Equality Rights, ed. L. Smith and others
(Saskatoon: Canadian Human Rights Reporter, 1986) 37–8.
2 Lee Dembart, “Letters,” Atlantic Monthly, February 1994: 11.
3 Michael Ignatieff, Human Rights as Politics and Idolatry, ed. Amy
Gutman (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2001).
4 This is true, now, even though section 2 refers only to “male” citizens
in connection with the electorate.
5 Roberta W. Francis, “History,” [updated] 23 July 2002, Equal Rights
Amendment, [visited] 4 August 2002,
<http://www.equalrightsamendment.org/era.htm>: 2.
6 Ann Douglas, Terrible Honesty: Mongrel Manhattan in the 1920s
(New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 1995).
7 Francis 3
8 Anne Peters, Women, Quotas and Constitutions: A Comparative Study
of Affirmative Action for Women under American, German, European
Community and International Law ( The Hague: Kluwer Law
International, 2000) 94.
9 Peters 95.
10 Other modifications have accommodated the fact that female
employees, as a group, are smaller and weaker than men. To hire more
women (especially in fire departments, police departments, and the
armed forces), job qualifications are modified.
11 Peters 95; see also Michael M. v. Superior Court of Sonoma County,
450 U.S. 464, 469 (1981); quoted in Peters 95. See also Schlesinger v.
Ballard, 419 U.S. 498 [1975]; cited in Peters 96.
12 In 1992, with the ERA still not ratified, that number was used for the
Madison Amendment.
13 Francis 1.
14 For the latest information, see “What’s New,” [updated] 5 November
2003, The Equal Rights Amendment, [visited] 28 December 2003,
<http://members.aol.com/eraCampaignWeb/new.html>.
15 See Peters 281, 286–287, 290, 294.
16 Executive Order Establishing the President’s Committee on Equal
Employment Opportunity, Exec. Order No. 10,925, 3 C.F.R. 1959–1963
Comp. 448 (6 March 1961), Part 3, Section 301, Subsection 1, quoted
in Peters 32; U.S. Equal Employment Opportunity Commission,
[visited] 18 January 2004
<http://www.eeoc.gov/abouteeoc/35th/thelaw/eo-10925.html>.
17 Executive order – Equal Employment Opportunity, As Amended, Exec.
Order No. 11,246, 3 C.F.R. 1964–1965 Comp. 339 (24 September 1965)
Subpart B, Section 202, Subsection 1; This Nation, [visited] 18
January 2004, <http://www.thisnation.com/library/print/eo-
affirmative2.html>; quoted in Peters 32.
18 Exec. order 36, Fed. Reg. 17,444 and 23,152 (1971); the four groups
were “Blacks, Native Americans, Latinos/as, and Asian Americans.”
19 U.S.C. Title 29, Chapter 8, Section 206, (D)(1) (2000), Legal
Information Institute, [visited] 18 January 2004,
<http://www.thecre.com/fedlaw/legal6/uscode29-206.htm>.
20 Here are two important American cases that went before the Supreme
Court: United Steelworkers v. Weber, 443 U.S. 193 (1979), and
Adarand Constructors v. Pena, 513 U.S. 200 (1995).
21 Peters 287.
22 See Adarand Constructors v. Pena, 513 U.S. 1108 (1995).
23 Civil Rights Act of 1964, Pub. L. No. 88-352, Title VII (1997)
(codified as amended in 42 U.S.C., U.S. Equal Opportunity
Commission, [visited] 18 January 2004,
<http://www.eeoc.gov/policy/vii.html>.
24 Regents of University of California v. Bakke 438 U.S. 265 (1978).
25 Grutter v. Bollinger (2003); Gratz v. Bollinger (2003).
26 Another test is called “intermediate scrutiny.” In this case, the
government interest must be merely “important,” not “compelling.”
The means must be merely “substantially related” to the government
interest, not narrowly defined.
27 “Government Publications: U.S. Government Information by Agency
and Department,” [dated] 13 June 2001, Northwestern University
Library, [visited] 5 October 2002,
<http://www/library.northwestern.edu/index.html>.
28 “Violence against Women Office,” [dated]10 September 2002,
Northwestern University Library [visited] 5 October 2002,
<http://www.ojp.usdoj.gov/vawo/>.
29 “U.S. Department of Labor, Women’s Bureau,” [dated] 5 October 2002,
Northwestern University Library, [visited] 5 October 2002,
<http://www.do.gov/wb/welcome.html>.
30 The Legal Education and Action Fund was established by feminist
lawyers in 1985 and supported partly by Status of Women Canada –
which is to say, by Canadian taxpayers. Its main function is to fund
and organize feminist interventions before the Supreme Court.
According to its website, LEAF is “a national, non-profit organization
committed to using the provisions of the Canadian Charter of Rights
and Freedoms to promote equality for women … LEAF undertakes
legal action by intervening at the Canadian appellate courts on
significant cases that will establish important principles of equality for
women. LEAF’s cases are selected by its National Legal Committee …
LEAF has … intervened in over 140 cases and has helped establish
landmark legal victories for women on a wide range of issues from
violence against women, sexual harassment, pregnancy discrimination,
sex bias in the employment standards, spousal support and
reproductive freedoms” (“About LEAF,” [undated], LEAF: Women’s
Legal Education and Action Fund, [visited] 2 November 2004,
<http://www/leaf.ca/about-mandate.html>: 1).
Some feminists have criticized LEAF as a liberal organization that
promotes the interests of middle-class white women. See Women’s
Legal Strategies in Canada, ed. Radha Jhappan (Toronto: University
of Toronto press, 2002). In her review of that book, Lauren Bowen
notes that it “is situated in legal literature rather than political science
scholarship. More specifically, the intended audience … seems to be
the Canadian legal left … The most frequently cited illustration of the
flaws in feminist legal strategies utilized in litigation since 1985 is
LEAF … The primary criticisms – much like criticism leveled against
the National Organization for Women’s Legal Defense and Education
Fund in the U.S. context – is that rights discourse is used to reinforce
power and privilege. Because rights are universal, those with privilege
can claim them as well. The tendency among LEAF lawyers to proceed
form fundamental assumptions about women’s shared experiences and
subjugation abstracts the reality of oppression for most women and
tends to render the quest for equality an attempt to acquire the same
privileges that too many men enjoy. To argue that point, several of the
authors use as an illustration the case of Symes v. Canada (1993)
where one of the founding LEAF members argued that the cost of her
full-time nanny should be a business deduction when filing her
income tax return. The situation and exploitation of the nanny was not
relevant to the case, suggesting … that gender equality was to be
understood in largely white and middle class terms” (“Women’s Legal
Strategies in Canada,” [dated] 2003, Law and Politics Book Review,
[visited] 25 November 2004,
<http://www.bsos.umd.edu/gvpt/lpbr/subpages/reviews/jhappan-
radha.htm>: 1-2).
Not all critics of LEAF are feminists, of course. See Christopher
Manfredi, Feminist Activism in the Supreme Court: Legal
Mobilization and the Women’s Legal Education and Action Fund
(Vancouver: ubc Press, 2004). Manfredi makes it clear that LEAF has
institutionalized the perspective of ideological feminism. “There is no
doubt,” he writes, “that the [ideological feminist] movement
succeeded completely in one respect: it established the constitutional
and jurisprudential basis for a comprehensive theory of substantive
equality in Canadian law. Unlike its counterpart in the United States,
LEAF never viewed its objective as the attainment of ‘same treatment’
for women and men. Although it obviously sought to eliminate
gender-based distinctions that disadvantage women, it also sought to
preserve or establish such distinctions where they benefited women.
Consequently LEAF did not intervene to support just any equality rights
or sex discrimination claim. Nowhere is this more apparent than in
Brodsky and Day’s 1989 study for the Canadian Advisory Council on
the Status of Women and LEAF’s intervention in Weatherall. In the
former, Brodsky and Day lamented the number of sex discrimination
claims then being brought on behalf of men; in the latter, LEAF
intervened specifically to avoid a formal equality outcome that would
extend the same privacy rights to male inmates as female inmates
enjoyed” (Manfredi 193; his emphasis).
31 This phrase, “recognition as persons,” makes it sound worse than it
was. Canadians had always recognized that women were human
beings and therefore “persons” in the broad sense of that word. The
reference here is to a strictly legal sense. Were women persons – that
is, legally competent – for the specific purpose of this or that law?
32 In 2004, word got out that the National Action Committee was mired
in financial turmoil, partly because an earlier government had cut its
funding to the committee, but also because the NAC had failed to pay
its taxes and was therefore required to pay for both the interest and
penalties. Not everyone – not all women or even all feminists –
received this news with dismay. (Michael Friscolanti, “Women’s
Group Wants Bailout,” National Post, 9 March 2004: A-1, A-5).
Whatever happens to this particular lobby group, though, Status of
Women Canada will remain a well-funded and influential organ of the
Canadian government.
33 Christopher P. Manfredi, The Canadian Feminist Movement,
Constitutional Politics, and the Strategic Use of Legal Resources
(Vancouver: Simon Fraser University: University of British Columbia
Centre for the Study of Government and Business, 2000), 19.
Manfredi says that this council is not unique; there is also the Ministry
for Small Business, which acts like an advocacy group within the
government.
34 Lavell v. Canada (A.G.), [1974] S.C.R. 1349.
35 Manfredi 23; quoting Lavell.
36 Bliss v. Canada (A.G.), [1979] 1 S.C.R. 183; this decision was
overturned in Brooks v. Canada Safeway Ltd., [1989] 1 S.C.R. 1219.
37 Manfredi 27.
38 In the end, this flexibility was somewhat limited by the interpretive
rules of sections 1 and 33. “Under Section 1,” for instance, “Charter
guarantees are subject to reasonable limits, provided these can be
shown to be justified within the parameters of a free and democratic
society. Thus, when a court agrees that a government law infringes on
the Charter, it must determine whether that law, nonetheless, should
stand because the infringement is reasonable and demonstrably
justified in the name of a competing right, value or principle. This can
be especially controversial because it requires judges to interpret what
is or is not a ‘reasonable’ infringement of Charter rights, and what
rights are more important to society than others” (Centre for Research
and Information on Canada, The Charter: Dividing or Uniting
Canadians? cric Papers, no. 5 (Ottawa: Center for Research and
Information on Canada, 2002) 17.
39 Michael Mandel, The Charter of Rights and the Legalization of Politics
in Canada (Toronto: Thompson Educational Publishing, 1994) 377–8.
See also Rainer Knopff and F.L. Morton, Charter Politics (Toronto:
Nelson Canada, 1992) 252.
40 Eugene Meehan and others, The 2000 Annotated Canadian Charter of
Rights and Freedoms (Toronto: Carswell, 1999) 839.
41 “Our Equality Rights in the Charter,” [undated], Court Challenges
Program of Canada, [visited] 28 September 2004,
<http://www.ccppcj.ca/e/i-charter.html>:6.
42 “Our Equality Rights” 6.
43 “Our Equality Rights” 6–7.
44 During the 1990s, feminism became deeply rooted in Canadian
institutions. The Court Challenges program was disbanded in 1992 but
resurrected in 1994, under great pressure from interest groups, as an
independent and nonprofit organization (even though it receives much
of its budget from Heritage Canada, a federal agency supported by
taxpayers). The Court Challenges Program was to have a budget of
$2.75 million annually between 1998 and 2003. Each court challenge
was to be allotted $60,000 from taxpayers, along with $35,000 for any
subsequent appeal or intervention. “Finally,” according to an annual
report, “the Program was granted status as a charitable organization in
May 2000. While the focus of our efforts will be on fundraising from
government sources, the program can now raise funds from the private
sector” (Yvan Beaubien and others, Court Challenges Program of
Canada: Annual Report [for] 1999–2000 [Winnipeg, 2000] 20). This
is most unusual: a federal program set up to expedite challenges to
federal law. It solicits private funds, presumably from the groups that
have something to gain by a court challenge under the Charter. Once
again, this is an arm of the government acting as a lobby group.
45 Beaubien 11.
46 Law Society of British Columbia v. Andrews, [1989] 1 S.C.R. 143. Other
cases in which LEAF has been involved include Boston v. Boston,
[2002] 2 S.C.R. 413 (which supported “double dipping” from an ex-
husband’s income, that is, accessing his pension twice); Irshad
(Litigation guardian of) v. Ontario (Ministry of Health) (2001) 55 O.R.
(3d) 43 (C.A.), application for leave to appeal dismissed 13 September
2001, [2001] S.C.C.A. No. 218 (Q.L.) (which was about access to
medicare for disabled female immigrants); R. v. Darrach, [2000] 2
S.C.R. 443 (which upheld the “rape shield” law: see chapter 9); and
Blencoe v. British Columbia (Human Rights Commission), [2000] 2
S.C.R. 307 (which concerned excessive delays in the investigation of a
complaint against someone accused of sexual harassment). Other cases
include the following: New Brunswick (Minister of Health and
Community Services) v.G.(J.) [J.G.], [1999] 3 S.C.R. 46 (about access
to legal aid in custody suits brought by unmarried women); British
Columbia (Public Service Employee Relations Commission) v. British
Columbia Government and Service Employees’ Union, [1999] 3 S.C.R.
3 (about work standards that favour men); and R. v. Ewanchuk, [1999]
1 S.C.R. 330 (about the definition of “no” in cases of rape).
47 Manfredi, “Canadian Feminist” 32; quoting Law Society of British
Columbia, note 46 at 174.
48 Manfredi, “Canadian Feminist” 33; quoting R. v. Turpin, [1989] 1 S.C.R.
1296 at 1332.
49 Manfredi, “Canadian Feminist” 33.
50 Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination against
Women (CEDAW): Reference Document (Ottawa: Department of Justice,
1985), 7 (our emphasis).
51 Canadian Association of University Teachers, “CAUT’s Policy
Statement on Positive Action to Improve the Status of Women in
Canadian Universities: Preamble,” CAUT Bulletin (March 1991): 12.
Several years later, Maureen Webb distinguished three types of
discrimination in Canadian law. First, direct discrimination exists
“where an employer adopts a practice or rule which on its face
discriminates on a prohibited ground. For example: ‘No Catholics or
no women or no blacks employed here.’” Second, adverse effect
discrimination “arises where an employer for genuine business
reasons adopts a rule or standard which is on its face neutral, and
which will apply equally to all employees, but which has a
discriminatory effect upon a prohibited ground on one employee or
groups of employees in that it imposes, because of some special
characteristic of the employee or group, obligations, penalties, or
restrictive conditions not imposed on other members of the work
force.” Third, systemic discrimination is “institutionalized
discrimination or discrimination which pertains to a system. It is often
used interchangeably with the term ‘adverse effect discrimination,’
although the two are not really synonymous … Certainly, systemic
discrimination often includes adverse effect discrimination, but it can
also include direct discrimination, such as action taken by the
employer on the basis of racial or gender stereotypes. Indeed, systemic
discrimination often includes subtle unconscious forms of direct
discrimination which may be difficult to prove but which
disadvantage minorities in cumulative ways through ‘chilly
environments’ or lack of mentorship” (Maureen Webb, “The Law:
What is Discrimination and How Can It be Proved?” in CAUT Bulletin:
Status of Women Supplement (April 1996): 3; quoting the Supreme
Court case Ontario Human Rights Commission v. Simpson-Sears,
[1985], 2 S.C.R. 536 at para. 18.
52 A Guide to the Court Challenges Program of Canada (Winnipeg, MB,
2002) 4.
53 Canada, Department of Justice, Toward Equality (Ottawa: Ministry of
Supply and Services, 1986) 3–4, 13, 49–56; quoted in Knopff and
Morton, Charter Politics, 192n55.)
54 F.L. Morton and Rainer Knopff, The Charter Revolution and the Court
Party (Toronto: Broadview Press, 2000) 122.
55 Recommendation 5 in National Symposium on Women, Law and the
Administration of Justice Department of Justice: Proceedings of the
Symposium (Ottawa: Department of Justice, 1992).
56 National Symposium 3: 3.
57 Canadian Bar Association, Task Force on Gender Equality in the Legal
Profession, Touchstones for Change: Equality, Diversity, and
Accountability: The Report on Gender Equality in the Legal
Profession (Ottawa: Canadian Bar Association, 1993).
58 Touchstones 13. Apart from any other reason, for its optimism was a
demographic one: 50% of all law students, even then, were women.
The march of progress, says the report, “requires a focus on systemic
and group-based inequalities” and “encompasses the right to have
one’s differences acknowledged and accommodated both by the law
and by appropriate social and institutional policies and practices”
(Touchstones 13). The process had already begun, when the Supreme
Court “rejected the so-called ‘similarly-situated test’ applied in the
Courts below in favour of an approach focusing on the remedying of
disadvantage. The Court defined the purpose of equality guarantees as
promoting the equality of historically and socially disadvantaged
groups in a proactive and systematic way” (Touchstones 14). On
sexual equality in the legal profession, Touchstones defines “gender
bias” as “the predisposition or tendency to think about and behave
toward people primarily on the basis of their sex. Gender bias also
refers to the greater value society places on men” (Touchstones 12).
The gynocentrism of this definition was even more evident in its
elaboration. The barriers of gender bias were said to “have an adverse
impact on women, attitudes and behaviours … which are based on
stereotypical beliefs about the nature and roles of the sexes, myths and
misconceptions about the economic and social problems encountered
by women, and the treatment of real differences between men and
women in a manner which disadvantages women, by ignoring or
devaluing the female difference. Gender bias links the individual
biased behaviour to its systemic origins” (Touchstones 12; quoting
Gender Equality in the Canadian Justice System: Summary Document
and Proposals for Action [Ottawa: Department of Justice, 1992] 17.)
Finally, Touchstones makes a distinction between direct and indirect
discrimination.
59 Touchstones 13.
60 “Employment Equity Act, R.S.C. 1995, c. 44, s. 2: “Purpose of Act,”
Department of Justice Canada, [visited] 28 January 2004,
<http://laws.justice.gc.ca/en/E-5.401/49263.html>.
61 Status of Women Canada, Setting the Stage for the Next Century: The
Federal Plan for Gender Equality (Ottawa: Status of Women Canada,
1995).
62 Report by the Government of Canada to the U.N. Commission on
Human Rights Special Rapporteur on Violence Against Women
(Ottawa: Status of Women Canada, 1998), Status of Women Canada,
[visited] 27 October 2004, <http://www.swc-
cfc.gc.ca/pubs/unreport/unreport_e.html>.
63 Canadian Experience in Gender Mainstreaming (Ottawa: Status of
Women Canada, December 2001), Status of Women Canada, [visited]
27 October 2004,
<http://www.swc.gc.ca/pubs/0662667352/200112_0662667352_4_e.ht
ml>.
64 “Canadian Experience” 1.
65 “Canadian Experience” 2.
66 Note here that section 15 of the Charter does not list groups; it lists
only the “enumerated” grounds of illegal discrimination: race, national
or ethnic origin, colour, religion, sex, age, and mental or physical
disability. These exclude sexual orientation and other grounds, so
lawyers have used analogies to support the claims of some groups. See
A Guide to the Court Challenges Program of Canada (Winnipeg,
2002) 3.
67 F.L. Knopff and Rainer Morton, Charter Politics (Scarborough, ON:
Nelson Canada 1992) 253, 255.
68 Manfredi, “Canadian Feminist” 40–1.
69 Manfredi, “Canadian Feminist” 47.
70 Bertha Wilson, untitled paper, in Gender Equality: A Challenge for the
Legal Profession/La profession juridique face aux defies de l’égalité
des sexes (Ottawa: Canadian Bar Association, 1992) [unpaged
manuscript]; papers presented at Conference of the Canadian Bar
Association Continuing Legal Education Committee and Task Force
on Gender Equality, Toronto, 29–30 October 1992. (The passage
appears on page 5 of her speech, but the pagination is not continuous.)
For a biography of Bertha Wilson, see Mary Ellen Anderson and
Bertha Wilson, Judging Bertha Wilson: Law as Large as Life
(Toronto: Published by the Osgoode Society for Canadian Legal
History by the University of Toronto Press, 2001).
71 Catharine A. MacKinnon, “Making Sex Equality Real,” in Righting the
Balance: Canada’s New Equality Rights, ed. Lynn Smith and others
(Saskatoon: Canadian Human Rights Reporter, 1986) 37–8.
72 MacKinnon 40–1.
73 See R. v. Bernardo (1994), 121 D.L.R. (4th) (Ont. C.A.), leave to appeal
to S.C.C. refused; [1995] S.C.C.A. 113; French Estate v. Ontario (A.G.),
[R. v. Bernardo] (1996), 134 D.L.R. (4th) 587 (Ont. Gen. Div.),
affirmed: (1988), 38 O.R. (3d) 347 (C.A.), leave to appeal to S.C.C.
refused [1998] S.C.C.A. No. 139; Kane v. Church of Jesus Christ
Christian Aryan Nations, [1992] No. 3, 1992, 18 C.H.R.R.D./1268; R. v.
Butler, [1992] 1 S.C.R. 452; R. v. Keegstra, [1996] 1 S.C.R. 458; R. v.
Seaboyer; R. v. Gayme, [1991] 2 S.C.R. 577; R. v. Sullivan, [1991] 1
S.C.R. 489; Law Society of British Columbia v. Andrews, [1989] 1 S.C.R.
143;Borowski v. Canada (A.G), [1989] 1 S.C.R. 342; Tremblay v.
Daigle, [1989] 2 S.C.R. 530; Tomen v. Ontario School Teachers’
Federation, [1989] S.C.C.A. No. 372; Brooks v. Canada Safeway Ltd.,
[1989] 1 S.C.R. 1219; and Canadian Newspapers Co. v. Canada (A.G.),
[1988] 2 S.C.R. 122.
74 These works include one book, M. Eberts and others, The Case for
Women’s Equality: The Federation of Woman Teachers’ Associations
of Ontario and the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms
(Toronto: The Federation, 1991), and several articles; “Sex Equality
and Nation-building in Canada: The Meech Lake Accord,” in Tulsa
Law Journal, 25 (1990): 735–57; “Making Sex Equality Real,” in
Righting the Balance: Canada’s New Equality Rights, ed. Lynn Smith
and others (Saskatoon: The Canadian Human Rights Reporter, 1986);
“Feminist Approaches to Sexual Assault in Canada and the United
States: A Brief Retrospective,” in Challenging Times: The Women’s
Movement in the United States and Canada, ed. Constance Backhouse
and David H. Flaherty (Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press,
1992) 186–92.
75 Carol Gilligan, In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and
Women’s Development (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1982).
76 Kim Campbell, “The Courage to Listen: How Inclusive Justice Can
Bring about Gender Equality and More,” in Gender Equality: A
Challenge for the Legal Profession, ed. Lynn Smith (Ottawa: Secretary
of State Women’s Program, 1992), 10; bound proceedings of the
Conference of the Canadian Bar Association’s Continuing Legal
Education Committee and Task Force on Gender Equality.
77 Annette Baier, “The Need for More than Justice in Science, Morality
and Feminist Theory,” in Science, Morality and Feminist Theory, ed.
Marsha Hanen and Kai Nielsen, Canadian Journal of Philosophy,
supplement 13 (Calgary: University of Calgary Press, 1987) 56.
78 Faye J. Crosby and others, “Affirmative Action: Psychological Data
and the Policy Debates,” [dated] 2003, American Psychological
Association Institutional Access: PsycArticles, [visited] 2 June 2003,
<http://www.psycinfo.com/library/display.cfm?
document=amp/2003/february/amp58293.html/>; published in
American Pyschologist 58.2 (February 2003): 93–115. Crosby is very
influential. See Susan D. Clayton and Faye J. Crosby, Justice, Gender,
and Affirmative Action (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press,
1992); and Faye J. Crosby and Cheryl VanDeVeer, eds., Sex, Race, and
Merit: Debating Affirmative Action in Education and Employment
(Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 2000).
79 Crosby and others 11.
80 Crosby and others 18 (our emphasis).
81 Crosby and others 10.
82 Consider one document from McGill University: The Annual Report
on Full-Time Academic Staffing Changes (D02–72), which was
presented to the Senate on 16 April 2003 by McGill’s vice-principal,
academic. Table 1 summarizes academic hiring at McGill from 1
January to 31 December 2002. The percentage of women in the pool
of applicants can be derived from the table and compared to the
number of women hired. All things being equal, fair hiring would be
indicated by a percentage of women hired equal to that of women in
the pool of applicants. Considering all those hired, in other words,
there should be one woman for every four people hired according to
the pools of female and male applicants. In fact, however, there is one
woman for every three. The rate of hiring women, therefore, is about
30% higher for women than it should be, given their representation in
the pool. A breakdown by faculty (those in which enough people were
hired to make the analysis statistically significant) shows that women
have a 56% advantage over men in engineering, 30% in science, and
27% in arts. Only in medicine were women hired at the rate indicated
by the pool.
83 Grant Brown, “The Politics of Preference: A Catalogue of Criticisms
of Employment Equity,” unpublished draught paper, 11.
84 Stephen Stern, “Jews and Employment Equity: An Unholy Alliance,”
Viewpoints, 23 (March 1995): 5. The author’s point, however, is that
Jews are now turning away from this tradition.
85 One historical account makes it clear that “there can be no doubt that
some of those in authority in the University had become alarmed by
the rapid rate of change in its character and that measures were taken
in the late 1920s and 1930s to limit the number of Jewish students
admitted to McGill. One of those measures was to require a higher
percentage in high school leaving examinations from Jewish
candidates than from others. The inevitable result was that the Jewish
students were on the whole more intelligent, more hardworking, and
won more prizes. In response to protests from the Jewish community
the measures were abandoned during the Second World War, and the
percentage began to rise again. By 1964, the last year statistics
concerning religion were gathered, it stood at over 28%” (Stanley
Frost and Sheila Rosenberg, “The McGill Student Body: Past and
Future Enrolment,” McGill Journal of Education, 15.1 (winter 1986):
43.
86 Promoting or protecting the gospel of love and truth, for example, has
been used repeatedly to justify inquisitions, witch hunts, and wars. But
religious ends are not the only ones that can be distorted as
justifications for brutality. Both the Marxist “classless society” and the
Nazi “organic community” were used in the twentieth century to
legitimate mass murder. It will not do to trivialize the problem at hand
by arguing that these examples of ends justifying means were extreme.
Of course they were. In addition, however, they were the logical
results of a mentality that, even under far more benign circumstances,
fails to acknowledge a moral bottom line beyond which we cannot
move without destroying the lofty ideals we are supposedly pursuing.
It will not do, moreover, to argue that some ends are better than
others. Who, after all, is to set the standard? An ideological cadre?
Perhaps, for those who sincerely believe that they alone know what is
best for everyone else. A survey of public opinion? Perhaps, for those
who assume that morality and popularity are synonymous. The point
here is that anything at all can be justified by intelligent and sincere
people in the name of some ostensibly or even truly noble end. The
premise is flawed, inherently flawed.
But could some means not be justified as ends in themselves and
not merely in view of other ends? Discrimination against men is
perfectly reasonable, many women (and some men) have come to
believe, because men supposedly deserve it. They believe that
discrimination against men can be justified not only on the grounds of
creating more opportunities for women (the means to an end) but also
on the grounds of punishing men (the end in itself). Variants of this
argument have been used not only by journalists and bureaucrats but
also by academics, those who are usually assumed to set the standard
for intellectual acuity (though not necessarily for moral insight).
87 Stanley Fish, “How the Pot Got to Call the Kettle Black,” Atlantic
Monthly, November 1993: 128–36.
88 John P. Field, “Letters,” Atlantic Monthly, February 1994: 8.
89 Stanley Fish, “Stanley Fish Replies,” Atlantic Monthly, February 1994:
12.
90 Steven Yates, “Letters,” Atlantic Monthly, February 1994: 10.
91 Fish 12.
92 Lee Dembart, “Letters,” Atlantic Monthly, February 1994: 11.
93 Fish 12.
94 Some groups do present special problems within any democratic
society but not because of any innate characteristics. Included are
those who oppose democracy but use its institutions to secure power
before destroying it, which is what the Nazis did in Weimar Germany.
Almost anything can be tolerated in a democracy except intolerance.
95 Neither is the world of art a microcosm of the larger society. Edward
Roth-stein has used similar arguments in connection with the
controversy of government funding for the National Endowment for
the Arts. Rothstein’s problem is what he calls the “ideology of
democracy.” According to this way of thinking, writes Rothstein, “not
only are all people created equal but so are all ideas and all cultures.
Even art, an essentially undemocratic achievement by extraordinary
gifted individuals, is thrust into a marketplace marked by clamorous
demands for democratic distribution” (“Where a Democracy and Its
Money Have No Place,” New York Times, 26 October 1997: 2:1). Once
that idea triumphs, Rothstein notes, it follows that rewards are based
on politics, not merit.
96 The longer a degree takes, however, the more expensive it is for the
university.
97 Consider the following: “Yet, there are many hurdles for those seeking
to do research at the MCRTW [McGill Centre for Research and Teaching
on Women]. There are, to begin, the challenges faced by younger
faculty members who, during the hiring freeze period, were assigned
large teaching loads making time for research limited. With many of
the women among these faculty members also called upon to take on
more than their share of committee work to provide gender
representation, time to do research has been at premium” (Shree
Mulay, “News from the MCRTW,” Newsletter (September 2001): 1.
98 Fish 12.
99 In “Politics of Preference,” Brown observes that “the debate concerns
preferential practices directly involving employment, rather than those
relating to education, welfare, or other social benefits which might
indirectly affect employment opportunities. The distinction is
important because job competitions are zero-sum games: an advantage
given to one candidate necessarily entails a handicap for the others. In
contrast, directing special attention toward certain groups in other
areas of social policy does not entail harming anyone else. Thus, to
use a standard illustration, segregating girls and boys in high school
science and math classes might benefit the girls in some ways without
causing the boys’ performance to degenerate [although the same
principle could be applied in ways, such as sexually segregated
schools, that would benefit boys at least as much as girls without
harming the latter] … Education, job training, and other pre-
employment equalization policies tend to expand the pool of qualified
candidates, whereas employment equity tends to constrict that pool”
(Brown 3; his emphasis). By focusing attention on individuals rather
than groups, opportunities for improvement would be made available
to everyone in need. And if most of the individuals in need were to
come from this or that group, then so be it.
100 Pay Equity Review: Introduction,” [dated] 21 January 2002,
Government of Canada, [visited] 20 October 2002,
<http://www.payequityreview.gc.ca/1200–e.html>.
101 “It’s Time for Working Women to Earn Equal Pay,”[undated], AFL-CIO,
[visited] 17 October 2002,
<http://www.aflcio.org/women/equalpay.htm>: 1–2 (our emphasis).
102 Strategy,” [undated], The Men’s Health Network, [visited] 15 March
2003, <http://www.menshealthnetwork.org/new_goals.html>: 2.
Warren Farrell points out that the ratio of work-related accidents is 2.4
men to 1 woman (Women Can’t Hear What Men Don’t Say: Destroying
Myths, Creating Love [New York: Penguin Putnam, 1999] 237).
American state laws, too, require public jurisdictions to eliminate sex-
based wage disparities. In Minnesota, for example, pay equity “is a
method of eliminating discrimination against women who are paid less
than men for jobs requiring comparable levels of expertise. This goes
beyond the familiar idea of ‘equal pay for equal work’ where men and
women with the same jobs must be paid equally. A policy to establish
pay equity usually means: 1) that all jobs will be evaluated and given
points according to the level of knowledge and responsibility required
to do the job; and 2) that salary adjustments will be made if it is
discovered that women are consistently paid less than men for jobs
with similar points … Pay equity does not replace collective
bargaining.” (“Pay Equity/Comparable Worth”, [dated] 5 October
2002, Minnesota North Star, Department of Employee Relations,
[visited] 17 October 2002, <http://www.doer.state.mn.us/lr-peqty/lr-
peqty.htm)>: 1).
103 Morley Gunderson and Paul Lanoie, “Program Evaluation Criteria
Applied to Pay Equity in Ontario,” published by Montreal’s Centre for
International Research and Analysis on Organizations (CIRANO) as
Working Paper 99s-38. See “Scientific Papers,” [dated] November
1999, CIRANO, [visited] 17 October 2002,
<http://www.cirano.qc.ca/en/publications.php?
annee=1999&cat=cs&tri=aut&filtrer=Execute>. Gunderson is CIBC
Professor of Youth Employment at the University of Toronto and
Professor at the Centre for Industrial Relations and the Department of
Economics. Lanoie works at CIRANO.
104 Gunderson and Lanoie 1.
105 Gunderson and Lanoie 1 (our emphasis). They add, “The
appropriateness of this target could be questioned especially in light of
the recent controversial evidence … indicating that females in Canada
(unlike in the U.S. and unlike males in Canada) are not significantly
penalized by working in female-dominated jobs” (Gunderson and
Lanoie 1).
106 Gunderson and Lanoie 9.
107 Gunderson and Lanoie 13.
108 Morton and Knopff, Charter Revolution 125.
109 Morton and Knopff, Charter Revolution 126.
110 Martin Loney, “Pay’s the Thing: The Federal Government’s Huge Pay-
Equity Bill Is a Monumental Boondoggle,” Time (Canadian edition),
24 August 1998, 56. Commenting on the gender war over pay equity
in the United States, Loney observes that in marketplace economics,
what might “appear to be discriminatory merely reflects the simple
laws of supply and demand, rather than any evil, masculine
conspiracy” (David Thomas, Not Guilty: The Case in Defense of Men
[New York: Morrow, 1993] 73). The same thing would be true of the
entertainment industry or any other industry. The fact that more people
buy tickets to see a male movie star than a female one (Thomas 74–7),
for instance, provides no reason to assume that Hollywood moguls
discriminate against the latter.
111 The wage gap might never close, because many women might continue
to take time off for their children or prefer to work part-time for many
years. As a result, the pool of women at the top might always be
smaller than the one for men. In this sense, the “glass ceiling” would
remain.
112 “Age discrimination continues to damage our society, reducing both
the incomes and the self-confidence of millions of Americans. A Louis
Harris survey, conducted in 1989, reported that one million workers
aged 50 to 64 believed that they would be forced to retire before they
were ready. Most of this group, anticipating an unwanted early
retirement, said they would prefer to work for years longer. Another
Harris survey, conducted in 1992, found that 5.4 million older
Americans – one in seven of those 55 and older who were not working
at that time – were willing to work but could not find a suitable job.
These discouraging statistics were cited in The Untapped Resource, a
1993 report on ‘The Americans Over 55 at Work Program,’ a 5–year
research effort conducted by the Commonwealth Fund to examine the
productive potential of older Americans” (“Age Discrimination: A
Pervasive and Damaging Influence,” [dated] 17 January 2002,
Administration on Aging, [visited] 15 March 2003,
<http://www.aoa.gov/factsheets/ageism.html>: 1). “From 1991 to
1995, an average of 17,000 workers annually brought age
discrimination complaints to the Equal Employment Opportunity
Commission (EEOC)” (“Age Discrimination” 3).
113 Weatherall v. Canada (A.G.), [1993] 2 S.C.R. 872.
114 Meehan 684.
115 Katherine Boo, “The Black Gender Gap,” Atlantic Monthly, January-
February 2003: 107.
116 Boo 107.
117 Boo 107.
118 Boo 108.
119 Paul Offner; quoted in Boo 108.
120 Boo 108.
121 Boo 109.
122 Jean Bethke Elshtain, “Thinking about Women, Christianity, and
Rights,” in Religious Human Rights in Global Perspective: Religious
Perspectives, ed. John Witte and Johan D. Van der Ryver (The Hague:
Martinus Nijhoff, 1996) 146.
123 Elsthain 147.
124 Elsthain 147.
125 Elshtain 148–9.
126 Elshtain 150.
127 Elshtain 152.

CHAPTER SIX

1 “Parenting after Separation,” [undated], Ontario Women’s Network on


Child Custody and Access (OWNCCA), [visited] 19 December 2002,
<http://www.owjn.org/custody/parent.htm>: 3.
2 K.C. Wilson, The Multiple Scandals of Child Support, 2nd ed.
(Richmond, VA: Harbinger Press, 2003) 6–7; 50.
3 Donna Laframboise, “This Is about Punishing Dad: Myth of the
Deadbeat Dad,” National Post, 28 March 2000: B-1. This is a
Canadian case; Americans face similar problems, but their taxes are
lower.
4 Robert Seidenberg, The Father’s Emergency Guide to Divorce-
Custody Battle: A Tour through the Predatory World of Judges,
Lawyers, Psychologists, and Social Workers in the Subculture of
Divorce (Takoma Park, MD: JES Books, 1997) 53–4.
5 What are the actual statistics on custody? Answering that question is
more complicated than one might think. American judges, according to
Robert Seidenberg, grant paternal custody in approximately 10% of the
cases (Seidenberg 11) and only in 3% to 5% of them when custody is
contested (Seidenberg 15). Canadian judges, according to Glenn
Cheriton, are not much different. They grant paternal custody in 11%
of the cases, joint custody in 12%, and maternal custody in 76% (other
arrangements being made in 1%). They grant material custody much
more often, though, after common-law separations. (Glenn Cheriton,
Child Support, Divorce, Custody, Access and Government Policy
[Ottawa: Commoner’s Publication Society, 1998]), 39.
Most divorced or separated parents do settle custody and child
support privately and sometimes even amicably. In Divorced Dads:
Shattering the Myths (New York: Tarcher/Putnam, 1998) Sanford
Braver points out that 18% of American divorce-and-custody cases
are settled by default (referring to the findings of Eleanor E. Maccoby
and Robert H. Mnookin in Dividing the Child: Social and Legal
Dilemmas of Custody [Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press,
1992]). This can mean one of three things: the husband and wife agree
over custody; one of them does not care enough to dispute the matter;
or one of them is “so distraught or otherwise impaired that he or she
cannot raise objections” (Braver 89). Another 14% are “self-settled.”
This means that disputes are settled without resorting to lawyers.
Some cases cannot be settled so amicably. Therefore, 9% resort to
mediators and 53% to lawyers. That comes to 94%. All of these cases,
presumably, end up with the ex-spouses agreeing on custody and other
aspects of divorce (although many male ones end up “agreeing”
because they believe that they have no hope of winning in the first
place). Only 5% end up in adjudication; they are brought before
judges, who impose decisions.
Only the relatively few problem cases come to light in newspaper
articles or on the websites of advocacy groups. Why worry about
them? For three reasons. One is that these cases are settled by the law,
and the law has a very powerful symbolic function, in addition to its
practical ones. In cases of this kind, it reveals very clearly what
society has come to believe about men, women, and children. Another
reason is that real people are involved, not merely statistical
abstractions. If the law is unfair for even a minority of citizens – in
this case, all divorced or separated fathers, including those whose
cases never come to light – then its legitimacy must surely be
questioned. Of even greater interest here, though, is its moral
legitimacy. But perhaps the most important reason is that all men who
pay child support are now under continual surveillance by the
government, even if they have never been in default. We discuss this
problem elsewhere.
6 Ideological rhetoric is present occasionally in the claims of advocates
for both divorced or separated mothers and divorced or separated
fathers; some people, both women and men, are at least partly
motivated by self-interest on either the individual level or the group
level. Neither side, generally speaking, is entirely altruistic. Neither
side is motivated entirely by the interests of children. This does not
mean, however, that either side ignores the interests of children – or,
for that matter, of society as a whole – because both sides have also
campaigned for particular (though often conflicting) interests of
children.
7 Wendy McElroy, “Does Rape Violate the Commerce Clause of the
Constitution?” [dated] 3 July 2002, WendyMcElroy.co: A Site for
Individualist Feminism and Individualist Anarchism, [visited] 1 June
2002, http://www.zetetics.com/mac/articles/brzonkala.html>: 4; this
article appeared in Ideas on Liberty, 50: 1 (2000).
8 Stephen Baskerville, “The Myth of Deadbeat Dad,” Liberty (June
2002): 27.
9 K.C. Wilson, “Co-parenting and Shared Parenting: Why It Should
Almost Always Be Used, and How to Do It,” [dated] 2000, Harbinger
Press, [visited] 3 June 2003, http://wheres-
daddy.com/fatherhood/childsupport.htm.; referring to data in Judi
Bartfeld and Daniel R. Meyer, “Are There Really Deadbeat Dads? The
Relationship between Ability to Pay, Enforcement, and Compliance in
Nonmarital Child Support Cases,” Social Service Review, 68.2 (1994):
219–35; also dp#994–93, Madison, WI: Institute for Research on
Poverty, March 1993.
10 Baskerville, “Myth” 28.
11 Baskerville, “Myth” 27.
12 The term “divorce revolution” was coined by Lenore Weitzman in the
title of her book and the term “divorce culture” by Barbara Dafoe
Whitehead in the title of hers; we have already referred to the former
and will refer to the latter in due course.
13 Baskerville, “Myth” 28. The same point is made by Seidenberg,
although he adds that the whole move to get women off welfare in this
particular way was provoked by false statistics (which we discuss in
appendix 3). “President Clinton, Secretary of Health and Human
Services Donna Shalala, and Attorney General Janet Reno, along with
a host of senators and representatives, proclaimed there was a ‘$34
billion child-support gap’ and claimed that stronger child support
enforcement measures could remove 800,000 mothers and children
from the welfare roles. But the ‘$34 billion gap’ is a fiction. It has its
roots in a hypothetical model that occurs in a single paper created by a
single individual – Elaine Sorensen of the Urban Institute, a liberal
think-tank in Washington, D.C.” (Seidenberg 65; citing Noncustodial
Fathers: Can They Afford to Pay More Child Support?, a report
produced in 1994 at the Urban Institute, Washington). “According to
the statistics of the Census Bureau and the Federal Office of Child
Support Enforcement, the ‘collection gap’ for the period Ms. Sorensen
examined was not $34 billion, but somewhere between $3 and $5
billion” (Seidenberg 59; citing Seventeenth Annual Report to
Congress, for the Period Ending September 30, 1992, a report from
the Department of Health and Human Services, Office of Child
Support Enforcement).
Wilson mentions the same problem, claiming that the figure can be
established only if “1. All custodial parents [usually mothers] have
orders for child support. (Commonly, 44 to 48% do not seek one.) 2.
Those without orders are getting no child support. (At least 32% say
they are.) 3. There is no joint custody. (Between 10 to 15% of
currently divorced couples use joint custody.) 4. All cases have their
child support amounts set according to the recently introduced
Wisconsin Guidelines (which less than one-third of all states use). 5.
All obligators (non-custodial parents; fathers) are making average or
better incomes and able to pay these amounts” (Wilson, Multiple
Scandals 6–7). According to Seidenberg, “[C]hild support
enforcement has been ineffective in bridging this gap, as the
Government Accounting Office … has reported, because 66 percent of
unpaid child support is due to the obligor’s inability to pay. Further, 73
percent of all child support collections comes from non-welfare cases”
(Seidenberg 59; citing Seventeenth Annual Report). “Collecting more
money from these fathers has no effect on the welfare roles.
Nonetheless, based on ‘Ms. Information,’ the 104th Congress passed
draconian bills to revoke driver’s and professional licenses from
fathers who fall behind in child support” (Seidenberg 59).
Elsewhere, Seidenberg discusses another contested statistical
figure: that fathers win half the battles over custody. He traces this
figure to a story run by the Washington Post (Barbara Vobejda and
D’Vera Cohn, “As Custody Laws Level the Field, Father Often Does
Better,” Washington Post, 14 November 1994: A-1 ff.). The authors
claim that divorced fathers face little or no discrimination in court.
After observing that “studies suggest” this, they fail to identify a
single one. Instead, they refer to three isolated cases. “Three cases
from three separate jurisdictions do not a trend make,” writes
Seidenberg, “much less prove that fathers are winning half the time.
Moreover, all the cited cases had received national media coverage, a
fact that itself throws the authors’ ‘50-percent’ premise into question.
Thousands of fathers lose custody every week, and nobody writes
about it. But when a mother loses custody, it is, literally, headline
news. The media is its own best evidence that a father winning
custody is still a ‘man-bites-dog’ story” (Seidenberg 60 [his
emphasis]).
Even government figures can be misleading. “Deadbeat Dad
statistics published by the U.S. government include fathers who are
only marginally behind in child support, fathers who are paid up on
child support but whose ex-wives have falsely reported them as not
paying, fathers who have moved back in with the mother and children,
and fathers who are literally dead (according to the Government
Accounting Office, 14 percent of ‘Deadbeat Dads’)”(Seidenberg 112;
citing “Mothers Say Fathers Unable to Pay,” Speak Out for Children,
8.1 [1992–1993]).
Of more importance here, though, are some other statistics that
Seidenberg gathered. According to him, approximately 90% of what is
due for child support is paid voluntarily by divorced fathers who have
jobs (Seidenberg 114; citing “Mothers Say”), most failures to pay
being due to unemployment. Not surprisingly, moreover, willingness
to pay is directly related to access. Fathers with joint custody pay 90%
of what they owe; those with visitation pay 79%; and those with
neither pay only 45% (Seidenberg 122; citing U.S. Bureau of the
Census, “Child Support and Alimony: 1989,” Current Population
Reports, Series P-60, no. 173 [Washington, D.C.: Government Printing
Office, 1991]).
14 Wilson, Multiple Scandals, 25. “Only 4% of the non-custodial parents
whose earnings drop by more than 15% are able to get a reduction in
support payments” (Elaine Sorensen, “A Little Help for Some
‘Deadbeat Dads,’” Washington Post, 15 November 1995, A-25);
quoted in Wilson, Multiple Scandals 51.
15 “Prior to 1989, non-welfare cases generally were argued on a case-by-
case basis but within parameters established by statute and case law.
With the Family Support Act of 1988, the U.S. Congress established
funding incentives for states to adopt statewide child support
guidelines. The states had only one year to implement statewide
presumptive guidelines – but in reality, the deadline was tighter since
most state legislatures do not operate year-round. Federal regulations –
without requiring any specific guidelines – require that state guidelines
be based on economic data and result in an economically appropriate
award. The intent of the new law and regulations was to boost the
level of award ‘adequacy,’ to create uniformity in application for child
support awards, and to simplify the process of child support
determination – all of which theoretically would reduce the incentive
to seek modifications or to contest the original finding” (R. Mark
Rogers and Donald J. Bieniewicz, Child Cost Economics and
Litigation Issues: An Introduction to Applying Cost Shares Child
Support Guidelines, [dated] 17 october 2002, [visited] 29 December
2003,
<http://www.guidelineeconomics.com/files/LitigationIssues.pdf>: 2.
This paper was presented at the Southern Economic Association
Annual Meeting, Section for the National Association of Forensic
Economics (Alexandria, Virginia, 12 November 2000). See also the
published version of this paper: R. Mark Rogers and Donald J.
Bieniewicz, “Child Cost Economics and Litigation Issues: An
Inroduction to Applying Cost Shares Child Support Guidelines,” in
Assessing Damages in Injuries and Deaths of Minor Children (Tucson,
AZ: Lawyers and Judges Publishing Company, 2002).
16 Wilson, Multiple Scandals 25–6.
17 “Prosecutive Guidelines and Procedures for the Child Support
Recovery Act of 1992,” [dated] 25 February 1997, Office of the
Attorney General, [visited] 21 June 2002
<http://www.usdoj.gov/ag/readingroom/childspt2.htm>: 1.
18 “Prosecutive Guidelines” 2–3.
19 The act had previously been known as Bill hr 1488.
20 “Johnson Announces Hearing on H.R. 1488, the ‘Hyde-Woolsey’ Child
Support Bill,” [dated] 8 March 2000, Advisory from the Committee on
Ways and Means Subcommittee on Human Resources, [visited] 9
December 2002,
<http://waysandmeans.house.gov/humres/106cong/hr-18.htm>: 1.
21 Federal Child Support Guidelines: A Technical Report,” Research
Report CSR-1997–IE: 2, 4.
22 “Family Responsibility Office: Introduction,” and “Enforcement,”
[undated], Ontario: Ministry of Community, Family and Children’s
Services, [visited] 22 December 2002,
<http://www.gov.on.ca/css/page/services/fro/>: 1–3.
23 See Braver.
24 The eight-year study, called Noncustodial Parent: Parents without
Children, began in 1985 at Arizona State University. Braver’s
colleagues were Sharlene Wolchik and Irwin Sandler. In 1996, as a
result, Braver served on a panel for the conference called in response
to President Clinton’s Fatherhood Initiative.
25 Braver 124–45.
26 Braver 87–107.
27 Braver 55–86.
28 Braver 108–23.
29 Braver 16–37.
30 Braver 38–54.
31 Braver 128–9; referring to A. Burns and C. Scott, Mother-Headed
Families and Why They Have Increased (Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence
Erlbaum Associates, 1994).
32 Braver 124–45. Although this figure shocks the public, as Braver
shows, it is accepted by the authors of both academic or popular works
on the topic. See, for example, David Chambers, Making Fathers Pay
(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1979) 29, and Seidenberg 35.
Ditto for feminists. See Lenore J. Weitzman, The Divorce Revolution:
The Unexpected Social and Economic Consequences for Women and
Children in America (New York: Free Press, 1985) 460 – although
Weitzman’s use of some other statistics is highly questionable, to say
the least, as we show further on in this chapter and in appendix 3.
33 According to Statistics Canada, the figure is 74.05% for 1992–94. See
Cheriton 13; citing catalogue number 84–213.
34 Candis McLean, “Legal Bloodletting: Maintenance-Enforcement
Programs Are Ruining Too Many Lives,” The Report, 15 April 2002:
4.
35 Stephen Baskerville, “Q: Is Court-ordered Child Support Doing More
Harm Than Good?” [dated] 2 August 1999, Insight on the News,
[visited] 1 July 2002, <www.insightmag.com/main.cfm?
include=detail&stroyid=215429>: 2.
36 John Tierny, “New Look at Realities of Divorce,” New York Times, 11
July 2000: B-1; citing Margaret F. Brinig and Douglas W. Allen,
“These Boots Are Made for Walking: Why Most Divorce Filers Are
Women,” American Law and Economics Review 2 (2000): 126–69.
37 Tierny B-1.
38 Margaret F. Brinig; quoted in Tierny B-1.
39 Seidenberg 112–113.
40 Our premise in this chapter is that men face severe problems in
connection with divorce and custody. But men face severe problems
even in connection with separation after cohabiting. And we are not
referring only to “palimony.” Grant A. Brown has written a brilliant
analysis of the Canadian laws that govern “unjust enrichment,” for
instance (in “Unjust Enrichment in Cohabitation,” an unpublished
manuscript). This term refers to lawsuits in which one partner, usually
a woman, claims to have been denied adequate monetary
compensation for services provided within a common-law
relationship. Brown analyzes one case that went to the Supreme Court:
Peter v. Beblow [1993] 1 S.C.R. 90; (1993) 44 F.L.R. (3d) 329. Mrs Peter
sued Mr Beblow for unjust enrichment at her expense. Here is what
happened. Mrs Peter and her four children came to live with Mr
Beblow and his two children. They agreed to pool their resources. His
task was to provide room and board, hers to maintain the house and
look after the children (her children alone after several years, because
the Beblow children had grown up and moved out). When they
separated, after twelve years, Mrs Peter claimed that the years at home
had deprived her of a college education and higher career expectations
(even though the main reason that she had stayed home in the first
place was to look after her own children, not Mr Beblow and his
children, and the two had agreed on this arrangement from the very
beginning). The Court agreed with Mrs Peter, nonetheless, that Mr
Beblow had been unjustly enriched at her expense and therefore made
him pay her restitution. Brown shows that the Court’s calculations
were based on illogical, false, or openly biased principles (such as
calculating the monetary value of services provided by Mrs Peter but
not of those provided by Mr Beblow). In fact, he shows that the legal
system governing cases of this kind reveal systemic discrimination
against men (not merely the opinions of these justices but the laws
themselves) and for explicitly political reasons (because the Court
cited the “feminization of poverty” and the undervaluation of
“traditional women’s work” in the home as major problems to be
solved by using the law in this way). In short, the system is corrupt.
Some details of this case – it is taught uncritically and even
sympathetically in law schools – are so preposterous, so grotesque,
that we encourage readers to contact the author, at
[email protected], for more information.
41 Braver refers to Martha Fineman, The Illusion of Equality: Rhetoric
and the Reality of Divorce Reform (Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1991); Kathleen Mahoney, “Gender Issues in Family Law:
Leveling the Playing Field for Women,” Family and Conciliation
Courts Review 34 (1996): 198–218; Lenore J. Weitzman, The Divorce
Revolution: The Unexpected Social and Economic Consequences for
Women and Children in America (New York: Free Press, 1985); Terry
Arendell, Mothers and Divorce: Legal, Economic and Social
Dilemmas (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1986); Fathers
and Divorce (Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage, 1995); and Mary Ann Mason,
The Equality Trap (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1988).
42 Seidenberg 7.
43 See Weitzman.
44 Geoffrey Christopher Rapp, “Lies, Damned Lies, and Lenore J.
Weitzman,” <http://www.acbr.com/biglie.htm>: 1. This website is
undated and has no name other than the title of this page.
45 Rapp 1.
46 Braver 119–21.
47 Braver 121–2.
48 Braver 114.
49 Braver 118–19.
50 Braver 116.
51 David Blankenhorn, Fatherless America: Confronting Our Most
Urgent Social Problem (New York: Basic Books, 1995), 156–7;
quoted in Braver 118.
52 The National Institute of Mental Health acknowledges that the number
of male suicides per year is on average four times the number of
female suicides. They explain this phenomenon in various ways. Men
use guns more often than women, for instance, and are therefore
successful more often. Or men are more aggressive than women
(“Frequently Asked Questions,” [updated] 3 January 2000, National
Institute of Mental Health, [visited] 21 December 2002,
<http://www.nimh.nih.gov/research/suicidefaq.cfm>: 1). But scholars
have begun to examine variables such as marital status. Both R.G.
Rogers (“Marriage, Sex, and Mortality,” Journal of Marriage and the
Family 57 [1995]: 515–26) and A.J. Kposowa (“Marital Status and
Suicide in the National Longitudinal Mortality Study,” Journal of
Epidemiology and Community Health 54 [2000]: 254–61) found that
divorced or separated men are much more likely than divorced or
separated women to commit suicide. Because divorce often separates
men from their children, observe J.S. Wallerstein and S. Blakeslee,
they often experience depression, failure, and self-hatred (Second
Chances: Men, Women, and Children a Decade after Divorce [New
York: Ticknor and Fields, 1989] 235). See also J.M. Ross, The Male
Paradox [New York: Simon and Schuster, 1992] 154–7). This topic
has not yet been studied adequately, but a great deal of anecdotal
evidence links divorce, custody battles, unfair child-support payments,
and separation from children with depression and suicide among men.
See also Associated Press [David Crary], “Divorced Fathers Snap
under Pressure,” Washington Times, 25 November 2002: A-7).
53 “These results dramatise the terrible consequences of being a divorced
man in America, and lead to the question: why are divorced men
killing themselves … As Perrault and Farrell observe, while social,
psychological, and even personal problems facing women are readily
denounced, societal institutions tend to ignore or minimise male
problems as evident in suicide statistics … As depression and poor
mental health are known markers of suicide risk, it may well be that
one of the fundamental reasons for the observed association between
divorce and suicide in men is the impact of post divorce (court
sanctioned) ‘arrangements’” (Augustine J. Kposowa, “Divorce and
Suicide Risk,” Journal of Epidemiology and Community Health, 57.12
[December 2003]: 993).
54 Baskerville, “Myth” 30.
55 Wilson, Multiple Scandals 20.
56 Margaret F. Brinig; quoted in Tierny B-1.
57 Ronald K. Henry, “Child Support at a Crossroads: When the Real
World Intrudes upon Academic Advocates, [dated] 1999, Alliance for
Non-custodial Parents Rights, [visited] 1 July 2002,
<http://www.ancpr.org/ronhenry.htm>, 24, note 26; this article was
published in Family Law Quarterly 33.1 (1999): 235–58.
58 Braver 23–5.
59 Braver 54.
60 For the statistical profile of an American middle-class family, see
Henry.
61 In the United States, according to Rogers and Bieniewicz, there are
several basic child-support models. The Wisconsin model is based on
a percentage of the noncustodial parent’s income; that of the custodial
parent is considered irrelevant. The percentage varies according to
income but increases with the number of children. Only about a dozen
states use this model. The Incomes Shares model (also known as the
Robert Williams model) takes into account the incomes of both
parents. It is based on the assumption that a child’s standard of living
should remain the same after a divorce (Wilson, Multiple Scandals
66). Child-support payments rise with income. About thirty-five states
use this model. The Delaware-Melson model, a hybrid based on the
other two, was created for welfare families. Only a few states use it
(Rogers and Bienewicz 2).
62 According to Finance Canada, 99% of the money collected for child
support comes from men (Cheriton 15, 23, and 33).
63 Roger Gay observes that child support has been used to prevent the
impoverishment of custodial parents, usually wives. This makes it a
kind of hidden alimony. Gay, who has testified in Congress, found that
“traditional child support law held that to a practical extent, children
should be sheltered from the standard of living loss that accompanies
divorce. This led to what has been known as a standard of living
adjustment or ‘add-on’ in some models. No one had derived a formula
for calculating the amount of the adjustment, and some researchers
seemed to believe such derivation impossible” (Roger F. Gay, “Child
Support Project Summary,” [dated] 25 May 2002, Project for the
Improvement of Child Support Litigation Technology, [visited] 3 July
2002, <http://www.geocities.com?CapitolHIll/5910/index.html>: 2).
He finds that no fair calculation is possible unless it makes a careful
distinction between child support and spousal support. Hidden
alimony is a very serious moral and legal problem because it involves
the government in politically motivated duplicity and thus reinforces
public cynicism (Gay 2). Referring to another problem, Gay observes
that we need data on how much is actually spent on children, in order
to develop a complete theoretical model.
64 In 1999, according to one American study, the average cost of one
child was approximately $600 a month. Child tax benefits were
approximately $200 a month, however, which meant that the final cost
was approximately $400 a month. The average award was between
$600 and $1,300 a month, nonetheless, and was paid entirely by the
non-custodial parent (Wilson, Multiple Scandals 65; he refers to a
study by the Family Economics Research Group [Department of
Agriculture]. For a household with an annual income of $12,000 to
$90,000, the money actually spent on one child ranged from $462 to
$995 a month.)
65 According to longitudinal studies on the children of single parents,
however, it has become clear that two parents are better than one. It
makes sense. After all, sharing the work load and time spent with
children, no matter how unequally, is surely better – and easier – than
not doing so. But given the political and ideological rhetoric glorifying
single mothers, saying so in public had to be supported by statistical
research. Among the first to provide evidence of this kind was Barbara
Dafoe Whitehead (The Divorce Culture: Rethinking Our Commitments
to Marriage and the Family [New York: Random House, 1996]). Here
are some recent findings. The children of single parents are less likely
to stay in school (Brigitte Berger, “The Social Roots of Prosperity and
Liberty,” Society, 35.3 [March-April 1998]: 44; Linda J. Waite, “Does
Marriage Matter?” Demography, 32.4 [November 1995]: 483, 494);
more likely to live in poverty (Waite 494); less likely to be adequately
socialized (Sanford M. Dornbusch and others, “Single Parenthood,”
Society 30:5 (July 1996): 30); more likely to be unmarried when they
have children of their own (Waite 494); and so on. According to one
authority, the two-parent household is “by far the most emotionally
stable and economically secure arrangement for child rearing” (Berger
44). So much for the need of children for two parents, whether
biological or adoptive. What about the specific need for fathers?
Among the first to discuss that was David Blankenhorn. According to
Michael Gurian, at any rate “the single most important factor in
determining if a male will end up incarcerated later in life is …
whether or not he has a father in the home” (The Good Son: Shaping
the Moral Development of Our Boys and Young Men [New York:
Jeremy Tarcher, 1999] 182).
66 When American noncustodial parents have their children for 20% of
the time, according to Paul Henman and Kyle Mitchell, the cost is
40% of what it would be in an intact middle-income couple household
and more than 50% of what it would be in an intact low-income
household. This is explained by the cost of maintaining two
households and of providing transportation (Paul Henman and Kyle
Mitchell, “Estimating the Costs of Contact for Non-resident Parents: A
Budget Standards Approach,” Journal of Social Policy 30.3 [2001]:
495–520). Many Canadian mothers have figured out that the ideal
situation is to have their former husbands care for the children 40% of
the time. This way, the former remain “receiving parents” and are
allowed to collect child-support payments. In addition, they reduce
their own expenses. While the children are living with their fathers,
after all, the latter must provide for their daily needs. And it does not
work that way in reverse (Soever 26)!
67 In the United States, say Rogers and Bieniewicz, “[u]se of gross
income for guidelines ignores the advantage that custodial parents
receive from preferential tax treatment. This advantage typically is
worth several hundred dollars in net income per month. For example,
at gross income of $4,000, the custodial parent with two children has
about $370 more net income per month than the noncustodial parent to
support the children (roughly $4,400 after tax extra income annually).
At low-income levels, the difference is quite striking. A little above
the poverty level, for equal levels of gross income, the custodial parent
has 30 to 50 percent more after-tax income than the non-custodial
parent for which to support the children due to favorable tax treatment.
On a final note regarding ability to pay near the poverty level, the
above analysis does not include discussion of other potential cost
offsets that a custodial parent has that the NCP [non-custodial parent]
does not have – or at least the CP has more readily. Food stamps, WIC
[Women, Infants, and Children], Medicaid, housing subsidies are
generally more available to the CP and are not part of the formula for
sharing child costs and cost offsets with the NCP. Because of these tax
code changes, for a given level of gross income, the custodial parent
has a significantly higher ability to provide the CP’s share of child
costs compared to the NCP. Use of gross income without adjustments
for sharing the child tax benefits between both parents clearly creates
an unequal burden for the NCP” (Rogers and Bieniewicz 10–11). They
add that “the same standard of living cannot be sustained as in an
intact two-parent household. Notably, the maximum standard of living
that can be maintained in both households is the average income of
both parents (Rogers and Bieniewicz 16).
68 The notion of a “standard case,” according to Henry, is based on the
assumption that American women earn only approximately 75% of
what men earn. (Henry 24, note 21). Guidelines were established on
the basis of a hypothetical family consisting of a custodial parent, a
noncustodial parent, and two children. Henry refers to several flawed
figures. “Twenty-five percent of gross income is used as an average
child support guideline amount for two children” (Henry 23, note 20).
That 25% was based on the dubious figure – 75% – just mentioned.
We showed in chapter 5, however, that the latter was skewed in favour
of women. Besides, it would not reflect the situations of actual people
involved in particular conflicts. It would surely be more fair to
calculate on the basis of each case. If the woman earns more than the
average woman, for instance, then that fact would be factored into the
amount of child support. In other words, a just system would look at
the specific earnings of both the father and the mother. Guidelines
could specify amounts as percentages of actual incomes, for instance,
rather than as theoretical averages.
69 Roger F. Gay, “A Return to Welfare as We Knew It: The Beginning of
the End of Child Support Reform,” [dated] 21 March 2002, Project for
the Improvement of Child Support Litigation Technology, [visited] 1
July 2002; published at Men’s News Daily and Toogood Reports,
<http://www.geocities.com/capitolhill/5910/Georgia_consequences.ht
m>: 2.
70 Consider the case of Darrin White of Prince George, British Columbia.
White “killed himself a month after a judge ordered him to make
spousal and child support payments more than double his income …
White was ordered to pay $2,071 a month to support his ex-wife and
three children. He was already paying $439 a month to support an
older child from a previous marriage, bringing his total monthly
obligations to $2,510. But White’s after-tax monthly income was only
$950 in disability stress pay” (Canadian Press, “Support Payment
Suicide: Man Told to Pay Twice What He Made,” Toronto Sun, 23
March 2000: 59).
71 McLean 1. Similar things have happened elsewhere. In Britain, the
National Association for Child Support Action has noted fifty-five
cases of suicide (“The Book of the Dead,” [undated] National
Association for Child Support Action,[visited] 5 December 2002,
<http://www.nacsa.org/>; cited in Baskerville, “Myth” 30).
72 Nicholas Riccardi and Greg Krikorion, “Failure to Provide: Los
Angeles County’s Child Support Crisis,” Los Angeles Times, 11
October 1998, A-1; cited in Henry, 25, note 29.
73 Wilson, Multiple Scandals 44.
74 Wilson, Multiple Scandals 28.
75 Wilson, Multiple Scandals 44.
76 Baskerville, “Myth” 30.
77 According to Wilson, his company is worth $40 million and has
expanded into Canada and Australia (Wilson, Multiple Scandals, 57).
Other companies include Lockheed Martin and Maximus. “Frequently,
all three child-support collection companies will not just act as
administrator but adjudicator, issuing administrative child support
orders. That is, they set and alter the amounts of support in cases for
which they are paid a percentage of what they collect and/or a fee for
opening and closing cases” (Wilson, Multiple Scandals 58). What
about due process?
78 Baskerville, “Myth” 29.
79 “Formula for the Tables of Amounts Contained in the Federal Child
Support Guidelines: A Technical Report,” Research Report CSR-1997–
IE.
80 Alar Soever, “The Federal Child Support Guidelines: A Breakdown of
Democratic Process and the Canadian Legal System,” [dated] 4 April
2002, Fathers Are Capable Too, [visited] 17 February 2004,
<http://www.fact.on.ca/fathome/header.htm>: 28.
81 Soever 2.
82 Soever 18.
83 Cheriton, personal communication.
84 The English tradition of common law, stretching back five hundred
years and recognized today in countries such as Britain, the United
States, and Canada, presumes that any child born during a marriage is
the husband’s. The goal is to prevent children from being branded
“illegitimate.”
85 “United States Supreme Court Refuses to Hear Case of Paternity Fraud
Victim,” [dated] 12 June 2002, PRWeb: The Free Wire Service,
[visited] 10 December 2002,
<http://www.prweb.com/releases/2002/6/prweb40284.php>: 1.
86 “Father Takes DNA Paternity Fraud Case to U.S. Supreme Court,”
[dated] 31 May 2002, Men’s News Daily, [visited] 1 July 2002,
<http://www.mensnewsdaily.com’stories/newswire053102a.htm>: 1.
87 “Father Takes DNA” 1.
88 Legislation varies wildly from one of these states to another. In 1994
Illinois passed the Unlawful Visitation Interference law (Public Act
8896). By late 2002, a bill pending in Vermont would make it a felony
for mothers to spread false allegations of this kind, put her in jail for
up to two years, and fine her up to $5,000.
89 Martin Kasindorf, “Men Wage Battle on ‘Paternity Fraud,’” USA
Today, 3 December 2002: A-03.
90 Burt Riddick; quoted in Kasindorf.
91 Mary Ann Sieghart, “Women Behaving Badly,” London Times, 28
November 1998: 22.
92 Baskerville, “Q” 4.
93 Baskerville, “Q” 3.
94 There is a debate over the statistics on how many men presumed to be
biological fathers are, in fact, biologically unrelated to their presumed
children. Carolyn Abraham writes that the lowest figure would be 5%
and the highest 30%, with 15% to 18% being commonly accepted
(Carolyn Abraham, “Mommy’s Little Secret,” Globe and Mail, 14
December 2002: F-1).
95 Cristin Schmitz, “Man Cut off from Son at Birth: Must Pay Child
Support: Full Amount Owed Even Though Stepfather Also Pays,
Ontario Court Orders, National Post, 6 April 2002: A-02.
96 Consider the storm of controversy that followed Vice-President Dan
Quayle’s comments about Murphy Brown. He was widely ridiculed for
criticizing a show that allowed the leading character to bring up a baby
without a father. Single mothers have been praised, moreover, on
countless talk shows. But support for single motherhood by choice,
which does not apply to mothers who are either widowed or
abandoned, comes not only from popular culture. See below for a
discussion of the Feminist International Network of Resistance to
Reproductive and Genetic Engineering.
97 Sarah Schmidt, “Ontario Court Gives Mother Sole Power on Child
Surname: Decision Based on Wording of Statute from Peterson Era,”
[dated] 28 June 2002, [no name for website], [visited] 23 September
2002,
<http://www.lapresrupture.qc.ca/cpaJune28_SarahSchmidt.html>: 1;
this story actually appeared in the National Post on 21 June. See
Kreklewetz v. Scopel (2002) 60 O.R. (3d) 187 (C.A.).
98 Schmidt 1.
99 Schmidt 1.
100 Schmidt 2.
101 Trociuk v. British Columbia (Attorney General) 2003 S.C.C. 34. “On the
basis of his sex, the impugned provisions expose the father to the
possible arbitrary exclusion of his particulars from his children’s birth
registration, and, consequently, of his participation in choosing their
surname. Moreover, having been so exposed, the father is provided no
recourse. The impugned distinctions affect significant interests and do
so in a way that the reasonable claimant in the appellant’s
circumstances would perceive as harmful to his dignity. A birth
registration is not only an instrument of prompt recording. It evidences
the biological ties between parent and child, and including one’s
particulars on the registration is a means of affirming these ties.
Contribution to the process of determining a child’s surname is another
significant mode of participation in the life of a child … Arbitrary
exclusion from these means of participation negatively affects an
interest that is significant to a father” (Trociuk v. British Colmbia
(Attorney General), [visited] 16 January 2004,
<http://www.lexum.unmontreal.ca/csc-
scc/en/rec/texte/2003scc034.wpd.txt>. Note, however, that mothers
may still refuse to acknowledge the surnames of fathers in specific
circumstances – notably rape and incest.
102 Baskerville, “Q” 1–3.
103 Baskerville, “Myth” 30. The increase in the amount of money
collected – it doubled between 1992 and 2000 – is accomplished not
by “collecting from fathers in welfare-related cases but from
increasing the number of employed, middle-class fathers” (Baskerville,
“Myth” 30) and increasing the amount that each owes.
104 Robert O’Harrow, “Uncle Sam Has All Your Numbers: Huge Net for
Dead-beat Dads Catches Privacy Criticism,” Washington Post, 27 June
1999: A-01; quoted in Baskerville, “Myth” 30.
105 Steve Dasbach, Libertarian Party press release, 11 February 1998;
quoted in Baskerville, “Myth” 30.
106 Baskerville, “Myth” 31.
107 Baskerville, “Q” 2–3.
108 Baskerville, “Myth” 28.
109 Seidenberg 48–9.
110 “About,” [undated], National Child Support Enforcement Association,
[visited] 3 July 2002, <http://www.ncsea.org/about>, quoted in
Baskerville, “Myth” 28.
111 Baskerville, “Myth” 28.
112 Baskerville, “Myth” 28–9.
113 F.L. Morton and Rainer Knopff, The Charter Revolution and the Court
Party (Toronto: Broadview Press, 2000) 107.
114 Seidenberg 11.
115 Gene Colman; cited in “Fathers Lose in Family Court Because of
Judicial Interpretation Says Respected Family Law Lawyer,”
[undated], Canada Court Watch Report, [visited] 9 December 2002,
<http://www.shareparenting.com>: 1.
116 Carey Linde; quoted in “Fathers Lose” 1.
117 Linde; quoted in “Fathers Lose” 1–2.
118 Edward Greenspan; quoted in “Fathers Lose” 2.
119 Other books include the following: Jeffrey Leving and Kenneth
Dachman, Fathers’ Rights: Hard Hitting and Fair Advice for Every
Father Involved in a Custody Dispute (New York: Basic Books, 1997);
John Steinbreder and Richard Kent, Fighting for Your Children: A
Father’s Guide to Custody (Dallas: Taylor, 1998); Douglas Darnall,
Divorce Casualties: Protecting Children from Parental Alienation
(Dallas: Taylor, 1998); Richard Warshak, Divorce Poison: Protecting
the Parent-Child Bond from a Vindictive Ex (New York: ReganBooks,
2001); Richard Gardner, The Parental Alienation Syndrome: A Guide
For Mental Health and Legal Professionals (Cresskill, NJ: Creative
Therapeutics, 1998); Ashton Applewhite, Cutting Loose: Why Women
Who End Their Marriages Do So Well (New York: HarperCollins,
1997); and Carleen Brennan and Michael Brennan, Custody for
Fathers: A Practical Guide through the Combat Zone of a Brutal
Custody Battle (Costa Mesa, CA: Brennan, 1994). The latter is a typical
how-to manual: how to beat a system, legally, that is stacked against
fathers. It includes advice on how to win custody, warnings against
procedural errors, definitions of legal jargon, discussions of the
psychology of judges, suggestions for clothing to be worn in court,
insights on body language, and so on. Unlike some guides, this one
avoids a polemical tone and advises readers to work within the system.
It compares the problem to a football game, which requires strategies
and counterstrategies.
120 “Canadian Families against Abuse by the Legal System,” [updated] 23
July 2002, Surviving the Horrors of Canada’s Morally Corrupt Family
Court Legal System, [visited] 9 December 2002,
<http://sharedparent.freeyellow.com/SurvivingTheHorrorsOfFamilyCo
urt.pdf>.
121 “Canadian Families” 1.
122 Paula Roberts, “[An Ounce of Prevention and a Pound of Cure:]
Developing State Policy on the Payment of Child Support Arrears [by
Low-income Parents],” [dated] May 2001, Alliance for Non-Custodial
Parents Rights, [visited] 1 July 2002; published by the Charles Stewart
Mott Foundation, the Ford Foundation, the Public Welfare Foundation,
the Moriah Fund, and the Open Society Institute,
<http://www.ancpr.org/developing_state_policy_on_the_p.htm>: 6.
123 United States v. Timothy Gordon Faase, 265 f.3d 475 (2001). Glenn
Reynolds argues that the framers of the Constitution wanted strict
limitations on federal powers and that these were gradually increased
by exploiting the Commerce Clause to regulate things other than
commerce. This strategy received its first setback in the case of United
States v. Lopez, 514 U.S. 549 (1995), when the “Court of Appeals for
the Fifth Circuit struck down the 1990 Gun-Free School Zones Act,
finding it beyond the power of Congress to enact. Such a finding is all
but unheard of in the post-New Deal era” (Glenn Harlan Reynolds,
“Kids, Guns, and the Commerce Clause: Is the Court Ready for
Constitutional Government?” [dated] 10 October 1994, Cato Institute:
Policy Analysis, 216, [visited] 23 September 2002,
<http://www.cato.org/pubs/pas/pa-216.html>: 1.
A second rebuff to the overextension of the Commerce Clause
occurred in United States v. Morrison, 529 U.S. 598 (2000). Christy
Brzonkkala alleged “that she was raped by respondents while the three
were students at the Virginia Polytechnic Institute and that this attack
violated 42 U.S.C.§13981, which provides a federal civil remedy for the
victims of gender-motivated violence” (“United States v. Morrison et
al.,” [undated], FindLaw, [visited] 31 December 2002,
<http://caselaw.lp.findlaw.com/cgi-bin/getcase.pl?
court=us&navby=case&vol=000&invol=99>: 1). This section was
part of the Violence against Women Act of 1994. Her case was argued
by the government, which intervened to “defend the section’s
constitutionality.” The majority opinion, citing Lopez as a precedent,
upheld the district court’s view that “Congress lacked authority to
enact §13981 under either §8 of the Commerce Clause or §5 of the
Fourteenth Amendment, which Congress had explicitly identified as
the sources of federal authority for §13981” (Find-Law 1).
124 Contino v. Leonelli-Contino (2003), 67 O.R. (3d) 703 (C.A.).
125 Karen M. Weiler and Marc Rosenberg, “Contino v. Leonelli-Contino,”
[dated] 28 October 2003, Court of Appeal for Ontario, [visited] 16
January 2004,
<http://www.ontariocourts.on.ca/decisions/2003/october/continoC3992
8.htm>.
126 McLean 4.
127 Rogers and Bieniewicz 11.
128 This model uses “actual costs as measured by surveys” rather than
indirect estimation and theoretical concepts. It is based on surveys of
single-parent households, moreover, and not of intact ones. “Similarly,
the appropriate income used in the support tables is average gross
income of the two parents instead of combined income. The Cost
Shares methodology explicitly shares between the parents both child
costs and child cost offsets. An explicit measure of child-related tax
benefits is used as a cost offset as an intermediate step in determining
the economically appropriate child support award … The Cost Shares
model has components for various major child cost categories. These
are housing, food, transportation, clothing, health, child care and
education, and ‘other.’ Each category is based on an average of the
expenditures by category from survey data” (Rogers and Bieniewicz
11). This new method of calculating the cost of child support, which
avoids many of the problems inherent in earlier ones, establishes basic
costs “for a single-parent household using an average of both parents’
income as the income factor. The basic child support table has child
costs for a single-parent household according to gross income”
(Rogers and Bieniewicz 13). It adds other expenses when necessary.
The new method deducts from the tax benefit that a custodial parent
receives. And it “allocates the net child cost obligation (net of tax
benefits) between the two parents based on each parent’s share of
combined after-tax income that is above a recommended self-support
level” (Rogers and Bieniewicz 14). “Families within the survey varied
as to whether they spent specifically on day-care or medical insurance.
While the medical insurance likely averaged a small figure, the child
care figure is quite significant. With the new category for ‘child care
and education,’ it is easy to exclude this category from the total and to
treat child care and education as an ‘add-on’ in the Cost Shares model
… Importantly, explicit dollar values for a presumptive award by
category allow for a specific basis for rebutting the
presumption”(Rogers and Bieniewicz 13).
129 “Building Child Support Science from First Principles,” [dated] 7
September 1999, Project for the Improvement of Child Support
Litigation Technology, [visited] 1 July 2002,
<http://www.geocities.com/CapitolHill/5910/principles.html>: 1.
130 “Building” 2, 5.
131 In marital relationships, which fall under federal jurisdiction, payments
end only when children leave school. This could be many years after
they become young men and women. In common-law relationships,
which fall under provincial jurisdiction, the obligation for child
support ends when children come of age.
132 Soever 26–9.
133 Francis v. Baker, [1999] 3 S.C.R. 250; cited in Soever 3.
134 Soever is referring to the Supreme Court’s interpretation of section
26.1(2) in the Divorce Act of 1985. This appears in its decision on
Francis v. Baker (1999). “In some cases,” according to section 41,
“courts may conclude that the applicable Guideline figure is so in
excess of the children’s reasonable needs that it must be considered to
be a functional wealth transfer to a parent or de facto spousal support. I
wholly agree with the sentiment of Abella J.A. that courts should not
be too quick to find that the Guideline figures enter the realm of wealth
transfers or spousal support.” Courts must be flexible about applying
the Guidelines, in other words. This is made clear in the summary, too:
“A broad interpretation of the word ‘inappropriate’ in s.4 does not
deny children of high income parents any of the intended benefits of
the Guidelines because these have not displaced the Divorce Act,
which clearly dictates that maintenance of the children, rather than
household equalization or spousal support, is the objective of child
support payments. In order to recognize that objective, as well as to
implement the fairness and flexibility components of the Guidelines’
objectives, courts must therefore have the discretion to remedy
situations where Table amounts are so in excess of the children’s
reasonable needs that they no longer qualify as child support.” Because
this case refers to “reasonable support” in the context of wealth,
however, the matter is still unclear. What about “reasonable support”
in the context of relative poverty? Is it ever permissible for child
support to be used as spousal support?
135 Seidenberg 182–3.
136 The celebration of Mother’s Day is an annual extravaganza in many
newspapers. Whole pages are devoted to this secular (and commercial)
festival (“Your Moms, Your Muses,” Montreal Gazette, 5 May 2003:
D-1; Lisa Fetterman, “Can’t a Breast Be Just a Breast?” Montreal
Gazette, 5 May 2003: D-2; “Your Mothers, in Your Own Words,”
Montreal Gazette, 5 May 2003: D-3). This is reflected, of course, in the
television schedule; many shows feature special episodes for the
occasion.
137 Janet Bagnall, “Helping Single Parents,” Montreal Gazette, 31 January
2003: A-19.
138 Bagnall A-19.
139 Susanne Hiller, “And Baby Makes Two: With the Ticking of Their
Biological Clocks Growing Ever Louder, More and More Women Are
Deciding to Have Children on Their Own through Insemination from
an Anonymous Donor,” National Post, 17 January 2004: sp1, sp6.
140 Jane Mattes; noted in Hiller sp6.
141 Cathy Ruberto, quoted in Hiller sp6.
142 Hiller sp6.
143 Hiller sp6.
144 On single mothers in particular, for instance, see Jane Mattes, Single
Mothers by Choice: A Guidebook for Single Women Who Are
Considering or Have Chosen Motherhood (New York: Times Books,
1994); Joan Anderson, The Single Mother’s Book: A Practical Guide
to Managing Your Children, Career, Home, Finances, and Everything
Else (Atlanta, GA: Peachtree, 1990); Bobbie Reed, Single Mothers
Raising Sons (Nashville, TN: T. Nelson, 1988); Patrice Karst, The
Single Mother’s Survival Guide (Freedom, CA: Crossing Press, 2000);
and Marsha R. Leslie, ed., Single Mother’s Companion: Essays and
Stories by Women (Seattle, WA: Seal Press, 1994). On single parents in
general (including single mothers), see Marge M. Kenndy and Janet
Spencer, The Single-Parent Family: Living Happily in a Changing
World (New York: Crown, 1994); Shirley M.H. Hanson, ed., Single
Parent Families: Diversity, Myths, and Realities (New York: Haworth,
1995); Sharon Yoder, The Single Parent Guidebook: Up, Up and a
Way to Personal Fulfillment (Georgetown, DE: Fruit-Bearer Publishing,
2000); Marion Peterson and Diane Warner, Single Parenting for
Dummies (New York: Wiley, 2003); Ruth Bowdoin, The Single Parent
(Brentwood, TN: Webster’s International, 1990); Karin L. Swisher, ed.,
Single Parent Families (San Diego, CA: Greenhaven Press, 1997);
Richard Worth, Single-Parent Families (New York: F. Watts, 1992);
Thomas D. Yawkey and Georgianna M. Cornelius, eds., The Single
Parent Family: For Helping Professionals and Parents (Lancaster, PA:
Technomic, 1990); Timothy Scott, The Single Parent Family Guide:
How to Raise Your Family Strong (Springfield, MA: Public Information
Center, 2001); Brook Noel and Art Klein, The Single Parent Resource
(Beverly Hills, CA: Champion Press, 1998); Brenda Elwell, The Single
Parent Travel Handbook (Seacaucus, NJ: GlobalBrenda, 2002); Saran
Pirch, ed., Single Parents: The Golden Rules for Raising Children
Alone (Los Angeles: General, 1994); Karen L. Kinnear, Single
Parents: A Reference Handbook (Santa Barbara, CA: abc-clio, 1999);
Linda Foust, The Single Parent Almanac: Real-World Answers to Your
Everyday Questions (Rocklin, CA: Prima, 1996); André Bustanoby,
Single Parenting (Grand Rapids, MI: Zondervan, 1992); Jane Hannah
and Dick Stafford, Single Parenting with Dick and Jane (Nashville,
TN: Family Touch Press, 1993); and Sara Dulaney, The Complete
Idiot’s Guide to Single Parenting (New York: Alpha Books, 1998).
145 Jane Bock; quoted in Cindy Rodriguez, “Single, Pregnant and Proud of
It,” Montreal Gazette, 10 February 2003: D-3.
146 Bock D-3.
147 Surrogacy sounds like a new idea, and it has not been common in our
society for a long time. Nevertheless, women bore children for other
women (and their husbands) in ancient Israel, ancient India, and
elsewhere. Only one aspect of modern surrogacy is new: using
artificial insemination to get the sperm.
148 Gena Corea, The Mother Machine: Reproductive Technologies from
Artificial Insemination to Artificial Wombs (New York: Harper and
Row, 1985).

CHAPTER SEVEN
1 Andrea Dworkin, “Suffering and Speech,” in In Harm’s Way: The
Pornography Civil Rights Hearings, ed. Catharine A. MacKinnon and
Andrea Dworkin (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1997) 25.
2 Helen Fisher, Why We Love: The Nature and Chemistry of Romantic
Love (New York: Henry Holt, 2004) 110 (her emphasis).
3 Ken Tucker, “Rich Man, Poor sobs: Donald Trump Lords over a
Group of Eager Apprentices, and Viewers Reap the Rewards,”
Entertainment Weekly, 13 February 2004: 63.
4 Andrea Dworkin and Catharine A. MacKinnon, “Pornography and
Civil Rights: A New Day for Women’s Equality,” [dated] 1988,
Andrea Dworkin Web Site, <http://www.nostatusquo.com?
aclu/dworkin/other/ordinance/newday/t2b.htm>: 1.
5 See “Federal Statutes Relating to Crimes Against Children,” Crimes
against Children, [undated] Federal Bureau of Investigation, [visited]
21 June 2002, <http://www.fbi.gov/hq/cid/cac/federal.htm>: 2–8.
6 United States of America v. David Hilton no. 98–1513, United States
Court of Appeals for the First Circuit.
7 Ashcroft, (A.G.) v. Free Speech Coalition, 353 U.S. 234 (2002).
8 “Ashcroft, Attorney General, et al. v. Free Speech Coalition et al,”
[undated] lii [Legal Information Institute][visited] 17 February 2004,
<http://supct.law.cornell.edu/supct/html/00-795.I.s.html>: 3–4.
9 “Division A – Trafficking Victims Protection Act of 2000,” Violence
against Women Office, 18 June 2002, United States Department of
Justice, Office of Justice Programs, 24 June 2002,
<http://www.ojp.usdoj.gov/vawo/laws/vawo2000/stitle_a.htm> .
10 “Division A” 1–2. The Victims of Trafficking and Violence Prevention
Act, moreover, held that existing legislation and law enforcement did
not acknowledge the gravity of these offenses and were unable either
to deter trafficking or to punish traffickers with suitably strong
penalties. To improve this situation and make the reduction of
trafficking a priority, it mandated the following: an interagency task
force, with members appointed by the president and including the
secretary of state, to collect and organize data, consult governmental
or nongovernmental agencies, and so forth; a special office within the
secretary of state; educational and economic opportunities, including
programs to promote women’s participation in economic decision
making, for victims and potential victims; assistance, including
resettlement, through development agencies to victims in foreign
countries; assistance to foreign countries, threatening loss of economic
aid to those that fail to comply; special benefits or services to victims
– even aliens – in the United States, which could be enhanced by
special grants from the attorney general; and special “training” for
government personnel.
11 Street prostitution is illegal in Nevada, but brothels are legal (although
small counties are allowed to prohibit them). Prostitutes have ninety-
day licenses from specific counties and work on three-week shifts
(with one week off between each). The Board of Health requires them
to use condoms in licensed brothels and to be tested regularly: every
week for gonorrhea and every month for syphilis and hiv. Those
infected by gonorrhea or syphilis may not work until they have
received medical treatment and can show negative test results. Those
who still show positive results may no longer work as prostitutes.
Various security systems (including proximity to police offices,
security fences, and guards) protect them from unwanted customers
and violence. The cost of protection, however, is a loss of freedom.
They may not leave their brothels without chaperones, for instance.
And when they do leave, they may not go just anywhere. Prostitutes
pay as much as 40% of their earnings, plus room and board, to brothel
owners. In addition, they pay for all medical tests. And they receive no
benefits packages. (“Report and Recommendations in Respect of
Legislation, Policy and Practices Concerning Prostitution-Related
Activities,” [updated] 5 February 2004, Department of Justice
Canada, [visited] 9 February 2004,
<http://canada.justice.gc.ca/en/news/nr/1998/part3.html>:30).
Advocacy groups complain, not surprisingly, that prostitutes are
exploited by state interference.
12 Criminal Code [of Canada], R.S.C. 1985, c. C-46, s. 163, Part V: Sexual
Offences, Public Morals and Disorderly Conduct,” CanLII [Canadian
Legal Information Institute], [visited] 11 February 2004,
<http://www.canlii.org/ca/sta/c-46/sec163.html>.
13 Bill C-15A.
14 Kirk Makin, “Child-Porn Bill Would Narrow Legal Defence,” Globe
and Mail, 11 February 2004: A-7.
15 R. v. Sharpe, [2001] 1 S.C.R. 45; cited in Makin A-7.
16 “Report” 26.
17 John Lowman, Prostitution Law Reform in Canada [dated] 1997,
[visited] 10 February 2004,
<http://mypage.uniserve.ca/~lowman/ProLaw/prolawcan.htm>: 1.
18 Lowman 7.
19 Lowman 22 note 3; he refers to the following: R. v. Skinner (1987), 35
C.C.C. (3d) 203, 58 C.R. (3d) 137, 79 N.S.R. (2d) 8; overd); Stagnitta
(1987), 36 C.C.C. (3d) 105, 43 D.L.R. (4th) 111, 58 C.R. (3d) 164 (Alta.
C.A.) and Reference Re Sections 193 and 195.1(1)(C) of the Criminal
Code, 56 C.C.C. (3d).
20 Criminal Code [of Canada], R.S.C. 1985, c. C-46, s. 210–213, Part VII:
Disorderly Houses, Gaming and Betting,” [updated] 31 August 2003,
Department of Justice Canada, [visited] 10 February 2004,
<http://laws.justice.gc.ca/en/c-46/41639.html>: 18–20.
21 Indictable offenses, by contrast, are higher offenses and heard by
judges and juries.
22 [Federal-Provincial-Territorial Working Group] “Report and
Recommendations in Respect of Legislation, Policy and Practices
concerning Prostitution-Related Activities,” [updated] 5 February
2004, Department of Justice Canada, [visited] 10 February 2004,
http://canada.justice.gc.ca/en/news/nr/1998/part3.html. This document
originated in 1998.
23 “Report” 27.
24 “Report” 29.
25 It has always been hard to convict pimps, because most prostitutes are
afraid to testify against them.
26 Complicating this discussion is the fact that violence against female
prostitutes seems to be rising in British Columbia. According to
Lowman, the law marginalizes these women, pushing them “out of
residential areas into darkly lit industrial back streets” (Lowman 21) or
country roads. But is the number of murders really rising, or has it
been inflated because of one horrific series of murders? Police
discovered a huge number of bodies buried on a farm near Vancouver,
but they were all women who had been murdered by a single person.
Robert William Pickton, if convicted, would take his place as the
worst serial killer in Canadian history (Philip Saunders and Justin
Thompson, “The Missing Women of Vancouver,” [dated] 7 February
2004, CBC [Canadian Broadcasting Corporation] News,
<http://www.cbc.ca/news/features/bc_miss-ingwomen.html>).
27 “Report” 29.
28 This solution involved a change from the type of offence regulated by
213, from summary to the more serious “hybrid” one, which means a
judge must decide the level of offense. In this case, the police need not
catch people in the act of sex or of arranging to have sex; the police
would need only “reasonable grounds to believe” that they either have
done so or are likely to do so in the immediate future (“Report” 4).
Lowman studied the statistics on offences and sentences. At first,
despite variation across the country, more prostitutes than customers
were charged. But by the 1990s, he adds, the reverse was true. “‘The
change shows officers now recognize sex workers are actually victims
and police resources are better spent pursuing johns and pimps. In the
past, prostitutes have been penalized, jailed, fined and shifted from
neighborhood to neighborhood, but no concentrated effort was made
to go after the customers, and we firmly believe that these men are
predators.’ Vancouver’s Mayor, Philip Owen, agreed: ‘I think the
whole thing is to rescue the women’” (K. Pemberton, “Policy Not to
Arrest Constitutes First in Canada,” Vancouver Sun, 18 February 1997:
B-1; quoted in Lowman 14).
29 “Report” 12.
30 “Report” 13.
31 “Report 4–5.
32 “Report” 6.
33 “Report” 16.
34 “Report” 23.
35 “Report” 24.
36 “Report” 9.
37 Lowman 13.
38 “Report” 23.
39 “Report” 24.
40 In jurisprudence, MacKinnon has become a feminist icon. With a BA
from Smith, a jd from Yale Law School, and a PHD in political science
from the University of Michigan, she is the Elizabeth A. Long
Professor of Law at the University of Michigan and has taught at other
prestigious law schools in the United States and elsewhere: the
University of Chicago, Yale, Harvard, Stanford, the University of
Minnesota, the University of California at Los Angeles, the University
of Toronto, and the University of Basel. In 1978, she was admitted to
the Connecticut Bar and in 1986 to that of the Supreme Court.
MacKinnon has crafted two major legal doctrines: that sexual
harassment is a form of sex discrimination and that porn is a violation
of human rights. In 1986 the Supreme Court accepted her theory of
sexual harassment. She has been even more successful in Canada,
though, where she has worked closely with the feminist Legal
Education and Action Fund (LEAF) and has influenced Canada’s
Supreme Court with her views on equality, porn, and hate speech
(Kristin Switala, ed., “Catharine MacKinnon,” [dated] 1999, Feminist
Theory Website, [visited] 23 October 2002,
<http://www.cddc.vt.edu/feminism/MacKinnon.html>: 1). She has
been active in both countries on behalf of feminists as lead counsel or
co-counsel, author of briefs or affidavits, expert witness, consultant,
and so on. MacKinnon has almost single-handedly changed the legal
landscape and therefore the cultural landscape as well. Given her
predilection for conflating quite different phenomena, her influence
extends from porn and sexual harassment to legislation on rape and
various other crimes.
In addition, MacKinnon has published a great deal. Her books
alone include In Harm’s Way: The Pornography Civil Rights Hearings
and Pornography, ed. with Andrea Dworkin (Cambridge: Harvard
University Press, 1997); Civil Rights: A New Day for Women’s
Equality, with Andrea Dworkin (Minneapolis: Organizing against
Pornography, 1988); Only Words (Cam-bridge: Harvard University
Press, 1993); Toward a Feminist Theory of the State (Cambridge:
Harvard University Press, 1989); Feminism Unmodified: Discourses
on Life and Law (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1989); Sexual
Harassment of Working Women: A Case of Sex Discrimination, with
Thomas Emerson (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1979); and
The Case for Women’s Equality: The Federation of Woman Teachers’
Associations of Ontario and the Canadian Charter of Rights and
Freedoms, with M. Eberts and others (Toronto: The Federation, 1991).
41 Dworkin is neither a lawyer nor an academic. Like MacKinnon,
however, she is an expert when it comes to rhetoric. She is even better
known than MacKinnon, in fact, due to her predilection for highly
articulate and quotable rabble rousing. Consider the first epigraph of
this chapter, for instance, where she implies (among other dubious
things) that “normal men” are “rapists,” that “hatred of women” is
“accepted” and “unchallenged.” Dworkin is often accused of
manhating (that is, of misandry), although her followers have tried
hard to refute that accusation. On this topic, see Nikki Craft, “The Lie
Detector,” [undated], No Status Quo, [visited] 16 January 2003,
<http://www.nostatusquo.com/aclu/dworkin/LieDetect.html>. Not one
of the items refuted, however, is about hatred as such; each is about
something that could be linked to hatred. According to one possible
lie, Dworkin is “antisex.” No, says the site, “her early fiction is
especially rich with narration about both lesbian and heterosexual
lovemaking (Craft 1). But Craft says nothing about her later work.
Besides, fictional accounts do not necessarily imply approval or
disapproval. According to another possible lie, Dworkin considers it
legitimate for battered women to kill their partners. This, says Craft, is
true. Dworkin said precisely that in 1991 at a conference on women
and mental health. Craft offers no comment, however, on whether
vigilantism is compatible with the rule of law. Consider the following
passage: “It is fine for her [the victim of porn, although the context
makes it clear that porn and rape are synonymous] to hate those who
ripped into her if hate keeps her willing to talk, unwilling to let silence
bury her again” (Dworkin, “Suffering and Speech” 34). Dworkin is
probably referring directly to anger rather than hatred. Indirectly,
though, it probably amounts to hatred – that is, to the cultural
propagation and institutionalization of hostility toward a specific
group of people (usually, though by no means always, based on
biological characteristics). Hatred for her is merely the political means
to an ideological end.
42 Dworkin is MacKinnon’s close friend and political ally. Due to their
close collaboration, it is very hard to speak of one without the other.
Educated during the 1960s at Bennington College in Vermont, known
for its leftist politics and bohemianism, Dworkin became a feminist
activist and writer. Along with essays and articles, especially on porn,
she has written several works of non-fiction, including Letters from a
War Zone (New York: Lawrence Hill, 1993); Intercourse (New York:
Simon and Schuster, 1997); Right-Wing Women (New York: Perigee
Books, 1983); Pornography: Men Possessing Women (New York:
Dutton, 1989); Our Blood: Prophecies and Discourses on Sexual
Politics (New York: Harper and Row, 1976); Woman Hating (New
York: Dutton, 1974); and Life and Death (New York: Free Press,
1997). Her point of view, she notes, is based on the personal
experience of being “finger-raped” at the age of nine by a stranger;
being physically abused by male doctors performing an internal exam
on her (when she was jailed during a protest against the Vietnam War),
and being a battered wife. Dworkin’s nonfiction is based on her
personal experiences as a “survivor,” she claims, not ideology.
Her fiction goes far beyond the personal, she claims also, because it
mixes intellect, imagination, emotion, the collective nature of
women’s experience, and the literary process itself. Here are some
titles: Mercy (New York: Four Walls Eight Windows, 1980); Ice and
Fire (New York: Weidenfeld and Nicolson, 1987); and The New
Womans Broken Heart: Short Stories (East Palo Alto, CA: Frog in the
Well, 1980).
43 MacKinnon, Toward 248. See also Wendy McElroy, “Does Rape
Violate the Commerce Clause of the Constitution?” [dated] 3 July
2002, WendyMcElroy.co: A Site for Individualist Feminism and
Individualist Anarchism, [visited] 1 June 2002,
<http://www.zetetics.com/mac/articles/brzonkala.html>: 3; this article
appeared also in Ideas on Liberty, 50.1 (2000).
44 MacKinnon, “The Roar on the Other Side of Silence,” in In Harm’s
Way: The Pornography Civil Rights Hearings, ed. Catharine A.
MacKinnon and Andrea Dworkin (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 1997) 18–19.
45 MacKinnon, “Roar,” 11–12; see also Andrea Dworkin, “Suffering and
Speech,” in In Harm’s Way: The Pornography Civil Rights Hearings,
ed. Catharine A. MacKinnon and Andrea Dworkin (Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 1997) 25–6.
46 MacKinnon, “Roar” 20–1.
47 MacKinnon, Toward ix–xi; see also 1–80.
48 Dworkin, “Suffering” 35.
49 Dworkin, “Suffering” 28–9.
50 Nonetheless, MacKinnon points out that her legal battles have led to
“professional shunning and blacklisting, attacks on employment and
publishing, deprivation of research and grant funding, public
demonization, litigation and threats of litigation, and physical assault”
(MacKinnon, “Roar” 18–19).
51 Martha C. Nussbaum, Sex and Social Justice (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1999) 155.
52 Nussbaum 181.
53 Andrea Dworkin; quoted in Philip Elmer-Dewitt, “On a Screen Near
You,” Time, 3 July 1995: 43.
54 Dworkin, “Suffering” 35.
55 Dworkin, “Suffering” 25.
56 Dworkin, “Suffering” 35–6.
57 Dworkin, “Suffering” 35–6.
58 Andrea Dworkin and Catharine A. MacKinnon, “Findings,” [dated]
1988, Pornography and Civil Rights: A New Day for Women’s
Equality, [visited] 8 March 2003, <http://www.nostatusquo.com?
aclu/dworkin/other/ordinance/newday/t2b.htm>: 1.
59 James B. Jacobs and Kimberly Potter, Hate Crimes: Criminal Law and
Identity Politics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998) 120.
60 Hudnut v. American Booksellers Assoc., 475 U.S. 1001 (1986).
61 Andrea Dworkin and Catharine A. MacKinnon, “The Antipornography
Civil Rights Ordinance: A Brief Description,”[dated] 30 September
2001, No Status Quo, ed. Nikki Craft, [visited] 8 March 2003,
<http://www.nostatusquo.com/aclu/dworkin/OrdinanceBriefDescriptio
n.html>: 1.
62 Andrea Dworkin and Catharine A. MacKinnon, “Causes of Action,”
[dated] 1988, Pornography and Civil Rights: A New Day for Women’s
Equality, [visited] 8 March 2003, <http://www.nostatusquo.com?
aclu/dworkin/other/ordinance/newday/t2d.htm>: 1.
63 Minneapolis Ordinance, 1983, section 3, subsection 1; quoted in In
Harm’s Way 428, 435.
64 MacKinnon, “Roar” 17–24.
65 Switala 6.
66 Louis Robinson v. Jacksonville Shipyards Inc ., 760 F. Supp. 1486
(1991).
67 R. v. Keegstra [1990] 3 S.C.R. 697.
68 A factum is a document filed to set out the claim, defense, projection,
and so on for either defense or prosecution.
69 Catharine A. MacKinnon and Andrea Dworkin, “Statement by
Catharine A. MacKinnon and Andrea Dworkin Regarding Canadian
Customs and Legal Approaches to Pornography,” in No Status Quo 1.
70 Christopher P. Manfredi, The Canadian Feminist Movement,
Constitutional Politics, and the Strategic Use of Legal Resources
(Vancouver: Simon Fraser University and University of British
Columbia, Centre for the Study of Government and Business, 2000)
36.
71 R. v. Butler, [1992] 1 S.C.R. 452.
72 Manfredi 37.
73 Manfredi 37.
74 Butler at 464.
75 Butler at 485. The Supreme Court does not accept all cases, and we
have no reason to assume that it would accept one about allegedly
harmful effects of pornography on men. Judging from Butler, in fact, it
probably would not. Sexual equality could remain an abstraction, in
other words, unless the entire legal system – including everyone who
interprets and enforces the law – chooses to make it a reality. Our
contention in this book is that, the Charter notwithstanding, Canadian
men face systemic discrimination.
76 Manfredi 37–8.
77 MacKinnon and Dworkin, “Statement” 3.
78 Catharine Mackinnon; quoted in Nadine Strossen, Defending
Pornography: Free Speech, Sex, and the Fight for Women’s Rights
(Toronto: Scribner, 1995) 229.
79 MacKinnon; quoted in Strossen 229.
80 MacKinnon and Dworkin, “Statement” 1.
81 MacKinnon and Dworkin, “Statement” 2.
82 “There has been a growing recognition in recent cases that material
which may be said to exploit sex in a ‘degrading or dehumanizing’
manner will necessarily fail the community standards test, not because
it offends against morals but because it is perceived by public opinion
to be harmful to society, particularly women” (R v. Butler [1992] 1
S.C.R., [visited] 27 December 2003,
<http://www.lexum.umontreal.ca/csc-
scc/en/pub/1992/vol1/html/1992scr1_0452.html>:454. We are not sure
about the title of this site, which seems to be a transcription from a
written document. The page quoted has no title or date.)
83 Gloria Steinem, “Hollywood Cleans Up Hustler,” New York Times, 7
January 1997: A-17.
84 Steinem A-17.
85 Philip Elmer-Dewitt, “On a Screen near You,” Time, 3 July 1995: 43.
For practical reasons, many feminists have adopted what amounts to
an anti-sex or neo-puritanical position (which we discuss in chapter 8).
Hence their demands for “sexual correctness.” For ideological reasons,
however, many feminists have adopted the opposite position. They
argue – ironically agreeing with some misogynistic theologians and
philosophers, albeit for different reasons – that women have some
innate affinity for the material, the carnal, the physical, or the
immanent. Only men, they believe, are fixated on the immaterial, the
spiritual, the intellectual, or the transcendent. What they mean is that
women, supposedly being more concerned than men with the things of
this world, are more life-affirming and “nurturing” than men. Among
the more famous advocates of this profoundly dualistic approach is
Marilyn French. See her Beyond Power: On Women, Men, and Morals
(New York: Ballantine, 1985).
86 Although gnosticism influenced Judaism during the Hellenistic period,
it never had the massive impact on Judaism that it did on Christianity,
because the Hellenistic period was only one period among many in the
history of Judaism. It was the founding period, however, of
Christianity. The Hebrew Bible (including the Torah) had been orally
transmitted, written down, and edited much earlier. Not surprisingly, it
evokes a very different attitude toward the material world – including
sex, marriage, and the family.
87 Martha C. Nussbaum, Sex and Social Justice (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1999).
88 Catharine A. MacKinnon; quoted in Nussbaum 214.
89 Nussbaum 77.
90 American society is ambivalent about sex and prudery. The latter has a
long and unbroken tradition, which surfaces occasionally, especially in
times of crisis or when people are provided with an ideological excuse
for it. But the sexual revolution has made deep inroads.
91 Martin Buber, I and Thou, tr. Walter Kaufmann (New York: Scribner,
1970).
92 Throughout this trilogy, we argue that the end cannot justify the means.
(We identify the belief that ends can justify means with ideologies of
both the left and the right). And yet we argue here that people may, in
some situations, be legitimately “used,” “exploited” or “objectified” as
the means to other ends. But the inconsistency is more apparent than
real. When people say that “ends cannot justify the means,” they are
using an abbreviation. The whole expression would make it clear that
good ends cannot justify evil means. The question here is whether
sexual activity is an evil means. We say no, not necessarily. There are
evils associated with both porn and prostitution, to be sure, and those
should be eliminated.
93 Wendy McElroy, XXX: A Woman’s Right to Pornography (New York:
St Martin’s Press, 1995).
94 Jacobs and Potter 128. “Passing hate crime laws is now the fallback
position for those who wish to denounce prejudiced and bigoted
thought and expression via criminal law. By linking hate speech
prohibitions to generic criminal law, many well-meaning advocacy
groups and politicians seek to shake a fist at the kind of ideas,
opinions, and degenerate personalities that ‘right-thinking’ people
abhor. But we must consider whether punishing crimes motivated by
politically unpopular beliefs more severely than crimes motivated by
other factors itself violates our First Amendment traditions … In
Wisconsin v. Mitchell, the Supreme Court drew a sharp line between
laws that punish expression per se and those that punish expression
that manifests itself in, or is integrally connected to, criminal conduct.
Laws that punish expression itself are constitutionally unacceptable,
but laws that punish expression linked to criminal conduct are
constitutionally acceptable. Thus, federal and state legislatures have a
green light to target politically unpopular prejudices for more severe
punishment, whenever these prejudices can be linked to a generic
crime” (Jacobs and Potter 128).
95 Jacobs and Potter 121.
96 F.L. Morton and Rainer Knopff, The Charter Revolution and the Court
Party (Peterborough, ON: Broadview Press, 2000) 66.
97 Alan Borovoy, The New Anti-Liberals (Toronto: Canadian Scholars’
Press, 1999).
98 Morton and Knopff 15–26.
99 Fisher 110 (her emphasis).
100 Susan G.E. Frayser, Varieties of Sexual Experience: An
Anthropological Perspective on Human Sexuality (New Haven, CT:
hras Press, 1985) 9–11.
101 G. Robina Quale, A History of Marriage Systems (New York:
Greenwood Press, 1988).
102 Nussbaum’s position is odd, if you think about it, in view of her belief
that female eroticism is a good thing and should never have been
repressed in the first place.
103 Inherent in play, therefore, are two seemingly opposed outcomes:
unruliness and rebelliousness or even violence on the one hand,
imagination and curiosity on the other. The two are only “seemingly”
opposed, because the latter would be impossible without some
measure of the former.
104 Japan has tried to have it both ways. It could adapt with great speed
and relative ease to modernity, an adaptation of colossal proportions,
but largely because it carefully maintained traditional social structures
at the same time. The corporation and even the state became surrogate
families, evoking both loyalty and duty. The system worked very well
until quite recently, when corporate efficiency required “downsizing,”
which has meant abandoning members of what amounts to a national
extended family.
105 Communism in China has taken a different route, an innovative one.
Although the government still tolerates no political dissent, it tolerates
and even encourages economic innovation (at least in some regions).
Tacitly, moreover, it tolerates social and cultural change as well. Our
point is merely that totalitarian societies must either change in some
fundamental way or disappear.
106 The extraordinary popularity of romance novels has been discussed in
Time: “A few statistics: romance novels are read by 51 million
Americans. They account for more than half of all paperback fiction
sold in the U.S. If you thought feminist, postmodernism and the Internet
had done away with the romance novel, think again. The number of
romance-novel readers in the U.S. has risen 18% since 1998” (Lev
Grossman, “Rewriting Romance: Bodice Rippers Are More Popular
Than Ever, and Julia Quinn Is Taking Them into the Postfeminist
Future,” Time, 3 February 2003: 50). What has changed is the
portrayal of women, not that of men. Women are no longer fragile and
vulnerable.
107 In the SCUM Manifesto (London: Olympia Press, 1971), Valerie
Solanas explained her hatred toward men, which resulted in a physical
attack on pop artist Andy Warhol. The title of her tract refers to the
Society for Cutting up Men. Solanas was eulogized as insane (and thus
not responsible for her behaviour) but intelligent (and thus of interest
to feminists) in a critically acclaimed movie that was directed by Mary
Harron: I Shot Andy Warhol.
108 Robin Morgan, Demon Lover: On the Sexuality of Terrorism (New
York: Norton, 1989). Morgan is no marginal figure. On the contrary,
she has scaled the heights of mainstream feminism. Once the editor-in-
chief of Ms. magazine, she founded the Sisterhood is Global Institute,
a feminist think tank, was named woman of the year in 1990 by the
Feminist Majority Foundation, and has served on the boards of both
American and international feminist organizations. In 1990, moreover,
she received the National Endowment for the Arts Prize in poetry.
109 Marilyn French, Beyond Power: On Women, Men, and Morals. French
is famous for her feminist fiction, too, notably The Women’s Room
(New York: Summit, 1977).
110 Marilyn French, The War against Women (New York: Summit, 1992).
111 Some religious communities oppose masturbation, at least officially, on
other grounds. Traditional Jews and Christians, for instance, trace the
prohibition to Genesis 38:9. Judah has told Onan to have sex with
Tamar and thus continue the lineage of her dead husband Er (Onan’s
brother). “But Onan, knowing that the line would not count as his, spilt
his seed on the ground every time he slept with his brother’s wife, to
avoid providing off-spring for his brother” (New Jerusalem Bible). To
punish Onan, God kills him. But punish him for precisely what? For
masturbating or for refusing to do his duty by honouring the custom
known as “levirate marriage”? Whatever the original sense of this
story, it has been interpreted for many centuries as a prohibition of
masturbation – possibly as a way of promoting marital fidelity. This
interpretation has been legitimated, among Catholics, by the Thomist
tradition of natural law. Because the function of semen is reproduction,
masturbation goes against nature. Natural law’s rule of “double effect”
might have been used by non-Catholics, however, to argue that
masturbation is acceptable. Its main function is to relieve sexual
tension, a useful mechanism that is found not only in all human
societies but also in some primate species; its unintended side effect is
to release semen.
112 In the first place, this argument is based on inconsistency. It is one
thing for Christian fundamentalists to take fantasies at face value. They
take biblical passages at face value, after all, and acknowledge
literalism as a legitimate method of interpretation. But ideological
feminists are not Christian fundamentalists (although, as ideologues,
they are indeed fundamentalists). In fact, they routinely denounce both
the literal and the figurative messages of biblical passages. These, they
argue, are nothing more, and nothing less, than evil collective fantasies
intended to oppress women. For some reason, however, they are
willing to accept the most literal approach to personal fantasies (at
least those of men). Outsiders may be forgiven, then, for suspecting
them of intellectual dishonesty and political opportunism.
113 Peter H. Klopfer, and others, “Kids, tv Viewing, and Aggressive
Behavior,” Science, 297.5578 (5 July 2002): 49–50. For a history of
studies, see Children and Television Violence, [visited] 12 June 2003,
<http://www.abelard.org/tv/tv.htm>.
114 Some women, too, like porn. And not only lesbians or those who like
the “respectable porn” that we discuss in appendix 5. So do gay men.
But when feminists attack porn, those populations are usually ignored.
Feminists attack only straight men, because they hold only straight
men – that is, supposedly, innate misogynists – responsible for creating
and maintaining patriarchy.
115 Frederick Matthews, The Invisible Boy: Revisioning the Victimization
of Male Children and Teens (Ottawa: Minister of Public Works and
Government Services Canada; Health Canada, catalogue no. h72–
21/143–1996e, 1996), 16.
116 Lowman 22.
117 Katherine Setzer, “Where the Boys Aren’t: The Skinny on Porn for
Girls Who Like Girls,” Montreal Hour, 31 July 1997: 13 (her
emphasis).

CHAPTER EIGHT

1 Catharine A. MacKinnon, Toward a Feminist Theory of the State


(Cam-bridge: Harvard University Press, 1989) 141.
2 Celia Kitzinger, “Experiential Authority and Heterosexuality,” in
Changing Our Lives, ed. Gabriele Griffin (London: Pluto Press, 1994)
143; cited in Daphne Patai, Heterophobia: Sexual Harassment and the
Future of Feminism (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1998) 168.
3 Naomi Wolf, The Beauty Myth: How Images of Beauty Are Used
against Women (New York: Morrow, 1991).
4 Naomi Wolf, Fire with Fire: The New Female Power and How It will
Change the Twenty-first Century (New York: Random House, 1993).
5 Naomi Wolf, “The Silent Treatment,” New York Magazine, 1 March
2004.
6 Naomi Wolf; quoted in Josh Goodman, “Who Else Is Tired of Naomi
Wolf?” Yale Herald, 27 February 2004.
7 Wolf, “Silent.”
8 Anne Applebaum, “Get a Grip, Naomi,” Montreal Gazette, 29
February 2004: A-11; reprinted from the Washington Post.
9 Goodman.
10 Patai xii–xiii.
11 Title IX of the Education Amendments of 1972, 20 U.S.C. §1681 et seq.
12 Williams v. Saxbe, 413 F. Supp. 654 (D.D.C. 1976).
13 Alexander v. Yale University, 631 f. 2d. 178 (2d Cir. 1980).
14 Moire v. Temple University School of Medicine, 613 F. Supp. 1360 (E.D.
Pa. 1985).
15 Meritor Savings Bank v. Vinson, 477 U.S. 57 (1986).
16 In 1992, Congress passed these measures as part of its Higher
Education Amendments of 1992. “Victims’ Assistance: Campus Sex
Assault Victims’ Bill of Rights,” 2000, Security on Campus, Inc., 3
July 2002, <http://www.campussafety.org/victims/billofrights.html>.
17 “Pamphlet 12 – Sexual Harassment: Part III [Division XV.1] of the
Canada Labour Code (Labour Standards),” [dated] 21 October 2002,
Government of Canada, [visited] 14 February 2004, <http://info.load-
otea-hrdc-rhc.gc.ca/publications/labour_standards/harassment.shtml>:
1.
18 “Pamphlet 12” 1.
19 “Harassment and the Canadian Human Rights Act,” [undated],
Canadian Human Rights Commission, [visited] 14 February 2004,
<http://www.chrcccdp.ca/publications/chra_har-lcdp.asp?1=e>:1.
20 “Pamphlet 12” 1.
21 “Pamphlet 12” 2.
22 Catharine A. MacKinnon, Sexual Harassment of Working Women: A
Case Study of Sexual Discrimination (New Haven, CT: Yale University
Press, 1979).
23 Catharine A. MacKinnon, “Sexual Harassment: Its First Decade in
Court,” in Feminism Unmodified: Discourses on Life and Law
(Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1987) 107; quoted in Patai 47.
24 Patai 28.
25 Patai 28.
26 Patai 41.
27 Patai 170.
28 MacKinnon, Sexual Harassment 217–18.
29 Ted Gest and Thom Grier, “Thomas and Hill: Once More with
Feeling,” U.S. News and World Report, 8 June 1992: 10.
30 Barbara Kantrowitz, “Striking a Nerve,” Newsweek, 21 October 1991:
36 (her emphasis). We looked this up on microfilm, but that particular
page had not been photographed!
31 This study is from Newsweek. We referred to a similar study, from
Time, in chapter 3. Both were conducted in 1991. The questions asked
were slightly different, but both reveal the same basic pattern:
Americans differ widely on how to define sexual harassment.
32 Patai 29.
33 Patai 30.
34 Patai 43.
35 Patai 179.
36 Katie Roiphe, The Morning After: Sex, Fear, and Feminism (Boston:
Little Brown, 1993) 99–101.
37 Gest and Grier 39.
38 Patai 163–4.
39 Louis Robinson v. Jacksonville Shipyards Inc., 760 f. Supp. 1486
(1991).
40 Gest and Grier 39.
41 Gest and Grier 39.
42 Gest and Grier 39.
43 Patai 26.
44 John Leo, “Harassment’s Murky Edges,” US News and World Report,
21 October 1991: 26.
45 Patai 23.
46 We refer to the Nicene Creed’s filioque clause. Does the Holy Spirit
proceed from the Father alone (as it does according to Eastern
Orthodox churches) or from the Father and (que) the Son (as it does
according to the Roman Catholic Church)?
47 Patai 165.
48 Leo 26.
49 See Paul Nathanson, “I Feel, Therefore I Am: The Princess of Passion
and the Implicit Religion of Our Time,” Implicit Religion 2.2 (1999):
59–87.
50 Kitzinger 143.
51 Kitzinger 143; quoted in Patai 168.
52 Patai 168 (her emphasis).
53 Patai 46.
54 “The Antioch College Sexual Offense Prevention Policy,” approved by
the Board of Trustees on 8 June 1996, Antioch College, 3 July 2002,
<http://www.antioch-college.edu/survival/html/sopp.html>.
55 Patai 176.
56 Francine Prose, “Bad Behavior: The Salem Witch Hunts Become a
Metaphor for a Trial over a Teacher’s Crude Language,” New York
Times Magazine, 26 November 1995: 34–6.
57 Prose 34.
58 Prose 36.
59 Ministry of Education and Training, Ontario, Framework Regarding
Prevention of Harassment and Discrimination in Ontario Universities
(Toronto, 1993).
60 Ministry 2.
61 Paul Benedetti and Andrew Dreschel, “Harassment Policy Stirs Heated
Debate in Ontario Universities,” Montreal Gazette, 20 February 1994:
A-5.
62 [William C. Leggett], “Queen’s and the ‘Zero-Tolerance’ Issue:
Principal’s Statement to the Senate,” February 17, 1994.
63 Benedetti and Dreschel A-5.
64 Benedetti and Dreschel A-5.
65 Ministry 4–5.
66 Benedetti and Dreschel A-5. See also Peter Emberley, Zero Tolerance:
Hot Button Politics in Canada’s Universities (Toronto: Penguin,
1996); Graham Good, Humanism Betrayed: Theory, Ideology, and
Culture in the Contemporary University (Montreal: McGill-Queen’s
University Press, 2001); Martin Loney, The Pursuit of Division: Race,
Gender, and Preferential Hiring in Canada (Montreal: McGill-
Queen’s University Press, 1998); Joan McEwen, Report in Respect of
the Political Science Department of the University of British Columbia
(Vancouver: President’s Office, University of British Columbia, 1995).
67 Katie Roiphe, The Morning After: Sex, Fear, and Feminism (Boston:
Little Brown, 1993) 97.
68 Patai 52.
69 Patai 53.
70 Patai 80.
71 The underlying goal of demonizing men is to separate them from
women, says Patai, which “explains why there has never (to my
knowledge) been a workshop on, say, how to keep oneself from taking
offense at trivial slights or innuendos, or how to respond to an
unwanted sexual overture in a spirited way that ends the problem.
Instead, the suggested (and, increasingly, mandatory) workshops and
training sessions are designed to bring an ever greater range of
behavior within the purview of sexual harassment regulations” (Patai
46).
72 Patai 144, referring to Alice Echols, Daring to Be Bad: Radical
Feminism in America, 196 7–1975 (Minneapolis, MN: University of
Minnesota Press, 1989).
73 Sheila Jeffreys, Anticlimax: A Feminist Perspective on the Sexual
Revolution (London: Women’s Press, 1990).
74 Patai 130.
75 Patai 130–1.
76 Arianne Haley, “Letters,” Ms., October 1987: 10.
77 Patai 118.
78 Sue Wilkinson and Celia Kitzinger, eds., Heterosexuality: A Feminism
and Psychology Reader (London: Sage, 1993).
79 Mary Crawford, “Identity, ‘Passing,’ and Subversion,” in Wilkinson
and Kitzinger 44; quoted in Patai 133.
80 Sandra Lee Bartky, “Hypatia Unbound: A Confession,” in Wilkinson
and Kitzinger 41; quoted in Patai 133.
81 Sandra Lipsitz Bem, “On the Inadequacy of Our Sexual Categories: A
Personal Perspective,” in Wilkinson and Kitzinger 42; quoted in Patai
133.
82 Patai 133.
83 Patai 139.
84 Patai 140–1.
85 Marilyn Frye, “Willful Virgin, or Do You Have to Be a Lesbian to Be a
Feminist?” in Willful Virgin: Essays in Feminism, 197 6–1992
(Freedom, CA: Crossing Press, 1992), 129; quoted in Patai 143. This
essay was originally presented as a speech in 1990 at the National
Women’s Studies Association Conference.
86 Patai 11.
87 Patai 12.
88 Patai 135.
89 Patai 6–7.
90 Patai 160.
91 This book is about men, not women. Nevertheless, it would not do to
ignore the effect on women of this preoccupation with sexual
harassment. “My own observations of students in women’s studies
classes,” writes Patai, “have led me to believe that years of exposure to
feminist-promoted scare statistics have succeeded in imbuing many
young women with a foreboding sense of living under constant threat
from predatory men. The offer of an escape from this threat is a strong
inducement to conformity to feminist blandishments. This, at least, is
the more generous interpretation of the vigilante atmosphere promoted
in the name of feminism. A less benign explanation is also possible:
No social group selflessly refrains from using whatever weapons its
historical moment makes available in order to gain money, position,
fame (of a sort), and retribution, all in the name of equity and
righteousness” (Patai 35).
92 Patai 159.
93 John Stoltenberg, Refusing to Be a Man: Essays on Sex and Justice
(1989; New York: Meridian, 1990).
94 Patai 150.
95 John Stoltenberg, End of Manhood: A Book for Men of Conscience
(New York: Dutton, 1993).
96 Today, the Roman Catholic Church focuses heavily on family life.
Rejecting the notion of gay marriage to protect the sanctity of
marriage is only one example of that. But, as some modern Catholics
point out, the tradition has historically ascribed a lower status to
family life than to ascetic life.
97 Patai 43.
98 Priscilla Painton, “Woman Power,” Time, 28 October 1991, 12. And let
us not forget the new frontier that could open up for insurance brokers.
If employers could be held responsible for misconduct on the part of
their employees – even if the former were unaware of it at the time and
even if the latter had been correctly indoctrinated – they could hardly
afford not to carry insurance against the inevitable plague of law suits.
The same goes for individuals. What man could afford to take a job
without being insured against charges of sexual harassment? In view
of the fact that two female police officers in Long Beach were
awarded $3.1 million after three years of sexual taunts from
colleagues, it is clear that the financial stakes are truly staggering
(Gest and Grier 38). In 1988, a survey of Fortune 500 companies
commissioned by Working Woman found that ignoring the problem of
sexual harassment can cost up to $6.7 million a year in absenteeism,
employee turnover, and lost productivity (Nancy Gibbs, “Office
Crimes,” Time, 21 October 1991, 30). It is hard to see how either the
magazine or the companies themselves can possibly know this.
99 “If Your Most Valuable Assets Were at Risk,” ad supported by Altria,
Kraft Foods, Philip Morris International, and Philip Morris usa,
Harper’s Magazine, March 2004: 1.
100 Training Services by The Edge, [undated], The Edge, [visited] 14
February 2004, <http://www3.sympatico.ca/theedgeq/trainserv.html>.
101 Most people but not all. Members of some religious and ethnic
communities – the Amish and the Hasidim, say, or some Muslims and
Hindus – maintain traditional standards. Because many of them live
primarily within their own communities, however, this is not quite the
problem that it would be otherwise.
102 Few cultures have admired short hair on women, but they have usually
insisted that women either cover their hair or pile it up on their heads.
This was certainly true in the West until very recently. No woman with
high social status, or the hope of attaining it, would ever “let down her
hair” in public; that was reserved for the boudoir. Ancient Egypt was
an apparent exception. Egyptian women wore their hair long. In fact,
though, women (and men) shaved their heads and wore wigs. This had
nothing to do with sex and everything to do with climate and hygiene.
103 Leo 26.
104 Camille Paglia, “A Call for Lustiness,” Time, 23 March 1998: 54.
CHAPTER NINE

1 Sherene Razack, Canadian Feminism and the Law: the Women’s Legal
Education and Action Fund and the Pursuit of Equality (Toronto:
Second Story Press, 1991) 111.
2 Grant A. Brown, “Gender as a Factor in the Response of the Law-
enforcement System to Violence against Partners,” Sexuality and
Culture 8:3–4 (summer 2004).
3 Don Macpherson, “Misogynistic Entertainment,” Montreal Gazette, 6
February 2004: A-15.
4 “[Article 4: Relevancy and Its Limits: Rule] 412: Sex Offense Cases;
Relevance of Alleged Victim’s Past Sexual Behavior or Alleged
Sexual Predisposition,” [dated] 1 December 2002, Federal Rules of
Evidence, [visited] 17 March 2003,
<http://www.house.gov/judiciary/Evid202.pdf>: 6–7 [22–3 of 43].
(The first page numbers are those of the document; the second are
those of the computer.)
5 Kevin D. Smith, “Navigating the Rape Shield Maze: An Advocate’s
Guide to mre 412,” [dated] November 2002, [visited] 13 March 2003,
<http://www.jagcnet.army.mil/jagcnetInternet/Homepages/ac/tjagsaWe
b.nsf/8f7edfd4
48e0ec6c8525694b0064ba51/1cb55669b226e35485256ca3005497a7/$
file/Article%201.pdf> : 10. (There is no separate title for the website,
although it seems to be a pamphlet from The Army Lawyer, da pam
27–50–357.)
6 “[Article 4: Relevancy and Its Limits: Rule] 413: Evidence of Similar
Crimes in Sexual Assault Cases,” [dated] 1 December 2002, Federal
Rules of Evidence, [visited] 14 March 2003,
<http://house.gov/judiciary.Evid2002.pdf>: 7 [23 of 43].
7 “[Article 4: Relevancy and Its Limits: Rule] 414: Evidence of Similar
Crimes in Child Molestation Cases,” [dated] 1 December 2002,
Federal Rules of Evidence, [visited] 14 March 2003,
<http://www.house.gov/judiciary.Evid2002.pdf>: 7–8 [23– 24 of 43];
“[Article 4: Relevancy and Its Limits: Rule] 415: Evidence of Similar
Crimes in Civil Cases Concerning Sexual Assault of Child
Molestation,” [dated] 1 December 2002, Federal Rules of Evidence,
[visited] 14 March 2003,
<http://www.house.gov/judiciary.evid2002.pdf>: 8 [24 of 43].
8 “Section 2246 [of Title 18],” [undated], U.S. Code, [visited] 15 March
2003, <http://www4.law.cornell.edu/uscode/18/2246.html>: 1; this
website is run by the Legal Information Institute at Cornell University.
Section 2242 of Title 18, United States Code, defines a sexual abuser
as someone who “knowingly causes another person to engage in a
sexual act by threatening or placing that other person in fear (other
than by threatening or placing that other person in fear that any person
will be subjected to death, serious bodily injury, or kidnapping); or
engages in a sexual act with another person if that other person is – (A)
incapable of appraising the nature of the conduct; or (B) physically
incapable of declining participation in, or communicating
unwillingness to engage in, that sexual act; or attempts to do so, shall
be fined under this title, imprisoned not more than 20 years, or both.”
9 Charles R. Nesson, Eric D. Green, and Peter L. Murray, “Rule 413:
Evidence of Similar Crimes in Sexual Assault Cases,” [dated] 21
November 1999, Problems, Cases and Materials on Evidence,
[visited] 19 October 2004,
<http://www.law.harvard.edu/publications/evidenceiii/main.htm>: 3.
10 Nesson, Green, and Murray 2.
11 “[Article 4: Relevancy and Its Limits: Rule] 403: Exclusion of
Relevant Evidence on Grounds of Prejudice, Confusion, or Waste of
Time,” [dated] 1 December 2002, Federal Rules of Evidence, [visited]
13 March 2003, <http://www.house.gov/judiciary/Evid2002.pdf>: 4
[20 of 43].
12 FRE 404 is on Character Evidence Not Admissible to Prove Conduct;
Exceptions; Other Crimes. FRE 405 is on Methods of Proving
Character. The former states that “Evidence of other crimes, wrongs,
or acts is not admissible to prove the character of a person in order to
show action in conformity therewith. It may, however, be admissible
for other purposes, such as proof of motive, opportunity, intent,
preparation, plan, knowledge, identity, or absence of mistake or
accident, provided that upon request by the accused, the prosecution in
a criminal case shall provide reasonable notice in advance of trial, or
during trial if the court excuses pretrial notice on good cause shown,
of the general nature of any evidence it intends to introduce at trial”
([Article 4: Relevancy and Its Limits: Rule] 404: Character Evidence
Not Admissible to Prove Conduct; Exceptions; Other Crimes,” [dated]
1 December 2002, Federal Rules of Evidence, [visited] 13 March
2003, <http://www.house.gov/judiciary/Evid2002.pdf>: 4 [20 of 43]).
13 She was referring to s. 635.
14 Nesson, Green, and Murray 6.
15 Molinari; quoted in Nesson, Green, and Murray 6.
16 Molinari; quoted in Nesson, Green, and Murray 6.
17 “93.671: Family Violence Prevention and Services/Grants for Battered
Women’s Shelters …” [undated], Catalog of Federal Domestic
Assistance, [visited] 18 March 2003,
<http://www.cfda.gov/public/viewprog/asp?progid=1314>: 1. The
goal of this act is to “assist States and Indian Tribes in the prevention
of family violence and the provision of immediate shelter and related
assistance for victims of family violence and their dependents.” Here
is the history. “The Family Violence Prevention and Services Act
(fvpsa) was enacted as Title III of the Child Abuse Amendments of
1984, P.L. 98–457. It was reauthorized and amended for fy 1995
through fy 2000 by P.L. 103–322, the Violent Crime Control and Law
Enforcement Act of 1994 (the Crime Bill). The reauthorization of the
Child Abuse Prevention and Treatment Act on October 3, 1996
contained a technical amendment affecting funding levels under the
fvpsa” (“Legislative authority,” [undated], Family Violence Prevention
and Services Programs, [visited] 20 March 2003,
<http://www.acf.dhhs.gov/programs/ocs/01comply/famvio.htm>: 1).
(“Legislative authority” is not a separate page of this site, merely a
separate section.)
18 James Jacobs and Kimberly Potter, Hate Crimes: Criminal Law and
Identity Politics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998) 40.
19 Jacobs and Potter 69.
20 Jacobs and Potter 74.
21 Feminists have encouraged women to sue for damages. On 15 May
2000, this new system hit a snag in the United States. Feminists had
been agitating for the ability of a victim to sue her rapist in federal
court, basing her case on the Constitution’s Commerce Clause and its
Equal Protection Clause. The test case was United States v. Morrison,
529 U.S. 598 (2000). In this case Christy Brzonkala, of Virginia
Polytechnic Institute and State University, claimed that she had been
raped in September 1994 by Anthony Morrison and James Lan-dale
Crawford, two football players who, within an hour of meeting
Brzonkala, had allegedly pinned her down on her bed in a dorm and
taken turns raping her. The school’s disciplinary hearing found only
one of them guilty and suspended him for two years. Then, just before
the football team’s opening game, the school not only reversed its
decision but also gave him a full athletic scholarship. Later, Brzonkala
sued both men for violating her civil rights and the school for privately
adjudicating a criminal case of rape and for giving preferential
treatment to male athletes over female athletes, which was against
Title IX of the Civil Rights Act.
The Supreme Court ruled 5 to 4 that “Congress exceeded its
authority when it passed the provision of the 1994 Violence Against
Women Act that granted victims of rape, stalking and other “gender-
motivated” crimes the power to file federal civil lawsuits against their
alleged attackers” (Geraldine Sealey, “High Court Nixes Rape
Lawsuits: Congress Exceeded Its Authority, Majority Rules,” [dated]
15 May 2000, ABC News, [visited] 13 March 2003,
<http://abcnews.go.com/sections/us/DailyNews/scotus_raperuling000
515.html>: 1). Police power is a local power, according to the
majority, not a federal one. And if Congress were to regulate gender-
motivated violence, then it would have to regulate all types of
violence. According to the minority, on the other hand, Congress had
examined a great deal of data to the effect that violence against
women affected interstate commerce (Sealey 2). The two female
justices took opposing positions. Sandra Day O’Conner voted with the
majority, Ruth Bader Ginsburg with the minority. Some observers said
that the majority vote might have been intended mainly to support the
judicial trend toward protecting states’ rights. Other observers said
that it usurped the legislative function of Congress.
But the problem for feminists was the government’s retreat from its
willingness to protect women from violence by men. Patricia Ireland,
president of the National Organization of Women (NOW) declared that
the “Supreme Court has said not just that women’s right to be free
from violence is not protected by the U.S. Constitution but that the
Constitution actually prohibits Congress from providing such
protection. I’ve never seen a more compelling argument for a
constitutional amendment guaranteeing women’s equality” (Reported
in Wendy McElroy, XXX: A Woman’s Right to Pornography [New
York: St Martin’s Press, 1995] 4; no details given).
NOW declared that this case was about limiting the power of
women. McElroy declared that it was about limiting the power of
Congress, which had been slowly eroding due to expanded
interpretations of the Commerce Clause. Had section 13981 of the
Violence against Women Act stood, she concludes, it would have been
most beneficial to upper-class women fighting divorce cases or
educated women with cases against universities. “Unless the
application of the VAWA were to be massively expanded to include
such issues as child support and alimony – an expansion that may well
have been envisioned by its advocates – the VAWA’s greatest victory
may be as an ideological symbol. It symbolized and institutionalized
the political belief that women must receive special protection from
men. When confronted with violence and its redress, the VAWA said
that women are not to be treated as individuals but to be accorded
privileges as the members of a class. Curt Levey, an attorney for the
Center for Individual Rights, which provided legal representation for
Anthony Morrison, commented that “although today’s decision will be
viewed as a historic setback for feminist advocacy groups, it is a
victory for American women, whose safety is best preserved by
strengthening local law enforcement, rather than by relying on federal
bureaucrats” (McElroy 5).
22 “Division A – Trafficking Victims Protection Act of 2000,” Violence
against Women Office, 18 June 2002, United States Department of
Justice, Office of Justice Programs, 24 June 2002,
<http://www.ojp.usdoj.gov/vawo/laws/vawo2000/stitle_a.htm>.
23 “Division A” 1–2. The Victims of Trafficking and Violence Prevention
Act, moreover, held that existing legislation and law enforcement did
not acknowledge the gravity of these offenses and were unable either
to deter trafficking or to punish traffickers with suitably strong
penalties. To improve this situation and to make the reduction of
trafficking a priority, it mandated the following: an interagency task
force, with members appointed by the president and including the
secretary of state, to collect and organize data, consult governmental
or nongovernmental agencies, and so forth; a special office within the
secretary of state; educational and economic opportunities, including
programs to promote women’s participation in economic decision
making, for victims and potential victims; assistance, including
resettlement, through development agencies to victims in foreign
countries; assistance to foreign countries, threatening loss of economic
aid to those that fail to comply; special benefits or services to victims
– even aliens – in the United States, which could be enhanced by
special grants from the attorney general; and special “training” for
government personnel.
24 “Division B –Violence against Women Act of 2000,” 18 June 2002,
Violence against Women Office, United States Department of Justice,
Office of Justice Programs, 24 June 2002
<http://www.ojp.usdoj.gov/vawo/laws/vawo2000/stitle_b.htm>.
25 “Division B” 20.
26 “Division B” 5.
27 “Division B” 11.
28 “Publications,” [undated] Violence against Women Office, United
States Department of Justice, Office of Justice Programs, [visited] 24
June 2002, <http://www.ojp.usdoj.gov/vawo/publications.htm>.
29 “Federal Statutes Relating to Crimes against Children,” [undated],
Crimes against Children Program, [visited] 19 November 2001,
<http://www.fbi.gov/hq/cid/cac/federal.htm>. For aggravated sexual
abuse, see section 2241(A)(C); for sexual abuse – that is, sexual acts –
see section 2243; for prostitution, see section 2421, section 2422, and
section 2423(A)(B).
30 National Sex Offender Registry: Crimes against Children, [undated],
Federal Bureau of Investigation, [visited] 16 June 2005
<http://www.fbi.gov/hq/cid/cacregistry.htm>: 1.
31 “Registry” 1.
32 Criminal Code [of Canada], R.S.C. 1985, c. C-46, s. 276.
33 Criminal Code [of Canada], R.S.C. 1985, c. C-46, s. 277.
34 Criminal Code [of Canada], R.S.C. 1985, c. C-46, s. 276.
35 Criminal Code [of Canada], R.S.C. 1985, c. C-46, s. 276.
36 Criminal Code [of Canada], R.S.C. 1985, c. C-46, s. 276.
37 Criminal Code [of Canada], R.S.C. 1985, c. C-46, s. 277.
38 Criminal Code [of Canada], R.S.C. 1985, c. C-46, s. 666. The word
“offence” is interesting, because it is broader than the word “assault.”
Any infraction can be cited as evidence of bad character, not only one
with some bearing on the case (that is, an assault).
39 R. v. Seaboyer; R. v. Gayme, [1991] 2 S.C.R. 577.
40 Razack 112.
41 Christopher P. Manfredi, The Canadian Feminist Movement,
Constitutional Politics, and the Strategic Use of Legal Resources
(Vancouver: Simon Fraser University and University of British
Columbia, Centre for the Study of Government and Business, 2000)
35–6.
42 In Canadian Newspapers Co. v. Canada (A.G.), [1988] 2 S.C.R. 122, an
Ontario man was tried for committing a sexual assault, contrary to
section 246.2(A) of the Criminal Code, R.S.C. 1970, c. C.-34. “At the
outset of the trial, the complainant, who was the accused’s wife,
applied through counsel for an order under s[ection] 442(3) of the
Code, directing that the identity of the complainant and any
information that could disclose it not be published in any newspaper or
broadcast.” This presented the problem “of the freedom of the press
guaranteed in s[ection] 2(B) of the Canadian Charter of Rights and
Freedoms” and whether section 442(3) [was] “justified on the basis of
s[ection] 1 of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms.” The
Supreme Court found that section 442(3) did infringe the freedom of
the press but that section 442(3) did “not infringe or deny the
accused’s right to a public hearing and that section 442(3) was
justified on the basis of s[ection] 1 of the Canadian charter of Rights
and Freedoms.”
43 “Report by the Government of Canada to the U.N. Commission on
Human Rights Special Rapporteur on Violence against Women,”
[dated] 8 December 1998, Status of Women Canada, 2 July 2002
<http;//www.swc-cfc.gc.ca/pubs/unreport/unreport_e.html>: 3.
44 These cases showed that the legislation could impinge on civil liberties
or cause other problems in connection with due process (“The Victims
of Domestic Violence Act Revisited: A Practitioner’s Guide,” [dated]
December 2001, The Saskatchewan Advocate, [visited] 3 March 2004,
<http://www.stla.sk.ca/vict1201.shtml>:1). See Bella v. Bella, [1995]
S.J. No. 253 (Q.B.); Mosoinier v. Mosoinier, [1997] S.J. No. 732 (Q.B.);
Endicott v. Endicott, [1995] S.J. No. 317 (Q.B.); MacDonald v. Kwok,
[1997] S.J. No. 467 (Q.B.); Dolgopol v. Dolgopol (1995), 127 Sask. R.
237 Q.B.; and so on.
45 Crimes fall into three categories. Indictable offenses, the most serious,
are defined by federal legislation. Summary offenses, less serious, are
usually defined by provincial or municipal legislation. Hybrid offenses
are those that can be classified as either indictable or summary.
46 “Report” 6.
47 See “Gender-based Analysis [GBA],” 27 December 2001, Status of
Women Canada, 2 July 2002 <http://www.swc-cfc.gc.ca/gba-
acs/english/about/html>.
48 “Report” 10.
49 “Report” 11.
50 “Report” 12.
51 “Women and the Knowledge-based Economy and Society Workshop,”
28 October 1998, Status of Women Canada, 2 July 2002,
<http://www.swccfc.gc.ca/publish/kbeswk-e.html> [page 1]; the
conference, held on 15 June 1998, was “hosted by Status of Women
Canada in partnership with the Policy Research Secretariat.”
52 Razack 111. On the fifteenth anniversary of the Montreal Massacre, the
same argument was featured. “We know that violence against women
persists as a result of women’s economic, social and political
inequality. This is where violence has its roots. And if we are ever to
stop violence against women, we must address the things that
contribute to women’s inequality such as inadequate wages” (Basil
Hargrove, “Inequality at Root of Violence against Women,” National
Post, 6 December 2004: FP-17). The author is president of the
Canadian Auto Workers union, so he has an obvious reason for
focusing on economics. And his main point is actually about women
who lack the financial resources to leave dangerous men. Like many
other observers and activists, though, he conflates what causes women
not to leave dangerous men with what causes those men to become
dangerous in the first place. A few days later and in connection with
the same anniversary, something similar was put forward in another
newspaper. “Lépine, it was argued, was a madman from whose actions
no valid conclusions could be drawn. The other men, the ones
responsible for killing 593 women in Quebec since 1989, well, who
knows what their problem is? But we do know. It’s a refusal to admit
women have equal rights, that they have the right to decide what to
study, what job to hold, where to live, whether or not to marry or have
children” (Janet Bagnall, “Finally, Men Are Catching On,” Montreal
Gazette, 10 December: 2004 A-27). But, feminist orthodoxy
notwithstanding, we actually know nothing of the kind. The link
between violence and inequality – economic, social, political, or even
symbolic – is by no means obvious. A much more obvious link would
be between violence and size; bullies (from any group) are usually
bigger than their victims (from any group).
53 “Report” 9.
54 One method is to ruin a man’s reputation, and often his career, by
making false charges of domestic violence (which are hard to recover
from even if proven in court to be false). Farrell refers to Thomas
Kiernan, who reports (in “Voice of the Bar,” letter to the editor, New
Jersey Law Journal [21 April 1988]: 6) that he attended four seminars
for wives seeking divorces and that, in all four cases, a female lawyer
advised the women to create records of wife abuse – whether true or
false – before filing papers. Doing so makes it far more likely for them
to get their husbands kicked out and thus, indirectly, to gain custody of
the children (who are already living with their mothers in “stable”
environments). Another method is psychological abuse. A great deal
has been written over the past thirty years about its use by men. Very
little, however, has been written about the other side of that coin
(except in connection with these lesbians who abuse their partners).
“Now that we know that men are abused at least as much,” writes
Farrell, “it will be easier to study the entire abuse system – male and
female, psychological and physical. What little we do know about
heterosexual psychological abuse seems to indicate that the sexes
swear and insult each other about equally, and that women threaten
men with violence more” (Warren Farrell, Women Can’t Hear What
Men Don’t Say: Destroying Myths, Creating Love [New York:
Tarcher/Putnam, 1999] 154). Both women and men have distinctive
techniques, and these really do conform to stereotypes. “Men are more
likely to disappear at work, disappear into a project in the garage, or
disappear into a bottle; to withdraw behind a newspaper or in front of
the tv; to become addicted to sports or to gambling. Women are more
likely to shop and spend, nag and manipulate, or withdraw from sex or
into a romance novel. Contrary to popular opinion, both are about
equally likely to have affairs. Both sexes employ forms of power
intended to compensate for feelings of powerlessness. Both sexes
experience Pyrrhic victories” (Farrell 154). Like many other observers,
Farrell points out that women usually have an advantage over men in
conflicts over relationships: verbal and emotional skills. “In the arena
of relationship arguments,” he writes, “women are about as much the
masters as men are on football fields. But women’s misuse of
relationship power is legal; men’s misuse of physical power is illegal.
The illegality of physical abuse makes men more restrained in the use
of their physical power than women are in the use of their relationship
power. This might be called ‘The Great Inequality’” (Farrell 161).
55 Murray A. Straus and Richard J. Gelles, Physical Violence in American
Families: Risk Factors and Adaptations to Violence in 8,145 Families
(New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Press, 1990); cited in Farrell 139.
56 See, for example, Susan Sorenson and Cynthia A. Telles, “Self-Reports
of Spousal Violence in a Mexican-American and Non-Hispanic White
Population,” Violence and Victims, 6.2 (1991): 3–15, or Boyd C.
Rollins and Yaw Oheneba-Sakyi, “Physical Violence in Utah
Households,” Journal of Family Violence 5.4 (1990): 301–9.
57 Coramae Richey Mann, “Getting Even? Women Who Kill in Domestic
Encounters,” Justice Quarterly 5.1 (March 1988): 33–51; cited in
Farrell 140.
58 Farrell 129 (his emphasis).
59 Farrell 129.
60 Farrell 131.
61 Farrell 131.
62 U.S. Department of Justice, Federal Bureau of Investigation, Bureau of
Justice Statistics, National Survey of Crime Severity (Washington, DC:
U.S. Government Printing Office, 1985), #NCJ-96017; quoted in Farrell
131, his emphasis). This study was conducted by Marvin E. Wolfgang,
Robert M. Figlio, Paul E. Tracy, and Simon I. Singer at the Center for
Studies in Criminology and Criminal Law, the Wharton School,
University of Pennsylvania.
63 Ileana Arias and Patti Johnson, “Evaluations of Physical Aggression
among Intimate Dyads,” Journal of Interpersonal Violence, 4.3
(September 1989): 303; cited in Farrell 131.
64 Barbara J. Morse, “Beyond the Conflict Tactics Scale: Assessing
Gender Differences in Partner Violence,” Violence and Victims, 10.4
(1995): 251–72; cited in Farrell 128.
65 Farrell 138.
66 Suzanne K. Steinmetz, “Women and Violence,” American Journal of
Psychotherapy, 34.3 (1980): 334–50; cited in Farrell 139.
67 Farrell 130.
68 Suzanne K. Steinmetz, “A Cross-cultural Comparison of Marital
Abuse,” Journal of Sociology and Social Welfare, 8.2 (July 1981):
404–14; cited in Farrell 145. Farrell notes, however, that the samples
from some countries – Canada, Puerto Rico, Finland, and the United
States – were small.
69 Farrell 145–6.
70 Jerry Adler, “The Numbers Game,” Newsweek, 25 July 1994: 57–8.
71 Adler 57. In a letter to the editor of Newsweek, its director
acknowledged this error but without apologizing for it: “Yes, statistics
are often misused, confusing and sometimes just plain wrong. Being
acutely aware of this fact, we have spent countless hours collecting a
broad range of statistical information about domestic violence and its
effects. We do not ‘assert’ that any figure is true. Rather, we give out
as much information as possible from a variety of sources so the
reader can make an informed decision (Sue Osthoff, “Letters: What’s
in a Number?” Newsweek,29 August 1994: 17).
72 Daniel Maier, of the American Medical Association, had this to say:
“In our attempt to add perspective to the number of women killed by
husbands and boyfriends, we reported that domestic abuse kills as
many women in five years as the total number of Americans who lost
their lives in the Vietnam War. Stated correct, this comparison should
read, ‘Domestic violence kills nearly as many women each decade as
Americans who lost their lives in the Vietnam War.’ The AMA
apologizes for the error and any confusion it may have caused”
(Daniel J. Maier, “Letters,” Newsweek, 29 August 1994: 16-17; his
emphasis).
73 Adler 57. In another letter to the editor of Newsweek, The American
Medical Association admitted this error and did apologize. “Stated
correctly,” noted its director of news and information, “this
comparison should read, ‘Domestic violence kills nearly as many
women each decade as Americans who lost their lives in the Vietnam
War’” (Daniel J. Maier, “Letters: What’s in a Number?” Newsweek, 29
August 1994, 17; his emphasis).
74 Adler 58.
75 Philip Cook, Abused Men: The Hidden Side of Domestic Violence
(Westport, CN: Praeger, 1997) 12.
76 Cook 2.
77 Glenda Kaufman Kantor, 1992 National Alcohol and Family Violence
Survey; cited in Farrell 133. This survey was conducted at the
University of New Hampshire’s Family Research Lab; Farrell’s data
printout was provided by Jana L. Jasinski. Other studies confirmed
fact that women can be violent. According to one on dating couples,
women were five times as likely as men to be severely violent (Jan E.
Stets and Debra A. Henderson, “Contextual Factors Surrounding a
Conflict Resolution While Dating: Results from a National Study,”
Family Relations, 40.1 [January 1991]: 29–36; cited in Farrell 134).
According to another, this tendency increased as the emotional stakes
got higher for women (Mary Riege Laner and Jeanine Thompson,
“Abuse and Aggression in Courting Couples,” Deviant Behavior, 3.3
(April-June 1982): 229–244; cited in Farrell 134.)
78 Cook, 15–18.
79 Cook 18.
80 Cook 14.
81 “The U.S. Justice Department studied the rates for 1979 through 1988
and found that about 20 percent more females than males were slain
by their mates. The figures for 1988 are the most accurate, as the
Bureau of Justice Statistics surveyed a larger-than-usual number of
homicides, about 8,000 in seventy-five large urban areas. The results
of this survey, not released until 1994, show that of all white family
murder victims, 62 percent were wives and 38 percent were husbands.
For black family spouse murders, wives were just about as likely to
kill their husbands as husbands were to kill their wives: 47% of the
victims of a spouse were husbands and 53% were wives. For both
black and white victims, about 40 percent of the men and 60 percent of
the women were killed by their spouses” (Cook 19–20).
82 U.S. Department of Justice, Federal Bureau of Investigation, Crime in
the United States (Washington, DC: U.S. Government Printing Office,
1990). The table on page 11, “Victim Offender Relationship by Race
and Sex,” notes that multiple-offender cases are not broken down by
sex; only single-victim-single-offender cases are.
83 Farrell 152.
84 Cited but not named in Patricia Pearson, “Women Behaving Badly,”
Saturday Night, 19 September 1997: 98.
85 Pearson 98.
86 Pearson 100.
87 Farrell 136.
88 Farrell 136.
89 Farrell 127.
90 Farrell 127.
91 Farrell 128.
92 Farrell 128 (our emphasis).
93 Israeli women are indeed conscripted for military service but not for
combat.
94 Farrell 149.
95 Farrell 147 (his emphasis).
96 Karl Pillemer and David Finkelhor, “The Prevalence of Elder Abuse: A
Random Sample Survey,” Gerontologist, 28.1 (1988): 51–7; cited in
Farrell 147.
97 The National Longitudinal Study of Youth, appendix c, in Murray A.
Straus, Beating the Devil Out of Them: Corporal Punishment in
American Families (New York: Lexington Books, 1994) 25; John
Ditson and Sharon Shay, “Use of a Home-based Microcomputer to
Analyze Community Data from Reported Cases of Child Abuse and
Neglect,” Child Abuse and Neglect, 8.4 (1984): 503–9; cited in Farrell
147. Mothers are statistically more likely than fathers to abuse their
children, it is often said, merely because they spend more time than
fathers with their children; fathers might be just as abusive as mothers
in different circumstances. But that hardly exonerates abusive mothers.
The mere fact that any mothers hit their children undermines the
angelic stereotype of mothers, one that supports the ideological notion
that women in general are innately caring and loving and “nurturing.”
98 Farrell 148 (his emphasis).
99 Farrell 148.
100 Lynn Magdol, Terrie E. Moffitt, Avshalom Caspi, and others, “Gender
Differences in Partner Violence in a Birth Cohort of 21–year-olds:
Bridging the Gap between Clinical and Epidemiological Approaches,”
Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology, 65.1 (1997): 68–78;
cited in Farrell 148.
101 Farrell 148 (our emphasis).
102 Farrell 134–5.
103 Steinmetz, “Women and Violence”; cited in Farrell 137.
104 Farrell 137.
105 Farrell 124.
106 Alice Myers and Sarah Wright, eds., No Angels: Women Who Commit
Violence (London: HarperCollins, 1996).
107 Donald G. Dutton, “Patriarchy and Wife Assault: The Ecological
Fallacy,” Violence and Victims, 9.2 (1994): 167–78.
108 Susan C. Turrell, “A Descriptive Analysis of Same-Sex Relationship
Violence for a Diverse Sample,” Journal of Family Violence, 15.3
(2000): 281–93.
109 Farrell 147. Farrell cites one study, according to which 45% of gay
women reported physical violence from their latest female partner,
versus 32% of straight women who reported physical violence from
any of their male partners (Gwat-Yong Lie, Rebecca Schilit, Judy
Bush, and others, “Lesbians in Currently Aggressive Relationships:
How Frequently Do They Report Aggressive Past Relationships?”
Violence and Victims, 6.2 (1991): 125–6; cited in Farrell 146).
According to another study, 7% of gay women reported that they had
been raped by female dates versus 9% of straight women who reported
that they had been raped by male dates (Pamela A. Brand and Aline H.
Kidd, “Frequency of Physical Aggression in Heterosexual and Female
Homosexual Dyads,” Psychological Reports, 59.3 (1986): 1311; cited
in Farrell 146–7).
110 Lenore E.A. Walker, The Battered Woman Syndrome, 2d ed. (New
York: Springer, 2000).
111 Farrell 140.
112 Brown 65.
113 See U.S. Department of Justice, Bureau of Justice Statistics, Selected
Finding: Violence between Intimates (Washington, DC: U.S. Department
of Justice, Bureau of Justice Statistics, 1994) 6; cited in Farrell 152.
114 Farrell 152.
115 Brown 75–6 (his emphasis).
116 Brown 61.
117 Brown 69.
118 Susan Brownmiller, Against Our Will: Men, Women, and Rape (New
York: Simon and Schuster, 1975).
119 See Razack.
120 McElroy 2.
121 Intimate-partner violence (current or former spouses, girlfriends,
boyfriends) was declining in the United States during the late 1990s;
there were fewer murders, too, than in any year since 1976. “Between
1976 and 1998, the number of male victims of intimate partner
homicide fell an average 4% per year and the number of female
victims fell an average 1%. The number of female victims of intimate
violence declined from 1993 to 1998. In 1998 women experienced an
estimated 876,340 violent offenses at the hands of an intimate, down
from 1.1 million in 1993. In both 1993 and 1998, men were victims of
about 160,000 violent crimes by an intimate partner.” (“Intimate
Partner Violence,” [page 1]). This pattern followed other drops in the
crime rate; the violent crime rate declined 15% between 1973 and
2000. (“Crime and Victims Statistics,” 7 April 2002, Bureau of Justice
Statistics, United States Department of Justice, Office of Justice
Programs, Bureau of Justice Statistics, 21 June 2002,
<http://www.ojp.usdoj.gov/bjs/cvict.htm>).
122 In United States v. Lanier, 123 f..3d 945 (1997), MacKinnon wrote the
brief for Vivian Archie and the National Coalition against Sexual
Assault. She argued that Lanier, a judge, had violated the constitutional
equality of five women by raping them. He appealed the case to the
Supreme Court, but his appeal was denied. Moreover, MacKinnon has
been involved in several Canadian cases of this kind. Her point of view
prevailed in Canadian Newspapers Co. v. Canada (A.G.), [1988] 2
S.C.R. 122, which was about preventing anyone from publishing the
name of an alleged rape victim. Her position, that names should not be
revealed, was partially successful in Seaboyer 577. In this case, which
involved a challenge to the rape-shield law (see below), she supported
the intervention of LEAF with an affidavit and factum. In M.(K) v. M.
(H), [1992] 3 S.C.R. 6, MacKinnon successfully supported LEAF in a
case before the Supreme Court, arguing that the statute of limitations
in proven incest cases violates sexual equality (although the case was
decided on another basis: the legal irrelevance of time limitations on
discrete torts and breaches of fiduciary responsibilities to children). In
Norberg v. Wynrib [1992] 2 S.C.R. 226, she successfully supported LEAF
once again, this time to argue that equality under the law mandated
damages for a woman whose physician had kept her addicted to drugs
(in return for sex). MacKinnon has been involved, through LEAF, in
other Canadian cases, too. (Kristin Switala, ed., “Catharine
MacKinnon,” [dated] 1999, Feminist Theory Website, [visited] 23
October 2002, <http://www.cddc.vt.edu/feminism/Mackinnon.html>:
6–10). These include: “Re D.P. [a reference case about an unnamed
minor or other protected person, in which the government has referred
a specific question to the court], convicted child molester should not
be permitted to be called to the bar in Ontario (won); and Jane Doe v.
Metropolitan Toronto (Municipality) Commissioners of Police (1990),
74 O.R. (2d) 225, woman raped by serial rapist suing Toronto police for
violation of sex equality rights and for negligence in failing to warn
(won; going to trial); A.L., battered women’s sex equality rights
violated by decision not granting her victim compensation (lost, appeal
pending).” See also French Estate v. Ontario (A.G.) [R. v. Bernardo]
(1996), 134 D.L.R. (4th) 587 (Ont. Gen. Div.), affirmed: (1988), 38
O.R. (3d) 347 (C.A.), leave to appeal to S.C.C. refused [1998]
S.C.C.A. No. 139.
123 For discussions of I Shot Andy Warhol and Thelma and Louise, along
with many other movies of this type, see Paul Nathanson and
Katherine K. Young, Spreading Misandry: The Teaching of Contempt
for Men in Popular Culture (Albany: State University of New York
Press 2001).
124 Catharine MacKinnon, Only Words (Cambridge: Harvard University
Press, 1994).
125 Carlin Romano, “Between the Motion and the Act,” Nation, 15
November 1993, 563–70. By that time, many academics agreed with
MacKinnon. Some academics at Harvard said so, at any rate; Lindsay
Waters and others attacked his “use of rape as a tool for the conduct of
criticism” (“Exchange: Words Are All I Have,” The Nation, 27
December 1993: 786). See also Richard Lacayo, “Assault by
Paragraph,” Time, 17 January 1994: 37.
126 Edward O. Laumann and others, The Social Organization of Sexuality:
Sexual Practices in the United States (Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1994).
127 Listen to McElroy: “Ominously, the VAWA does not clearly delineate
what constitutes ‘gender-motivated violence,’ allowing the term to
cover conceivably any situation of abuse that involved gender hostility.
This is promising for feminists who routinely consider even words and
images to be a form of gender violence. Such arguments led Supreme
Court Justice Sandra Day O’Connor to state, ‘your approach … would
justify a federal remedy for alimony or child support.’ Arguably, that is
precisely what radical feminists wanted and hoped to achieve through
the VAWA. Radical feminists want a war on ‘gender violence’ similar to
the ‘War on Drugs’ – that is, zero tolerance backed by maximum force.
To this end, the VAWA attempted to create a special class of crime
defined by ideology. A major tenet of radical feminism is that violence
against women is part of a political campaign that men as a class inflict
upon women as a class. The fact that real violence against women –
E.G., murder, battery, rape – has been steadily and steeply declining
since 1990 in no way impacts their passionate cry for harsher
enforcement. Facts are often irrelevant to ideology.” Jacobs and Potter,
too, complain about its loose definition of crime, which “could
transform virtually any intergroup crime into a hate crime” (Jacobs and
Potter 40). Hate crimes are caused by prejudice, they say, a factor that
should increase the punishment. The fact that any woman who has
been beaten by a man could already have sued, moreover, made a new
law redundant. Its value was purely symbolic. They conclude that its
creation was a political response to political demands from a lobby
group. It was expedient because it involved no major budgetary
consequences, because it provided a way for politicians to appear
tough on discrimination and intolerance, and because it was vaguely
worded (Jacobs and Potter 78).
128 “Rape,” [dated] 2000–2003, Cool Nurse, [visited] 10 April 2003,
<http://www.coolnurse.com/rape.htm>: 1.
129 Lawrence A. Greenfeld, “Sex Offenses and Offenders: An Analysis of
Data on Rape and Sexual Assault,” [dated] 7 February 1997, Violence
against Women Online Resources, [visited] 10 April 2003,
<http://www.vaw.umn.edu/documents/sexoff/sexoff.html>: 34, 35.
130 Greenfeld 35.
131 Greenfeld 34.
132 Greenfeld 35.
133 Greenfeld 35.
134 Criminal Code of Canada, R.S.C. 1985, C-46, s. 271.
135 “Sexual Harassment: Legal Definitions,” [undated], Memorial
University, [visited] 11 April 2003,
<http://www.mun.ca/sexualharassment/Lgality.html>: 3.
136 Criminal Code of Canada, R.S.C. 1985, C-46, s. 272.
137 “Sexual Harassment” 3.
138 Criminal Code of Canada, R.S.C. 1985, C-46, s. 273.
139 “Sexual Harassment” 3.
140 Maire Gannon, Feasibility Study on Crime: Comparisons between
Canada and the United States, catalogue number 85F0035XIE (Ottawa:
Statistics Canada, Canadian Centre for Justice Statistics, 2001) 11.
(The title page indicates that this is an “irregular” periodical.)
141 Gannon 11.
142 Pamela Cross, “The Uniqueness of Sexual Assault Cases, [dated] April
2000, Ontario Women’s Justice Network, [visited] 13 March 2003,
<http://www.owjn.org/issues/assault/unique.htm>: 1.
143 Cross 1.
144 Cross 2.
145 The lower classes worried much less about privacy, mainly because
they could not afford it. Until the nineteenth century, for instance, poor
people in Europe often lived in one-room dwellings; whole families
slept in one bed— if they had beds at all. In the early Middle Ages,
even feudal courts often slept together in great halls; whatever privacy
they had would have been minimal indeed by Victorian standards.
Later kings and queens, moreover, were sometimes observed by
courtiers as a matter of policy: to ensure that royal marriages were
consummated.
146 Cross 2.
147 Cross 2.
148 Cross 2.
149 Cross 2.
150 Cross 2.
151 Cross 1.
152 Frederick Mathews, The Invisible Boy: Revisioning the Victimization of
Male Children and Teens (Ottawa: Health Canada, Minister of Public
Works and Government Services Canada, 1996) [catalogue no. H72–
21/143–1996E] 1996). This noteworthy – indeed almost unprecedented –
report is available also at <http://www.hc-
sc.gc.ca/hppb/familyviolence/html/invisible.htm>; from the National
Clearinghouse on Family Violence, Health Promotion and Programs
Branch, Health Canada Address Locator: #0201A1, Ottawa, Canada, KIA
IB4; and by calling (613) 957–2938, (613) 941–8930, or 800–267–1291
(fax).
153 In chapter 1, Mathews discusses the sheer prevalence of violence
against boys and men (but without ignoring violence against girls and
women) in its many forms: sexual abuse; incest involving siblings;
physical abuse involving siblings; sexual harassment; prison rape;
physical abuse, emotional abuse, and neglect; corporal punishment;
communal and institutional violence; suicide; street youth;
prostitution; children with disabilities; images of violence against boys
and men in the mass media; and professional responses to boys and
men as victims as a factor in establishing prevalence. Although Math-
ews writes primarily about Canada, he does refer to American studies.
“In the United States,” he writes, “72% of juvenile homicide victims
were male” (Mathews 23).
154 Mathews 27, 32.
155 Mathews 28 (our emphasis).
156 Mathews 30; referring to studies by M. Perovich and D. I. Templer in
1984 (59%); A.N. Groth in 1979 (66%); and J. Briere and K.
Smiljanich in 1993 (80%).
157 Mathews 30; referring to a study by M.J. O’brien in 1989.
158 Mathews 29.
159 Mathews 29.
160 Mathews 23–4; referring to a American study by the Office of Juvenile
Justice and Delinquency Prevention in 1995.
161 Mathews 49 (his emphasis).
162 Molinari; quoted in Nesson, Green, and Murray 7.
163 Canadian feminists recognized this ambivalence, but Pamela Cross
argued that “[a]ny ambiguity was to be interpreted as a no, or at least
be heard as a demand for further discussion” (“Justice Issues: Defining
Consent: What Does R. v. Ewanchuk Mean for Us?” [dated] March
2000, Ontario Women’s Justice Network, [visited] 20 March 2003,
<http://www.owjn.org/issues/assault/consent.htm>: 2.
164 Razack 25.
165 These statements are allowed in every American state. To gauge the
importance of this mentality, you have only to examine a website
operated by the National Center for Victims of Crime (“Victim Impact
Statements,” [dated] 2003, National Center for Victims of Crime,
[visited] 11 April 2003,
<http://www.ncvc.org/gethelp/victimimpactstatements/>).
166 Martha C. Nussbaum, Sex and Social Justice (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1999) 180.
167 Nussbaum 180. On its website, the Department of Justice says that
“[v]ictims of crime have the right to submit a victim impact statement
to the court describing the harm or loss they have suffered from a
crime. The victim may choose [to] read their statement aloud at the
sentence hearing. The court must take the victim impact statement into
account when sentencing the offender” (“Victims Matter,” [dated] 20
December 2002, Department of Justice, [visited] 20 March 2003,
<http://www.canada.justice.gc.ca/en/dept/pub/voc/victimsmatter.html>
: 1).
168 The line separating essentialism from dualism is very thin and
probably of more theoretical than practical importance. To believe that
all history revolves around your own group, after all, surely implies
that it revolves in addition around any opposition to your own group. If
history is all about women, then it can also be about an allegedly
titanic and historic conspiracy of men to change history in their own
favour.
169 Andrea Dworkin, “Suffering and Speech,” in In Harm’s Way: The
Pornography Civil Rights Hearings, ed. Catharine A. MacKinnon and
Andrea Dworkin (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1997) 33–4.
170 Dworkin, “Suffering” 34.
171 Jane Aiken, “Leveling the Playing Field: FRE 412 & 415: Evidence
Class as a Platform for Larger (More Important) Lessons,” [dated] 28
October 2002, Washington University in St Louis School of Law,
Faculty Working Papers Series, paper no. 0 2–10–05, [visited] 13
March 2003,
http://law.wustl.edu/Academics/Faculty/Workingpapers/fre12.pdf: [3].
(There is no home page apart from this one, and since there is no
pagination; we counted the pages manually, including the title page.)
172 Aiken [3–4].
173 Seventy-fifth Annual Academy Awards, ABC, WVNY, Burlington,VT, 23
March 2003.
174 This might sound like nit-picking, but remember that some legal
definitions of rape are very specific indeed. The offense of sexual
assault includes any conduct proscribed by Title 18 of the United
States Code. Section 2246 of the code defines “sexual act” in a
technical way and includes a particular type of contact: “the intentional
touching, either directly or through the clothing, of the genitalia, anus,
groin, breast, inner thigh, or buttocks of any person with an intent to
abuse, humiliate, harass, degrade, or arouse or gratify the sexual desire
of any person.” (“Section 2246 [of Title 18],” [undated], U.S. Code,
[visited] 15 March 2003,
<http://www4.law.cornell.edu/uscode/18/2246.html>: 1; this website is
run by the legal Information Institute at Cornell University.
175 “That was great. I was like, I don’t know what the hell is happening
here, but I’m gonna go with it!” (Halle Berry; cited by Daniel Fierman,
in “The Big Night,” Entertainment Weekly, 4 April 2003: 28).
176 According to Canada’s Criminal Code, “No consent is obtained, for
the purposes of sections 271, 272 and 273, where (a) the agreement is
expressed by the words or conduct of a person other than the
complainant; (b) the complainant is incapable of consenting to the
activity; (c) the accused induces the complainant to engage in the
activity by abusing a position of trust, power or authority; (d) the
complainant expresses, by words or conduct, a lack of agreement to
engage in the activity; or (e) the complainant having consented to
engage in sexual activity, expresses, by words or conduct, a lack of
agreement to continue to engage in the activity” (Criminal Code of
Canada, R.S.C. 1985, C-46, s.273.
177 Pamela Cross, “Sexual Assault: Introduction to Legal Options, [dated]
November 2001, Ontario Women’s Justice Network, [visited] 13 March
2003, http://www.owjn.org/issues/assault/qa.htm>: 1.
178 R. v. Ewanchuk, [1999] 1 S.C.R. 330.
179 “If at any point the complainant has expressed a lack of agreement to
engage in sexual activity, then it is incumbent on the accused to point
to some evidence from which he could honestly believe consent to
have been re-established before he resumed his advances.” (Pamela
Cross [citing R. v. Ewanchuk], “Defining Consent: What Does R. v.
Ewanchuk Mean for Us?” [dated] March 2000, Ontario Women’s
Justice Network, [visited] 1 April 2003,
<http://www.owjn.org/issues/assault/consent.htm>: 8).
180 Mathews 10.
181 Mathews 36; referring to study by J. Brière, D. Evans, M. Runtz, and
T. Wall in 1988.
182 Mathews 35; referring to Sepler’s “Victim Advocacy and Young Male
Victims of Sexual Abuse: An Evolutionary Model,” in The Sexually
Abused Male, ed. Mic Hunter, vol. 1 (Lexington, MA: Lexington
Books, 1990), 73–85.
183 Mathews 52–3.
184 Mathews 53.
185 Mathews 12.
186 Mathews 190.

CHAPTER TEN

1 “Women’s Studies Program,” [undated], McGill [University], [visited]


11 March 2004, <http://www.mcgill.ca/mcrtw/programs/>: 1.
2 Daphne Patai “Exchange on Heterophobia” [between Daphne Patai
and Christine Littleton], [dated] 29 September 2001, Books on Law,
Book Reviews, Jurist: The Law Professors’ Network, [visited] 4
August 2002, <http://jurist.law.pitt.edu/lawbooks/revapr99.htm>: 8–9.
3 Paul R. Gross, Norman Levitt, and Martin W. Lewis, eds., The Flight
from Science and Reason (New York: New York Academy of
Sciences; Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1996); Paul
R. Gross and Norman Levitt, Higher Superstition: The Academic Left
and Its Quarrels with Science (Baltimore, md; Johns Hopkins
University Press, 1998).
4 A classic example from the mid-nineteenth century comes from the
pen of Charles Dickens. Visited by the ghost of Jacob Marley, in A
Christmas Carol, Ebenezer Scrooge refuses to believe his own eyes.
“Why do you doubt your senses?” asks the ghost. “Because … a little
thing affects them. A slight disorder of the stomach makes them
cheats. You may be an undigested bit of beef, a blot of mustard, a
crumb of cheese, a fragment of an underdone potato. There’s more of
gravy than of grave about you, whatever you are” (Charles Dickens, A
Christmas Carol: A Ghost Story of Christmas [1843; London:
Gollancz, 1983]: 29).
5 In Higher Superstition, Gross and Levitt argue that academics in the
“hard” sciences have not taken the attack seriously for several reasons.
It makes no sense in scientific terms, for instance, and many scientists
sympathize with the general goals of ideologies on the political left. In
addition, however, they argue that scientists should take it seriously.
6 Gross and Levitt discuss several postmodern variants of the attack on
science, including the attacks not only of “radical feminism” but also
of radical environmentalism (which includes “ecofeminism” and
“Goddess” cults), radical forms of the animal-rights movement, and
racism (which includes “Afrocentrism”). Although the authors refer
often to ideologies on the political right, including Christian
fundamentalism (which sponsors “Creation science”), their book is
about ideologies on the political left. Why? Because the latter, unlike
the former, are firmly established in universities, including the most
prestigious ones, and thus in direct conflict with scientists.
7 Meera Nanda, “The Science Question in Postcolonial Feminism,” in
Gross, Levitt, and Lewis 420–36. Nanda agrees with other postcolonial
(or postmodern) feminists that science has been used by imperialists to
exploit and subju-gate non-Western societies. She disagrees with their
opposition to science, nonetheless, because non-Western societies have
used local traditions to exploit and subjugate their own women. The
only way to challenge those traditions effectively, she argues, is
through science. Following Ernest Gellner, she believes that “while the
historic origin of reason was culturally bound (à la Durkheim and
Weber), scientific rationality, understood as a sensibility, a
temperament, a style of thought, can be adopted by diverse cultures
situated in different geographical, historical and linguistic spaces. The
scientific temper is universally miscible with other cultures – with
often unexpected and transformative results – because it is based on
one clear and distinct idea that the rational mind cannot ignore,
namely, ‘that anything which is in conflict with independently,
symmetrically established evidence, cannot be true’ and must be
refused” (Nanda 428; her emphasis). Nanda’s opposition to those who
attack science is clearly motivated as much by political expediency,
though, as any genuine appreciation of science per se. She believes,
correctly, that science will make evident – if not immediately, then
eventually – all the errors of those who oppress women. But would she
accept scientific evidence for things she does not want to believe about
women (or men)? Scientific truth is the means to a political end for
her, not an end in itself. Many scientists agree with her, no doubt, but
the ultimate primacy of politics over truth is something that should
worry them.
8 See Gross and Levitt.
9 For detailed essays defending chaos theory as it is used by scientists
from the distortions promoted by postmodernists (and therefore by the
ideologues supported by them), see Jean Bricmont, “Science of Chaos
or Chaos in Science,” in The Flight from Science and Reason, ed. Paul
R. Gross, Norman Levitt, and Martin W. Lewis (Baltimore: Johns
Hopkins University Press for the New York Academy of Sciences,
1996) 131-75. The entire book, however, is useful as a scientific
critique of those who have tried to undermine science.
10 Edward de Bono, Lateral Thinking: A Textbook of Creativity (London:
Ward Lock Educational, 1970).
11 Janet Radcliffe Richards, “Why Feminist Epistemology Isn’t,” in
Gross, Levitt, and Lewis, 385–412; Mary Beth Ruskai, “Are ‘Feminist
Perspectives’ in Mathematics and Science Feminist?” in Gross, Levitt,
and Lewis 437–42.
12 Elizabeth Grosz (her emphasis); quoted in Richards 385.
13 Richards 387–8.
14 Richards 389 (her emphasis).
15 Richards 407.
16 Daphne Patai and Noretta Koertge, Professing Feminism: Cautionary
Tales from the Strange World of Women’s Studies (New York: Basic
Books, 1994).
17 Noretta Koertge, “Feminist Epistemology: Stalking an Un-dead
Horse,” in Gross, Levitt, and Lewis, 413–19.
18 Koertge, “Feminist Epistemology” 414.
19 Koertge, “Feminist Epistemology” 414.
20 Koertge, “Feminist Epistemology” 417.
21 Koertge, “Feminist Epistemology” 417.
22 Koertge, “Feminist Epistemology” 418.
23 Research on differences between male and female brains is interpreted
by feminists of the ideological – that is, essentialist – school in ways
that make men and women fundamentally different (not merely
different in some ways or in ways that can be modified by culture).
24 Donna Haraway, “Situated Knowledges,” in Simians, Cyborgs and
Women: The Reinvention of Nature, ed. D. Haraway (New York:
Routledge, 1990).
25 Dozens of current books and articles reiterate these fundamental
motifs: see L. Nelson, Who Knows: From Quine to a Feminist
Empiricism (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1990); L. Alcoff
and E. Otter, eds. Feminist Epistemologies (New York: Routledge,
1993); L. Code, What Can She Know? Feminist Theory and the
Construction of Knowledge (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press,
1991); S. Harding, Whose Science? Whose Knowledge? Thinking from
Women’s Lives (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1991); H.
Longino, Science as Social Knowledge (Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press, 1990); K. Lennon and M. Whitford, eds., Knowing
the Difference: Feminist Perspectives in Epistemology (London:
Routledge, 1994).
26 Paul Nathanson, “I Feel, Therefore I Am: The Princess of Passion and
the Implicit Religion of Our Time,” Implicit Religion, 2.2 (1999): 59–
87.
27 Patai and Koertge found that many, though not all, female students
were hostile toward men. “Some said male students interrupt women,
talk too much, question the authority of the female professor, are
defensive when the topics of rape or wife battering come up, and in
general, ‘just don’t get it.’ Others, however, were appalled at how
rudely the more radical women students treated any males who strayed
into ‘their’ classes.” In the words of one women’s studies professor,
“What amazes me is that these students would rather believe men are
evil than that they can change”(Patai and Koertge 144).
28 Joy Magezis, Women’s Studies (Chicago: ntc Publishing Group, 1996).
29 Patai and Koertge 110.
30 Patai and Koertge 8–9.
31 The Canadian link between research on women and feminist activism
is evident in the following letter, sent by E-mail, from Monica Hotter,
acting director of the McGill Centre for Research and Teaching on
Women: “Please circulate to graduate students in your department:
Doing research on women? Interested in feminist theory and activism?
Didn’t know McGill had a Women’s Centre?” (7 January 2004).
32 Patai and Koertge 177.
33 Magezis 1.
34 Simon Fraser University, Department of Women’s Studies,
advertisement, CAUT Bulletin, December 2004: b2 (our emphasis).
35 Magezis 13.
36 Patai 8–9.
37 Many of them did so in connection with a controversy over an online
colloquy, set up by the Chronicle of Higher Education, on Patai’s
views of women’s studies. We will discuss the content of that colloquy
later. Here, we refer to the controversy over it: “Daphne Patai,
Women’s Studies, and the Chronicle,” WMST-L, [dated] I October 2000,
Chronicle of Higher Education [visited] 29 September 2002,
<http://research.umbc.edu/~korenman/wmst/patai1.html>. Among the
very few who actually acknowledged that Patai had a useful point to
make was Viki Soady at Valadosta State University: “I do not often
agree with Daphne, but if we cannot listen to ‘difference’ how can we
continue to speak to how we must honor it and enjoin others to do so?
What I hear coming from Daphne is a legitimate belief that Women’s
Studies needs to be self-reflexive and to critique its positions and
effectiveness” (Soady, “Daphne” 10). But even Soady goes on to say
that she knows from personal experience “the transformative effect
that feminist theory and ethnic theory are having way down here in the
deep rural South where I have toiled for six years now” (Soady,
“Daphne” 10). It is precisely this “transformative effect” that Patai
questions in the specific context of education. Soady is surely a model
of tolerance, but she still fails to take Patai’s critique seriously. Much
more representative than Soady, in any case, was Jenea Tallentire, a
graduate student at the University of British Columbia: “I guess I
should credit people with more ability to think for themselves, but I do
believe that those who are predisposed to see the study of women as
pointless – or dangerous – can use Patai’s voice, supported by such a
well-known forum, to damage ws and the study of women in all areas.
It is not just the voice, it is the editorial support that is vital here. So
what do we do? Solicit editors with our own pieces? Go [to] the
newspapers and offer columns?” (Tallentire, “Daphne” 13). Actually,
feminists have been doing precisely those things for many years. And
for the record, Patai does emphasize the importance of studying
women. She just denies the legitimacy of doing so through the
exclusive lens of feminist ideology.
38 Daphne Patai, “The State of Women’s Studies,” [dated] 4 October
2000, Chronicle of Higher Education: Colloquy Live, [visited] 4
August 2002,
<http://chronicle.com/colloquylive/transcripts/2000/10/20001004patai.
htm>: 1.
39 Better still, of course, are testimonials from male academics. “The
chair of my department (history),” says Rosa Maria Pegueros at the
University of Rhode Island, “stopped by my office yesterday
afternoon. He had been on-line and was baffled by Daphne Patai’s
arguments. He says that he is confused by this controversy because his
experience with the feminists on this campus is a very favorable one
… Why is she saying those things? he asked me” (Pegueros,
“Daphne” 14).
40 Tallentire, “Daphne,” 15.
41 Littleton, “Exchange” 11.
42 Littleton, “Exchange” 15.
43 Beatrice Kachuck, “Rebuttal to Article by Daphne Patai published in
Chronicle of Higher Education,” [dated] 29 September 2001, [visited]
4 August 2002,
<http://www.umass.edu/wost/articles/vision2k/kachuck.htm>: 1.
44 Heather S. Kleiner, “State” 7.
45 The same anecdotal evidence is sometimes presented from the
perspective of students. Susan Kane, now a librarian at the University
of Washington, writes the following: “I was a student in American
Studies at the University of Michigan in the early 1990’s, where I saw
evidence of ‘orthodoxies’ within Women [sic] studies – and in other
disciplines. I evaluated each with a critical eye and believed only what
made sense to me. Why do you [Patai] assume that undergraduates are
stupid?” (Kane, “State” 6).
46 Adrienne McCormick, “State” 13–14.
47 Patai, “State” 14.
48 Diana Blaine, “State” 10.
49 Kristin Rusch, “State” 13.
50 Lisa Jadwin, “State” 8.
51 Patai, “State” 2.
52 Patai, “State” 3.
53 See Katherine K. Young, “Having Your Cake and Eating It Too:
Feminism and Religion,” in Journal of the American Academy of
Religion, 67.1 (March 1999): 167–84; Rita M. Gross, “A Rose by Any
Other Name …: A Response to Katherine K. Young,” in Journal of the
American Academy of Religion, 67.1 (March 1999): 185–94; and
Katherine K. Young, “Rejoinder to Rita M. Gross,” in Journal of the
American Academy of Religion, 67.1 (March 1999): 195–8.
54 Patai, “State” 4–5.
55 Littleton, “Exchange” 14.
56 Patai, “Exchange” 18.
57 Jane Elza, “State” 9.
58 Patai “State” 9.
59 Except in Britain and Australia, however, the term “women’s studies”
remains far more common on websites (see appendix 11), than either
“gender studies” or “feminist studies” and their variants.
60 Status of Women Supplement, in CAUT Bulletin, 48:9 (October 2001).
61 Katherine Side, Status 3.
62 The academic jargon of feminists (and other postmodernists) clearly
spills over into everyday life. Even Gloria Steinem ridicules it
deliciously: “[T]hese poor women in academia have to talk this silly
language that nobody can understand in order to be accepted, they
think. If I read the word ‘problematize’ one more time, I’m going to
vomit. If I hear people talking about ‘feminist praxis’ – I mean, it’s
practice, say practice” (Gloria Steinem; interviewed by Cynthia
Gorney, “Gloria,” [dated] 1995, Mother Jones [visited] 23 October
2002,
<http://www.motherjones.com/mother_jones/ND95/gorney.html>: 1.)
Jargon-filled postmodern writing, she says, is “gobbledygook.” Our
point here, though, is merely to indicate the link between elite
feminists and other feminists. Steinem and other celebrated activists
can get away with criticism of women’s studies. But not academics.
Professionally, most find it prudent to toe the line. Those who fail at
least to acknowledge and tolerate jargony (or radical) feminist
analyses, after all, are accused of not being “inclusive” (referring, of
course, only to women).
63 Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Edward Craig, 10 vols.
(New York: Routledge, 1998).
64 George Steiner, “Books of Knowledge,” review of the Routledge
Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Edward Craig, New York Times Book
Review, 5 July 1998: 12.
65 See Joan Korenman, “Internet Resources for Women’s Studies,”
[updated] 29 May 2002, Monash University, [visited] 5 August 2002,
<http://www.lib.monash.edu.au/subjecs/WomensStudies/Internet.html
>. Listed on the Internet are no fewer than 1,990 sites, all about
resources on women. Korenman is director of the Center for Women
and Information Technology, at the University of Maryland, Baltimore
County. Many web pages are produced and maintained by women’s
studies departments. See, for example, “Statistical Sources on Women
and Gender,” [dated] 22 February 2002, Women’s Studies Librarian’s
Office, University of Wisconsin, [visited 4 August 2002],
<http://www.library.wisc.edu/libraries/WomensStudies/stats.htm>.
66 Gerri Gribi, “Women’s Studies Programs Mailing List,” [updated] 2
August 2002, CreativeFolk.com, [visited] 5 August 2002,
<http://creativefolk.com/ws.html>.
67 Joan Korenman, “E-mail Forums and Women’s Studies: The Example
of WMST-L,” [undated], CyberFeminism, [visited] 5 August 2002,
<http://www.spinifexpress.com.au/cf/cfjoan.htm>): 1; Spinifex Press
is an Australian publisher of feminist books.
68 “National Organization for Women Foundation, [undated], National
Organization for Women Foundation, [visited] 5 August 2002,
<http:///www.nowfoundation.org/about.html>: 1.
69 “National Organization for Women Foundation.”
70 See, for example, “2002 News Releases,” [undated], National
Organization for Women, [visited] 5 August 2002],
<http://www.now.org/press/00press.html> 1. One news item, listed for
15 December 2000, was billed “NOW Activists Vow to Turn Deep
Anger into Determined Activism.”
71 “Action Center Calendar,” [undated], National Organization for
Women, [visited] 5 August 2002, <http://www.now.org/calendar.html>.
72 Steinem had an unusual childhood. Even though she did not have much
formal education as a child, because her family was constantly on the
road, she eventually went to Smith College. There, she majored in
government and graduated as a Phi Beta Kappa in 1956. After two
years in India on a fellowship, she became a freelance columnist and
the author of several books, including Outrageous Acts and Everyday
Rebellions, 2nd ed. (New York: Holt, 1995) and Revolution From
Within: A Book of Self-Esteem (Boston: Little, Brown, 1993).
73 “About Us,” [undated], Ms Foundation for Women, [visited] 5 August
2002, <http://www.ms.foundation.org/about.html>.
74 “About the Feminist Majority Foundation, [undated], Feminist
Majority Foundation, [visited] 5 August 2002,
<http://www.feminist.org/welcome/index.html>.
75 “About the Feminist Majority Foundation.”
76 “Feminist Bookstores, Publishers, Reviews, Lists and Electronic
Versions of Women’s Studies Books,” [updated] 22 January 2002,
Women’s Studies Librarian’s Office, University of Wisconsin System,
[visited] 5 August 2002,
<http://www.library.wisc.edu/libraries/WomensStudies/books.htm>.
One mentions a coalition of thirty “women-centered” presses.
77 The word “elite” refers either to the academic elite or the political elite.
Betty Friedan is not an academic, for instance, but she is a member of
the upper middle class.
78 Steinem, in fact, argues that feminism is “essentially a populist
movement” (Gloria Steinem; interviewed by Cynthia Gorney see note
50.)
79 Untitled, [dated] 31 July 2000, National Action Committee on the
Status of Women, [visited] 25 October 2002,
<http://www2.vpl.vancouver.bc.ca/dbs/cod/orgPgs/4/4870.html>.
80 “Welcome,” [updated] 27 May 2002, Status of Women Canada,
[visited] 23 October 2002, <http://www.swc-cfc.gc.ca/direct.html>.
81 “Women’s Program,” [updated] 2 February 2000, Status of ‘Women
Canada, [visited] 5 August 2002, <http://www.swc-
cfc.gc.ca/wmnprog/mandate.html>.
82 “National Day of Remembrance and Action on Violence against
Women,” [updated] 6 December 2001, Status of Women Canada,
[visited] 5 August 2002, <http://www.swc-cfc.gc.ca/dec6/index.html>.
83 After the Montreal Massacre (Gerry Rogers, 1990). This video was
produced by the National Film Board of Canada, Studio D (which
specialized in feminist productions), and the Canadian Broadcasting
Corporation. Waking Up to Violence (Sharon Bartlett, 2000). This
video features interviews with counselor Dale Trimble.
84 “Promoting Your Research,” [updated] 2 February 2002, Status of
Women Canada, [visited] 5 August 2002, <http://www.swc-
cfc.gc.ca/publish/research/020225–promotion-e.html> 6.
85 Pierrette Bouchard, Isabelle Boily and Marie-Claude Proulx, “School
Success by Gender: A Catalyst for the Masculinist Discourse,
[updated] 15 April 2003, Status of Women Canada, [visited] 8 June
2003,
<http://www.swccfc.gc.ca/pubs/0662882857/200303_0662882857_1_
e.html>. This website includes the obligatory disclaimer: “The
research and publication of this study were funded by Status of
Women Canada’s Policy Research Fund of Status of Women Canada.
This document expresses the views of the authors and does not
necessarily represent the official policy of Status of Women Canada or
the Government of Canada” (Bouchard 1). But would Status of
Women Canada display this report on its official website if it did not
represent the agency’s policy?
86 Bouchard, Boily, and Proulx 19–37.
87 Bouchard, Boily, and Proulx 17.
88 Bouchard, Boily, and Proulx 18.
89 On one site mentioned in the report, for instance, someone urges
visitors to harass Martin Dufresne (a male feminist): “Call him collect
to let him know what you think. Preferably, call him at 3:00 … in the
morning” (Bouchard 71).
90 In our own research, so far, we have focused exclusively on what
women are saying about men, but we do at least acknowledge the
limitations of this approach. First, it does not represent all women.
Second, it does not represent even all feminists but only the feminists
we describe as “ideological,” and we define that word very carefully
indeed. It refers to a mentality that has had a long history, one that
originated thousands of years before the advent of feminism and is
given expression today by both men and women on both sides of the
political spectrum. In fact, we discuss at great length nine specific
characteristics of ideology in any form. Feminists who reject those
characteristics, or at least most of them, are clearly not ideological
feminists (except insofar as they refuse to acknowledge the existence
of ideological feminism). We have no problem whatsoever with
feminists who believe that sexual equality is something that they must
begin to practise now (by treating men with respect as their equals),
not some utopian ideal that can be achieved only by practising
inequality in the meantime. And it is not a matter only of prudence on
the grounds that most people, treated as political pawns, will react
negatively in one way or another. It is ultimately a matter of both
moral consistency and insight into the human condition. There are,
fortunately, many women, including many feminists, who see that both
sexes are thoroughly human in a thoroughly ambiguous and complex
world. They see that both sexes are morally implicated in existing
forms of injustice, though sometimes in different ways, and thus
morally obliged to take seriously the needs and problems of those they
consider “others,” as a way of fostering not merely nominal peace but
genuine and enduring reconciliation.
91 Bouchard, Boily, and Proulx 2.
92 “Refused by All-Girl Team, Boys Charge Discrimination,” Montreal
Gazette, 21 December 1994: BI.
93 Bouchard, Boily, and Proulx 132, note 26; the report refers to Martin
Dufresne, “Masculinisme et criminalité sexiste,” Recherches
féministes, 11.2 (1998): 125–37; for the sake of variety, possibly, it
replaces “masculinist” on several occasions with the less trendy but
still common “patriarchal.”
94 The report discusses this theory of backlash three times (Bouchard,
Boily, and Proulx 46, 49, and 89).
95 The authors have clearly made an effort to avoid words that would be
associated immediately with what we call “ideological feminism” (but
which others call “gender feminism,” “radical feminism,” and so on).
Although “ideology” itself actually occurs only seven times, possibly
because of the dual meaning and consequent ambiguity, it is replaced
over and over again with the more fashionable, postmodernist,
“discourse.” In these cases, both words mean much the same thing.
96 The word “discourse,” or “discourses,” occurs no fewer than 151 times,
often in connection with “masculinism” or “masculinist” (which
occurs 105 times).
97 Another postmodernist code word, “deconstruction,” is used only once,
but in the classic postmodernist sense: “It is important to deconstruct
these perceptions and show that girls still have many barriers to
overcome in pursuing their chosen educational and professional paths”
(Bouchard, Boily, and Proulx 91).
98 Bouchard, Boily, and Proulx 91.
99 Bouchard, Boily, and Proulx 10. The report refers also to “scientific
theories developed in the field of women’s studies” (Bouchard, Boily,
and Proulx 16), even though that field is synonymous with feminism
and thus often eschews anything recognizable as a scientific
empistemology. Elsewhere, the report “contrasts this [masculinist]
discourse with some existing factual data on the same issues”
(Bouchard, Boily, and Proulx 4). Whatever the report says is factual or
even scientific, in short, but whatever their critics say is “discourse.”
100 “Alleged” or “allegedly” occurs 19 times; “apparent,” “apparently,” or
“appears to,” 6 times; and “so-called,” 4 times.
101 Bouchard, Boily, and Proulx 56–9.
102 Bouchard, Boily, and Proulx 56.
103 Bouchard, Boily, and Proulx 56.
104 In chapter 1, “The Globalization Context,” the authors make it clear
that when they refer to girls, they refer to both girls and women
everywhere. They quote statistics on education, poverty, violence, and
so on, from all over the world. When they refer to boys or men, on the
other hand, they insist on “contextualization.” Here are some
examples. All the men’s groups in their study, we read, “use the same
local, regional or national events as springboards for their claims,
always taking care not to mention the benefits and privileges men and
boys enjoy around the world. It would certainly be risky for
masculinists to acknowledge the low literacy rates and poverty of
women in most countries of the world” (Bouchard, Boily, and Proulx
36). But elsewhere we read that the “first aspect of this discourse,
beyond its various facets or the arguments it uses, is the fact that it
generalizes to an entire gender phenomena that appear in both genders
and are present in gender sub-groups” (56). Never mind that this is
precisely what they themselves have done on behalf of women. Read
this, for instance: “Among these students, researchers have found that
school resiliency is essentially a female characteristic” (57). Never
mind that the authors condemn essentialism over and over again. For
example: “These comments [by men’s groups] reflect an essentialist
perspective and the concept of [feminist] usurpation [in the lives of
boys]” (40). Never mind, in fact, that profoundly essentialist and
therefore also dualist forms of feminism have been fashionable and
influential for the past thirty years (a major problem that we discussed
fully in Spreading Misandry). In a note on a survey of violence against
women, moreover, Bouchard and her colleagues complain that it
“underestimates the real incidence of violence against women because
it did not include the Northwest Territories, where violence is
especially widespread” (135). In other words, the problem is violence
against women as a class; the fact that aboriginal women and other
specific groups of women are far more likely to be the victims of
violence than other women is considered irrelevant.
105 The report refers to “the political and economic division of power that
still subordinates women” (Bouchard, Boily, and Proulx 44). There are
other forms of power, but even these are not divided up so neatly.
Besides, we keep reading about the need to “contextualize.”
Consistency alone, therefore, should require these authors to make it
clear that not all women have less political or economic power than
men.
106 Frederick Mathews, The Invisible Boy: Revisioning the Victimization of
Male Children and Teens (Ottawa: Health Canada, Minister of Public
Works and Government Services Canada, 1996).
107 Mathews, 12.
108 Bouchard, Boily, and Proulx 80.
109 Bouchard, Boily, and Proulx 16, 26–34, 38, 46–9, 54–6.
110 Mathews 9.
111 Mathews 9–10.
112 Mathews 10.
113 F.L. Morton and Rainer Knopff, The Charter Revolution and the Court
Party (Peterborough, ON: Broadview Press, 2000) 129.
114 Morton and Knopff 129.
115 Morton and Knopff 132.
116 Morton and Knopff 133; referring to Paul Butler, “Racially Based Jury
Nullification: Black Power in the Criminal Justice System,” Yale Law
Journal 105.3 (December 1995): 677–725, which was noted in (among
many other sources) “When Jurors Ignore the Law,” New York Times,
27 May 1997: A-24.
117 Morton and Knopff 133; referring to “For Black Scholars Wedded to
Prism of Race, New and Separate Goals,” New York Times, 5 May
1997: A-14.
118 Women’s Law Journal of Legal Theory and Practice, [visited] 13 June
2003, <http://gort.ucsd.edu/newjour/w/msg02265.html>: 1.
119 Andrea Dworkin, “Against the Male Flood: Censorship, Pornography
and Equality,” Harvard Women’s Law Journal 8 (spring 1985): 1–30;
Jennifer Gerarda Brown, “‘To Give Them Countenance’: The Case for
a Women’s Law School,” Harvard Women’s Law Journal 22 (spring
1999): 1–38; G. Kristian Miccio, “A Reasonable Battered Mother?:
Redefining, Reconstructing, and Recreating the Battered Mother in
Child Protective Proceedings,” Harvard Women’s Law Journal 22
(spring 1999): 89–122; Margaret A. Baldwin, “Public Women and the
Feminist State,” Harvard Women’s Law Journal 20 (spring 1997): 47–
162; Emma Coleman Jordan, “Race, Gender, and Social Class in the
Thomas Sexual Harassment Hearing: The Hidden Fault Lines in
Political Discourse,” Harvard Women’s Law Journal 15 (spring 1992):
1–24; Jennifer L. Bradfield, “Anti-Stalking Laws: Do They
Adequately Protect Stalking Victims?” Harvard Women’s Law Journal
21 (spring 1998): 229–66; Amy H. Hemko, “Single-Sex Public
Education after VMI: The Case for Women’s Schools,” Harvard
Women’s Law Journal 21 (spring 1998): 19–78; Catharine A.
MacKinnon, “Rape, Genocide, and Women’s Human Rights,” Harvard
Women’s Law Journal 17 (spring 1994): 5–16; Nancy K. Kubasek,
Jennifer Johnson, and M. Neil Browne, “Comparable Worth in
Ontario: Lessons the United States Can Learn,” Harvard Women’s Law
Journal 17 (spring 1994): 103–32; Julie Taylor, “Rape and Women’s
Credibility: Problems of Recantations and False Accusations Echoed
in the Case of Cathleen Crowell Webb and Gary Dotson,” Harvard
Women’s Law Review 10 (spring 1987): 59–116; Lenora Ledwon,
“Melodrama and Law: Feminizing the Juridical Gaze,” Harvard
Women’s Law Journal 21 (spring 1998): 141–78; Rosemary C. Hunter,
“Gender in Evidence: Masculine Norms v. Feminist Reforms,”
Harvard Women’s Law Journal 19 (spring 1996): 127–68; Elizabeth A.
Pendo, “Recognizing Violence against Women: Gender and the Hate
Crimes Statistics Act,” Harvard Women’s Law Journal 17 (spring
1994): 157–84; Martha Minow and others, “Perspectives on Our
Progress: Twenty Years of Feminist Thought,” Harvard Women’s Law
Journal 20 (spring 1997): 1–46; Cynthia Grant Bowman and
MaryBeth Lipp, “Legal Limbo of the Student Intern: The
Responsibility of Colleges and Universities to Protect Student Interns
against Sexual Harassment,” Harvard Women’s Law Journal 23
(spring 2000): 95– 132; A.W. Phinney III, “Feminism, Epistemology,
and the Rhetoric of Law: Reading Bowen v. Gilliard,” Harvard
Women’s Law Review 12 (spring 1989): 151–80; Audrey E. Stone and
Rebecca J. Fialk, “Criminalizing the Exposure of Children to Domestic
Violence: Breaking the Cycle of Abuse,” Harvard Women’s Law
Journal 20 (spring 1997): 205–28; Meg Penrose, “I said, ‘No,’”
Harvard Women’s Law Journal 23 (spring 2000): 247–8.
120 John Sedgwick, “Beirut on the Charles,” Gentleman’s Quarterly,
February 1993, 154–5.
121 Sedgwick 156–7.
122 Sedgwick 201.
123 Morton and Knopff 132.
124 Morton and Knopff 131–3.
125 Morton and Knopff 128.
126 Morton and Knopff 147.
127 “About NWLC,” [dated] 2000, National Women’s Law Center, [visited]
13 June 2005, <http://www.nwlc.org/display.cfm?
section=About%20NWLC>:1.
128 Brentwood Academy v. Tennessee Secondary School Athletic
Association, 531 U.S. 288 (2001).
129 “The Supreme Court and Women’s Rights: Fundamental Protections
Hang in the Balance,” [dated] June 2001, National Women’s Law
Center, [visited] 5 August 2002,
<http://www.nwlc.org/pdf/SupremeCtReport.pdf>. So far, only two
women have been appointed to the Supreme Court. Sandra Day
O’Connor was appointed in 1981, the first women to hold this
position, and Ruth Bader Ginsberg in 1993. As of 1999, 20.6 % of
federal court judges were women – up from 9.5 % in 1997.”
GenderGap in Government,” [undated], GenderGap, [visited] 25
October 2002, <http://www.gendergap.com/governme.htm>: 2.
130 Christopher P. Manfredi, The Canadian Feminist Movement,
Constitutional Politics, and the Strategic Use of Legal Resources
(Vancouver: Simon Fraser University and University of British
Columbia, Centre for the Study of Government and Business, 2000)
28.
131 “LEAF: Then and Now,” [dated] 2000, Women’s Legal Education and
Action Fund, [visited] 3 April 2002, <http://www.leaf.ca/leaf01.html>
1.
132 Manfredi 29.
133 Manfredi 29.
134 Manfredi 29.
135 “About Court Challenges,” [undated], Court Challenges Program of
Canada, [visited] 4 August 2002, <http://www.ccppcj.ca/e/info.html>.
136 “About Court Challenges.”
137 Manfredi 30.
138 Manfredi 30.
139 Manfredi 31.
140 The Court Challenges Program’s volunteer board of directors has
included Shelagh Day (a founder of LEAF and a previous vice-president
of the National Action Committee on the Status of Women and a
member of the Court Challenges Equality Panel and Chantal Tie (a
lawyer with experience in LEAF interventions). The Advisory
Committee has included Lynn Smith (a professor of law at the
University of British Columbia and a president of LEAF); Juanita
Westmoreland (a member of LEAF, a chair of the Ontario Employment
Equity Commission, and a Quebec judge); and Sheilah Martin (author,
with Kathleen E. Mahoney, of Equality and Judicial Neutrality
[Toronto: Carswell, 1987]). And the Equality Panel has included
Claudyne Bienvenue (who has been on the Quebec Human Rights
Tribunal and has been director of the University of Guelph’s Human
Rights and Equity office); Yvonne Peters (a social worker and lawyer
interested in equality and human rights); Leslie MacLeod (who has
been on the boards of several Status of Women councils and a
consultant on equality and disability); and Martha Jackman (a
professor of law at the University of Ottawa and who has been
managing editor of the Canadian Journal of Women and the Law).
141 Morton and Knopff 128.
142 Morton and Knopff 27.
143 Morton and Knopff 107.

CHAPTER ELEVEN

1 “Gloria Steinem “ [undated], Wisdom Quotes, [visited] 8 March 2004,


<http://www.wisdomquotes.com/002551.html>. We are unable to find
the original source for this quotation.
2 Karen DeCrow, interview by Jack Kammer, in his Good Will toward
Men: Women Talk Candidly about the Balance of Power between the
Sexes (New York: St Martin’s Press, 1994), 58; quoted in Daphne
Patai, Heterophobia: Sexual Harassment and the Future of Feminism
(Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1998) 129.
3 And just as Jews are not necessarily anti-Christian. We chose the
reverse analogy, though, because the problem is deeply rooted only in
Christianity. Christian theology must make sense of the fact that Jews
do not believe in Jesus as a divine redeemer. As a result, Christians
have always been tempted to react with hostility toward Jews. But
Jewish theology does not refer at all to Christianity. If Jews are hostile
to Christians – and many are, unfortunately – it is due mainly to the
history of Christian anti-Judaism (which led to secular antiSemitism).
4 Rabbinic interpreters of scripture have always pointed with pride to
the ancient Israelites, whose insight into human nature prevented them
from trying to hide the flaws of their heroes. It could be argued less
charitably, though, that what we see as flaws, the ancients saw as
virtues. There is probably some truth in both appraisals.
5 Modern Jews explain this away in connection with fear of invasion or
disapproval of specific religious practices.
6 Never mind that all of the earliest Christians were themselves Jews.
Modern Christians, especially academics and theologians who want to
dissociate the gospel from anti-Semitism, explain this term in the
Gospel of John as a result of the split between Jews and Christians. At
one time, “the Jews” included Jewish Christians; now, especially after
the influx of gentiles, it no longer did.
7 This should be self-evident to almost everyone, although women have
been taught by feminists to fear not only men but also life itself.
Myrna Blyth, retired editor of Ladies’ Home Journal, has written a
scathing attack on women’s magazines (including her own). These, she
says, have supported a “culture of fear” and promoted the “victim
virus” among women. And precisely this mentality, she adds, is what
they exploit to sell liberal-to-left-leaning feminism. See Spin Sisters:
How the Women of the Media Sell Unhappiness – and Liberalism – to
the Women of America (New York: St Martin’s Press, 2004).
8 The process had always been politicized to some extent and
occasionally – think of the Dred Scott case, for instance, which was
about slavery to a very significant extent.
9 Mircea Eliade would be among the most famous sources for the idea
that there is something quasi-religious about secular political
ideologies. He pointed out in Myths, Dreams and Mysteries: The
Encounter between Contemporary Faiths and Archaic Realities (New
York: Harper, 1960) the striking similarities between traditional forms
of religion and political ideologies such as communism and fascism.
He argued that the only difference, albeit a very important one
(because it involves the defining feature of religion), is that traditional
religions mediate experiences of the sacred (in some traditions, of
God) and purely political ideologies do not. In all other ways – social,
economic, political, moral, aesthetic, and so on – political ideologies
are the functional equivalents of traditional religions. For Cimini’s
argument, see Mark Cimini, “Religion versus Religion,” [February
1999], DA*DI, [visited] 24 June 2000, <http://www.dadi.org>.
10 Roger Kimball, Tenured Radicals: How Politics Has Corrupted Our
Higher Education (New York: Harper and Row, 1990). See also
Dinesh D’Souza, Illiberal Education: The Politics of Race and Sex on
Campus (New York: Vintage Books, 1992).
11 It is no accident that Mel Gibson, a very traditional Catholic, produced
a movie about Jesus that focuses exclusively and almost sadistically
on the latter’s suffering: for over two hours, the camera lingers
obsessively on the body of a young man being caned, ripped, flayed,
crushed, and strangled. In The Passion of the Christ, released in 2004,
viewers are expected to experience that suffering vicariously and thus
feel gratitude for being spared similar suffering – which is to say,
gratitude for divine grace. This is consistent with traditional Catholic
piety (or at least one form of it). For approximately five hundred years,
at least since the fifteenth century, Catholic art has encouraged intense
emotional identification with the suffering of Jesus, Mary, and the
saints or martyrs. Why, then, has Gibson’s movie been so popular
among evangelical Protestants? It is true that Protestants rejected the
Catholic approach to piety, but some of them gave it new life in a
slightly different form. Instead of gruesome suffering, they
emphasized sentimental sweetness. Either way, the spotlight is on
emotion. Unlike other Protestants, especially the Puritans of early New
England, evangelicals have relied heavily on it. To be saved, after all,
requires a conversion experience, one that involves a highly emotional
passage from the anxiety over sin to joy over conversion; the entire
process is accompanied by emotionally charged sermons and
ceremonies. This form of Protestantism produced several massively
popular “great awakenings” in the nineteenth century. Either directly
or indirectly, moreover, it produced anti-intellectual movements such
as fundamentalism and pentecostalism in the early twentieth century
and the “charismatic movement” in the late twentieth century (often
within Anglican, Catholic, and other traditional churches). Evangelical
Protestantism now sets the general tone for American religion and also
for the secular popular culture that is derived from it. It takes very
little imagination to see the continuity between revival meetings and
talk shows – especially that of Oprah Winfrey, who prefers “uplifting”
topics and guests to the sleazy ones preferred by other hosts. Both
phenomena focus attention on people who testify in public that they
were once “in denial” (lost) but are now “in recovery” (saved).

APPENDIX ONE

1 Some people who enjoy popular culture have nothing but scorn for
academics who claim to have discovered sinister subtexts almost
everywhere in their favourite productions. To some extent, this
response reveals anti-intellectualism, but it reveals in addition an
understandable rebellion against academic cynicism. At the very least,
academics should acknowledge that popular culture has more than one
function, that entertainment is one of them, and that not everyone is
equally affected by political or ideological subtexts.
2 Warren Farrell, The Liberated Man: Beyond Masculinity; Freeing Men
and Their Relationships with Women (New York: Random House,
1975); Why Men Are the Way They Are: The Male-Female Dynamic
(New York: Berkeley, 1986); The Myth of Male Power: Why Men Are
the Disposable Sex (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1993); and
Women Can’t Hear What Men Don’t Say: Destroying Myths, Creating
Love (New York: Jeremy Tarcher, 1999).
3 Sacred history is another matter entirely. According to traditional
religions, primaeval events – in Western religions, these would include
the Creation, the Exodus, the Crucifixion, and so on – are indeed
repeatable. In fact, they can be re-experienced by the pious,
sacramentally, in connection with rituals and festivals.
4 Protestants rejected Thomist rationalism, based on Aristotelianism,
which had long been accepted by Roman Catholicism. They did so as a
corollary to their rejection of anything but faith as a way of attaining
salvation. The earliest debates were over “good works” as the human
contribution to personal salvation, but it soon became clear to
Protestants that reason was no more helpful. In fact, they argued, it
could be an impediment to salvation. Catholics agreed that reason had
its limits; for the specific purpose of salvation, it had to be
supplemented by faith. But they were careful not to deny the value of
reason for other purposes. This attempt to integrate faith and reason
led them to difficulties in the seventeenth century, unfortunately, when
reason, in the form of science, actually contradicted some of the
doctrines considered necessary for salvation.

APPENDIX TWO

1 Judith Levine: Harmful to Minors: The Perils of Protecting Children


from Sex (Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press, 2002) 30.
2 Estelle Freedman, “‘Uncontrolled Desires’: The Response to the
Sexual Psychopath, 1920–1960,” Journal of American History 71.1
(1987): 83–106; quoted in Levine 31.
3 Levine 32.
4 Levine xxiii–xxiv.
5 Levine 33.
6 Levine 36.
7 Levine 36.
8 Levine 37–8.
9 Levine 26.
10 Levine 27.
11 Levine xxiv.
12 Levine xxviii.
13 Levine xxx.
14 Kee MacFarlane; quoted in Levine 23.
15 Levine 24.
16 Levine 25.
17 Levine 25.
18 Levine xxi.

APPENDIX THREE

1 In avoiding tyrannies of the majority, however, democracies can easily


succumb to the opposite problem. When minorities band together, after
all, they can become the majority. In one sense, this is an old problem.
It has always happened in democracies with multiparty electoral
systems, which are based on proportional representation. Because no
one party can easily attain a clear majority, coalitions of other parties
use their combined power to influence or even dominate the
government; it can stay in power only by making deals with them.
Even though very few Israelis are religious Jews, for example, Israel’s
religious parties wield a great deal of power in the country’s unstable
governments.
In another sense, though, this problem is much more recent and is
the result of naive assumptions made in many Western societies about
political correctness, on the one hand, and “pluralism,” “diversity,” or
“multiculturalism” on the other. These societies no longer accept the
fundamental principle of all democracies: majority rule (albeit with
safeguards to prevent tyranny). The whole notion of a majority, in
fact, has been “deconstructed” by postmodernists and their ethnic,
sexual, or other allies. It is now known pejoratively as “the dominant
culture,” one that exerts “hegemony” merely by existing. Canada is a
good example. Although Canada was founded by Christians and
although most Canadians associate themselves at least marginally with
Christianity (no matter how secularized), the vaguest reference to
Christianity in public life is now considered an affront to Canadian
minorities. Even so, not all non-Christians are offended (Josh Freed,
“Christmas Part of My Tradition,” Montreal Gazette, 14 December
2002, A-3; Morton Weinfeld, “Merry … Oops, Happy Holidays,”
Canadian Jewish News, 9 January 2003: 10).
In 2002, the Royal Canadian Mint referred to the “twelve days of
giving,” whatever that means (Arthur Kaptainis, “Christmas Trounces
Political Correctness,” Montreal Gazette, 24 December 2002: A-1),
and the Gap instructed clerks to say “happy holidays” or “season’s
greetings” to customers instead of the supposedly offensive “merry
Christmas” (Sarah Staples, “Christmas Is In Again at the Gap,”
Montreal Gazette, 14 December 2002: A-15). These examples are
trivial. Others are not so trivial. Given their newfound political clout,
due to strategic alliances with feminists, gay activists have succeeded
in getting elementary schools to use textbooks that promote
acceptance of homosexuality (even in places where most parents
oppose it on religious grounds) and will almost certainly succeed in
the legalization of gay marriage (even though that could, arguably,
undermine this institution for the majority) by claiming, apart from
anything else, that merely being unmarried is tantamount to lacking
human dignity. In other words, the very fact of being a minority is
inherently undignified and therefore intolerable, which is a dangerous
point of view in any democracy. This particular political strategy,
undermining the “dominant” culture, is hardly confined to gay
activists. Nor did they invent it. It just so happens that their current
demands are among the more dramatic ones.
2 Frans de Waal, Peacemaking among Primates (Cambridge: Harvard
University Press, 1989) 232–3.
3 Jerry Adler, “The Numbers Game,” Newsweek, 25 July 1994: 57.
4 One reason for avoiding statistical arguments is simply that statistics
go out of date very quickly. Even if nothing changes from one decade
to the next, for example, statistics based on the earlier date would
normally be considered unacceptable.
5 A social problem is like a disease in one way; it cannot be cured
merely by getting rid of symptoms. Even in the most practical sense,
therefore, the end cannot be said to justify the means.
6 Adler 56.
7 Philip Sullivan, “Acceptable Scholarship,” University Affairs, January
1996: 23.
8 Lenore J. Weitzman, The Divorce Revolution: The Unexpected Social
and Economic Consequences for Women and Children in America
(New York: Free Press, 1985).
9 Geoffrey Christopher Rapp, “Lies, Damned Lies, and Lenore J.
Weitzman,” [undated], [untitled website], [visited] 16 June 2005,
<http://www.acbr.com/biglie.htm>: 1–2.
10 Rapp 1. Actually, more than a typo was involved. The carelessness, so
to speak, was pervasive. “Once given access to the files,” writes Rapp,
“Peterson began to recreate Weitzman’s study using exactly the same
228– person sample and the methods described in The Divorce
Revolution. He found that the information in Weitzman’s computer
file in many cases did not match up with the paper records of the
original respondent interviews. ‘The computer file was supposed to be
coded from the paper records,’ he says, ‘but the computer file in fact
did not reflect the paper records. For example, suppose the computer
file said a person’s income was $27,000 last year, but when I looked at
the paper records it turned out that it was $37,000’” (Rapp 5).
11 These figures were more in line with those of national studies, writes
Rapp, but still misleading. “The problem seems to lie in the ‘ratio of
income to needs’ used by Weitzman, Peterson, and others. Weitzman
asked 114 women and 114 men to report pre- and post-divorce income
for both themselves and their spouses, adjusting for alimony and child
support payments where applicable. Then, she compared these figures
to each person’s ‘economic need,’ based on the Bureau of Labor
Statistics’ Lower Standard Budget for an urban family of four in 1977,
to arrive at her ratio. Even as corrected by Peterson, her data was
sketchy: income or needs data was missing for 134 of the respondents,
and, according to Peterson, the data for family size, age of the
household head, oldest child, and other relevant variables was
‘problematic’ with notable ‘inconsistencies.’ From this admittedly
flawed data set, an income/needs ration was derived, and the results
labeled ‘standard of living’ …
“In the real world, standard of living is determined not simply by a
ratio of income to needs, but also by a lifetime of economic choices,
earnings, investments, and purchases. An accurate measure of
standard of living would necessarily include property owned, savings,
houses, furniture, automobiles, the neighborhood one lives in,
clothing, and the like, most of which is typically divided between
spouses in a divorce settlement. It seems unlikely that the average man
would have a 10 percent higher standard of living after losing half of
his marital property, much less a 42 percent increase. Pollock points
out that Weitzman’s income/needs ratio ‘omits completely any prior
assets that people have. In divorce settlements, so much of the issue is
who gets what, and it’s not just alimony or child support but also the
division of the others assets. And most of the studies that I’ve read
have omitted that part.’
“Warren Farrell … agrees with Pollock and adds that Weitzman’s
and other studies usually omit several expenses which men face.
‘There are five expenses that men have after divorce, typically
speaking, that Weitzman, just didn’t measure,’ he says. These include:
mortgage payments on a home they no longer live in, rent on a home
or apartment they do live in, child support payments, alimony, and
higher percentages of dating expenses. Says Farrell, ‘No one that I
know has controlled for all five of these variables’” (Rapp 5–6).
12 One variable is the different taxation rates of custodial and
noncustodial parents (which we discuss in chapter 6). The latter are
not allowed to claim child-support payments as tax deductions, but the
former are allowed to do that and also to claim children as dependents.
Another variable is the money spent by noncustodial parents on
visiting children. In other words, custody amounts to a financial prize.
Moreover, former wives are often awarded alimony for at least a few
years.
13 Atlee Stroup and Gene Pollock, “Economic Consequences of Marital
Dissolution,” Journal of Divorce and Remarriage 22 (1994): 37–54.
For additional sources on the economic problems faced by both
divorced fathers and divorced mothers, see the Rocky Mountain
Family Council’s site Fact Sheet: The Grass Isn’t Greener: The
Damaging Effects of Divorce, [visited] 18 December 2002,
<http://www.rmfc.org/fs/fs0030.html>. Economic problems are not the
only ones faced by divorced or separated men. This site has a very
useful bibliography referring to studies showing that they face greater
medical and psychiatric risks than married men.
14 Rapp 3.
15 Angela James; quoted in Rapp 3.
16 Rapp 3.
17 Rapp 3–4.
18 Rapp 4.
19 Christina Hoff Sommers; quoted in Rapp 4.
20 F.F. Furstenburg, “Good Dads – Bad Dads: The Two Faces of
Fatherhood,” in The Changing American Family and Public Policy,
ed, A.J. Cherlin (Washington, DC: Urban Institute Press, 1988; quoted
in Braver 56–7.
21 Cathy Young, “First Wives Club: Some Comments,” [undated],
Balance: The Inclusive Vision of Gender Equality, [visited] 16
December 2002,
<http://www.taiga.ca/~balance/index003/wives.html>: 1; also
published in the Philadelphia Inquirer, 7 October 1996: A-13.
According to the criteria that we presented in Spreading Misandry, this
movie could be classified as misandric. We did not do so in that book,
though, because it could also be described as misogynistic. In this
case, classification depends heavily on the identity of viewers. For
most male (and at least a few female) viewers, the movie is clearly
misandric. After all, it ridicules and attacks all three ex-husbands and
implies that all husbands are stereotypically worthless louts. And for
most female viewers, that presentation is satirical but also justified.
But for other female (and at least a few male) viewers, this movie is
clearly misogynistic. Why? Because it presents the protagonists – and,
by implication, all wives – as vengeful harpies who should never have
been married in the first place. Unfortunately, First Wives is not
merely misanthropic. It does not attack both men and women, after all,
but either men or women. It all depends on who the viewers are and
their ability or lack of ability to place the movie in its larger cultural
context.
22 Elizabeth Gleick, “Hell Hath No Fury: The First Wives Club Packs
Multiplexes with Women Who Recognize the Plot and Want the
Message: Get Even, Then Get over It,” Time, 7 October 1996: 80–5.
23 Maureen Dowd, “Men Behaving Badly,” New York Times, 29
September 1996: 4, 15.
24 Young 1.
25 Young 2.
26 Erin Pizzey, Scream Quietly or the Neighbours Will Hear
(Harmondsworth, England: Penguin, 1974).
27 Erin Pizzey, Prone to Violence (Feltham, England: Hamlyn, 1982).
28 Suzanne K. Steinmetz, “The Battered Husband Syndrome,”
Victimology 2 (1977–78): 499–500.
29 Murray A. Straus, Richard J. Gelles, and Suzanne K. Steinmetz,
Behind Closed Doors: Violence in the American Family (New York:
Anchor Press/Doubleday, 1980), 40–1; cited in Warren Farrell, Women
Can’t Hear What Men Don’t Say: Destroying Myths, Creating Love
(New York: Jeremy P. Tarcher/Putnam, 1999) 129.
30 A British survey of the mid-1990s found that more men than women
were being assaulted at home. Researchers found that 18% of men and
13% of women claimed to have been the victims of domestic violence.
According to Malcolm George in an interview by the British
Broadcasting Corporation, “You’re confronting here two taboos. One
is that women can be violent and the second is that men can be beaten
up by their wives. And that is something that nobody wants to take on
board” (“Britons Say More Men Assaulted at Home,” Montreal
Gazette, 8 December 1994: A-19).
31 Farrell 142.
32 Farrell 142.
33 Philip W. Cook, Abused Men: The Hidden Side of Domestic Violence
(West-port, CT: Prasger, 1997), 111 (reporting on the reaction to
Suzanne Steinmetz).
34 Cook 112 (reporting on his interview with Steinmetz).
35 Straus; cited in Cook 116.
36 R.L. McNeely; cited in Cook 119.
37 Mark Schulman, “A Survey of Spousal Violence against Women in
Kentucky” (Washington, DC: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1979),
Study No. 792701. Research was conducted by the Kentucky
Commission on Women and sponsored by the Department of Justice,
Law Enforcement Assistance Administration; cited in Farrell 143.
38 See Murray A. Straus, “Physical Assaults by Wives: A Major Social
Problem,” Current Controversies on Family Violence, ed. Richard
Gelles and Donileen Loseke (Newbury Park, CA: Sage, 1993) 72–3;
cited in Farrell 143.
39 Patricia Pearson, “Women Behaving Badly,” Saturday Night,
September 1997: 93.
40 Pearson 94.
41 Leslie W. Kennedy and Donald G. Dutton, “The Incidence of Wife
Assault in Alberta,” Canadian Journal of Behavioral Science 21.1
(1989): 40–54. Research was done at the University of Alberta’s
Population Research Laboratory.
42 Adler 56.
43 John Fekete, Moral Panic: Biopolitics Rising (Montreal: Robert
Davies, 1995) 71.
44 See also R. Emerson Dobash, Russell P. Dobash, and others, “The
Myth of Sexual Symmetry in Marital Violence,” Social Problems 39.1
(February 1992): 71– 91. Critiques of what has been dubbed the
“Battered Husband Syndrome” (which we discuss in chapter 9) have
entered the popular press as well. See Jack C. Straton, “The Myth of
the ‘Battered Husband Syndrome,’” Masculinities 2 (1994): 79–82).
The author discusses flaws in Straus’ Conflict Tactics Scale studies
(cts). “Perhaps,” replied Straus, “the most important conceptual error
is the belief that the Conflict Tactics Scale is deficient because it does
not measure the consequences of physical assault [such as physical
and emotional injury], or the causes [such as a desire to dominate].
This is akin to thinking that a spelling test is inadequate because it
does not measure why a child spells badly, or does not measure
possible explanations of poor spelling. The concentration … on acts of
physical assault [of specific kinds and degrees of severity] is deliberate
and one of its strengths. The attacks … are examples of blaming the
messenger for the bad news. Moreover, no matter what one thinks of
the cts, at least four studies that did not use the cts also found roughly
equal rates of violence by women” (Straus; cited in Cook 116).
45 Fekete 72.
46 Lenore E.A. Walker, The Battered Woman (New York: Harper and
Row, 1979), xv (our emphasis).
47 Walker 98 (our emphasis).
48 Walker 170.
49 Walker xi.
50 Lenore E.A. Walker, “Psychology and Violence against Women,”
American Psychologist 44.4 (April 1989): 695.
51 Walker, Battered Woman, xvii.
52 Walker, Battered Woman, 246.
53 Christina Hoff Sommers, “The Spouse Abuse Myth,” USA Today, 26
October 1994: 13.
54 Christina Hoff Sommers, “The New Mythology,” National Review, 27
June 1994: 30–4; “More on Superbowl Violence,” [undated], World
Wide Web Virtual Library: Men and Domestic Violence Index, [visited]
18 December 2002,
<http://www.vix.com/men/battery/newmyth.html>.
55 Lynda Gorov, “Activists: Abused Women at Risk on Super Sunday,”
Boston Globe, 29 January 1993: 13.
56 Sommers, “Superbowl Violence” 2.
57 Ken Ringle, “Debunking the ‘Day of Dread’ for Women: Data Lacking
for Claim of Domestic Violence Surge after Super Bowl,” Washington
Post, 31 January 1992: A-01; Robert Lipsyte, “Violence Translates at
Home,” New York Times, 31 January 1993: 8.5.
58 Bob Hohler, “Super Bowl Gaffe Groups Back off on Violence Claims,”
Boston Globe, 2 February 1993: 1.
59 Sommers, “Superbowl Violence” 2.
60 Sommers, “The Spouse Abuse Myth” 13.
61 Gloria Steinem, Revolution from Within: A Book of Self-esteem
(Boston: Little Brown, 1993).
62 “The ‘Stolen Feminism’ Hoax: Anti-feminist Attack Based on Error-
Filled Anecdotes,” [dated] September-October 1994, Extra! [visited]
19 December 2002, <http://www.fair.org/exra/9409/stolen-feminism-
hoax.html>.
63 “Christina Hoff Sommers’ Reply to Charges Disseminated by the Left
Wing Media Watchdog Group fair (Fairness and Accuracy in
Reporting, [dated] 15 March 1995, The Debunker’s Domain, [visited]
19 December 2002, <http://www.debunker.com/texts/fair2.html>: 1.
64 “The Violence against Women Survey,” conducted by the Ministry of
Industry, Science, and Technology (cat. 11-001E) and reported by
Statistics Canada in The Daily, 18 November 1993.
65 Fekete 82.
66 Fekete 80–1.
67 Fekete 84–5 (his emphasis).
68 Changing the Landscape: Ending Violence – Achieving Equality, Final
Report of the Canadian Panel on Violence against Women (Ottawa:
Minister of Supply and Services, 1993); cat. no. SW45–1/1993E; quoted
in Fekete 99ff.
69 David Thomas, Not Guilty: The Case in Defense of Men (New York:
Morrow, 1993) 146.
70 Farrell 142–3.
71 Farrell 143.
72 Grant A. Brown, “Gender as a Factor in the Response of the Law-
enforcement System to Violence against Partners,” forthcoming
article.
APPENDIX FOUR

1 William Safire, “Linguistically Correct,” The New York Times


Magazine, 5 May 1991 20.
2 Safire 20.
3 John Sopinka, “Freedom of Speech,” University Affairs, April 1994,
13.
4 Allan C. Hutchinson, “Like Lunches, Speech is Never Free,”
University Affairs, June–July 1994: 12.
5 Hutchinson 12.
6 Dan Osmond, “Letters,” University Affairs, April 1996: 28.
7 Sanjay Suri, “Objectionable Toys Withdrawn,” India Abroad, 12
September 1992: 25.
8 Edward W. Said, Orientalism (New York: Vintage Books, 1979) 285–
7.
9 The most thorough examination of this problem has been made,
ironically (or not), by a German Christian: Katherina von Kellenbach,
Anti-Judaism in Christian-Rooted Feminist Writings: An Analysis of
Major American and West German Feminist Theologians (Ann Arbor,
MI: University Microfilms International, 1987). Kellenbach’s
introduction is intensely moving, and the analysis is brilliant. Even so,
she sees no parallel between Jewish-Christian relations and male-
female relations. She recognizes “the Fall” as a projection of Original
Sin onto Jews, but not onto men. This might be understandable if the
context were general. But the context is very specific: feminism. The
primary “others” of feminists are men, after all, not Jews. In spite of
everything, she fails to make the logical and even obvious connection.
10 Mark Cladis, “Mild-Mannered Pragmatism and Religious Truth,”
Journal of the American Academy of Religion 60.1 (1992): 19–33.
11 James B. Wiggins, “Openings and Closings,” Journal of the American
Academy of Religion 60.1 (1992): 109.
12 George Jonas, “Denying Their Saviour,” Montreal Gazette, 27
December 1998: A-11.
13 Bob Morris, “A Model Family,” New York Times Magazine, 12
November 1995: 93 (his emphasis).
14 Jean Bethke Elshtain, “Trial by Fury,” review of The Real Anita Hill:
The Untold Story, by David Brock, New Republic, 6 September 1993:
33.
15 Carolyn L. Karcher, The First Woman in the Republic: A Cultural
Biography of Lydia Maria Child (Durham, NC: Duke University Press,
1994).
16 Drew Gilpin Faust, “Remembering Lydia: The Life of an Abolitionist
Who Was Nearly Erased from History,” review of The First Woman in
the Republic: A Cultural Biography of Lydia Maria Child, by Carolyn
L. Karcher, New York Times Book Review, 8 January 1995: 25.
17 Faust 25.

APPENDIX FIVE

1 In 1985, Juliette Woodruff estimated that 99% of the readers were


women (“A Spate of Words, Full of Sound and Fury, Signifying
Nothing: Or, How to Read in Harlequin,” Journal of Popular Culture
19.2 [fall 1985]: 27). There is no reason to believe that anything has
changed in that respect over the past fifteen years.
2 In this respect, though things have changed a lot over the past few
decades. By the 1990s, these genres had been successfully integrated –
at least in the movies and on television. No one is surprised any more
to find female protagonists “kicking butt.” We discuss this
phenomenon in Spreading Misandry.
3 Sarah Bird, “Rules of the Game,” Entertainment Weekly, 16 August
1991: 32.
4 Angela Miles, “Confessions of a Harlequin Reader: Romance and the
Myth of Male Mothers,” Canadian Journal of Political and Social
Theory/Revue canadienne de théorie politique et sociale 12.1–2
(1988): 1–37.
5 Miles 28.
6 Miles 28.
7 Miles 2 (her emphasis).
8 Miles 2.
9 Miles 4.
10 Miles 7–8 (her emphasis).
11 Miles 8.
12 Miles 4.
13 Miles 5 (her emphasis).
14 Miles 16.
15 The filmed version of Gone with the Wind (Victor Fleming, 1939) was
restored and re-released in 1998.
16 It is the direct ancestor of at least one sitcom, too. Ally, the protagonist
of Ally McBeal, is not exactly a feminist. She has a high-powered
career in law, to be sure, but she spends most of her time whining
about her love life, worrying about her biological clock or about her
daughter, and indulging in neuroticism. And, as outraged feminists
have pointed out, she wears miniskirts in court. (Even worse, Calista
Flockhart, who plays Ally, looks emaciated enough to cause rumours
that she has anorexia.) Troy Patterson points out that Scarlett and Ally
have many characteristics in common. Each belongs to a ruling class
(Southern gentry and Northeastern meritocracy); each yearns for an
unavailable man (Ashley and Billy); and each “expresses her romantic
torment with big eyes that brattishly bug out at a perceived affront and
a fat bottom lip alternately trembled in heartbreak, nibbled comically
in fluster, and protruded in coquettish pouts. Scarlett and Ally are
fairy-tale princesses who bear about as much resemblance to real
women as Barbie and Skipper. The fact that there’s no longer a place
in the fairy tale for Rhett Butler seems one small stop for Girl Power”
(“Scarlett Letters,” Entertainment Weekly, 23 October 1998 82).
17 Helen Taylor, Scarlett’s Women: Gone With the Wind and Its Female
Fans (London: Virago Press, 1989) 139.
18 Taylor 117–18.
19 We have already discussed the contention of Angela Miles that the
heroes in romance novels are really mothers in drag. In one biography
(Margaret Mitchell [Boston: Twayne, 1991]), Elizabeth Hanson
observes that the author of Gone With the Wind did indeed apply some
of her mother’s characteristics to Rhett (and to at least one female
character as well). This is hardly surprising for a writer. Like other
observers of human nature, she understood that many characteristics –
such as strength, courage, endurance, and caring – are commonly
found in both men and women. The particular characteristic under
discussion here, though, is the potential for violence. Mitchell did not
identify this with her mother. Nor is there any evidence to suggest that
fans of her book and the movie based on it have ever identified it with
either women or mothers. Besides, Rhett is associated specifically
with sexual violence, not merely the destructive aspect of nature in
general. It is true that motherhood, in both psychoanalytical and
mythological terms, has a “dark side.” Children do worry about being
engulfed or destroyed by their mothers. But for Miles to admit this
would defeat her whole argument. She wants to glorify mothers (and,
by extension, women), not to demonize them. Her whole article is
based on the assumption that mothers (that is, women) are inherently
benevolent, not that they are both benevolent and malevolent. To say
that Rhett Butler is really a “mother,” therefore, would mean rejecting
the superficial and sentimental notion of motherhood promoted by
Miles and seeing him as a Western version of India’s Kali, the Great
Mother who is associated with cosmic destruction as well as creation.
20 Taylor 115.
21 Tom Kuntz, “Rhett and Scarlett: Rough Sex or Rape? Feminists Give a
Damn,” New York Times, 19 February 1995: iv.7.
22 Friedman; quoted in Kuntz 7.
23 Sommers (her emphasis); quoted in Kuntz 7.
24 When TV Guide conducted a survey among celebrities, Tea Leoni
observed that in the category of most romantic video rental, “Hands
down, it’s Gone with the Wind. When he grabs her and takes her up the
stairs …” But Julie White disagreed: “That’s a rape video! I’m going
with Casablanca on this one.” We wrote to TV Guide for this
reference but have received no reply.
25 Friedman; quoted in Kuntz 7.
26 Friedman; quoted in Kuntz 7.
27 Margaret Mitchell, Gone with the Wind (New York: Pocket Books,
1936) 783. Interviewed about her character in Mary Reilly, the servant
of Dr Jekyll and Mr Hyde, Julia Roberts said much the same thing:
“She gets attracted to someone capable of hurting her. That’s the way
life is, isn’t it?” (quoted in Jeff Gordinier, “Living the Life of Reilly:
Clearing Up for Scrutiny of Her Latest Film, Julia Roberts Has
Nothing to Hyde,” Entertainment Weekly, 23 February 1996: 24).
28 Friedman; quoted in Kuntz 7.
29 Sommers; quoted in Kuntz 7.
30 Friedman; quoted in Kuntz 7.
31 Taylor 113.
32 Elaine Gignilliat, “Books of Love,” 20/20, ABC, WVNY-TV,
Burlington,VT, 13 August 1981.
33 Juliette Woodruff, “A Spate of Words, Full of Sound and Fury,
Signifying Nothing: Or, How to Read in Harlequin,” Journal of
Popular Culture 19.2 (fall 1985): 28.
34 Miles 9.
35 Miles 27.
36 Miles 27.
37 Miles 11.
38 Miles 16.
39 Miles 4.
40 See Nancy Chodorow, The Reproduction of Mothering: Psychoanalysis
and the Sociology of Gender (Berkeley: University of California Press,
1978). Not all feminists, including ideological feminists, care about
psychoanalysis. But many still believe that it can serve their purposes.
Chodorow, by no means a marginal figure in feminist circles, is still
cited in feminist bibliographies and course reading lists in women’s
studies. Among her more recent works is Femininities, Masculinities,
Sexualities: Freud and Beyond (Lexington, KY: University of
Kentucky Press, 1994).
41 Miles 21.
42 Miles 25.
43 Miles 2.
44 Ironically, this is linked to the more general dichotomy between mind
or spirit (good) and body (evil) that is rejected by most feminists as a
characteristically “male” or “patriarchal” way of thinking.
45 See Marilyn French, Beyond Power: On Women, Men, and Morals
(New York: Ballantyne, 1985). Originally, we intended to discuss
French’s book, what we call a “Summa feministica,” in one volume of
this trilogy. Due to lack of space, even with three volumes, we have
decided to do so in a separate book on how feminist ideology has been
translated into feminist theology. We hope to call this book “Beyond
the Fall of Man” (which, confusingly, is what we had originally
intended to call this trilogy).
46 Miles 28.
47 Miles 28.
48 Miles 28.
49 Miles 28.
50 See Mary O’Brien, The Politics of Reproduction (Boston: Routledge
and Kegan Paul, 1981).
51 Miles 23–4.
52 Dorothy Dinnerstein, The Mermaid and the Minotaur: Sexual
Arrangements and Human Malaise (New York: Harper and Row,
1976); Jane Flax, Psycho-analysis, Feminism, and Postmodernism in
the Contemporary West (Berkeley: University of California Press,
1990).
53 Miles 24.
54 Adrienne Rich; quoted in Miles 30.
55 Miles 5.
56 Catherine Keller, From a Broken Web: Separation, Sexism, and Self
(Boston: Beacon Press, 1966).
57 For a lengthy treatment of this particular argument, see Keller.
58 Miles 7.
59 Kelli Pryor, “Love Takes a Holiday,” Entertainment Weekly, 16 August
1991: 18.
60 Pryor 18 (our emphasis).

APPENDIX SIX

1 “Fourth World Conference on Women Beijing Declaration,” [dated]


18 April 2002, United Nations, Division for the Advancement of
Women, [visited] 5 August 2002,
<http://www.un.org/womenwatch/daw/beijing/platform/declar.htm>.
We will refer to this document as “the Beijing Declaration.”
2 “Fourth World Conference on Women Platform for Action,” [dated]
18 April 2002, United Nations, Division for the Advancement of
Women, [visited] 5 August 2002,
<http://www.un.org/womenwatch/daw/beijing/platform/plat1.htm>.
We will refer to this document as “the Beijing Platform.”
3 General Assembly of the United Nations, “Annex: Further Actions
and Initiatives to Implement the Beijing Declaration and Platform for
Action,” Twenty-third Special Session, Agenda Item 10, a/res/s-23/3,
10 June 2000. We found this document at the following website:
<http://www.un.org/womenwatch/daw/followup/reports.htm>; we will
refer to it as “the Annex.”
4 The Optional Protocol, Text and Materials: The Convention on the
Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination against Women (New
York: United Nations, Division for the Advancement of Women,
Department of Economic and Social Affairs, 2000).
5 Optional Protocol 1.
6 United Nations, Universal Declaration of Human Rights; reprinted in
Journal of Religious Pluralism, 3 (1993): 1–8 (our emphasis).
7 Beijing Platform, section 295.
8 Beijing Platform, section 26.
9 “Fourth World Conference on Women Platform for Action,” [dated]
18 April 2002, United Nations, Division for the Advancement of
Women, [visited] 5 August 2002,
<http://www.un.org/womenwatch/daw/beijing/platform/plat2.htm>: 9.
10 Readers are told to see Annex IV to the Beijing Platform, submitted by
Canada. See “Amendments to the Initial Position of the Group of 77
(Draft Platform for Action)” [undated], Linkages [visited] 5 August
2002, <http://www.iisd.ca/linkages/4cwc/dpa-012.html>. For some
reason, the word “gender” is not defined there, either.
11 Beijing Platform, section 295.
12 Annex 24 (IV.72.e). This is a reference to 24 of the printout, or section
iv.72.2 of the document.
13 Annex 2 (I.4).
14 Annex 12 (II.I.27).
15 See, for instance, “Progress has been made to combat negative images
of women by establishing professional guidelines and voluntary codes
of conduct, encouraging fair gender portrayal and the use of non-sexist
language in media programmes” (12; I.j.28) and “Negative, violent
and/or degrading images of women, including pornography and
stereotyped portrayals, have increased in different forms using new
communication technologies in some instances, and bias against
women remains in the media” (12; I.j.29).
16 Annex 6 (II.D.13).
17 Annex 31 (IV.B.82.j).
18 Annex 35 (IV.D.93.a).
19 Annex 39 (IV.D.100.c).
20 “nac Young Womyn,” [undated], National Action Committee on the
Status of Women, [visited] 23 October 2002, <http://www.nac-
cca.ca/young/young_e.htm>.
21 Annex 1 (I.1).
22 Annex 8 (II.E.16).
23 Annex 29 (IV.B.79.a).
24 Annex 24.(IV.A.71.a)
25 Annex 38 (IV.98.c).
26 Annex 19 (IV.60).
27 Annex 19 (IV.60).
28 Annex 7 (II.D.14).
29 Annex 23 (IV.A.69.f; IV.A.70.d).
30 Annex 7 (II.D.14).
31 Annex 28 (IV.B.b).
32 Anne Peters, Women, Quotas and Constitutions: A Comparative Study
of Affirmative Action for Women under American, German, European
Community and International Law (The Hague: Kluwer Law
International, 2000), 94.
33 Peters 267.
34 Annex 31 (IV.B.82.h).
35 Annex 34 (IV.C.89).
36 Annex 21 (IV.A.66.a).
37 Annex 20 (IV.61).
38 Annex (IV.61).
39 Annex 16 (III.43).
40 Annex 36 (IV.D.95.g).

APPENDIX SEVEN

1 “Our Equality Rights in the Charter,” [undated], Court Challenges


Program of Canada, [visited] 4 August 2002,
<http://www.ccppcj.ca/e/info.html>: 2.
2 “Our Equality Rights in the Charter,” [undated], About Court
Challenges, [visited 17 October 2004], <http://www.ccppcj.ca/e/i-
charter.html>. Law v. Canada (Minister of Employment and
Immigration) [1999] 1 S.C.R. 497 requires that claims of discrimination
be based on three broad inquiries: whether the law, program, or
activity imposes differential treatment between the claimant and
others; whether this differential treatment is based on one or more
enumerated or analogous grounds, and whether the impugned law,
program, or activity has a purpose or effect that is substantially
discriminatory.
3 Eldridge v. British Columbia (A.G.), [1997] 3 S.C.R. 624.
4 “Our Equality Rights” 2.
5 Nicholas B. Dirks, Castes of Mind: Colonialism and the Making of
Modern India (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 2001) 15.
6 Dirks 13. Indian society had long been organized into varnas, classes
or castes, based on occupation: priests (brahmins), warriors and rulers
(kshatriyas), merchants (vaishyas), and servants (shudras). These
groups had gradually been subdivided into thousands of subgroups
(jatis) based on specific occupations and other criteria. But the
vicissitudes of history – invasions, migrations, politics, religious
conversions – had allowed some mobility. Not everyone agreed,
moreover, on the place of each jati or even each varna in the hierarchy.
The brahmins have articulated one hierarchy, based on ritual purity, but
not all Hindus have accepted it. Kshatriyas have sometimes considered
political power more important, for instance, than the ritual power of
brahmins.
7 This relatively fluid situation changed under the British after 1857.
Before that date, the British had felt no need to do much in India
except engage in commerce (and take whatever political or military
steps were necessary for that purpose, mainly preventing other
European powers from capturing their trade routes). British
commercial outposts in India, eventually territories, were administered
and defended entirely by the British East India Company. After 1857,
marked by what the British called the Great Mutiny and what the
Indians called the Great Rebellion, British India came under the direct
control of Parliament in London. In other words, the British became
much more closely involved in the administration of India as a colony.
The first step was to create a centralized bureaucracy. The British
could not do so very effectively at first, because they knew very little
about Indian society and culture. To learn more, they made use of
information gathered by missionaries, anthropologists, soldiers,
magistrates, and bureaucrats. Based on this information about caste,
they created administrative categories. But because much of their
information had come from the brahmins, who were their primary
informants, the hierarchy was defined largely by them. And, not
surprisingly, they ranked themselves at the top.
8 Dirks 5–6.
9 Dirks 13.
10 The outcastes were so called because they ranked below even the
lowest castes. The same thing applied to “tribals.”
11 This idea was generally accepted by the time of independence, but
some people worried about the possible consequences. They argued
that this system would not only perpetuate but also accentuate caste
consciousness and even promote “vested interests in backwardness.”
Others argued that the system should be seen as a temporary measure.
Still others argued that neutral factors – illiteracy, lack of land, low
income, and so on – should be used instead of caste as the criteria
defining eligibility for government help (Dirks 279).
12 Some took drastic action as individuals. “On September 19, 1990, a
student from Delhi University poured kerosene over his body and set
himself on fire … in the heat of emotion, in the context of an
impassioned protest against a government decision that was seen as
taking all future prospects of respectable employment away from
young people with upper-caste backgrounds … Within the next month,
more than 159 young people also followed suit, attempting suicide by
self-immolation; 63 succeeded. Another 100 people were killed in
police firings and clashes that accompanied the widespread protest”
(Dirks 275).
13 Dirks 5–6; caste consciousness has been supported not only by
Marxists, ironically, but also by postmodernists or postcolonialists.
14 Consider the case of Sri Lanka, which has had a similar history of
affirmative action for admission to universities. According to K.M. De
Silva, executive director of the International Centre for Ethnic Studies,
in Kandy, affirmative action began as a way to bring rural students
into the university system but was “transformed in the late 1970s to a
regional quota system cutting across ethnic and religious identities.
The introduction and implementation of preferential policies in Sri
Lanka’s university system, and the impassioned resistance to
modifying them, much less to reversing them, provide an excellent
introduction to the complex nature of Sri Lanka’s ethnic conflict and
the political ramifications of rivalries between Muslims and Tamils,
divisions among Tamils, and, of course, rivalries between Sinhalese
and Tamils” (K.M. De Silva, “Affirmative Action Policies: The Sri
Lankan Expeience,” Ethnic Studies Report, 15.2 [July 1997]: 245).
“Introduced as a temporary measure, this very limited exercise in
affirmative action has survived for over 25 years now, and there is no
sign that they [sic] will be abandoned anytime soon … [T]here have
been substantial changes in the system, changes which unfortunately
strengthen the forces opposed to its abandonment or radical reform
because with every mutation, one more element is added to a complex
system of vested interests that unite to secure its survival … Here we
need to make the point that one result of this system of admissions is
that the concept of academic merit has gone by the board. In the hard
choice between quality and quantity, quality has been sacrificed to a
much greater extent than in most other university systems in the third
world” (De Sliva, 282–3).
15 “Our Equality Rights in the Charter” 2.
16 “Our Equality Rights” 4.
17 “Our Equality Rights” 5.
18 “Our Equality Rights” 5.
19 “Our Equality Rights” 4.
20 See, for example, the Employment Equity Act (S.C. 1995, C.44), which
regulates employers with 100 or more employees.
21 Grant A. Brown, “The Politics of Preference: A Catalogue of
Criticisms of Employment Equity,” unpublished manuscript, 16.
22 Following the insight of St Paul, most traditional forms of Christianity
insist in one way or another on two fundamental principles. First, that
Christ has taken on guilt for the sins of his followers. Second, that he
paid the ultimate and complete price for those sins on the cross. That
is how Christ liberates Christians from sin. In the secularized version
discussed here, however, there is one significant difference. Christ
paid the price voluntarily; he sacrificed himself. Men are not
sacrificing themselves (even though some convince themselves of
that). On the contrary, they are being sacrificed by the state.
APPENDIX EIGHT

1 Grant Brown, “The Politics of Preference: A Catalogue of Criticisms


of Employment Equity,” unpublished draught paper, 8–9.
2 “Equity,” [undated] CAUT/ACPPU, [visited] 25 October 2002,
<http://www.caut.ca/english/issues/equity/>: 1.
3 “Equity” 4.
4 “Equity” 1.
5 “Equity” 2.
6 “Equity” 4.
7 In 2004, CAUT called on government officials to amend the
Employment Equity Act. Why? In order “to ensure that the Federal
Contractors Program is capable of being enforced through the
employment equity branch of the Canadian Human Rights
Commission” (“Council Adopts Policy Statement on Federal
Contractors Program,” CAUT Bulletin (January 2004): A-8.
8 “Equity” 4.
9 “Equity” 2.
10 “Equity” 2.
11 Pay Equity Review: “Terms of Reference,” [dated] 21 January 2002,
Government of Canada, [visited] 20 October 2002,
<http://www.payequityreview.gc.ca/1200–e.html.>: 2.
12 “Introduction,” Pay Equity Review 2.
13 “Request for Proposals,” Pay Equity Review 1.

APPENDIX NINE

1 “Lobby Activities: Custody and Access,” [dated] 2002, National


Association of Women and the Law, [visited] 16 December 2002,
<http://www.nawl.ca/lob-custody.htm>: 1.
2 American Law Institute, Principles of the Law of Family Dissolution:
Analysis and Recommendations (Newark, NJ: Matthew Bender, 2002).
The Institute outlines several problems confronting anyone seeking to
balance the conflicting principles involved in custody disputes.
3 American Law Institute 2.
4 American Law Institute 2.
5 American Law Institute 3.
6 American Law Institute 3.
7 American Law Institute 3.
8 American Law Institute 5.
9 American Law Institute 7.
10 American Law Institute 7–8.
11 American Law Institute 8.
12 American Law Institute 9.
13 American Law Institute 9.
14 American Law Institute 9.
15 American Law Institute 9–10.
16 American Law Institute 10.
17 American Law Institute 13.
18 Gloria Woods, “Father’s Rights Groups: Beware Their Real Agenda,”
[undated], National NOW Times, [visited] 1 July 2002
<http://www.now.org/nnt/03–97>: 1.
19 Woods 1.
20 Woods 1.
21 Michael Jackson provoked a journalistic feeding frenzy by dangling his
son over the railing of a hotel room in Berlin. The event took less than
five seconds, and the boy was in no obvious danger of falling, but
Jackson certainly confirmed his widely held reputation for
idiosyncratic behaviour. He made things worse several months later in
an interview made for the BBC and later shown in the United States on
ABC. Jackson referred to his penchant for inviting children to stay with
him and his children at Neverland (Jill Lawless, “Sleepovers in
Neverland: Cuddling Kids ‘Sweet,’ Jackson Says,” Montreal Gazette,
5 February 2003: D-5). What provoked Gloria Allred to discuss the
possibility of launching an investigation or lawsuit to remove any
children from Jackson’s care, however, was the fact that he
encouraged children to sleep with him in his bed. He accused the
journalists, in turn, of cynicism. By “sleep,” Jackson said, he had
meant slumber, not sex. Whatever. Jackson is clearly neurotic. He
clearly does things that look shocking to most people now. Children
sleeping in the same beds as their parents would not have looked
shocking in the nineteenth century or earlier (when most children,
except those of the middle and upper classes, routinely did so even if
only because they had no beds of their own). Nor would Jackson’s
childlike sentimentality. Of interest to us here, though, is merely the
fact that Jackson reinforced perceptions of fatherhood that are now
widespread. No wonder Allred referred over and over again to the
inherent danger posed to children by an “adult male” (Gloria Allred,
interviewed on Today, NBC, WPTZ, Plattsburgh, NY, 7 February 2003).
22 Woods 2.
23 “For the Sake of the Children: Report of the Special Joint Committee
on Child Custody and Access [Summary of Recommendations],”
[dated] December 1998, Parliament of Canada, [visited] 17 July 2002,
<http://www.parl.gc.ca?
InfoComDoc/36/1/sjca/Studies/Reports/sjcarp02/10–rec-e.htm>: 3; the
committee that prepared this report was jointly chaired by Landon
Pearson and Roger Gallaway.
24 “For the Sake” 3.
25 “For the Sake” 3.
26 “For the Sake” 10.
27 “For the Sake” 44.
28 “Violence against Women Survey,” [dated] 16 July 2002, Statistics
Canada, [visited] 17 July 2002
<http://www.statcan.ca/english/sdds/3896.htm>; quoted in “For the
Sake” 71.
29 “Genetic Wallets,” [dated] 10 April 2002, Fathers Are Capable Too,
[visited] 3 July 2002, <http://fact.on.ca/news0204/np020410.htm>;
also published as an editorial in National Post, 10 April 2002: A-17.
30 Bill C-22.
31 Here is section 16(10) of Canada’s Divorce Act of 1985: “In making an
order under this section, the court shall give effect to the principle that
a child of the marriage should have as much contact with each spouse
as is consistent with the best interests of the child and, for that
purpose, shall take into consideration the willingness of the person for
whom custody is sought to facilitate such contact.” And here is the
proposed revision of 16(10) in Bill C-22: “Without limiting the
generality of subsection (7), the court may include in an order under
this section a term requiring any person with parental responsibilities
who intends to change his or her place of residence or that of the child
to notify, at least sixty days before the change or within such other
period before the change as the court may specify, any other person
with parental responsibilities of the change, the time at which the
change will be made and the new place of residence for him or her or
the child, as the case may be.” The entire section on “maximum
contact” was gutted, in short, and replaced with something about
notifying either parent about a change of residence.
32 Cristin Schmitz, “‘Mother Gets All,’ in New Divorce Act,” National
Post, 18 December 2002: A-6.
33 Virginia McRae; quoted in Schmitz A-6.
34 Anne Cools; quoted in Schmitz A-6.
35 Jay Hill; quoted in Schmitz A-6.
36 Putting Children’s Interests First: Custody, Access and Child Support
in Canada (Ottawa: Department of Justice, 2002); see also “Putting
Children’s Interests First: Custody, Access and Child Support in
Canada: Federal, Provincial, Territorial Consultation,” [dated] March
2001, Department of Justice, [visited] 12 August 2002,
<http://www.canada.justice.gc.ca/en/cons/ConsultationDocumetn.pdf>
; part of a continuing “consultation process,” this document presents
the “issues” and is accompanied by a feedback booklet with responses
from the public (Putting Children’s Interests First: Custody, Access
and Child Support in Canada, Feedback Booklet [Ottawa: Department
of Justice, 2002]).
37 Alar Soever, “The Federal Child Support Guidelines: A Breakdown of
Democratic Process and the Canadian Legal System,” [dated] 4 April
2002, Fathers Are Capable Too, [visited] 17 February 2004,
<http://www.fact.on.ca/fathome/header.htm>: 15.
38 Putting Children’s Interests 43 (the page number is 43 on the printed
text; it is 47 on the computer screen); quoted in Soever 21.
39 From a letter of 19 June 2001 by Virginia McRae at the Department of
Justice; cited in Soever 22.
40 “Divorce Act, R.S., 1985 C.3 (2nd Suppl.),” Canada: Department of
Justice, 3 July 2002, <http://laws.justice.gc,ca/en/D-3.4/text.htm/>:
section 15.2.6 b.
41 Michael Higgins, “Divorce Laws Violate Charter: Lawsuit,” National
Post, 5 December 2002: A-12.
42 Gerald Chipeur relies on section 15 of the Charter, which is about
“equal protection and equal benefit of the law without discrimination
and, in particular, without discrimination based on … sex.” (item 42,
page 13) and on section 28: “Notwithstanding anything in this Charter,
the rights and freedoms referred to in it are guaranteed equally to male
and female persons” (43, 14).
According to Chipeur, moreover, “there exists an imbalance in
child custody laws and their implementation favouring the mother
over the father in the name of the best interests of the child” (6, 3). For
evidence, he points to the fact that in Canada “a divorced mother is
nearly ten times as likely as is a divorced father to receive sole
custody of their children” (26, 8) – the mother 80.4% and father 8.6%.
Chipeur uses several other arguments.
Family law proceedings often deny “fathers and men equality and
fundamental justice” (27, 8) because of “hearsay and unsworn
evidence (collected through child psychologists and others) in custody
hearings; a lax approach to due process; and an over-reliance on
independent child assessors, who vary widely in their skills, personal
preferences, prejudices, and sensitivities” (27, 8). This state of affairs
“violates fathers’ rights, including equality, liberty and privacy rights,
freedom of association and expression, and other common law and
statutory rights. Loss of custody stigmatizes fathers as inadequate or
unfit (34, 11) and causes them severe distress – loss of custody being
analogous to the death of a child or a missing child (41, 13) And this,
in turn, constitutes “cruel and unusual punishment” according to
section 12 of the Charter.
This bias against fathers not only violates the rights of fathers, says
Chipeur, but also interferes with family relationships and improperly
deprives children of family relationships (8 and 9, 4).
The test for establishing custody or access “treats parents whose
marriage has broken down differently than parents whose marriage is
intact by establishing a different test for interference in the
relationship between the parents and children” (10, 4).
Section 16(10) of the Divorce Act says that a child “should have as
much contact with each spouse as is consistent with the best interests
of the child,” but subjective interpretations of the “best interests of the
child” are given more weight than the idea of contact (28, 9) (although
that point might now be irrelevant, given the fact that Bill C-22 no
longer refers to the importance of contact).
Family relationships are permanent and independent of marriage or
divorce. “Absent a showing of harm or likelihood of harm, the parent-
child bond must remain inviolable … Prima facie, society must trust
both parents to look out for the best interests of their child (12, 5).
Because both parents contribute in distinctive ways to parenting,
there should be a presumption of joint custody and the state should
interfere in the relationship between parent and child only “when the
physical or psychological integrity of the child will otherwise be
harmed” (23, 7) – and not without hearing from the child.
For good measure, Chipeur cites the Canadian Bill of Rights and
several sections of the Divorce Act of 1985, especially 16(10).
43 Higgins; citing the suit.
44 Higgins A-10.
45 Higgins; citing the suit.
46 “Lobby Activities,” [dated] 2002, National Association of Women and
the Law, [visited] 18 January 2004, <http://www.nawl.ca/lob-
custody.htm>:1.
47 “Seven out of ten people in Ontario say child-support payments should
be withheld from women who deny access to their children to
husbands who pay child support, according to a poll for the Globe and
Mail by the Angus Reid Group. However, Ontario residents are
divided over whether women who repeatedly deny access should face
jail sentences” (“Poll Addresses Child Access,” Globe and Mail, 25
May 1998: A-5).
48 Pamela Cross; quoted at “Below[,] Their Propaganda at It’s [sic] Best,”
[dated] 30 March 2001, Fathers Canada, [visited] 21 December 2002,
<http://www.fathers.ca/take_action_2.htm>: 6.
49 “Media Pointers,” [dated] October 2002, Ontario Women’s Network on
Child Custody and Access (OWNCCA), [visited] 19 December 2002,
<http://www.owjn.org/custody/media.htm>.
50 This organization has a steering committee that includes
representatives from seven other mainstream organizations, including
Action Ontarienne contre la violence faite aux femmes, the Disabled
Women’s Network (DAWN Ontario), Education Wife Assault, the
National Association of Women and the Law, the Northwestern
Ontario Women’s Centre, the Ontario Association of Interval and
Transition Houses, and the Ontario Women’s Justice Network.
51 “Women’s (In)equality, [undated], Ontario Women’s Network on Child
Custody and Access (OWNCCA), [visited] 12 December 2002,
<http://www.owjn.org/custody/inequal.htm>: 4.
52 “The Ontario Women’s Network on Child Custody and Access: A
Backgrounder,” [undated], Ontario Women’s Network on Child
Custody and Access (OWNCCA), [visited] 19 December 2002,
<http://www.owjn.org/custody/.htm>: 1.
53 Cross 8.
54 “Family Law Reform and the Custody of Children: A Backgrounder,
[undated], Ontario Women’s Network on Child Custody and Access
(OWNCCA), [visited] 19 December 2002,
<http://www.owjn.org/custody/law.htm>: 3.
55 The Association for Genital Integrity applied to the Court Challenges
Program. Their goal was to apply the Canadian ban on female
circumcision to include male circumcision as well. Their application
was denied. Section 268 of Canada’s Criminal Code defines
“agggravated assault.” One subsection refers specifically to female
circumcision. The Court Challenges Program rejected this attempt to
create sexual equality, citing the fact that “aggravated assault” could
include male circumcision. In that case, though, why not either include
a subsection for male circumcision or exclude the one on female
circumcision? The “program’s Equality Rights Panel disagreed with
the group’s claim of discrimination, said Melina Buckley, acting
executive director of the program. ‘They are looking at it from a legal
perspective in terms of whether or not this is a test case that is going to
advance equality for a disadvantaged group and we are not convinced
that this was the case,’ she said” (Adrian Humphreys, “Group Denied
Public Funding to Fight Circumcision: Charter Equality for Males
Sought,” National Post, 12 February 2001: A-1 and A-2). In other
words, female adults should be considered a “disadvantaged group”
but not male infants.
56 “Women’s (In)equality” 2.
57 Warren Farrell, Women Can’t Hear What Men Don’t Say: Destroying
Myths, Creating Love (New York: Tarcher, 1999).
58 “Women’s (In)equality” 2.
59 “Media Pointers” 1.
60 Cross 2 (our emphasis).
61 “Lobby Activities” 2.
62 Willick v. Willick, [1994] 3 S.C.R. 670.
63 British Columbia (Public Service Employee Relations Commission) v.
British Columbia Government and Service Employees’ Union,
(B.C.G.S.E.U.), [1999] 3 S.C.R. 3.
64 “Women’s (In)equality” 3.
65 Women’s (In)equality 3.
66 “The Best Interests of the Child,” [undated], Ontario Women’s Network
on Child Custody and Access (OWNCCA), [visited] 19 December
2002, <http://www.owjn.org/custody/child.htm>: 1.
67 “Media Pointers” 2.
68 “Best Interests” 2.
69 “Best Interests” 2.
70 “Best Interests” 2.
71 “Best Interests” 3.
72 “Parenting after Separation,” [undated], Ontario Network on Child
Custody and Access (OWNCCA), [visited] 19 December 2002,
<http://www.owjn.org/custody/parent.htm>: 1.
73 “Parenting” 1.
74 In one documentary, viewers watch a male western-lowland gorilla
tenderly holds his infant Congo. The mother tries to take it away from
him, but he persists (Jean-Yves Collet, The Strange Adventure of
Mabeke the Gorilla [2001], Discovery, 21 January 2003). See also
“Headlines and Highlights,” [dated] 14 May 2002, African Wildlife
Foundation, [visited] 22 December 2002,
<http://www.awf.org/news/7377>:2; John Allman and others, “Parent
That Takes Care of Offspring Tends to Outlive the Other Parent, Study
Shows,” [dated] 9 June 1998, Caltech Press Releases, [visited] 22
December 2002, <http://pr.caltech.edu/media/lead/060898ja.html>: 2;
and David Geary and Mark Flinn’s study of the evolution of human
parenting behaviour: “Evolution of Human Parental Behavior and the
Human Family,” Parenting: Science and Practice, 1.1–2 (2001): 5–61.
In some primate species, females remain with other members of
their own birth groups; males do not. Among chimps, bonobos,
gorillas, and humans, however, males do; females do not. Geary and
Flinn argue, therefore, that we have inherited an inclination toward
patrilocality (and patrilineality) from closely related primates.
Consider the gorillas. Males have harems and enduring relationships
with females. Moreover, they are involved in parenting. Why?
Because, say Geary and Flinn, they know their own offspring. This
makes them willing to make heavy investments in parenting. Our
Australopithecine ancestors, four million years ago, had the same
strategy. Gradually, male dominance gave way to pair bonding,
though, due to changes – some of which had already occurred in
primates – such as the following: the similar size of males and
females; the long developmental period necessary for off-spring
(which made protection and provision more important); concealed
ovulation (which reduced mating competition between males); and
nonreproductive sexuality (which kept males sexually interested and
involved). Females gained from these developments, at least to the
extent of recognizing that their offspring needed the involvement of
fathers. With females remaining loyal to one male and thus making it
clear that their offspring belonged to that one male, the latter no longer
needed to supervise his harem so strictly. Geary and Flinn add that
primates have found it necessary to prevent, or at least discourage,
infanticide. “When infanticide risk is high, females copulate with
males who are likely to displace the dominant male and thus confuse
paternity. Males generally do not attempt to kill the infants of females
with whom they have copulated. Although infanticide might have
accompanied hominid evolution, that does not explain concealed
ovulation among humans” (Geary and Flinn 23). Why not? Because
“an evolved female strategy that confused paternity would be
associated with little or no male parenting, which is inconsistent with
the finding of male parenting in every human culture that has been
studied … and with the possibility that Australopithecine males
parented” (Geary and Flinn 24).
75 “Parenting” 1.
76 “Parenting” 1.
77 “Parenting” 2.
78 “Parenting” 2.
79 “Parenting” 2.
80 “Parenting” 2.
81 “Parenting” 2.
82 “Parenting” 3.
83 “Parenting” 3.
84 “Parenting” 3.
85 “Parenting” 3.
86 “Women’s Access to Justice,” [undated], Ontario Women’s Network on
Child Custody and Access (OWNCCA), [visited] 19 December 2002,
<http://www.owjn/custody/justice.htm>: 1.
87 “Parenting” 2.
88 “Family Law Reform” 2.
89 “Parenting” 3.
90 “Parenting” 3.
91 “Sample Letter to the Minister of Justice,” [dated] 2002, Ontario
Women’s Justice Network, [visited] 19 December 2002,
<http://www.owjn.org/custody/lob-let.htm>: 1.
92 “Lobby Activities” 2.
93 “Sample Letter” 1.
94 “Family Law Reform” 2.
95 “Parenting” 3.
96 “Parenting 3.
97 We refer to the media mavens and talk-show gurus for whom self-
realization, or “empowerment,” long ago replaced self-sacrifice as an
ideal worth at least acknowledging. Several factors explain that shift.
By the 1980s one result of a lengthy peace and a burgeoning economy,
for instance, was rampant hedonism. But another factor was the rise of
feminism. Some schools of feminism – the one popularized by
Marilyn French in the early 1990s is a good example – have
encouraged hedonism as a supposedly female and superior alternative
to male asceticism. Underlying that strategy is the belief that women
have been taught traditionally to “give” (submit) and men to “take”
(dominate). This teaching put women at a severe disadvantage to the
extent that this ideal was actualized in everyday life by both women
and men – that is, by genuinely submissive wives and genuinely
domineering husbands. Feminists are surely correct in arguing against
self-sacrifice as an ideal only for women. History reveals, however,
that self-sacrifice was an ideal for men, too, although it was not
supposed to be expressed in the same way. For one thing, men were
usually expected to sacrifice their lives for family and society in
hunting or in warfare. And this was not merely an abstract ideal.
Eventually, it was enforced by the state. Eventually, men were
expected to sacrifice much of their time at jobs outside the home that
were for most men every bit as boring or degrading as anything
women did inside the home. Men neither were, nor are, thrilled at the
prospect of spending their lives at jobs that make other people rich;
they accept it as a duty they owe to their families – if they can get
jobs.

APPENDIX TEN

1 James Gurney, Dinotopia: A Land Apart from Time (Atlanta: Turner,


1992).
2 See below. Those topics are almost always closely associated with
feminism. All are based on precisely the same assumptions about
“engaged scholarship,” “hegemonic discourses,” “subaltern
traditions,” “sites of resistance,” “transgression,” “alterity,”
“domination,” “oppression,” and so on. Each differs from the others
only in terms of its particular focus. And even the focus is usually
understood as one among several closely related ones.
3 Publications of the Modern Language Association of America 105.6
(1990): 1353– 1366. The conference took place in Chicago, 27–30
December 1990; 1,892 papers were presented.
4 Publications of the Modern Language Association of America, 115.6
(2000): 1413– 1532. The conference took place in Washington, dc, 27–
30 December 2000; 2,195 papers were presented.

APPENDIX ELEVEN

1 William Shakespeare, Romeo and Juliet, act 2, scene 2, lines 45–6.


2 Paul Nathanson and Katherine K. Young, Spreading Misandry: The
Teaching of Contempt for Men in Popular Culture (Montreal: McGill-
Queen’s University Press, 2001) 227.
3 “Mission Statement,” [dated] 2002–2003, University of Chicago,
Center for Gender Studies, [visited] 11 March 2003,
<http://humanities.uchicago.edu/org/cgs/mission.html>: 1.
4 “General Course Descriptions,” [dated] 26 November 2002, Gender
Studies [at] Indiana University [in] Bloomington, [visited] 11 March
2003, <http://www.indiana.edu/~gender/textonlyallabout.html>: 1.
5 “Courses,” [dated] 2002–2003, University of Southern California,
Gender Studies, [visited] 11 March 2003,
<http://www.usc.edu/dept/LAS/gsp/htm/courses.htm>: 2.
6 “Courses” 2.
7 “Courses” 7–8.
8 “Gender Studies at Northwestern,” [dated] 2002–2003, Northwestern
Gender Studies, [visited] 11 March 2003,
<http://www.genderstudies.northwestern.edu/aboutthe
program/index.htm>: 1.
9 “Gender Studies at Northwestern” 1.
10 “Gender Studies at Northwestern” 4.
11 “Courses,” [dated] 2002–2003, Northwestern Gender Studies, [visited]
11 March 2003,
<http://www.genderstudies.northwestern.edu/abouttheprogram/index.h
tm>: 1.
12 “Courses” 2.
13 Edith Zorychta, “The World of Women’s Studies,” CAUT Bulletin:
Status of Women Supplement, 48.8 (October 2001): 1.
14 Zorychta 1.
15 Zorychta 1.
16 Laura Mulvey, “Visual Pleasure and Narrative Cinema,” in Feminism
and Film Theory, ed. C. Penley (New York: Routledge, 1988). In this
famous essay, first published in 1975, Mulvey uses psychoanalysis to
discuss the “male gaze” of filmmakers.

APPENDIX TWELVE

1 “Funding,” [dated] 8 June 2003, Status of Women Canada, [visited] 6


January 2004, <http:www.swc-cfc.gc.ca/funding/prfcfp-
990902_e.html>.
2 Pierrette Bouchard, Isabelle Boily, and Marie-Claude Proulx, “School
Success by Gender: A Catalyst for the Masculinist Discourse,”
[updated] 15 April 2003, Status of Women Canada, [visited] 8 June
2003,
<http://www.swccfc.gc.ca/pubs/0662882857/200303_0662882857_1_
e.html> 17.
3 Institutions – government agencies, universities, and so on – routinely
insist on disclaimers. They do so not only to protect themselves but
also to assure authors that their academic freedom will be respected,
which would be impossible if authors were required to represent any
institutional point of view. These institutions routinely commission
reports, moreover, and pay for them. In the case of government
agencies, they do so in connection with establishing policies, because
they can evaluate the potential benefits and risks only on the basis of
reliable information and analysis of it. In this case, however, the
government agency is not politically neutral – that is, it is not engaged
only in gathering and analyzing information on an academic basis. The
official mandate of Status of Women Canada is to promote and fund
only research that will benefit women. It attracts only those authors,
therefore, who are willing – on political grounds – to fulfill that
mandate. It is a lamentable but observable fact that authors in this
situation tend, whether intentionally or not, to skew either the design
of their projects (asking some questions, say, but not others) or their
interpretations (or both). This has often been true of some male
scholars, as feminists like to point out, and it is just as true of some
female scholars – especially those who identify themselves with
feminism as a political movement. They justify this as “engaged
scholarship,” which we discuss in chapter 10. It is for this reason –
because the merits of arguments on the other side are not discussed or
even acknowledged – that we cast doubt on the academic credibility of
the report and draw attention to the outrage of paying for it out of tax
dollars – including those of male citizens and female citizens who
disagree with doctrines of ideological feminism.
4 Michael Higgins, “Men’s Groups Promoting Hatred, Federal Report
Says,” National Post, 30 May 2003: A-6, A-16.
5 See, for example, the following passage: “These [men’s] groups are
largely composed of white, heterosexual, middle-class men who have
not been successful in coping with the challenge to masculinity posed
by feminism” (Bouchard, Boily, and Proulx 66; referring to B. Lingard
and P. Douglas, Men Engaging Feminisms: Pro-feminism, Backlashes
and Schooling [Philadelphia: Open Univesity Press, 1999]).
6 Jon C. Bradley, “Why Boys Drop Out,” Montreal Gazette, 3
November 2004: A-27.
7 Bouchard, Boily, and Proulx 3.
8 Bouchard, Boily, and Proulx 3.
9 Bouchard, Boily, and Proulx 7.
10 Bouchard, Boily, and Proulx 26, 36.
11 Bouchard, Boily, and Proulx 37.
12 Bouchard, Boily, and Proulx 66.
13 Bouchard, Boily, and Proulx 29.
14 We are not referring here to the study of particular goddesses (such as
the Hindu Kali or Durga and the Buddhist Kuan Yin) in traditional
societies. We are referring to both academic and public interest in “the
Goddess” as a way of legitimating ideological feminism in modern
Western societies. Much has been written about “the Goddess” in the
secular fields of history, archaeology, and religious studies. Among the
most influential books have been Gerda Lerner’s The Creation of
Patriarchy (New York: Oxford University Press, 1986) and Marija
Gimbutas’s Civilization of the Goddess (San Francisco:
HarperSanFrancisco, 1991). Both authors tried to show that all of
history since the Neolithic period can be understood as a titanic
conspiracy of men against women (although neither author claimed
that every man consciously participates in this conspiracy). Lerner is a
historian, her specialty being women’s history. Gimbutas was an
archeologist. Her specific contribution was to argue that very ancient
Europeans worshipped a “Great Goddess.” For thousands of years,
apparently, they enjoyed equality and peace in what amounted to a
paradise under the aegis of this female deity; only when men rebelled
(for some reason that she never explained) under the aegis of a male
deity did paradise end and the present state of inequality and war –
that is, patriarchy – begin. Anyone even vaguely familiar with the
biblical story of Adam and Eve (or, to be more precise, post-biblical
interpretations of it) can see that this is a feminist revision of what
Christians call the “Fall of Man.” In this version, of course, Original
Sin – the ultimate source of evil – is blamed on men instead of
women.
This proposition, not exactly easy to prove, has become the
historical (and ideological) framework that underlies some forms of
feminism at both the academic and popular levels. In Changing of the
Gods: Feminism and the End of Traditional Religions (Boston:
Beacon Press, 1979), for instance, Naomi Goldenberg says much the
same thing but from the perspective of pop psychology. So does Mary
Daly from that of “thealogy,” the feminist version of theology. Several
“documentaries,” moreover, have brought this message to the masses.
Beyond the Veil, for instance, was produced by Canada’s National
Film Board (more specifically by its explicitly feminist Studio d) and
thus financed by taxpayers. It presents contemporary Irish nuns as
latter day (albeit subconscious) followers of the “old religion,” the
good Goddess religion that was destroyed violently by St Patrick’s
evil religion and repressed ever since by a sinister church. Goddess
revivalism is not a fringe movement either within the university or
beyond it. And we do not refer merely to the growing popularity of
Wicca, supposedly a survival of (benign) witchcraft. We refer also to
the Sophia movement that has taken off (not without resistance) in the
Presbyterian and some other mainstream churches, the Holy Spirit
being identified with “Sophia” (wisdom) and thus as a female form of
God to be recovered after two thousand years of repression.
15 Marija Gimbutas, The Language of the Goddess (New York: Harper
and Row, 1989); Gerda Lerner, The Creation of Patriarchy (New
York: Oxford University Press, 1986); The Goddess Remembered,
directed by Donna Read, script by D.C. Blade, Donna Read, Gloria
Demers, 16 mm, 54 min. (Montreal: National Film Board of Canada:
Studio d, 1989); Behind the Veil: Nuns, directed by Margaret Westcott,
script and narration by Gloria Demers, 16 mm., 130 min. (Montreal:
National Film Board of Canada, 1984); and The Burning Times,
directed by Donna Read, script by Erna Buffie, 16 mm., 58 min.
(Montreal: National Film Board of Canada, Studio d, 1993).
16 Bouchard, Boily, and Proulx 33.
17 Bouchard, Boily, and Proulx 41.
18 Frederick Mathews, The Invisible Boy: Revisioning the Victimization of
Male Children and Teens (Ottawa: Minister of Public Works and
Government Services Canada; Health Canada [catalogue no. h72–
21/143–1996e] 1996), 11.
19 Bouchard, Boily, and Proulx 44.
20 Bouchard, Boily, and Proulx 59.
21 Bouchard, Boily, and Proulx 67.
22 Bouchard, Boily, and Proulx 69, 71.
23 Bouchard, Boily, and Proulx 74, 75.
24 Bouchard, Boily, and Proulx 82, 93.
25 Bouchard, Boily, and Proulx 93.
26 Bouchard, Boily, and Proulx 93.

APPENDIX THIRTEEN

1 Peter Neidig, “Women’s Shelters, Men’s Collectives, and Other Issues


in the Field of Spouse Abuse,” Victimology 9.3–4 (1984): 464–76.
2 Neidig began his article by pointing out two basic approaches, the
ideological and the empirical, in the study of domestic violence. Some
feminists, he wrote, presented case studies and analyzed them from an
ideological perspective. As examples, he cited Lenore Walker’s The
Battered Woman (New York: Harper and Row, 1979) and Del Martin’s
Battered Wives (New York: Pocket Books, 1976). In addition, Russell
Dobash and Rebecca Dobash (Violence Against Wives [New York:
Free Press, 1979]) represented “a variation of the pure sociological
approach in which any pretence of scientific neutrality is abandoned
for a stance of vigorous advocacy” (Neidig 464). Other researchers, he
noted, had emerged from clinically oriented social work. All tended to
identify characteristics of the victims, offer descriptions of the
victimizers, and recommend new institutional policies or legal
reforms. The essays in Patterns in Family Violence, edited by Margaret
Elbow (New York: Family Service Associates, 1972), exemplified this
approach. Still others had written sociological or epidemiological
analyses of spousal abuse. This empirical approach had been adopted
by Murray Straus, Richard Gelles, and Suzanne Steinmetz (Behind
Closed Doors: Violence in the American Family [New York:
Anchor/Doubleday 1981]). They and their students were using a
national survey to identify every conceivable variable that might
correlate with domestic violence.
3 Neidig 465.
4 Neidig 465.
5 Neidig 465–6.
6 Neidig 466.
7 Perry London, The Modes and Morals of Psychotherapy (New York:
Holt, 1964).
8 Neidig 466. It is at least conceivable, however, that this could be a
case of “both-and” rather than “either-or.” If the recent increase in
women’s power provokes frustration and even violence on the part of
some men, for example, it would hardly be surprising if these men
directed their anger and frustration at powerless wives. In short, people
generally attack only those who are not in a position to fight back and
refrain from attacking those who could retaliate physically or
otherwise.
9 Neidig 466.
10 Neidig 466–7.
11 Neidig 467.
12 D. Adams and I. Penn, “Getting Rid of the Excuses Men Use for
Abusing Women,” Practice Digest 4.1 (1981): 5–8.
13 Z. Mettger, “Help for Men Who Batter: Overview of Issues and
Programs,” Response 5 (1982): 1–23. Although Neidig did not
comment on this argument, it is worth noting Mettger’s assumption
that women can understand men better than men can understand
themselves. Women have wisely rejected this approach when applied
in reverse.
14 E. Hilberman, “Overview: The Wife-Beater’s Wife Reconsidered,”
American Journal of Psychiatry 137.11 (1980): 1336–7.
15 Neidig 469, 470.
16 Neidig 469, 470.
17 Neidig 470–1.
18 Andrew McCormack, Men Helping Men Stop Woman Abuse (Boston:
Emerge, 1979).
19 Neidig 474.
20 Neidig 472.
21 Neidig 472–3.
22 Neidig 467.
23 Neidig 467.
24 Ellen Pence, “Response to Peter Neidig’s Article: ‘Women’s Shelters,
Men’s Collectives and Other Issues in the Field of Spouse Abuse,”
Victimology 9.3–4 (1984): 479–80.
25 Jeffrey L. Edleson, “Violence is the Issue: A Critique of Neidig’s
Assumptions,” Victimology 9.3–4 (1984): 483–9.
26 Edleson 483, 484.
27 Emerge began in 1977 as the first program in the United States devoted
specifically to the goal of “challenging men to take responsibility for
stopping male violence.” Here is the mission statement on its website:
“Emerge believes that battering is a learned behavior, not a sickness.
Violence against women is a social problem requiring change at the
individual, cultural, and institutional levels. Counseling and education
for abusive men is one aspect of this change. We support grassroots,
institutional, and cultural efforts to stop battery, rape, child abuse, and
other degrading treatment of women and children and to build a non-
sexist society.” See “Emerge: Counseling and Education to Stop
Domestic Violence,” [dated] 1999, Emerge, [visited] 19 September
2002 <http://www.emergedv.com/>.
28 Edleson 486.
29 Neidig 464.
30 Pence 477.
31 Neidig 464.
32 Pence 478.
33 Pence 478.
34 Suzanne K. Steinmetz, “The Battered Husband Syndrome,”
Victimology 2.3–4 (1978): 499–509; Patricia Pearson, “Women
Behaving Badly,” Saturday Night, September 1997: 92–100; Pearson
used that article as the basis for When She Was Bad: Violent Women
and the Myth of Innocence (New York: Viking-Penguin, 1997).
35 Pence 469.
36 Pence 478.
37 Edleson 485.
38 Pence 479.
39 See Neil Boyd, The Beast Within: Why Men Are Violent (Vancouver:
Grey-stone Books, 2000). For alcohol: 22, 126, 145, 155–60, 178–9;
180–1; for drugs: 22, 155, 157, 160–1, 179–81.
40 Neidig 472.
41 Edleson 486, 487.
42 Neidig 473.
43 Edleson 486.
44 Edleson 484.
45 This was Lorena Bobbitt’s defense, although some feminists
disapproved. If she could use it, why not men?
46 “Jean Harris,” 20/20, ABC, WVNY-TV, Burlington,VT, 5 March 1993.
47 Barbara Walters, 20/20.
48 Pence 481–2.
49 Pence 481.
50 Neidig 474.
51 Edleson 488.
52 Pearson, “Women Behaving Badly” 96.
Index
Because this book is entirely about the legal regimes that govern men in
two countries, the list of entries under the corresponding words – men, law,
Canada, and United States – would have been extremely long and therefore
unhelpful. We have used these words in sub-headings, however, or in
parentheses after the names of government agencies, legislation, and so on.
On the other hand, even though this book is also entirely about misandry
and ideological feminism – and especially about the close relation between
them – the terms denoting these ideas are still unusual enough to merit
indexing. Readers should bear in mind, however, that both are often implied
even when not actually indexed.
For the sake of brevity, we have used “ideological” instead of the more
cumbersome “ideological feminist” (although most of the references would
apply to any ideology).
Sometimes this index refers to specific words that appear in the text. At
other times, though, it refers instead to general ideas found there. Examples
of double standards might appear in the text but not accompanied by the
words “double standards,” for instance; we have indexed them,
nevertheless, under that heading.
abortion, 154, 341
Abraham, Carolyn, 534n94
Abramson, Jill, 42
abuse. See child abuse, domestic violence
Action Plan of the Department of Justice on Gender Equality (Canada), 93
Adams, Damon, 140, 480
Adler, Jerry, 236, 350
adolescents, 344–5
Advisory Committee on Evidence Rules (United States), 226
affirmative action: and academic achievement, 99–100;
in American law, 86–9, 509n26;
in Canadian law, 93, 117, 409, 410–12;
and career trajectories, 108–9;
case study of, 410–12;
and caste, 313, 403–9;
and collectivism, 104;
and consequentialism, 100, 102, 313;
and democracy, 104, 409;
as discrimination, 101, 102–5, 110, 313;
and “diversity,” 100;
and divorced fathers, 109;
and double standards, 99, 105, 108, 109, 111, 475–6;
and dualism, 104;
in education, 88;
efficiency of, 110;
and equality of result, 110–11;
and euphemisms, 103;
and historical analogies, 102, 105;
and ideological feminism, 103–4, 313;
and ideological-feminist epistemology, 98, 107–8;
in India and Sri Lanka, 404–9, 603n14;
and the individual, 104, 111, 519n99;
and intellectual diversity, 100;
and intimidation, 410–12;
justifications proposed for, 98–110, 313;
as lesser of two evils, 103, 105;
and “level playing field,” 313;
at McGill University, 517n82;
and mentors, 107;
and misandry, 311;
motivation for, 103;
and political priority, 106;
and postmodernism, 98–9;
and quasi-religiosity, 408;
and quotas, 87–8, 93, 101–2, 116, 410–12, 517n85;
and race, 86–7, 88, 100;
and research grants, 101;
and resentment, 109;
and scapegoats, 104;
and statistics abuse, 99–100;
statistics on, 88, 99–100, 517n82;
as a temporary solution, 105;
and the university, 90, 92, 106, 517n82;
and the World Conference on Women (Beijing), 400
Aiken, Jane, 261
Alexander v. Yale, 195
alien abductions, 6, 8–10, 494n13, 495n26
alimony. See divorce Allen, Douglas, 132
Alliance for Non-Custodial Parents Rights, 536n122
Allred, Gloria, 605n21
Ambedkar, B.R., 405
American Association of University Women, 289
American College Health Association, 201
American Federation of Labor–Congress of Industrial Organizations
(AFLCIO), 112
American Law Institute, 415, 605n2
American Medical Association, 7, 236, 564n72
American Psychiatric Association, 6
American Psychological Association, 241
American Sociological Association, 352
androcentrism: and “bourgeoisie,” xii;
and double standards, ix, 400–1;
in egalitarian feminism, 318;
historical background of, 81–2;
and humanity as Man, 123;
and misogyny, x;
as “phallocentrism,” 116, 182, 217, 274, 303, 380, 397;
and postmodernism, 271. See also gynocentrism, misogyny
anorexia, 360–1
Anti-Klan Network, 227
Antioch College, 204–5
Anti-Pornography Civil Rights Ordinance (United States), 174
anxiety. See collective anxiety
Applebaum, Anne, 194
Archie, Vivian, 568n122
artificial insemination. See reproductive technologies
asexual reproduction. See reproductive technologies
Ashcroft, John, 289
Ashcroft, Attorney General, et al. v. Free Speech Coalition et al., 162
Association for Genital Integrity, 609n55
Atcheson, Beth, 306
Atkinson, Ti-Grace, 212
autonomy. See ideological separatism
B.C. Government and Service Employees’ Unionv. B.C. Public Service
Employees’ Relations Commission, 428–9
Backward Classes Commission, 406
Bagnall, Janet, 151
Baier, Annette, 98
Baker v. Francis. See Francis v. Baker
Bandura, Albert, 481–2
Bankier, Jennifer, 60–1
Baskerville, Stephen, 128–9, 139, 141, 143, 145
Bass, Ellen, 11
battered men, 233–48, 354–8;
allegedly masochistic, 242–3;
and child custody, 243;
evidence suppressed of, 239;
ignored by ideological feminists, 354;
and statistics abuse, 208–9, 233–9, 354–64;
and stoicism, 240–1;
underestimation of injuries, 235;
and untrained journalists, 239;
and untrained physicians, 235–6;
and untrained police, 239;
untrained public, 230, 593n30;
untrained to answer specific questions, 234–5;
untrained to seek help, 235, 239;
unwilling to leave children, 243–5;
unwilling to risk public humiliation, 239–40, 593n30;
by women, 233–48, 354–64, 563n54, 565nn77, 81, 567n121, 593n30
battered women, 223–66, 354–64;
and the Bobbitt Affair, 21–9;
in ideological feminism, 478–92;
“learned helplessness” of, 245;
and power, 617n8;
predictions of violence, 244;
and self-defense defense, 49n14;
and statistics abuse, 234–9, 354–64, 564nn71, 72;
unwilling to leave, 244;
and vigilantism, 244–5
Bayh, Evan, 128
Beblow v. Peter. See Peter v. Beblow
Behavioral Science Associates, 478
Beijing. See World Conference on Women
Bélanger, Jean, 55, 56, 57
Believe the Children, 12
Bentham, Jeremy, 347
Bernardo. See R. v. Bernardo
Bieniewicz, Donald J., 149, 525n15, 529n61, 531n67, 537n128
Bill C-20 (Canada), 163
Bill C-22 (Canada), 606n31
Bill C-41 (Canada), 230
Bill C-42 (Canada), 231
Bill C-46 (Canada), 230
Bill C-72 (Canada), 230
Bill of Rights (Canada). See Canadian Bill of Rights
Bill of Rights (United States), 82
Bird, Sarah, 374
birth registration. See fathers
black men, 119–21
black power, 320
Blaine, Diana, 284
Blanchard, E.G., 482
Blankenhorn, David, 135, 530n65
Bliss v. Canada, 90, 92
Bly, Robert, 476
Blyth, Myrna, 586n7
B’nai Brith Anti-Defamation League, 227
Bobbitt, John Wayne, 21, 25, 26, 499n14
Bobbitt, Lorena, 21;
and ideological strategies, 315;
in or out of control, 23, 25–6;
as a prototype, 499n14;
and self-defense, 23;
and temporary-insanity defense, 21, 23
Bock, Jane, 153
Boily, Isabelle, 293–9, 471–7, 581nn93, 95, 96, 582nn97, 99, 104, 105
Boo, Katherine, 119–21
Borovoy, Alan, 181
Bouchard, Pierrette, 293–9, 471–7, 581nn93, 95, 96, 582nn97, 99, 104,
105
Bowen, Lauren, 510n30
boys, 48–9, 63, 293–9, 331, 571n153
Bradley, Jon, 472
Bradley Amendment. See Social Security Act (United States)
Braver, Sanford, 131–6, 522n5, 526n32
Brentwood Academy v. Tennessee Secondary School Athletic Association,
305
Bricmont, Jean, 575n9
Brinig, Margaret, 132
Brodsky, Gwen, 306
Brooks v. Canada Safeway, 92
Brown, Grant: on affirmative action, 519n99;
on “compensatory justice,” 101;
on court bias against men, 245–7;
on identity politics, 407–8;
on police bias, 498n13;
on separation, 527n40;
on statistics abuse, 363
Brown, Helen Gurley, 50, 161
Brownmiller, Susan, 32, 248
Brzonkala, Christy, 558n21
Buckley, Melina, 609n55
Bucky, Raymond, 4, 13
Bureau of Justice Statistics (United States), 251
Butler. See R. v. Butler Butler, Paul, 301
CAUT Bulletin, 469–70
California Women’s Law Center, 358
Campbell, Kim, 97
Campus Sexual Assault Victims’ Bill of Rights, 196
Canada Labour Code, 196
Canada Safeway. See Brooks v. Canada Safeway
Canadian Advisory Council on the Status of Women, 305
Canadian Association of University Teachers (CAUT), 410–12, 604n7. See
also CAUT Bulletin
Canadian Bar Association, 93, 97, 303
Canadian Bill of Rights, 607n42
Canadian Broadcasting Corporation, 580n83
Canadian Civil Liberties Association, 181, 307
Canadian Federation of University Women, 289
Canadian Human Rights Act, 196
Canadian Human Rights Commission, 604n7
Canadian Journal of
Women and the Law, 306
Canadian Judicial Council. See National Judicial Institute
Canadian Labour Congress, 117
Canadian Medical Association, 7
Canadian Mental Health Association, 73
Canadian Newspapers Co.v. Canada, 230, 561n42, 568n122
Canadian Panel on Violence against Women, 362–3
Canadian Psychiatric Association, 7
Canadian reports: For the Sake of the Children, 150, 415, 421–3;
Principles of the Law of Family Dissolution, 415–20;
Putting Children’s Interests First, 415, 423–4, 607n36;
School Success by Gender, 293–9, 471–7;
Setting the Stage for the Next Century, 94;
War against Women, 71–8
castration, 25
Cauchon, Martin, 422, 437
censorship: and children, 345–6;
and ideological feminism, 281, 297, 473;
and political correctness, 207, 365, 368;
and political dissent, 381;
of pornography, 176, 180–1;
and statistics abuse, 355;
in the university, 100
Center for Gender Studies, 466
Center for Individual Rights, 558n21
Chambers, David, 526n32
chaos theory. See science
Charter of Rights and Freedoms(Canada): and affirmative action, 409;
and child custody, 435, 607n42;
and child support, 424;
and “distinct and insular” minorities, 92, 173;
and “enumerated grounds” of discrimination, 515n66, 602n2;
and equality of result, 90, 95, 123, 174, 428;
and freedom of expression, 230;
and hate laws, 171–2;
historical background of, 90–1, 95–6;
and “historically disadvantaged groups, 175, 514n58;
and ideological feminism, 304, 317;
and ideological indoctrination, 116;
and ideological strategies, 317;
and infringements, 512n38;
and judicial activism, 304–5, 307–8;
and law schools, 304;
and Legal Education and Action Fund, 510n30;
on men, 118, 148;
and Oakes test, 91;
politicized interpretations of, 181;
and prostitution, 163;
and rape, 228–30, 561n42;
section 15 of, 90, 92, 93, 94, 95, 148, 150, 428, 435, 515n66, 607n42;
section 28 of, 91, 94
Cheriton, Glenn, 522n5
child abuse, 11, 209;
in American law, 226, 228, 558n17;
in common law, 533n84;
and divorce, 437–8;
and divorced fathers, 144, 146;
and domestic violence, 420, 481;
by fathers, 566n97;
as father absence, 530n65;
and the McMartin witch hunt, 11, 15, 315;
by mothers, 566n97;
and pornography, 162, 170, 341;
and psychoanalysis, 495n26;
and sexual predators, 497n39;
and shared parenting, 433;
by single mothers, 144;
statistics on, 566n97;
and violence against women, 618n27. See also molestation
Child Abuse Prevention and Treatment Act (United States), 558n17
child custody: in American law, 416–21;
in Canadian law, 435, 606n31, 607n42;
and domestic violence, 424–38;
and fathers, 134, 313, 415–38, 606n31, 607n42;
and feminism, 415;
historical background of, 126;
in ideological feminism, 424–38;
loss of, 134;
and mothers, 126, 415–38;
and political correctness, 417;
rhetoric on, 523n6;
shared, 126, 148, 150, 416–17, 420–38;
sole, 129, 420–38;
and statistics abuse, 137–8;
statistics on, 433, 522n5, 524nn13, 14, 530n62, 531n66, 532n68,
607n42;
and violence against women, 424–38;
and witch hunts, 16–17, 18, 19. See also child support
child pornography. See pornography
Child Pornography Prevention Act (United States), 162
child support, 126–7, 415–38;
and age of children, 538n131;
in American law, 127–31, 147–8, 416–21;
amounts paid in, 534n103;
and bureaucratic nightmares, 138–9;
calculation of, 137, 148–50, 424, 529n61, 530n63, 531n67, 532n68,
537n128, 538n134;
in Canadian law, 131, 139–40, 144, 149, 424;
and children’s rights, 424;
cost of, 530n64, 531n66;
and “deadbeat dads,” 120, 128–9, 133, 135–6;
and due process, 533n77;
in feminism, 415;
in ideological feminism, 127, 424–38;
models of, 529n61, 537n124;
and paternity fraud, 140–2;
and paternity tests, 129, 140–2;
rates of compliance with, 136;
and scams, 139–43, 531n66;
and single mothers, 129;
and statistics abuse, 120, 128–9, 133, 136, 144;
statistics on, 139;
and suicide, 135, 138, 533n71;
and systemic bias, 137–8;
versus wife support, 127, 149–50, 424, 530n63;
and variables, 592n12;
and welfare fathers, 128, 545n103;
and working fathers, 129. See also child custody
child-support industry. See ideological industries
Child Support Recovery Act (United States), 129–30, 147
Child Support Team, 140
childbirth. See mothers
children. See child abuse, child custody, child support, children’s rights,
molestation, pedophilia
Children’s Institute International, 345
children’s rights. See rights
China, 549n105
Chipeur, Gerald, 424, 607n42
Chodorow, Nancy, 155, 384, 387, 599n40
Christianity: and civil religion, 505n37;
and communion, 164;
on eschatology, 172;
and evangelicalism, 587n11;
and ethics, 73;
on Fall of Man, 615n14;
and feminism, 369;
and fundamentalism, 550n112, 574n6;
and gnostic dualism, 176, 548n86;
and human rights, 122;
and ideological feminism, 319, 369, 550n112, 615n14;
on Jews, 104, 310, 369, 586nn3, 6, 596n9;
on masturbation, 550n111;
and modernity, 395;
in the public square, 370, 589n1;
on reason, 588n4;
on sacred time in, 588n3;
and secular religions, 401;
on self-sacrifice, 604n22;
on sex, 19, 183;
and “social power,” 381;
on vicarious guilt, 408;
on witches, 295;
on women, 181
Chronicle of Higher Education, 282–6, 576n37
Cimini, Mark, 319
civil religion, 505n37
civil rights. See ordinances, pornography
Civil Rights Act (United States), 88, 195–6, 558n21
Cladis, Mark, 369–70
Clayton, Susan, 98–100
Clinton, Bill, 289, 524n13
Cloud, John, 42
coercion. See rape, sexual harassment
Cohn, D’Vera, 524n13
collective anxiety, 3, 11, 17, 176–7, 344–5, 497n39
collective guilt, xi, 65, 104
collective punishment, xi collective stress, 16, 497n39
collectivism, xii, 104, 120–1, 278, 313
Colman, Gene, 146
Commerce Clause (United States): on child support, 127, 147, 148;
and ideological strategies, 317;
and noncommercial affairs, 536n123;
on pornography, 163;
on rape, 248, 558n21
Commission de l’équité solariale du Quebec. See Quebec Pay Equity
Commission
Commission on Human Rights. See United Nations
Commission on the Status of Women. See United Nations
Communicating Law (Canada), 163–4
communism, 28, 184, 549n105. See also McCarthy witch hunt
comparative suffering, 29, 36–7, 297–9, 373–90, 612n97. See also female
victims, male victims
Congressional Research Service, 86
conscription, 400, 408, 612n97
consequentialism: and affirmative action, 100, 102, 313;
and the Bobbitt Affair, 28;
in ideological feminism, xii, 19, 27–8, 313, 518n86;
and pay equity, 118;
and pornography, 178–9, 548n92;
and prostitution, 548n92;
and sexual harassment, 209;
and social problems, 590n5
conspiracies: in ideological feminism, 71, 167, 172, 198;
of liberals, 172;
of pornographers, 172;
and pornography, 167;
and sexual harassment, 198;
and theory of history, 19, 62–3, 71, 74, 82, 295, 298, 475, 615n14
Contino, Joseph, 148
Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination against
Women. See United Nations
Convention on the Rights of the Child. See United Nations
Cook, Philip, 236–8, 243–4
Cools, Anne, 423
Copps, Sheila, 70
Corea, Gena, 153–4
Cosmopolitan, 50
Cossette, Eric, 56
Cotler, Irwin, 424
Court Challenges Program (Canada): and caste, 407;
and equality of result, 92;
and female circumcision, 609n55;
and feminism, 512n44;
and “historically disadvantaged” groups, 91–2, 609n55;
and the Legal Education and Action Fund, 306–7;
personnel of, 585n140;
and women, 427
Cousineau, Gina, 55–6
Craft, Nikki, 544n41
Crawford, Mary, 212
Crews, Frederick, 495n26
Crichton, Michael, 46, 501n12
Crimes against Children Unit. See Federal Bureau of Investigation
critical theory. See ideological feminism; postmodernism
Crosby, Faye, 98–100
Cross, Pamela, 253–6, 258, 262, 425–8, 571n163
custody. See child custody Daly, Mary, 615n14
Darby, Tom, 206
Dasbach, Steve, 143
Davis, Laura, 11
Day, Shelagh, 306
daycare, 16–19. See also mothers
de Waal, Frans, 349
Deadbeat Parents Punishment Act (United States), 130, 147
Dearinge, De’Andre, 48–9, 502n36
Decade for Women. See
United Nations Declaration of Independence (United States), 82
Declaration on the Elimination of Violence against Women. See United
Nations
deconstruction. See ideological feminism, postmodernism
dehumanization of men, 332, 384, 486. See also misandry
dehumanization of women, 384. See also misogyny
Dembart, Lee, 104
democracy: and affirmative action, 104, 409;
and the arts, 518n95;
and debate, 77;
and egalitarian feminism, 325;
and freedom of expression, 368, 370;
and ideological feminism, xiv, 78, 221–2, 267–8, 325;
and intolerance, 518, n. 94;
and isolation of groups, 73;
as liberal state, 267;
majority and minorities in, 409, 589n1;
and morality, 325;
and political correctness, 322, 368, 370, 589n1;
and political transparency, 267–8;
postmodern jargon of, 322, 589, n. 1;
and public opinion, 321, 348;
and religion, 589n1;
and the university, 106–7;
as the welfare state, 267;
and the World Conference on Women (Beijing), 402
demonization of men. See misandry, witch hunts
Demos, John, 17
Denson-Gerber, Judianne, 342
Department of Economic and Social Affairs (United Nations), 391
Department of Education (United States), 289
Department of Health and Human Services (United States), 131, 139, 144,
228, 304
Department of Justice (United States), 228, 236, 251
Department of Labor (United States), 89
Depression, 497n39
Dershowitz, Alan, 22
Development Fund. See United Nations
deYoung, Mary, 3, 16, 19
dialogue. See intersexual dialogue
Diamond, Ann, 496n34
difference. See sex differences
Dinnerstein, Dorothy, 387
Directory of New Hires (United States), 128
Dirks, Nicholas, 404–6
discrimination, 81–124;
as affirmative action, 101–5, 110, 313;
by age, 117, 521n112;
in American law, 84–9;
and burden of proof, xi, 42, 73–4, 143–4, 313;
in Canadian law, 89–95, 513n51, 515n66, 602n2, 607n42;
as censorship, 180–1;
as conscription, 612n97;
and consequentialism, 518n86;
and custody, 145–6;
definition of, 82;
against divorced fathers, 146, 150, 524n13, 532n70, 607n42;
and double standards, 408, 612n97;
and egalitarian feminism, 312;
and “enumerated grounds,” 515n66;
and ideological feminism, 246–8;
and ideological strategies, 314–18;
and intention, 196;
by judges, 247;
against men, 174, 245–8; 303, 312, 527n40, 612n97;
as misandry, ix, xi, 92, 116, 118, 146, 174, 245–8, 311;
and motivation, 311–12, 408;
and pay equity, 113, 117;
by police, 245–6;
by prosecutors, 246–8;
in “reverse,” 103;
and sexual harassment, 195;
strategies of, 314–18;
or supply and demand, 520n110;
systemic, ix, xi, 92, 116, 118, 146, 174, 245–8, 311, 314, 323, 326,
403, 427–9, 513n51;
in the university, 207;
and “visible minorities,” 407–8;
against women, ix, 427–8
Division for the Advancement of Women. See United Nations
divorce, 125–56;
and alimony, 96, 129;
causes of, 132, 133;
and children, 437–8;
and “divorce culture,” 523n12;
and “divorce revolution,” 523n12;
and equality of result, 428–9;
and fundamentalism, 341;
and hierarchy, 313;
and ideological feminism, 128–9;
and ideological separatism, 128–9;
prevalence of, 128;
and standard of living after, 125, 133–5, 347–64, 591n11;
statistics on, 125, 132–5, 139, 351–2, 354, 356, 358, 360, 363, 522n5,
591nn10, 11, 12;
and suicide, 529n53;
and women, 128–9. See also child custody, child support, divorced
fathers, marriage, separation
Divorce Act (Canada): and child custody, 606n31;
and child support, 149–50, 538n134;
and domestic violence, 437, 538n134;
proposed changes to, 421–4, 426, 428;
and “maximum contact,” 431–2;
and stalking, 435
divorced fathers, 131–6, 415–38;
and access to children, 534n88;
and affirmative action, 109;
black men as, 120;
criminalization of, 143;
as “controlling,” 51, 127, 432;
discrimination against, 146, 150, 524n13, 532n70, 607n42;
false allegations against, 534n88;
historical background of, 126;
how-to books on, 535n119;
and married men, 592n13;
and misandry, 329;
misconceptions about, 131–6;
mobilization of, 146–8;
and political correctness, 429;
prejudice against, 607n42;
psychological state of, 133–5;
and recovered-memory syndrome, 6, 14, 18;
as “runaway dads,” 136;
and statistics abuse, 132, 133, 139, 351–4, 591nn10, 11;
as violent, 127, 424–38;
suicide of, 135, 138, 238, 532n70, 533n71;
support groups for, 146–7, 614n5;
against vested interests, 144–6;
websites for, 147. See also child custody, child support
DNA tests. See child custody, child support
Dobash, Rebecca, 481, 484
Dobash, Russell, 481, 484
Dobyns, Stephen, 205
documentaries: Behind the Veil, 615n14;
and “Goddess” revival, 615n14
Domestic Abuse Intervention Project, 478
Domestic Abuse Project, 478
domestic sphere, 81
domestic support. See child support
domestic violence, 233–48;
and the “abuse excuse,” 22–30;
in Canada, 230, 245–8;
and child custody, 424–38;
debate over, 233–48, 478–92;
and dualism, 486;
empirical approaches to, 616n2;
false accusations of, 563n54;
and family background, 238–9;
of gay people, 567n109;
and gynocentrism, 489;
by men, 21–9, 224, 424–38, 478–92, 617n8;
and murder, 238;
and political correctness, 436;
in popular culture, 239, 489;
and power, 617n8;
psychological forms, 563n54;
and rape, 358, 362;
remedies for, 498n13;
and shelter movement, 478–92;
and slapping, 239;
and statistics abuse, 232, 236, 250, 354–64;
statistics on, 233–9, 244, 354, 364, 422, 499, 498n13, 567n121,
593n30, 594n44;
and stereotypes, 486;
and suicide, 238;
techniques of, 563n54;
threats of, 563n54;
and vigilantism, 24–6, 73, 244;
by women, 233–48, 354–64, 563n54, 565nn77, 81, 567n121, 593n30.
See also battered men, battered women
domination. See power
double messages, 50, 383–4
double standards, ix, 118–19;
on abortion, 141;
on affirmative action, 99, 105, 108, 109, 111, 475–6;
on androcentrism, ix, 400–1;
on bad faith, 426;
on blaming the victim, 299, 489;
on the Bobbitt Affair, 23, 26;
on child custody, 433, 524n13;
on child support, 141;
on comparative suffering, 476;
on conscription, 400, 408, 612n97;
on conspiracies, 474;
on “control,” 433;
on the Court Challenges Program, 427;
on deconstruction, 296, 476;
on defensiveness, 47;
on dehumanization, 176;
on discrimination, 408;
on “diversity,” 278, 430;
on domestic violence, 235, 244, 245;
on education, 401;
on emotionalism, 427;
on essentialism, 582n104;
on exceptions, 317;
on financial backing, 427;
on gay porn, 188–9;
on generalizations, 475, 582n104;
on hate laws, xi;
on hate literature, 320;
on health, 400–1, 477;
on heterosexuality, 40;
on the Hill-Thomas Debate, 40–1, 45;
on indigenous cultures, 401;
institutionalization of, ix, 118;
on journalistic practices, 474;
on lesbian porn, 189;
on lobbying, 425;
on men and women as “machines,” 154;
on mentors, 474;
on misandry, 329–32;
on naming names, 476;
on the need for protection, 376;
on networking, 474;
on “objectification,” 180, 389–90;
on obscenity, 173;
on oversimplification, 474;
on pay equity, 118;
on peace, 388;
on political correctness, 207;
on political rhetoric, 474;
on popular culture, 40;
on popular psychology, 476;
on pornography, 173–4, 180, 185, 389;
on power, 428, 583n105;
on prostitution, 190–1;
on quotas, 476;
on rape, 260–1, 263–4;
on “role models,” 474;
on self-understanding, 617n13;
on sensitivity, 368;
on separate schools, 295;
on sexism, 40, 294, 387, 427, 474;
on sexual harassment, 40, 49, 502n37;
on statistics, 296, 582nn104, 105;
on stereotyping, 40, 390, 475;
on systemic discrimination, 429;
on teachers, 294–5;
on ulterior motives, 428;
in universities, 207;
on violence, 188;
on war, 388, 400;
and the World Conference on Women (Beijing), 400–1
Downing, Roberta, 98–100
Drouin, Sylvie, 55, 56
dualism: and affirmative action, 104;
definition of, xii;
and domestic violence, 486;
and equality of result, 123;
and essentialism, 312, 547n85, 572n168;
as gnosticism, 548n86;
in ideological separatism, 554n71;
as the “male model,” 74, 211, 599n44;
as misandry, 554n71;
and the Montreal Massacre, 69;
and romance novels, 286–389;
and sexual harassment, 203;
as victims versus victimizers, xii;
and witch hunts, 18–19, 29. See also essentialism, hierarchy
due process, 523:
in American law, 85, 225;
and child custody, 607n42;
and child support, 533n72;
and divorced fathers, 422, 436;
and domestic violence, 561n44;
and ideological strategies, 317;
and the “reasonable woman,” 203;
and shared parenting, 204;
and the university, 208;
and victimization industries, 158
Dufresne, Martin, 295, 476, 580n89
Dworkin, Andrea: on hatred, 260;
and ideological feminism, 544n41;
and linguistic inflation, 249;
and mainstream feminism, 168;
and misandry, 186, 191–2, 260, 320, 544n41;
on politics, 168;
on pornography, 160–92, 259;
on prejudice, 260;
on prostitution, 160–92, 259;
publications of, 301, 545n42;
on rape, 261, 544n41, 545n42;
on sex, 544n41;
and statistics abuse, 364;
and vigilantism, 73, 544n41. See also MacKinnon, Catharine
Eberts, Mary, 306
Echols, Alice, 201
École Polytechnique. See Montreal Massacre
Edge, The, 219
Edleson, Jeffrey, 478–92
education, 53, 100, 471–7, 493n1
education amendments. See Civil Rights Act of 1964 (United States)
egalitarian feminism: and androcentrism, 318;
and democracy, 325;
and discrimination, 312;
and dishonesty, 472;
and gender, 318;
and identity, 325–6;
and liberalism, 318;
and misandry, 214, 336;
moral implications of, 581n90;
and pornography, 176, 180;
and rape, 178, 259;
and sexual harassment, 196–218, 221;
and statistics abuse, 350–1. See also equality of opportunity
Ehrenreich, Barbara, 26–8
Eldridge v. British Columbia, 404
Eliade, Mircea, 319, 586n9
elite culture, 580n77
Elmer-Dewitt, Philip, 176, 547n85
Elshtain, Jean Bethke, 32, 41, 121–3
Elza, Jane, 286
Emerge, 487–8, 618n27
Emergency Intervention Orders (Saskatchewan), 230
Employment Equity Act (Canada), 94, 410–12, 604n7
Empowerment: in American law, 89;
and divorced fathers, 135;
and feminism, 194;
and ideological epistemology, 278;
and ideological feminism, 241;
and lobby groups, 291;
and misandry, 233;
and the Montreal Massacre, 69;
in popular culture, 50, 64, 134, 279–81, 323, 373, 390, 612n97;
and the World Conference on Women (Beijing), 397. See also power
ends and means. See consequentialism
Enlightenment, the: and ideological feminism, xii, 320;
and rights, 82;
and postmodernism, 338
entitlements. See legal entitlements
epistemology. See ideological epistemology
Equal Employment Opportunity Commission (United States): on sexual
harassment, 195, 199, 201–2, 208
Equal Justice for Women in the Courts Act (United States), 226
Equal Pay Act (United States), 87
Equal Protection Clause. See Fourteenth Amendment (United States)
Equal Rights Amendment (United States), 84, 95, 317, 402
equality, x, 116, 325, 366–7
equality of opportunity: in American law, 84;
in Canadian law, 84, 96, 403, 429;
and conservatism, 123;
and dishonesty, 472;
and education, 472;
historical background of, 83, 84–5, 123;
and liberalism, 123;
modified, 84, 92, 404;
and personal responsibility, 123;
and reform, 123;
and the World Conference on Women (Beijing), 400
equality of result, 391–402;
and affirmative action, 110–11;
in American law, 84, 510n30;
in Canadian law, 84, 90, 92, 94–6, 123, 150, 174, 403, 428, 510n30;
and divorce, 428–9;
and dualism, 123;
and “equality-seeking groups,” 93, 164;
as “equity,” 322;
historical background of, 83–4, 123;
and identity, 111;
in India, 404–9;
and legal entitlements, 83;
and revolutionism, 123;
and state regulation, 123;
and statistics abuse, 92, 313, 315;
and stereotypes, 403;
and the United Nations, 90, 92;
and utopianism, 83, 123;
and the World Conference on Women (Beijing), 400. See also
affirmative action, pay equity
equity. See equality of result, pay equity
Eriksen, Maria, 60
erotica. See pornography
essentialism: and “connectedness” of women, 210, 386–9;
and domestic violence, 29;
and dualism, 312, 547n85, 572n168;
and ideological feminism, xii, 18–19, 210, 310, 323, 341, 386–9,
547n85, 566n97;
and motherhood, 386, 566n97. See also dualism
Estrich, Susan, 25
Evans, Jamie Lee, 26
Ewanchuk. See R. v. Ewanchuk
Executive Order 10,925 (United States), 87
Executive Order 11,246 (United States), 87
Faase. See United States v. Timothy Gordon Faase
Fairness and Accuracy in Reporting, 358–60
false-memory syndrome. See recovered-memory syndrome
False Memory Syndrome Foundation, 13
Faludi, Susan, 352–3
family, 417–21
Family Law, 153
Family Law Committee (Canada), 423
Family Support Act (United States), 129, 525n15
family violence. See domestic violence
Family Violence Initiatives (Canada), 230
Family Violence Prevention and Services Act (United States)), 226,
558n17
Farrell, Warren: on domestic violence, 233–45;
on gay domestic violence, 567n109;
on misandry, 335;
on pay equity, 520n102;
on psychological abuse, 563n54;
on suicide, 529n53;
on statistics abuse, 591n11
fashion, 220–1
fathers: absence of, 150–5;
and biological connection, 140, 142–3, 534n94;
and child abuse, 566n97;
and child custody, 134, 313, 415–38, 606n31, 607n42;
as “controlling,” 432;
in ideological feminism, 312, 614n5;
importance of, 534n96;
as incompetent, 605n21;
and journalists, 128;
messages from women to, 154–6, 614n5;
in popular culture, 534n96;
prejudice against, 569n127;
replaced by the state, 155;
and “right to choose,” 141;
rights of, 96, 125–56;
in romance novels, 382;
and sons, 434, 530n65;
statistics abuse of;
statistics on, 140, 150, 534n94;
and surnames of children, 142, 148, 534n101;
on television, 534;
as violent, 424–38;
and the World Conference on Women (Beijing), 399. See also child
support, custody, divorced fathers
Father’s Day, 539n136. See also Mother’s Day
fathers’ rights. See rights
Faust, Drew Gilpin, 371–2
Federal Bureau of Investigation (United States), 228, 236. See also
Uniform Crime Reporting
Federal Case Registry (United States), 128
Federal Child Support Guidelines (Canada), 148, 421
Federal Contractors Program, 93, 409, 410–13, 604n7
Federal Protection for Rape Victims Act (United States), 224–5. See also
Federal Rules of Evidence
Federal Rules of Evidence (United States), 224–6, 557n12. See also rape
trials
Fekete, John, 357, 361–2
Feldman, Kathryn, 142–3
female victims: as a class, x, 95, 296;
and the Bobbitt Affair, 26–7;
and the “divorce revolution,” 129;
and domestic violence, 354–64, 567n109;
and experience, 229;
and the Hill-Thomas Debate, 37, 40;
in ideological feminism, 194, 229, 298;
lesbians as, 241, 567n109;
and loss of status, 242;
and misandry, 507n52;
and the Montreal Massacre, 61, 68, 71, 74–5, 194, 229, 298;
of murder, 565n81;
of pornography, 167;
of psychological abuse, 563n54;
and responsibility, 507n52;
in romance novels, 373;
of sexual harassment, 194, 204;
and statistics abuse, 354–64;
as “survivors,” 199, 215;
as unique, 298. See also domestic violence, murder, rape
femaleness, xii, 81, 92
feminism: and identity, 420;
and lobby groups, 289–91;
and misandry, 336–8;
moral implications of, 581n90;
and political correctness, 371–2;
and populism, 580n78;
and statistics abuse, 350–1;
types of, 336–7, 581n90. See also egalitarian feminism, ideological
feminism, male feminists
Feminist International Network of Resistance to Reproductive and Genetic
Engineering, 153, 213, 437, 506n46, 534n96
feminist liturgies. See quasi-religiosity
Feminist Majority, 291
Feminist Majority Foundation, 290–1, 550n108
feminization of poverty. See child support, divorce
Festinger, Leon, 482
Field, John, 102–3
Fifth Amendment (United States), 261
Finkelman, Larry, 61
Firearms Control Act (Canada), 231
First Amendment (United States), 167, 170, 172, 174, 181
Fish, Stanley, 102–4, 110
Fisher, Helen, 181–2
Flanders, Laura, 359, 360–1
Flax, Jane, 387
flirting. See sexual harassment
Flynt, Larry, 175–6
Fogle, Dale, 207
formal equality. See equality of opportunity
Fourteenth Amendment (United States), 88, 174, 248, 317
Francis v. Baker, 538n134
Frankfurt School. See critical theory, postmodernism
Franklin, George, 6
Fraser Committee. See
Special Committee on Pornography and Prostitution (Canada)
Frayser, Suzanne, 182–3
freedom of expression: and democracy, 368;
and equality, 366–7;
and political correctness, 41;
and power, 367–8;
and scholarship, 368;
and sexual harassment, 195;
and violence, 367–8;
and women, 220–1, 230
French, Marilyn, 185, 547n85, 599n45, 612n97
French Estate v. Ontario (A.G.). See R. v. Bernardo, 568n122
Friedan, Betty, 580n77
Friedman, Marilyn, 378–9
Frye, Marilyn, 213
fundamentalism. See ideology, religious fundamentalism
Gallway, Roger, 139
Gardner, Richard, 11, 114
Gartner, Rosemary, 61, 66
Gay, Roger, 137, 530n63
gay people, 61, 174–5, 188, 244, 322, 504n21, 567n109
gay women. See lesbians
Gayme. See R. v. Gayme
Gearhart, Sally Miller, 213
Geary, David, 610n74
Gelles, Richard, 233, 354–7
gender, 118;
breakdown of, 241–2;
and class or race, xii, 308, 320;
in egalitarian feminism, 318;
in popular culture, 332;
and the World Conference on Women (Beijing), 396–7. See also
masculinity
gender-based analysis. See ideological analysis
gender bias. See discrimination
Gender Lobby Day. See National Organization for Women
gender studies. See women’s studies
George, Malcolm, 593n30
Gharbi, Liass, 57
Gilligan, Carol, 97–8, 111
Gimbutas, Marja, 615n14
Ginsberg, Ruth Bader, 558n21
glass ceiling. See pay equity
Gleick, Elizabeth, 5, 12, 495n26
Glendon, Mary Ann, 300, 393–4
Gloria Steinem Award, 290
gnosticism. See dualism
Goddard, John, 15
Goddess. See quasi-religiosity
Goldenberg, Naomi, 615n14
Goldhagen, Daniel, 504n17
Gone with the Wind. See movies
Gore, Al, 128
gorillas, 610n74
Gorov, Lynda, 359
Graham, Bill, 206–7
Greenfeld, Lawrence, 251–2
Greenfield, Jeff, 24
Gross, Paul, 272–3, 574nn5, 6
Grosz, Elizabeth, 274
Gunderson, Morley, 114–16, 520n105
Gurian, Michael, 530n65
gynocentrism, ix-x;
and child custody, 120, 123, 150, 151–5;
and child support, 120, 123, 150, 151–5;
definition of, x;
and domestic violence, 489;
and double standards, ix, 400;
of elite culture, xiii;
and humanity as Woman, 123;
in the legal profession, 514n58;
male victims of, 266;
and misandry, x, 295, 309, 326;
and the Montreal Massacre, 66–73;
and pay equity, 116;
and sexual harassment, 201, 265;
and women’s studies, 287, 300, 306;
and the World Conference on Women (Beijing), 392–402. See also
androcentrism, misandry
Hall, G. Stanley, 344–5
Harlequin. See romance novels
Harraway, Donna, 277–9
Harris, Jean, 489
Harvard Law School, 302–3
Harvard Women’s Law Journal, 301–2
Hate Crime Statistics Act (United States), 226–7
hate crimes: and censorship, 548n94;
and ideological feminism, 297, 473, 569n127;
and lobby groups, 289;
and prejudice, 569n127;
and sex crimes, 251. See also hate legislation, hatred
hate legislation: and double standards, xi;
and ideological feminism, 186; 294;
in Canada, 172–3, 294, 297;
in the United States, 226–7, 251, 302, 569
hate literature. See misandry, misogyny
hatred, 25, 26, 68, 215–18, 260, 334–5, 544n41. See also anger, misandry,
misogyny, self-hatred
Health Canada. See Family Violence Initiatives (Canada)
hedonism, 17, 612n97
Henman, Paul, 531n66
Henry, Ronald, 136, 532n68
heroines. See popular culture
heterosexuality: in ideological feminism, xiv, 51, 161, 171–2, 175, 213–14,
384–5;
and linguistic inflation, 161;
as a luxury, 384;
“male feminists” on, 214;
nature and culture in, 503n39;
opposition to, 161, 209–18, 384–5;
and power, 197–8, 210;
privileges of, 93;
as rape, 161, 171–2, 178, 186, 211;
as “root cause” of female suffering, 384;
as sexual harassment, 51;
in social constructionism, 210;
and social needs, 210;
stereotypes of, 186;
and straight women, 384;
and violence against women, 224;
in women’s studies, 287, 300, 306. See also masturbation, rape
hierarchy, xii;
and affirmative action, 312–13;
and pornography, 383;
in romance novels, 383, 386–9;
and sexual harassment, 40, 47, 211. See also power, sex differences
Hill, Anita, 31–52, 198, 222, 500n8, 501n9
Hill, Jay, 423
Hill-Thomas Debate, 36–8
Hiller, Susanne, 152
Hindus, 369–70, 406, 597n19, 602n6. See also caste, India
homosexuality, 341. See also gay people, lesbians
honorary women. See gay men, male feminists
Hotter, Monica, 576n31
Hudnut v. American Booksellers, 170
human rights, 82–4, 121–3, 392–3. See also rights, women’s rights
Human Rights Tribunal (Canada), 116–17
husband abuse. See domestic violence
Hustler, 175–6
Hutchinson, Allan, 366–8
Hyde-Woolsey Act (United States), 130
identity politics: and alliances, 322;
and caste, 404, 407;
and comparative suffering, 297;
and dualism, 313;
and fragmentation, 325;
as an ideological strategy, 315
ideological epistemology: and affirmative action, 98, 107–8;
in “engaged scholarship,” 269, 287, 300, 397, 614n3;
in legal theory, 26, 41–2, 202–3;
and particularism, 278;
in politics, 278;
in popular psychology, 278–9;
and postmodernism, 26, 41–42, 202–3, 271–8, 296;
and revolutionism, 314;
in science, 270, 574nn5, 6, 7;
and sexual harassment, 201–4;
and subjectivity, 26, 41–2, 106, 202–3, 274–5, 282, 573n4;
and women, 277–8, 574n7;
in women’s studies, 582n99. See also science, women’s studies
ideological feminism: on affirmative action, 103–4, 113, 313;
on “backlash,” 61–2, 215, 351, 353, 581n94;
on battered men, 354;
on battered women, 478–92;
and black power, 320;
in Canada, 206–7, 304, 317;
centrality of men in, 217;
on child custody, 424–38;
on child support, 127, 424–38;
and collectivism, 313;
on consent, 196–7;
and consequentialism, xii, 19, 27–8, 313, 518n86;
on conspiracies, 198;
on contact with men, 197, 199, 311, 314;
on control, 221;
and critical theory, 320–1;
and “deconstruction,” 210, 476, 582n97;
and democracy, xiv, 78, 221–2, 267–8, 325;
and discrimination, 246–7, 248;
on divorce 128–9;
on domestic violence, 233–48, 478–92, 341;
and dualism, xii, 74, 104, 203, 211, 310, 324, 341;
on education, 293–9;
and egalitarian feminism, xii, 337;
and “engaged scholarship,” 269, 287, 300, 397, 614n3;
and the Enlightenment, xii;
on “eroticization of male power,” 177–8, 196–8; 209–10, 230, 245;
and essentialism, xii, 18–19, 210, 310, 323, 341, 386–9, 547n85,
566n97;
and euphemisms, xiv;
on fathers, 312;
fear promoted by, 215–16, 586n7;
and female victims, 194, 229, 298;
and freedom of expression, 219–21;
as “fringe,” 212, 550n108;
and fronts, xiv, 308, 318–23, 465–70, 576n31;
on “gender analysis,” 94, 231, 232, 315, 437;
hatred in, 25, 215–18, 260, 310–11;
on heterosexuality, xiv, 51, 161, 171–2, 175, 196–218, 341, 384–5,
554n71;
and hierarchy, 197, 312;
and identity, 325–6;
on the Internet, 150, 267, 269, 288–92, 413–14;
jargon of, 578n62, 581nn93, 95, 96;
on judicial activism, 304–8;
in law schools, 300–4;
and legal advocacy groups, 304–8, 510n30;
and lesbians, 209, 211, 310;
and mainstream feminism, 168, 550nn107, 108;
and “male feminists,” 61, 68, 75, 78, 214, 217–18;
and “male-identified women,” 213, 313;
on “masculinism,” 293–9, 581nn93, 96;
and misandry, 554n71;
and Modern Language Association, 439–64;
on the Montreal Massacre, 59–67, 361;
moral implications of, 581n90;
and neo-Romanticism, xii, 203–4, 320;
and other ideologies, xii;
on “patriarchy,” 271;
on pay equity, 313, 412–14;
on pleasure, 612n97;
and political correctness, 371–2;
in popular culture, 308;
on pornography 160–92, 312–13, 341;
and postmodernism, 167, 210, 267, 270, 319;
on power, 121–2, 167–72, 177–8, 196–8, 224, 612n97;
on prostitution, 165–6;
and prudery, 548n90;
on psychoanalysis, 344–5, 381, 384, 495nn17, 26, 599n40;
and quasi-religiosity, 314, 319, 586n9;
on rape, 97, 171–2, 175, 197, 229–30, 249–51, 259, 311, 341;
and revolutionism, 267, 313, 318–19;
on rights, 317;
on romance novels, 373–90;
on science, 270–6, 574nn5, 6, 7;
and selective cynicism, xii, 278, 312–13;
on separatism, 97, 197, 199, 200, 209, 211, 311, 320, 322, 554n71;
on sexual harassment, 196–218, 312;
and sexual polarization, 77;
and statistics abuse, 296, 313, 347–64;
on subordination of women, 170, 177–8, 180;
success of, 267, 270;
and stereotypes of men, 358;
in the university, 106;
and utopianism, 184–5, 221, 314, 318, 437;
and vigilantism, 544n41;
on violence against men, 224;
on violence against women, 53, 64–5, 69, 71, 76–7, 170, 224, 312,
424–38, 569n127;
and witch hunts, 17–20;
and women’s networks, 288–93;
and women’s studies, 267–300, 308, 320, 465–70, 576nn31, 37,
577nn39, 45;
and the World Conference on Women (Beijing), 391–402. See also
egalitarian feminism, equality of result, male feminists
Ideological fronts: “cultural studies” for ideology, 321;
“equality” for gynocentrism, 116;
“human rights” for women’s rights, 121–3;
and Marxism, 308, 465;
“pluralism” for essentialism, 318, 323;
“postmodernism” for ideology, 318;
“reform” for revolution, 318;
“women’s studies” for ideological feminism, xiv, 308, 318–23, 465–
70, 576n31
ideological fundamentalism. See fundamentalism
ideological indoctrination: in Canada, 116, 231;
and domestic violence, 436;
as an ideological strategy, 207–9, 317;
and pay equity, 116;
and sexual harassment, 43, 207–9, 213, 219;
in United States, 43, 227;
and violence against women, 227
ideological industries: child support, 126, 138–43, 533n77;
pay equity, 115;
single mothers, 152;
and victimization, 158;
victims of pornography, 161;
victims of prostitution, 161;
victims of sexual harassment, 198, 218–20, 283, 555n98;
and welfare, 120;
and witch hunts, 6, 11
ideological liturgies. See quasi-religiosity
ideological separatism: and affirmative action, 121;
and child custody, 437;
and divorce, 128–9;
and lesbians, 384–6;
and misandry, 153–4, 554n71;
and the Montreal Massacre, 66–7;
and pay equity, 121;
and reproductive autonomy, 153–4, 213;
and romance novels, 384. See also single mothers
ideological strategies, 314–18;
alliances, 316, 322;
in American law, 317;
bribery, 317;
bureaucratic legerdemain, 84, 87, 89, 94, 115–16, 150, 416;
in Canadian law, 304, 317;
and child support, 316;
and discrimination, 314–18;
“diversity,” 308;
double standards, 317;
and due process, 45, 208–9;
emergency situations, 317;
fronts, xiv, 308, 318;
identity politics, 315;
indoctrination, 207–9, 317;
infiltration, 308, 315, 318;
intimidation, 317, 410–12;
judicial activism, 304–8;
linguistic inflation, 317–18;
lying, 34–8, 69, 127;
mobilization of resentment, 315, 320, 324;
new industries, 317;
new moral panics, 324;
new standards, 317;
postmodernist jargon, 308;
redefinition of terms, 317;
“reeducation,” 317;
reinterpretation of laws, 317;
scapegoating, 324;
sensational trials, 315;
shaming men, 76, 208, 315, 317;
shifting of negative rights to positive ones, 317;
statistics abuse, 316–17, 324;
trump cards, 317. See also identity politics
ideological trump cards: and affirmative action, 107, 110;
“backlash,” 317;
and double standards, 118;
and fathers, 127;
and fear, 2;
“glass ceiling,” 297, 317;
power differential, 297;
and statistics, 426;
violence against women, 127, 157–8, 224, 248, 297, 317, 358, 435
ideology, 337;
and control, 184–5;
and democracy, 325;
and education, 100;
and fronts, 465;
and political correctness, 368;
and postmodernism, 368;
and power, 184–5;
and scholarship, xiv;
and self-righteousness, 33. See also collectivism, consequentialism,
dualism; essentialism, hierarchy, ideological analysis; quasi-religiosity,
revolutionism, utopianism
Ignatieff, Michael, 83, 152
immunities. See legal immunities
Implementing Order 4 to Executive Order 11,246 (United States), 87
in vitro fertilization. See reproductive technologies
incest, 6, 9, 17, 19, 495n17, 496n34. See also recovered-memory
syndrome, multiple-personality disorder, satanic-ritual abuse
Index to Canadian Legal Periodical Literature, 306
India, 404–9, 602n7. See also affirmative action
Indian Act (Canada), 90
Indiana University, 466–7
Indianapolis. See ordinances
Industrial Revolution, 113, 126, 497n39
inequality. See equality
informed consent. See rape, sexual harassment
insanity defense, 60, 62
Internal Revenue Service (United States), 130, 201
International Court of Justice (United Nations), 316, 392
International Network for Jewish Holocaust Survivors, 227
International Research and Training Institute for the Advancement of
Women. See United Nations
International Society for the Study of Multiple Personality Disorder and
Dissociation, 7
International Women’s Day. See United Nations
Internet: and critical theory, 319–20;
and fathers, 147, 420, 473–4;
and ideological feminism, 169, 294;
and men, 247–8;
and pay equity, 413–14;
and political polarization, 319–20;
and popular culture, 500n4, 549n106;
and pornography, 17, 162–3, 342–3, 345;
and post-modernism, 184–5;
and sex, 254;
and witch hunts, 12;
and women’s studies, 288–91, 466, 579n65
intersexual dialogue, 25, 49, 51, 336, 478
Ireland, Patricia, 290, 359–360, 558n21
Iyer, Aarti, 98–100
Jackson, Michael, 605n21
Jacksonville Shipyards. See Louis Robinson v. Jacksonville Shipyards
Jacobs, James, 170, 180–1, 226–7, 548n94, 569n127
Jadwin, Lisa, 285
James, Angela, 352
James, William, 10
Jane Doe v. Metropolitan Toronto (Municipality) Commissioners of Police,
568n122
Jeffreys, Sheila, 210
Jensen, Robert, 218
Jews: and affirmative action, 101–2, 108, 517nn84, 88;
and antiSemitism, 69, 107, 215–17, 297, 337–8, 350, 473;
in Christianity, 586nn3, 6, 596n99;
civil religion of, 505n38;
collective guilt ascribed to, 104;
and comparative suffering, 297;
and education, 408;
and equality, 181;
and Germans, 59;
in ideologies, 217, 335, 369–70;
and Israel, 589n1;
and lobby groups, 227;
and mentors, 108;
and minority groups, 410;
and quotas, 101–2, 517n85;
and “self-hatred,” 335. See also Judaism
johns. See prostitution
Johnson, Judy, 4, 5, 13
journalists: on fathers, 128;
on the Montreal Massacre, 55;
and popular psychology, 323;
and public opinion, xiv;
and statistics abuse, 342;
and witch hunts, 10–11, 20, 342, 345;
on women and children, 63
Judaism: and Christian feminism, 369, 596n9;
and Christianity, 104, 295, 310, 586nn3, 6;
and civil religion, 505n37;
and ethics, 73;
and gnosticism, 176, 548n86;
on masturbation, 550n111;
and modernity, 395;
and prejudice, 586n5;
in the public square, 370;
and sacred time, 588n3;
on vices and virtues, 586n4. See also Jews
Kaminer, Wendy, 45
Kane, Susan, 577n45
Kanisdorf, Martin, 140–1
Karcher, Carolyn, 371–2
Katz, Janet, 359
Keegstra. See R. v. Keegstra
Kellenbach, Katherina von, 596n9
Kemler, Lisa, 23
Kennedy, Duncan, 303
Kennedy, Edward, 37
Kennedy, Florynce, 212
Kentucky Commission on Women, 355
Kiernan, Thomas, 563
Kincaid, James, 343
King, Patricia, 24–5
Kitzinger, Celia, 203, 212
Kleiner, Heather, 283
Knopff, Rainer, 145, 181, 300–1
Koertge, Noretta, 275–7, 280
Korenman, Joan, 287–8
Koss, Mary, 357
Kposowa, Augustine, 135, 528n52, 529n53
Kreklewetz v. Scopel, 534n97
Krikorian, Greg, 138
Kuehl, Sheila, 358–9
Laframboise, Donna, 502n37
Lanier. See United States v.
Lanier Lanoie, Paul, 114–16, 520n102
Lavell v. Canada, 90
law enforcement. See police
law schools, 99–100, 514n58
Law v. Canada (Minister of Employment and Immigration), 403, 602n2
Leclair, Dominique, 55, 58
Legal Defense and Action Fund, 172, 510n30
Legal Education and Action Fund, 89, 305–7, 510n30, 513n46, 585n140;
critiques of, 510n30;
and Dworkin, 173;
and MacKinnon, 97, 172, 543n40, 568n122;
and pornography, 174;
and rape, 229–30;
and R.v. Seaboyer, 229–30, 232, 306, 568n122;
statistics on, 306–7;
and violence against women, 232
legal entitlements, 82–124
legal immunities, x, 82, 122–3
legal protections, x, 248, 312, 408
Leggett, William, 206
Lépine, Marc, 292, 314, 315, 361, 477;
biography of, 54–9;
and masculinity, 56–7, 59;
military interests of, 56, 57;
as “normal” man, 259;
relations with men, 56–8;
relations with women, 55–6
Lépine, Monique, 55
Lépine, Nadia, 55
Lerner, Gerda, 615n14
lesbians: and coming-out stories, 374–5;
and domestic violence, 504n21, 567n109;
and female victims, 241;
on heterosexuality, 209, 211–12, 214, 384–5;
and ideological feminism, 211;
and ideological separatism, 209, 322;
and literature, 175, 381;
and pornography, 175;
and sexual harassment, 198, 209;
and the World Conference on Women (Beijing), 399
Levine, Judith, 7, 11, 340–6, 496nn37, 38; 497n39
Levitt, Norman, 272–3, 574nn5, 6
Lewinsky, Monica, 215
liberal feminism. See egalitarian feminism.
Lindsey, Michael, 359
linguistic “inflation”: and heterosexuality, 199–201;
as an ideological strategy, 69, 198, 317;
and misandry, 249, 345. See also heterosexuality, ideological
feminism, pornography, prostitution, rape, sexual harassment,
violence, violence against women
Littleton, Christine, 283, 285
Loftus, Elizabeth, 15, 19
Lopez. See United States v. Lopez
Louis Robinson v. Jacksonville Shipyards, 172, 201
Love Your Body Day. See National Organization for Women
Lowman, John, 166–7, 190, 542nn26, 28
Lychner, Pam, 228
Lypsite, Robert, 359
M.(K) v. M. (H), 568n122
McCarthy, Sandra Bem, 212
McCarthy witch hunt. See witch hunts Maccoby, Eleanor E., 522n5
McCormack, Andrew, 481
McCormick, Adrienne, 283
McElroy, Wendy, 127–8, 180, 248, 558n21, 569n127
MacFarlane, Kee, 345
McGill Centre for Research and Teaching on Women, 519n97, 576n31
McGill University, 67, 102, 269, 517nn82, 85
Macias, Aurelia, 499n14
Macias, Jaime, 499n14
McIntyre, Sheila, 307
McIntyre, William, 91
Mack, John, 9
MacKinnon, Catharine, 248, 249–50, 301, 543n40;
in Canada, 96–7, 232, 543n40, 568n122;
on child custody, 96;
on civil suits, 167;
and democracy, 220;
on divorce, 96;
on domestic violence, 358;
on equality of result, 96–7, 123;
on “eroticization of male power,” 177–8, 196–8, 209–210, 230, 245;
as hate author, 186, 191–2;
and linguistic inflation, 249;
in mainstream, 168;
on politics, 167–8;
on pornography and prostitution, 160–92;
publications of, 543n40;
on rape, 149–250, 261;
retaliation against, 546n50;
and revolutionism, 167–8;
on sexual harassment 196–201, 209;
on speech-act theory, 200. See also Dworkin, Andrea
McLean, Candis, 132, 148
McLeod, Maureen, 237
McMartin, Peggy, 13
McMartin Preschool, 4–7
McNeely, R.L., 355
McPhedran, Marilou, 306
MacPherson, Don, 223
McRae, Virginia, 423
magazines: Cosmopolitan, 50;
Hustler, 175–6;
Ms, 491–2;
New York Times Magazine, 205;
Newsweek, 564;
and “objectification,” 159;
Playboy, 43;
and sexual harassment, 43, 50, 205;
Time, 353;
and statistics abuse, 353, 564
Magezis, Joy, 279–81
Mahoney, Kathleen, 116
Maier, Daniel, 564n72
Maines, Natalie, 365
majority. See democracy
male feminists: on “backlash,” 295;
on heterosexuality, 214;
as honorary women, xi, 214, 217, 472–3;
and identity problem, 217;
on “masculinism,” 295;
and misandry, 218, 332;
and the Montreal Massacre, 68, 75, 78;
motivations of, 61;
on women’s studies, 577n39
male victims: blamed, 299;
boys as, 48–9, 63;
as a class, x, 296;
of domestic violence, 354–64, 563n54, 567nn109, 121, 593n30;
gay men as, 567n109;
of gynocentrism, 266;
and identity, 217, 593n30;
and masochism, 242–3;
messages to, 266;
of misandry, 218, 336;
of molestation, 256–7;
of murder, 565n81;
of psychological abuse, 563n54;
of rape, 256–7, 265;
of sexual harassment, 46–8, 233–44;
stoicism of, 315;
trivialization of, 233–44, 265–6, 298–9;
of violence, 188, 593n30;
and witch hunts, 17–20;
of women, 233, 248, 257, 354–64, 563n54, 565nn77, 81, 567n121,
593n30. See also domestic violence, murder, rape
male violence. See violence against men, violence against women
maleness, xii, 81, 92, 326, 610n74
Mamet, David, 47
Mandal Commission, 406
Manfredi, Christopher: on Legal Education and Action Fund, 230, 305–7,
510n30;
on lobby groups, 511n33;
on Status of Women Canada, 90;
and Supreme Court of Canada, 95
Manitoba Women’s Advisory Council, 413
marriage, 182–3. See also divorce, separation
Martin, Lloyd, 342
Martin, Sheila, 116
martyrs, 27, 38, 110
Marxism: and consequentialism, 518n86;
and critical theory, 300, 303, 319–21;
and Enlightenment, 320;
and equality of result, 83;
and fronts, 308, 465;
and ideological feminism, 320–1, 465;
and ideology, 295;
and Catharine MacKinnon, 167;
and misandry, 330, 336;
and political correctness, 368;
and popular culture, 336;
and “quiet revolutions,” 325;
and self-criticism rituals, 208;
and victim classes, 336;
and the United Nations, 401;
and utopianism, 320. See also critical theory
masculinism. See misogyny
masculinity: after 9/11, 325, 334;
of boys, 8, 48–9;
collective, xii, 111, 123;
and contributions to society, 66–7, 114, 325–6, 501n14;
and double messages, 383–4;
in egalitarian feminism, 325–6;
and equality of result, 111;
and father-hood, 415;
in feminism, 420;
and heroism, 505n31;
and historical analogies, 59;
in ideological feminism, 325–6;
and ideological feminism, 398, 614n5;
loss of, 59;
of “male feminists,” 217;
of male victims, 48–9, 63;
of Marc Lépine, 55–8;
and meaning, 78;
of men, 25, 48, 64–5, 76, 114, 217;
and the Montreal Massacre, 65–7;
and personal identity, xii;
in popular culture, 64–5, 332–4, 505n31;
and power, 66;
and security, 66;
and self-sacrifice, 612n97;
and the World Conference on Women (Beijing), 398;
and women, 69, 420;
and women’s studies, 467–8
mass media. See also journalists, popular culture
masturbation, 550n111
Mathews, Frederick, 190, 256–7, 265–6, 298, 475, 571n153
Mattes, Jane, 152–3
Mayer, Jane, 42
Meese Commission (Canada), 341–2
Meiorin. See B.C. Government and Service Employees’ Union v. B.C.
Public Service Employees’ Relations Commission
memory. See alien abductions, multiple-personality disorder, recovered-
memory syndrome
Menendez, Eric, 21–2
Menendez, Lyle, 21–2
Meritor Savings Bank v. Vinson, 196, 199
Merton, Robert, 276
Mettger, Zak, 480, 617n13
Metropolitan Toronto. See Jane Doe v. Metropolitan Toronto
(Municipality) Commissioners of Police
Miles, Angela, 373–90
military conscription. See war
Milstone, Carol, 5, 6, 12
Minneapolis. See ordinances
Minnow, Martha, 301
minorities. See democracy
misandry, 197, 309, 544n41, 550n107: attempts to condone it, x–xi, 215–
17, 336;
attempts to justify it, 338–9;
attempts to trivialize it, xiii, 330–2;
and blame, x;
and business, 334–5;
and debate over domestic violence, 233–48;
definition of, x;
and dehumanization of men, 332;
and demonization of men, 332;
and divorced fathers, 329;
and double standards, 294, 330–2;
and dualism, 388;
effect on men, ix–xi, 92, 116, 118, 146, 174, 217, 245–8, 311, 335;
and egalitarian feminism, 214, 336;
and elite culture, xiii, 338;
and fear, 215–16, 586n7;
and feminism, 336–8;
and gynocentrism, x, 295, 309, 326;
as hate literature, 181, 185–6, 191–2;
and hatred, x, 215–18, 334–6;
and “heterophobia,” 214–15, 554n71;
and ideological separatism, 153–4, 554n71;
legalization of, 222;
through litigation, xiii–xv;
of male feminists, 218, 332, 335;
and male victims, 218, 336;
and Marxism, 330, 336;
and misogyny, xiii, 216, 330;
as a moral problem, 331;
in popular culture, xi, 209, 263–4, 329–39, 373–90, 592n21;
and postmodernism, 338–9;
public perception of, 329–39;
and rape, 259; 262, 311;
as revenge, 338;
and revolutionism, xv;
and ridicule of men, 332;
and self-hatred, 335;
and sexual polarization, 331, 338;
silences men, 41, 370;
Spreading Misandry on, 329–30;
and stereotypes, 263, 311; 331–2;
and systemic discrimination, ix, xi, 92, 116, 118, 146, 174, 245–8, 311;
and trivialization of men, 332;
and women, 215, 507n52;
and women’s studies, 280, 282, 286, 287. See also ideological
feminism
misogyny, ix, 59–62, 75, 202, 472;
and androcentrism, x;
as “backlash,” 293;
and envy of women, 66;
as hate literature, 171, 175–6;
and “heterophobia,” 161;
or “masculinism,” 293–9, 473;
and misandry, xiii, 216, 330, 547n85;
in popular culture, 223–4, 330;
and pornography, 160, 551n114;
and prostitution, 160;
silences women, 50, 168;
and stereotypes, 278, 358;
and the World Conference on Women (Beijing), 399
Mitchell, Kyle, 531n66
Mitchell, Linda, 358–9
Mitchell, Margaret, 377, 379
Mitchell. See Wisconsin v. Mitchell
Mnookin, Robert H., 522n5
Modern Language Association, 439–64
modernity, 497n39, 549n104
Moire v. Temple University School of Medicine, 195
molestation: and alien abductions, 494n13;
of boys, 3, 7–9, 11, 12, 15, 256–7;
and the mobilization of resentment, 315, 340–6;
and statistics abuse, 257;
and violence, 345–6;
by women, 257. See also incest, pedophilia, witch hunts
Molinari, Susan, 226, 259
Montreal Massacre: commemorations of, 67–71, 292–3;
documentaries on, 580n83;
events of, 53–4;
explanations of, 59–67, 562n52;
and female victims, 61, 68, 194, 229, 298;
and historical analogies, 67, 69;
and ideological feminism, 59–67, 361, 562n52;
and journalists, 55, 562n52;
and male students, 504n30;
and the mobilization of resentment, 315, 580n83;
on news shows, 63;
political repercussions of, 71–8;
and quasi-religiosity, 67–71, 292–3;
and scapegoats, 62;
and sexual polarization, 62, 562n52;
and statistics abuse, 361–2;
and stereotypes, 504n30. See also Lépine, Marc moral panics, 3, 361.
See also witch hunts
Morgan, Robin, 185, 550n108
Morris, Bob, 370–1
Morrison. See United Statesv. Morrison
Morrison, Anthony, 558n17
Morrison, Helen, 64
Morton, F.L., 145, 181, 300–1
mothers: and child abuse, 566n97;
and child custody, 155, 415–38;
and childbirth, 386;
as men in romance novels, 380–4, 597n19;
rights of, 125–56;
and the World Conference on Women (Beijing), 394, 399. See also
daycare
Mother’s Day, 539n136. See also Father’s Day
Mott Amendment, 86
Mount St Vincent University, 61
movies: American Psycho, 249;
The Animal, 333;
Charlie’s Angels, 64, 333;
Deuce Bigalow, Male Gigolo, 332;
Disclosure, 46–7;
Dude, Where’s My Car, 332;
Dumb and Dumber, 332;
and emotion, 587;
First Wives Club, 353–4, 592;
Freddy Got Fingered, 332;
Gone with the Wind, 188, 377–83, 597nn16, 19, 598n27;
Hart’s War, 333;
He Said, She Said, 334;
High Noon, 332;
Of Human Bondage, 176;
I Shot Andy Warhol, 212, 248;
Jay and Silent Bob Strike Back, 333;
and masculinity, 64–65, 332–3;
and misandry, 592;
Monster, 248–9;
on multiple-personality disorder, 5;
Oleanna, 46–7;
The Passion of the Christ, 587;
Pearl Harbor, 333;
The People vs. Larry Flynt, 175–6;
and political correctness, 64–5;
and pornography, 176;
Saving Private Ryan, 333;
and sexual harassment, 46–7;
and statistics abuse, 353–4;
Sybil, 5;
Thelma and Louise, 248–9, 334, 385;
The Thin Red Line, 333;
The Three Faces of Eve, 5;
Titanic, 64–5;
and violence against men, 212;
and violence against women, 248–9
Ms., 211
Ms. Foundation, 290. See also Gloria Steinem Award, Take Our Daughters
to Work Day
multiple-personality disorder, 3, 5–7. See also alien abductions
Murphy Brown, 534n96
Muslims, 369–70
Nanda, Meera, 574n7
Nation, The, 250
National Action Committee on the Status of Women: and the Charter, 90;
in financial turmoil, 511n32;
and “herstory,” 397;
as a lobby group, 291;
on pay equity, 413
National Advisory Council on Violence against Women (United States),
228
National Association for Public Interest Law, 304
National Association of Women and the Law, 90, 306, 413, 415, 428, 437
National Center for Health Statistics (United States), 153
National Child Support Enforcement Association, 145
National Clearinghouse for the Defense of Battered Women, 236, 564n71
National Coalition against Domestic Violence, 479
National Coalition against Sexual Assault, 568n121
National Coalition of Anti-Violence Programs, 504n21
National Council on Family Relations, 352
National Crime Information Center (United States), 228
National Crime Victimization Survey (United States), 234
National Day of Remembrance and Action on Violence against Women
(Canada), 292
National Education Association, 304
National Endowment for the Arts (United States), 518n95
National Film Board of Canada, 475, 580n83, 615n14
National Firearms Association, 73
National Institute of Mental Health (United States), 7, 528n52
National Judicial Institute, 116
National Juvenile Prostitution Survey (Canada), 190
National Labor Relations Act (United States), 87
National Organization for Women, 289–90;
on battered men, 235;
and Gender Lobby Day, 289;
and Legal Defense and Education Fund, 172;
and Legal Education and Action Fund, 510;
and Love Your Body Day, 289;
and misandry, 309;
and statistics abuse, 359;
and Watch Out, Listen Up! 290
National Organization for Women Foundation, 234, 289. See also Legal
Defense and Education Fund
National Parole Board (Canada), 232
National Sex Offender Registry (United States), 228
National Symposium on Women, Law and the Administration of Justice,
93
National Women’s Law Center, 304–5
National Women’s Studies Association, 285
negative rights. See rights
Neidig, Peter, 478–92, 616n2; 617nn8, 13
neo-Marxism. See critical theory
neo-Puritanism. See Christianity, sexual harassment
neo-Romanticism, 320, 323, 324, 345. See also adolescents, children
New Deal, 87
news shows: 20/20, 489;
Canada A.M., 63;
and domestic violence, 489;
Good Morning America, 358;
on the Montreal Massacre, 63;
Prime-Time Live, 14;
and satanic-ritual abuse, 14;
and statistics abuse, 358–9
newspapers: National Post, 472;
New York Times, 359, 370;
and statistics abuse, 359;
Washington Post, 359
Nightline, 22–5
nondiscrimination rights.
See equality of opportunity
Norberg v. Wynrib, 568n122
Northwestern University, 468–9
Notwithstanding Clause. See Charter of Rights and Freedoms (Canada)
Now, 25–6
Nussbaum, Martha, 168–9, 177–9
Oakes test. See Charter of Rights and Freedoms (Canada)
objectification: of men, 180;
need for, 177–80;
in popular culture, 159, 373;
by women, 180;
of women, 159–60, 170, 172, 180, 373
objectivity. See ideological epistemology
O’Brien, Mary, 155, 387
obscenity. See pornography
O’Connor, Sandra Day, 558n21, 569n127
Offender Tracking and Identification Act, 228
Office of Child Support Enforcement (United States), 128, 129, 524n13
Official Languages Act (Canada), 89
Offner, Paul, 120
Oleanna, 46, 47
Omnibus Budget Reconciliation Act. See Bradley Amendment (United
States)
Ontario, 206–7
Ontario Court of Appeal, 142, 148
Ontario Women’s Network on Custody and Access, 426, 609n50
Optional Protocol. See United Nations Optional Protocol
ordinances: Anti-Pornography Civil Rights Ordinance, 174;
Indianapolis, 170, 181;
Minneapolis, 171–2
Organization of Chinese Americans, 227
Owen, Philip, 542n28
Paglia, Camille, 161, 222, 279
Pal, Les, 307–8
palimony. See separation
Parsons, Talcott, 276
Pascoe, Herbert, 66
Patai, Daphne: and Chronicle of Higher Education, 282–6, 576n37;
on “heterophobia,” 311, 554n71;
on ideological epistemology, 275;
on ideological separatism, 277;
on sexual harassment, 195–217;
on women’s studies, 279–80, 282–6
paternity fraud. See child support
paternity tests. See child support
patriarchy. See androcentrism
Paul, Ellen Frankel, 221
Paul Amendment (United States), 86
pay equity, 111–18;
in American law, 86, 119–21;
in Canadian law, 93–4, 116–19, 412, 604n7;
case study of, 412–14;
and complaints-based approach, 116;
and consequentialism, 118;
definitions of, 83, 112;
as discrimination, 113, 117, 520n110;
and female-dominated jobs, 520n105;
and the “glass ceiling,” 112, 114, 117, 413, 521n111;
and gynocentrism, 116;
and housewives, 117;
and ideological feminism, 313, 412–14;
and the Internet, 413–14;
justifications proposed for, 313;
and “leakage,” 114;
and “level playing field,” 313;
and manual labour, 113;
and the market, 520n110;
moral evaluation of, 117–18;
and risk as a criterion, 113–14, 519n102;
and statistics abuse, 112, 117, 121;
statistics on, 93, 113–14, 119, 413, 427;
and vested interests, 115;
and “work of equal value,” 297, 519n102;
and the World Conference on Women (Beijing), 400;
young men as victims of, 119
Pearson, Patricia, 238–9, 491–2
pedophilia, 8, 340–6, 494n12. See also multiple-personality disorder,
recovered-memory syndrome, satanic-ritual abuse
Pegueros, Rosa Maria, 577n39
Pence, Ellen, 478–92
Pendergast, Mark, 15
Penn, I., 480
Persons case, 89
Peter v. Beblow, 527n40
Peterson, Richard, 351, 591nn10, 11
Phillips, Susan Elizabeth, 390
Pickton, Robert William, 542n26
Pizzey, Erin, 354
Platform for Action (Beijing). See World Conference on Women (Beijing)
play, 257, 277, 549n103
police, 245–6
political correctness, 365–72: and advertising, 465;
and business, 589n1;
in Canadian law, 173;
and child custody, 417;
and collective rights, 104;
and deconstruction, 370–2;
definition of, 365;
and democracy, 589n1;
and dissenters, ix;
and divorced fathers, 429;
and domestic violence, 429;
in education, 100;
and the family, 417;
and feminism, 371–2;
and freedom of expression, 41;
and The Gap, 590;
and gay men, 61;
in government, 76;
and hatred, 334–5;
and the Hill-Thomas Debate, 32–3, 40–1, 48;
and ideology, 368;
and Journal of the American Academy of Religion, 369–70;
and language, 369–70;
and law, 219;
and Marxism, 368;
and masculine identity, 334;
and Matchbox Toys, 369;
and men, 76;
and moral panics, 361;
as political expediency, 268, 371–2;
in popular culture, 26–7, 64–5, 377;
and pornography, 173;
and postmodernism, 303, 368, 370–2;
as revenge, 367;
and science, 271;
and selective cynicism, 371;
and “self-esteem,” 323;
as self-righteousness, 368, 371;
and sexual harassment, 207;
and social ideals, 417;
and social respectability, 430;
Spreading Misandry on, 331;
and the Swissair disaster, 370;
in the university, 204–7, 439;
and witch hunts, 10;
in women’s studies, 281, 465;
and “zero tolerance,” 220. See also sexual correctness
Pollock, Gene, 351–2, 591n11
popular culture: alleged innocence of, 330;
alleged triviality of, 330;
and anorexia, 360–1;
as a business, 334;
and egalitarianism, 336;
and elite culture, xiii, 588n1;
emotionalism in, 203, 587n11;
and ideological feminism, 308;
and male feminists, 335;
men in, xi, 174, 176, 209;
misandry in, xi, 209, 263–264, 329–39;
misogyny in, 223–4;
moral evaluation of, 331;
mothers in, 155;
and political correctness, 26–7, 64–5, 377;
popular psychology in, 323;
rape in, 188, 248–9;
and sexual harassment, 500n4;
and sexual polarization, 331–2;
and The Slap, 239;
and victims, 336;
violence in, 75, 176, 188–9;
women in, 64;
workplace flirtations in, 500n4. See also documentaries, magazines,
movies, romance novels, sports, television
popular psychology: and double standards, 476;
emotionalism in, 323;
and ideological epistemology, 278–9;
of journalists, 323;
and political correctness, 65;
in popular culture, 323;
as a replacement for morality, 24;
on talk shows, 19, 203, 264, 278, 323, 612n97;
and temporary-insanity defense, 24;
and victims, 203–4;
and witch hunts, 19
popular religion, 587n11
pornography, 159–92;
in American law, 162–3;
in Canadian law, 163;
and censorship, 181, 297, 368–9;
and children, 340–6;
and civil rights, 170–2;
and consequentialism, 178–9;
effects on men of, 173–4, 176;
equivalents for women of, 185;
in egalitarian feminism, 176, 180;
eroticism as, 161, 175, 180, 181;
evolution of, 181–2;
female victims of, 167;
for gay men, 174, 175, 188, 342, 551n114;
harms of, 178–9, 188–9;
in ideological feminism, 160–92, 313, 341–2;
on the Internet, 162–163;
for lesbians, 175, 551n114;
and linguistic inflation, 97;
and marriage, 182–4;
Meese Commission on, 341–2;
and minors, 187;
as misogyny, 160;
as obscenity, 173–4, 176;
as play, 183–4, 187;
and political correctness, 173;
and popular culture, 176, 379, 383–5;
possible solutions to, 189–91;
purpose of, 169;
as rape, 198;
as sexual harassment, 160–2;
and society, 189;
and Clarence Thomas, 32, 35, 39, 42;
victims of, 167;
and vigilantism, 341;
and violence, 160–1, 187–91;
and “willing victims,” 174, 313, 551n114;
and witch hunts, 17;
for women, 551n114;
women affected by, 169–76, 180. See also objectification, romance
novels
postmodernism: and affirmative action, 98–9;
and Afrocentrism, 574n6;
and “critical theory,” 300–3, 319–21;
and “cultural studies,” 321;
and democracy, 322, 589n1;
dishonesty of, 270;
and “engaged scholarship,” 269, 287, 397, 614n3;
and fronts, 318;
and ideological epistemology, 26, 41–2, 202–3, 271–8, 296;
and ideological feminism, 167, 210, 267, 270, 319;
and ideology, 368;
and the Internet, 184–5;
and legal theory, 202–3, 300–3;
and metaphors, 273;
and misandry, 338–9;
and modernism, 270–1;
and political correctness, 303, 368, 370–2;
on power, 278;
on scholarship, xiv;
on science, 271–3, 278;
on sexual harassment, 201–4;
as social constructionism, 271;
on subjectivity, 26, 41–2, 202–3, 274–5, 278;
on the West, 271;
on women, 277;
in women’s studies, 285. See also critical theory, ideological feminism
Potter, Kimberly, 170, 180–1, 226–7, 548n94, 569n127
power: and battered women, 478–92, 617n8;
and domestic violence, 478–92, 617n8;
economic, 198;
as the empowerment of women, 279, 373, 390, 397, 612n97;
“eroticization” of, 177–8, 196–8, 209–10, 230, 245;
and heterosexuality, 197–8, 210;
and identity, 66;
in ideological feminism, 121–2, 167–72, 170, 177–8, 180, 196–8, 224–
38;
and ideology, 184–5;
imbalance of, 47, 68, 157, 166, 171, 204, 210, 297, 428, 563n54,
617n8;
loss of, 66, 241–2, 617n8;
of men, x, 185, 204, 211, 224, 241–2, 297, 312, 336, 428, 501n14,
563n54, 617n8;
and the mobilization of resentment, 315;
over nature, 185;
physical, 178, 198, 617n8;
and political correctness, 367–8;
in postmodernism, 278;
professional, 204;
as protection, 241–2;
psychological, 51, 127, 432, 563n54;
and revolutionism, 313;
and sexual harassment, 201, 209;
social, 204;
of the state, 184–5;
and violence against women, 241–2, 478–92, 617n8;
of women, 47, 83, 197, 204, 222, 563n54, 617n8;
in women’s studies, 468;
and the World Conference on Women (Beijing), 399
prejudice: in American law, 548n94;
in Canadian law, 407;
and democracy, 370;
against divorced fathers, 607n42;
and “equity,” 322;
and hate crimes, 569n127;
and ideological epistemology, 274;
and ideological feminism, 260, 311;
and political correctness, 369–70;
in rape trials, 226–7, 229;
and women’s studies, 369–70, 467. See also discrimination, hatred,
stereotypes
presumption of innocence, 17, 432
Prevette, Jonathan, 48–9, 502n36
priest pedophiles, 3, 8
Princeton University, 200
privacy, 570n145
propaganda, 508n53
proportional representation, 93, 106–7, 110, 400
Prose, Francine, 205
prostitution: 159–92;
in American law, 162–3, 541n11, 560n23;
in brothels, 541n11;
in Canadian law, 163–7;
and drugs, 162;
and exit programs, 166;
in ideological feminism, 165–6;
and “johns,” 165–7, 542n28;
and linguistic inflation, 97;
and marriage, 183, 186–7;
and minors, 187;
and misogyny, 160;
and penalties, 165, 542n28;
and pimps, 542n25;
possible solutions to, 189–91;
and range of status, 161;
as rape, 165–6, 198, 501n11;
as sexual harassment, 160–2;
statistics on, 190, 541n11, 542nn26, 28;
on streets, 541n11;
and violence, 160–1, 162, 187–91, 542n26;
and the World Conference on Women (Beijing), 399
Protection of Children against Sexual Exploitation Act (United States), 342
Proulx, Marie-Claude, 293–9, 471–7, 581nn93, 95, 96, 582nn97, 99, 104,
105
Provost, Nathalie, 504n30
Pryor, Kelli, 390
psychoanalysis, 344–5, 381, 384, 495nn17, 26, 599n40
psychotherapists, 11, 12–14, 55
Puritanism. See Christianity, sexual harassment
quasi-religiosity, xii;
and affirmative action, 408;
and coming-out stories, 374–5;
and “Goddess” revival, 615n14;
and ideological feminism, 314, 319;
and the Montreal Massacre, 67–71, 98, 292–3;
and rape, 314;
and secular ideologies, 586n9;
and sexual harassment, 208, 314;
and the Sophia movement, 615n14;
and Wicca, 615n14;
and the World Conference on Women (Beijing), 401–2. See also
Montreal Massacre, Take Back the Night
Quayle, Dan, 534n96
Quebec, 324–5
Quebec Pay Equity Commission, 413
quotas. See affirmative action
R. v. Bernardo, 568n122
R. v. Butler, 173–5, 547nn75, 82
R. v. Ewanchuk, 262–3, 573n179
R. v. Gayme, 229
R. v. Keegstra, 172, 174
R. v. Seaboyer, 229–30, 232, 568n122
radical feminism. See ideological feminism
radicalism. See revolutionism
Rae, Stephen, 8, 9
Ramsey, JonBenét, 343
rape: alleged uniqueness of, 253–6;
ambiguity of, 571n163;
in American law, 224–6, 248, 251–3, 557n8, 558n21, 572n174;
in Canadian law, 228–30, 252–3, 262, 561n42, 572n176;
and consent, 171–2, 178, 186, 196–7, 225, 229–30, 259, 262–3,
572n176, 573n179;
and cultural coercion, 251;
definitions of, 249–63, 572n174;
domestic violence as, 358, 362;
double standards on, 260–1, 263, 264;
and drinking, 264;
in egalitarian feminism, 178, 259;
and heterosexuality, 171–2, 178, 186, 211;
and “eroticization of male power,” 177–8, 196–8, 209, 230, 245;
and freedom of the press, 561n42;
in Gone with the Wind, 377–80;
as a hate crime, 251;
in ideological feminism, 97, 171–2, 175, 197, 229–30, 248–51, 259,
311, 544n41, 545n42;
and implied consent, 262–3;
and kissing, 262;
and linguistic inflation, 249, 259, 262, 311, 358;
male victims of, 256–7, 265;
and physical coercion, 250–1;
in popular culture, 188, 248–9;
and pornography, 198;
and prostitution, 198, 501n11;
and psychological coercion, 250–1;
seduction as, 259, 262;
sexual harassment as, 194, 198–201, 207, 249–50;
and statistics abuse, 362–4;
as a subjective experience, 229–30;
and suing for damages, 558n21;
as trump card, 224, 248–50, 259;
and violence, 160–1, 162, 187–91;
and withholding consent, 211
rape trials: in American law, 224–6, 251–2, 253, 261;
in Canadian law, 228–30, 252–3, 568n122;
and objective evidence, 259;
and rape-shield laws, 224–30, 258–61, 557n12, 568n122;
and subjective stories, 259;
and victim-impact statements, 259
Rapp, Geoffrey Christopher, 134, 351–2, 591nn10, 11
Re D.P., 568n122
REAL Women, 307
reality shows: The Apprentice, 159;
and “objectification,” 159
recovered-memory syndrome, 3, 6, 9, 14–16, 19, 495n27, 496n34. See also
alien abductions
Regents of the University of California v. Bakke, 88
religion. See civil religion; quasi-religiosity
religious analogies: anti-Judaism and misandry, 596n9;
Christian self-sacrifice and sacrifice by the state, 604n22;
Holocaust memorials and Montreal Massacre memorials, 67, 69
religious fundamentalism: in Christianity, 341, 574n6, 587n11;
and ideological feminism, 551n112;
in Islam, 369;
and political correctness, 41, 207, 341, 574n6
Rendell, Steven, 359
Renner, Edward, 61
Reno, Janet, 524n13
repressed memories. See recovered-memory syndrome
reproductive autonomy. See ideological separatism
reproductive technologies, 153–5;
abortion 154, 341;
artificial insemination, 154, 211;
and ideological separatism, 153–4, 213;
parthenogenesis, 154;
sex selection, 154;
and single mothers, 152;
surrogacy, 154, 540n147;
in vitro fertilization, 154
revenge: in Christianity, 73;
and domestic violence, 24, 25;
in egalitarian feminism, 168–9;
as hatred, 25;
in ideological feminism, 26–8, 73, 169;
in Judaism, 73;
and justice, 367;
as misandry, 338;
and the Montreal Massacre, 65;
as political correctness, 367;
and victims, 24
revolutionism, xii;
cultural implications of, 318;
and equality of result, 92, 93, 96, 116;
and fronts, 318;
in ideological feminism, 267, 313–14, 318–19;
and infiltration, 318;
invisibility of, 318;
and justice, 507n51;
and misandry, xv;
and power, 313;
a quiet kind, 324–5;
and reformism, 313;
in the university, 313
Reynolds, Glenn, 536n123
Riccardi, Nicholas, 138
Rich, Adrienne, 387
Richards, Janet Radcliffe, 274–5
rights: American rhetoric of, 84, 510n30;
Canadian rhetoric of, 84, 307–8, 510n30;
of children, 125, 150–5, 393–4, 424, 125;
and collectivism, 84;
and conservatism, 84;
definition of, 82;
of fathers, 150–5;
historical background of, 82–4;
in ideological feminism, 317;
in individualism, 84;
and judicial activism, 304–8;
in liberalism, 84;
of the majority, 409;
of minorities, 409;
in natural law, 122;
of single mothers, 152;
and utopianism, 83;
of women, 81–156, 391–402. See also equality of opportunity, equality
of result, legal entitlements, legal immunities, legal protections,
women’s rights
Ringle, Ken, 359
Ritter, R., 482
rituals. See quasi-religiosity
Rogers, R. Mark, 149, 525n15, 529n61, 531n67, 537n128
Roiphe, Katie, 200, 201, 208, 279, 501n9
role models. See mentors
romance novels, 185, 373–90, 549n106, 596n1, 597n16
Romano, Carlin, 250
Romanticism. See neoRomanticism
Rothstein, Edward, 518n95
Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 287–8
Royal Canadian Mounted Police, 232
Royal Commission on New Reproductive Technologies (Canada), 153
rules of evidence. See Federal Rules of Evidence, rape
Rusch, Kristin, 284
Ruskai, Mary Beth, 274
sacrifice, 612n97. See also self-sacrifice
Safe Homes for Women Act (United States), 226
Safire, William, 365
Sagan, Carl, 9
St Jude de Laval hospital, 55, 58
Salem witch hunt. See witch hunts
satanic-ritual abuse, 1–12, 14, 19, 341, 495n26. See also alien abductions,
McMartin Preschool
scapegoats: and affirmative action, 104;
and ideological strategies, 324;
men as, x;
and the Montreal Massacre, 62;
and witch hunts, 16–19
scholarship, xiv, 74, 107, 269, 363;
as “engaged scholarship,” 269, 287, 300, 397, 614n3;
and freedom of expression, 368, 370;
in women’s studies, 287, 300, 306;
and the World Conference on Women (Beijing), 397. See also
women’s studies
science: and Afrocentrism, 574n6;
and animal-rights movement, 574n6;
and chaos theory, 272–3, 575n9;
and collectivism, 278;
and environmentalism, 574n6;
and ideological feminism, 270–6, 574nn5, 6, 7;
and objectivity, 270;
and political correctness, 271;
and postmodernism, 271–3, 278;
on reason, 574n6;
and religious fundamentalism, 270–1, 574n6;
and sex differences, 277;
and statistics, 349–50;
and universality, 278, 574n7;
and women, 574n7;
in women’s studies, 26, 41–2, 106, 202–3, 270, 274–5, 282, 573n4,
574nn5, 6, 7, 582n99.
Scopel v. Kreklewetz. See Kreklewetz v. Scopel
Seaboyer. See R. v. Seaboyer
secular religion. See quasi-religiosity
Sedgwick, John, 302
Seidenberg, Robert, 133, 144–5, 522n5, 524n13, 526n32
selective cynicism, xii, 278, 312–13, 368, 371, 432, 588n1
selective sensitivity, 368
self-defense defense, 21, 29, 499n14. See also temporary-insanity defense
self-hatred, 335
self-sacrifice, 612n97
Selinger, Stanley, 57
Sen, Amartya, 394
sensitivity training. See ideological indoctrination
separation, 155, 527n40. See also divorce
separatism. See ideological separatism
Sepler, Fran, 265
sex, 19, 176–7, 570n145.
See also femaleness, heterosexuality, homosexuality, maleness
sex differences, 97, 121–2, 201, 277
sex education, 341
sex selection. See reproductive technologies
sexism. See misandry, misogyny
sexual abuse. See molestation, rape
sexual assault. See rape, sexual harassment
sexual correctness, 194, 204–9, 220, 547n85. See also political correctness
sexual desegregation. See combat Sexual Experiences Survey, 357
sexual harassment, 31–52, 193–222;
in American law, 195–6;
in Canadian law, 196, 206–7;
by children, 48–9, 502n36, 502n37;
and consequentialism, 209;
and contact with men, 197, 199;
and control, 51;
defined by men, 40;
defined by women, 40, 50–51, 199, 202;
as discrimination, 195;
and dualism, 203;
and due process, 45, 208–9;
effect of debate on society, 218–22;
effect of debate on women, 555n91;
in egalitarian feminism, 196–218, 221;
and “eroticization of male power,” 177–8, 196–8, 209–10, 230, 245;
and evidence of crime, 209;
and evidence of harm, 196;
false accusations of, 209;
female victims of, 194, 204;
or flirting, 47, 500n4;
and freedom of expression, 195;
and gynocentrism, 201;
and the Hill-Thomas Debate, 37–8;
in ideological feminism, 196–218, 312;
and infantilization of women, 198, 221;
and insurance industry, 555n98;
intention of, 196, 202;
and legal theory, 202–3;
and lesbians, 198, 209;
and linguistic inflation, 44, 194, 198–9;
of men, 46–8;
and the mobilization of resentment, 315;
and prudery, 19, 205, 547n85, 548n90;
and political correctness, 207;
in popular culture, 33–4, 43, 46–7, 50, 205, 500n4, 501n12;
and pornography, 160–2;
possible solutions to, 51–2;
and postmodernism, 201–4;
as power, 201, 209;
and prostitution, 160–2;
and quasi-religiosity, 199, 200, 208;
as quid pro quo, 44, 51, 194, 198, 211;
rape as, 194, 198–201; 207, 249–50;
and “reasonable woman,” 201–4;
and “reeducation,” 207;
rise of, 49–50;
and sexual perspective, 201;
and statistics abuse, 39, 196, 200;
statistics on, 39, 43–4, 47, 196, 199, 200;
and teenagers, 501n9;
and vigilantism, 555n91;
and workplace environment, 40, 172, 195–6, 201–3;
“zero tolerance” for, 207, 220
sexual polarization: in education, 100;
effects on society, 507n52;
and fatherless families, 151;
and the Hill-Thomas Debate, 31, 50;
and ideological feminism, 77, 123;
institutionalization of, 325;
and misandry, 331, 338;
and the Montreal Massacre, 62, 75–6;
responsibility for, 507n52;
as a social fault line, 62;
and violence against women, 157;
and witch hunts, 18, 20
sexual segregation. See combat, ideological separatism
sexual stereotypes. See stereotypes
sexuality, 501n9
Shalala, Donna, 524n13
shelter movement. See domestic violence
Showalter, Elaine, 8, 10, 12, 19
Sieghart, Mary Ann, 141
silencing of men, 41, 370
silencing of women, 50, 168
Silverman, Earl, 363
Simpson, O.J., 315, 356, 361
single mothers: “biological clocks” of, 152;
and child abuse, 144;
and class, 153;
glorification of, 137, 151–3, 534n96;
historical background of, 151–3;
in popular culture, 152–3, 534n96;
popularity of, 539n14;
and problems of children, 530n65;
reproductive technologies for, 152;
and the “rights revolution,” 152;
social acceptance of, 152;
statistics on, 152–3, 251;
and the World Conference on Women (Beijing), 399. See also
children’s rights, fathers; single parents
Single Mothers by Choice, 153
single parents, 530n65
Sisterhood Is Global, 550n108
situation comedies: Ally McBeal, 500, 597n16;
Designing Women, 33–4;
and double standards, 40;
and fathers, 534;
Friends, 153;
Golden Girls, 40;
Men Behaving Badly, 239;
Murphy Brown, 534;
Sex and the City, 47, 153, 264;
and sexual harassment, 33–4, 500;
and sexual reputations, 264;
and single mothers, 152;
and violence against men, 239
Sixth Amendment (United States), 261
Smith, Carnell, 140, 147
Soady, Viki, 576n37
soap operas: Melrose Place, 47;
and sexual harassment, 47
social constructionism, 203, 209, 210, 271, 371
Social Security Act (United States), 129
socialization of boys. See masculinity
Society for Cutting Up Men, 550n107
Soever, Alar, 139–40, 149–50, 423–4, 531n66, 538n134
Solanas, Valerie, 185, 212, 474, 550n107
Soliciting Law (Canada), 163
Sommers, Christina Hoff, 279, 353, 358–61, 378–9
Sophia movement. See quasi-religiosity
Sopinka, John, 366–8
Sorensen, Elaine, 524n13
Special Committee on Custody and Access (Ontario), 434
Special Committee on Pornography and Prostitution (Canada), 163
Specter, Arlen, 36
Speigel, Herbert, 13
sports: and statistics abuse, 358–61;
Super Bowl Sunday, 358–61;
and violence against women, 358–61
sports shows: Super Bowl, 223–4;
and violence against women, 223–4
Spreading Misandry: critics of, 329–39;
on fronts, 465;
on honorary women, 472–3;
on ideology, 270, 473;
on masculine identity, 469;
on misandry in popular culture, 75, 266, 489;
and movies, 568n123, 592n21, 597n2;
on political correctness, 331;
on romance novels, 390;
on The Slap, 239;
on stereotypes, 290;
on women as fighters, 597n2
statistics: on affirmative action, 88, 99–100, 517n82;
on age discrimination, 521n112;
on alien abductions, 9, 350;
on anorexia, 360–1;
on battered men, 233–9, 354n64, 593n30, 594n44;
on battered women, 594n44, 233–9, 354–64, 593n30;
on biological fathers, 140, 534n94;
on black men, 119;
on Canadian Civil Liberties Association, 181;
on caste, 406;
on child abuse, 144;
on child custody, 433, 522n5, 524nn13, 14, 530n62, 531n66, 532n68;
607n42;
on child support, 139, 522n5, 524, 13, 530n64, 531n66;
and democracy, 348;
on divorce, 125, 132–5, 139, 351–2, 354, 356, 358, 360, 363, 522n5,
527n33, 591n11, 592n12;
on domestic violence, 233–9, 244, 354–64, 422, 498n13, 567n121,
593n30, 594n44;
on earning power, 427–8;
on education, 408, 493n1;
on father absence, 150;
on gay domestic violence, 244, 504n21, 567n109;
on Legal Education and Action Fund, 306–7;
and measurement scales, 594n44;
on men as daycare workers, 19;
on men at Montreal Massacre memorial, 67;
and modernity, 347–8;
on molestation, 8, 257, 494n. 12;
on molestation by women, 257;
on murder, 238, 565n81, 567n121;
on pay equity, 93, 113–14, 119, 413, 427;
on pedophilia, 8, 494n12;
on prostitution, 190, 541n11, 542nn26, 28;
on public opinion of witch hunts, 13;
on quotas, 88, 517n85;
on romance novels, 374, 549n106, 596n1;
and science, 349–50;
on sexual harassment, 39, 43–4, 47, 196, 199, 200;
on single mothers, 152–3, 251;
on suicide, 493n2, 528n52;
unreliability of, 44, 61, 196, 349–50, 542n26, 590n4, 594n44;
and variables, 236–7, 591n11, 592n12;
on violence, 567n121, 594n44;
on violence against men, 567n121, 571nn153, 156, 593n30, 594n44;
on violence against women, 61, 422, 567n121, 593n30;
on women as judges, 585n129;
on women as law students, 99, 304, 514n58;
on women in government jobs, 117;
on women’s studies, 287;
on workplace accidents, 114
statistics abuse, 347–64;
and anorexia, 360–1;
and bias, 350;
and battered men, 354–64;
and battered women, 354–64;
and child abuse, 144;
and child support, 120, 128–9, 133, 136, 426, 524n13;
data “aggregated” and “disaggre-gated,” 112, 113, 296, 315;
data “globalized” and “contextualized,” 582n104, 583n105;
and divorce, 132, 133, 139, 351–4, 591nn10, 11;
and domestic violence, 232, 236, 250, 354–64;
and double standards, 296, 582n104, 583n105;
and egalitarian feminism, 350–1;
and equality of result, 92, 313, 315;
of fathers, 150;
and female victims, 296, 354–64;
and feminism, 350–1, 363;
by ideological feminists, 296, 313, 347–64;
as an ideological strategy, 316–17, 324;
by journalists, 342;
by Legal Education and Action Fund, 306;
and manipulation of fear, 29, 555n91;
and March of Dimes, 359;
and methods, 348–9;
and molestation, 257;
and pay equity, 112, 117, 121;
and popular culture, 353–4, 358–60, 564;
and postmodernism, 350–1;
and rape, 362–4;
and sexual harassment, 39, 196, 200;
by Statistics Canada, 361–2;
and Super Bowl Sunday, 358–60;
and United Way, 363;
and violence against women, 61
Statistics Canada, 361–2
Status of Women Canada: and Charter of Rights and Freedoms, 90;
on child custody, 427;
on education, 471–7, 580n85;
and “engaged scholarship,” 614n3;
and feminist success, 307;
and financial backing, 427;
and ideological feminism, 289;
as a lobby group, 291–3, 511n32;
and Legal Education and Action Fund, 510n30;
and the World Conference on Women (Beijing), 94
Status of Women Supplement. See CAUT Bulletin
Steinem, Gloria, 45, 175–6, 318, 360, 578n62;
biographical background of, 579n72;
on populism, 580n78
Steiner, George, 287–8
Steinmetz, Suzanne, 354–6
stereoscopic model, 123
stereotypes, xi, 563n54;
and affirmative action, 98;
of Arabs, 369;
in Canadian law, 92;
and child custody, 435;
and comparative suffering, 389;
and democracy, 403, 407;
and discrimination, 311, 513n51;
and domestic violence, 245, 299, 486, 490, 563n54;
and double standards, 49, 390;
and equality of result, 403;
in court, 245–6;
in government reports, 75;
and gynocentrism, 514n58;
in ideological feminism, 18, 358;
of Jews, 335;
of minorities, 92, 403, 407;
of parents, 431;
and police, 246;
in popular culture, 290, 331–2, 373, 376, 378, 382, 592n21;
and rape, 263, 358;
in romance novels, 373, 376–80;
in schools, 475;
and science, 277–8;
and sexual harassment, 49, 513n51;
and Spreading Misandry, 290;
and violence, 75;
and witch trials, 12, 18;
and the World Conference on Women (Beijing), 396–7, 435, 601n15
stereotypes of men: black men, 32;
control freaks, 358;
evil or inadequate, xii, 36, 40, 246, 255, 260, 264, 309, 357, 373, 376,
378, 385, 390, 397, 475, 486, 592n21;
husbands, 592n21;
ignored by society, 27;
molesters, 12, 260, 263;
in popular culture, 373, 377, 378, 385, 389, 390;
in public opinion, 309;
sex addicts, 255;
sexual harassers, 40;
and self-defense, 299;
unfit parents, 431;
victims, 299;
violent aggressors, 245–6, 260, 263, 357–8, 475, 486;
wimps, 377
stereotypes of women: ditsy blonds, 33;
feminists, 27, 277–8;
lawyers, 514n58;
mothers, 431, 566n97;
nonviolent victims, 245, 358;
opponents of science, 277–8;
in popular culture, 290, 332, 373, 378, 390;
and rape, 261;
readers of romance novels, 382;
sexless beings, 36–7
Stern, Stephen, 101–2
Stoltenberg, John, 217–8
Straton, Jack C., 594n44
Straus, Murray, 233, 354–7, 594n44
Streetlight, 166
Strossen, Nadine, 176
Stroup, Atlee, 351–2
substantive equality. See equality of result
suffering. See comparative suffering
suicide: of boys, 298;
of divorced men, 135, 138, 238, 529n53, 532n70, 533n71;
of Marc Lépine, 58–9;
and sex differential, ix, 493n2, 528n52
Sullivan, Philip, 351
Super Bowl Sunday. See sports; sports shows
surrogacy. See reproductive technologies
Sybil case, 5, 18
Symes v. Canada, 510n30
systemic discrimination. See discrimination
taboos, 17, 63–4
Take Back the Night, 200, 314
Take Our Daughters to Work Day, 290
talk shows: 48 Hours, 9–10;
on alien abductions, 9–10;
Charlie Rose, 359;
and the mobilization of resentment, 128, 315;
Nightline, 22–6;
Oprah Winfrey, 476;
Politically Incorrect, 365;
and popular psychology, 19, 203, 264, 278, 323, 612n97;
and statistics abuse, 128, 359–60
Tallentire, Jenea, 283, 576n37
targets. See quotas
Tarnower, Herman, 489
Tavris, Carol, 10, 18
Taylor, Helen, 379–80
teachers. See male teachers
television, xi, xiii, See also action shows, drama shows, news shows,
reality shows, situation comedies, soap operas, sports shows, talk shows
temporary-insanity defense, 22;
historical analogies to, 23;
of Lorena Bobbitt, 21, 23;
in popular psychology, 24. See also self-defense defense
tender-years doctrine. See child custody
Tennessee Secondary School Athletic Association. See Brentwood Academy
v. Tennessee Secondary School Athletic Association
Tepper, Lynn, 24
Teres, Susan, 200
therapy, 11–13, 478–92
Thierry, Michel, 56
Thomas, Clarence, 31–2, 198, 315, 342
Thomas, David, 363
Trafficking Victims Protection Act (United States), 163, 227
Tribe, Laurence, 181
Trociuk v. British Columbia (Attorney General), 534n101
truth, 106, 338, 368, 574n7. See also ideological feminist epistemology,
political correctness, postmodernism, scholarship
Tucker, Ken, 159
Twenty-seventh Amendment (United States), 86
Unemployment Insurance Act (Canada), 90
Uniform Crime Reporting (United States), 251
unions, 112, 114, 181. See also AFL-CIO
United Nations: Commission on Human Rights, 231;
Commission on the Status of Women, 391, 400;
Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination against
Women, 87, 90, 92, 392, 400;
Convention on the Rights of the Child, 393, 424;
Decade for Women, 391–2;
Declaration on the Elimination of Violence against Women, 436–7;
Development Fund for Women, 391–2;
Division for the Advancement of Women, 391;
and ideological feminism, 83, 307, 316, 401–2;
International Research and Training Institute for the Advancement of
Women, 391, 395;
International Women’s Day, 292, 293;
Optional Protocol, 392;
and postmodernism, 400;
on proportional representation, 93;
and quasi-religiosity, 401–2;
Universal Declaration of Human Rights, 393–5;
on violence against women, 428;
World Health Organization, 7. See also World Conference on Women
(Beijing)
United States v. Lanier, 568n122
United States v. Lopez, 536n123
United States v. Morrison, 536n123, 558n21
United States v. Timothy
Gordon Faase, 536n123
United Way, 363
Universal Declaration of Human Rights. See United Nations
Université de Montreal. See Montreal Massacre
university: and affirmative action, 106;
and democracy, 106;
as a government agency, 106;
as an ideological factory, 106;
as a microcosm of society, 106–7;
and political correctness, 204–7, 439;
purpose of, 206;
and revolutionism, 313;
and sexual correctness, 204–9. See also postmodernism, women’s
studies
University of Michigan, 88
University of Oklahoma, 500n8
University of Southern California, 467–8
utopianism, xii;
and equality of result, 83;
and ideological feminism, 184–5, 221, 314, 318, 437;
and Marxism, 320;
and rights, 83;
and totalitarianism, 121, 326;
and the World Conference on Women (Beijing), 402
Victimology, 478–92
victims: blaming them, 46, 65, 489;
as a class, x, 315, 336;
in court, 571, 167;
and domestic violence, 29;
and the Hill-Thomas Debate, 36–8;
historical background of, 203;
in legal theory, 202–4;
and the mobilization of resentment, 315;
and moral responsibility, 24;
in popular psychology, 203–4;
and pornography, 167;
and revenge, 24;
rhetoric of, 324, 326;
and sexual harassment, 203–4;
and victimizers, x, 95, 151, 169;
and witch hunts, 10. See also comparative suffering, female victims,
male victims
Victims Assistance Orders (Saskatchewan), 230
Victims of Domestic Violence Act (Saskatchewan), 230
Victims of Trafficking and Violence Prevention Act (United States), 162,
227, 541n10, 560n23. See also Trafficking Victims Protection Act
vigilantism, 507;
and the Bobbitt Affair, 21–9;
and domestic violence, 24–6, 73, 244;
and ideological feminism, 544n41;
and the Montreal Massacre, 73;
and pornography, 341;
and sexual harassment, 555n91
Vinson, Mechelle, 198–9. See also Meritor Savings Bank v. Vinson
violence, 74–5;
and child custody, 424–38;
by fathers, 425–38;
and freedom of expression, 367–8;
and linguistic inflation, 69, 157;
in popular culture, 64, 75, 176, 188–9;
and pornography, 160–1, 187–91, 383;
and rape, 160–1, 162, 187–91;
in schools, 503n3;
by women, 565nn77, 81, 593n30. See also domestic violence, violence
against men, violence against women
violence against men, 571;
and hijackers, 64;
and ideological feminism, 71, 224;
and molestation, 345–6;
and murder, 565n77;
in popular culture, 188, 212, 239;
and rape, 256–7, 265;
statistics on, 567n121, 571nn153, 156, 593n30, 594n44;
by women, 233–48, 354–64, 565nn77, 81, 567n121, 593n30See also
battered men, domestic violence
violence against women, 354–64;
in American law, 224–8;
in Canadian law, 228–31;
and child custody, 424–38;
and heterosexuality, 224;
in ideological feminism, 53, 64–5, 69, 71, 76–7, 170, 224, 312, 424–
38, 569n127;
as ideological paradigm, 224;
as an ideological trump card, 157;
and linguistic inflation, 224;
murder, 565n77;
in popular culture, 223–4, 248–9;
and power, 241–2;
and statistics abuse, 61;
statistics on, 567n121;
and the World Conference on Women (Beijing), 399. See also battered
women, domestic violence, rape
Violence against Women Act (United States), 225, 226–28, 558nn17, 21;
and civil courts, 227;
and the Commerce Clause, 536n123;
historical background of, 227;
and ideological feminism, 569n127;
and linguistic inflation, 569n127;
and politics, 569n127;
and United Nations, 428
Violence against Women Office (United States), 89, 289, 228
Violence against Women Survey, 232, 422
Violent Crime Control and Law Enforcement Act. See Violence against
Women Act (United States), 225
Vobejda, Barbara, 524n13
wage gap. See pay equity
Wagner Act (United States), 87
Walker, Lenore, 22, 27, 244–5, 357–8, 480
Wallace, K.L., 257
Wallis, Peter, 141
Walters, Barbara, 489
war: and comparative suffering, 70–74;
and conscription of men, 241, 505n32, 612n97;
Marc Lépine’s interest in, 56–7;
and masculine identity, 333;
and self-sacrifice, 612n97;
and sexual desegregation, 67;
Vietnam War, 333–4;
World War II, 333–4
Warhol, Andy, 212, 248
Warrants of Entry (Saskatchewan), 230
Watch Out, Listen Up! See National Organization for Women
Weatherall v. Canada, 118, 510n30
Webb, Maureen, 513n51
Weitzman, Lenore, 133–4, 351–4, 523n12, 526n32, 591n10
Welfare Reform Act (United States), 130
White, Darrin, 532n70
Whitehead, Barbara Dafoe, 523n12, 530n65
Wicca. See quasi-religiosity
wife abuse. See domestic violence
Williams, Patricia, 301
Williams, Robert, 139
Williams v. Saxbe, 195
Willick v. Willick, 428
Wilson, Bertha, 92, 96
Wilson, K.C., 138, 524n13, 533n77
Winfrey, Oprah, 476
Wisconsin v. Mitchell, 548n94
witch hunts, 3–20;
causes of, 17;
and child custody, 16–17; 18, 19;
decline of, 12–14;
defining, 8;
government complicity in, 495n27;
and the Hill-Thomas Debate, 33;
and ideological feminism, 17–20;
and the Internet, 12;
McCarthy prototype of, 8, 14, 33;
and the McMartin preschool, 3–4, 5, 11, 13, 16, 33, 315;
and molestation, 340–6;
and political correctness, 10;
political subtext of, 340–6;
as projections of underlying stress, 16;
Salem prototype of, 12, 14, 33;
spread of, 10–12;
targets of, 14, 17, 18, 19;
See also multiple-personality disorder, recovered-memory syndrome,
satanic-ritual abuse
Wolf, Naomi, 27, 193–4, 360
women: abuse of, 11, 22–9;
and daycare, 16;
empowerment of, 64;
and fashion, 556n101;
in government jobs, 117;
and heterosexuality, 211–13, 384;
and housework, 527n40;
and identity, 69, 420;
and journalists, 63;
as judges, 585n129;
in the labour force, 194;
as law students, 99–100, 304, 514n58;
and misandry, 215;
networks of, 288–93;
and “objectification,” 159–60, 170, 172, 180;
in popular culture, 64, 333, 597n2;
and pornography, 169–76, 180;
and post-modernism, 277;
power of, 47, 83, 197, 204, 222, 593n30;
as researchers, 519n97;
and romance novels, 373–90;
and science, 574n7;
and self-sacrifice, 612n97;
social skills of, 65;
and violence, 233–48, 354–64, 563n54, 565nn77, 81, 567n121,
593n30
Women’s Bureau. See Department of Labor (United States)
Women’s Law Journal of Legal Theory and Practice, 301
Women’s Legal Education and Action Fund. See Legal Education and
Action Fund
women’s rights: in American law, 84–9;
through bureaucracy, 84;
in Canadian law, 84, 89–98;
as entitlements, 84;
and human rights, 81–124, 392–4;
and legislation, 84;
and motherhood, 125–56;
and the World Conference on Women (Beijing), 83, 391–402
women’s studies: and dissent, 281, 287;
and empowerment, 279–81;
as “engaged scholarship,” 269, 287, 300, 306, 397, 614n3;
as “feminist studies,” 286, 578n59;
as a front, 282–6, 321, 465–70, 576nn31, 37, 577nn39, 45;
or “gender studies,” 286, 577n59;
as group therapy, 280–2;
and gynocentrism, 280–1, 287;
and heterosexuality, 282;
as ideological feminism, 267–300, 308, 320, 465–70;
and the Internet, 288–91;
jargon of, 287, 578n62;
and law, 300–8;
as a lobby group, 287;
and men, 465–70;
and misandry, 280, 282, 286, 287;
and networks, 288;
and “outing,” 287;
the “personal is political” in, 279;
and political activism, 281–2;
and political correctness, 281, 578n62;
and postmodernism, 285;
and proselytism, 281–2;
and the publishing industry, 287–8;
on science, 26, 41–2, 106, 202–3, 270, 274–5, 282, 573nn4, 5, 6, 7,
582n99;
and statistics abuse, 287. See also ideological feminist epistemology
Woods, Gloria, 420
workplace environment. See sexual harassment
World Conference on Women (Beijing), 393–5, 437;
on affirmative action, 400, 402;
Beijing Annex, 392, 396–400;
Beijing Declaration, 392–3, 395–6;
Beijing Platform for Action, 392, 395–8;
and Canadian Beijing Facilitating Committee, 94;
and Canadian Beijing Preparatory Committee, 94;
on children’s rights, 393–4;
and democracy, 402;
on “engaged scholarship,” 397;
and Equal Rights Amendment (United States), 402;
on equality of opportunity, 400;
on equality of result, 90, 92, 391–402;
on the family, 393–4, 399;
on fathers, 399;
and gynocentrism, 392–402;
from human rights to women’s rights, 392–3, 399;
and ideological feminism, 391–402;
and lesbian mothers, 399;
and misandry, 394;
on misogyny, 399;
on mothers, 399;
on proportional representation, 400;
on religion, 395, 398–9;
on pay equity, 400;
on power, 399;
on prostitution, 399;
rhetorical strategies of, 395–8;
on single mothers, 399;
on stereotypes of women, 396–7, 601n15;
and utopianism, 402;
on violence against women, 399;
Western dominance at, 394–5, 398;
on women’s poverty, 394;
on women’s rights, 83, 392–402
World Court. See United Nations
World Health Organization. See United Nations
Wright, Lawrence, 15
Wuornos, Aileen, 249
Wynrib. See Norberg v. Wynrib
Yale Law Journal, 301
Yale University, 193–4
Yapko, Michael, 15
Yates, Stephen, 103
Young, Cathy, 353
Zorychta, Edith, 469–70

You might also like