the-film-cheat-screen-artifice-and-viewing-pleasure-9781501364990-9781501364983-9781501364952-9781501364969_compress
the-film-cheat-screen-artifice-and-viewing-pleasure-9781501364990-9781501364983-9781501364952-9781501364969_compress
the-film-cheat-screen-artifice-and-viewing-pleasure-9781501364990-9781501364983-9781501364952-9781501364969_compress
ii
The Film Cheat
Screen Artifice and Viewing Pleasure
Murray Pomerance
BLOOMSBURY ACADEMIC
Bloomsbury Publishing Inc
1385 Broadway, New York, NY 10018, USA
Bloomsbury Publishing Inc does not have any control over, or responsibility for, any third-
party websites referred to or in this book. All internet addresses given in this book were
correct at the time of going to press. The author and publisher regret any inconvenience
caused if addresses have changed or sites have ceased to exist, but can accept no
responsibility for any such changes.
To find out more about our authors and books visit www.bloomsbury.com and sign up for
our newsletters.
Don’t drag your tricks, but work as quickly as you can, bearing in
mind the Latin proverb, “Make haste slowly.”
HARRY HOUDINI
Not even the best magician in the world can produce a rabbit out of
a hat . . . if there isn’t already a rabbit in the hat.
LERMONTOV (ANTON WALBROOK) IN THE RED SHOES
vi
For
Stanley Cavell (1926–2018)
in cherished memory
and for
Abraham Kaplan (1918–93)
Who taught us both
Acknowledgments xii
OF SCRIPTS 11
1 Yesterdays 13
3 Narrative Transparency 23
5 Narrative Opacity 39
9 Only Pretending 68
10 Keeping Minutes 72
OF PERFORMANCES 79
11 Monster! 81
13 Pain 93
14 Measuring Up 98
x CONTENTS
15 Privacy 104
16 Dance 121
17 Keyed Up 127
20 Surrender 149
OF CAMERAS 153
21 Corral 155
22 Show Me 167
27 Moving On 199
29 Peek-a-Boo 205
OF SCENES 211
35 Heist 245
37 Stand-ins 257
OF JOINS 267
39 Believe in Me 269
41 Sequitur 278
46 By Contrast 308
FIGURE Campbell Scott and Rebecca Pigeon at Logan Airport in The Spanish
Prisoner (David Mamet, Jasmine Productions/Jean Doumanian Productions, 1997).
What I do is, I pretend to be the person I’m portraying in the film or play.
[. . .] You’re confused. It’s perfectly simple, a case in point: Lord of the
Rings. Peter Jackson comes from New Zealand, says to me, “Sir Ian, I
want you to be Gandalf the Wizard,” and I say to him, “You are aware
that I am not really a wizard.” And he said, “Yes I am aware of that, what
I want you to do is use your acting skills to portray the wizard for the
duration of the film.” So I said, “Okay,” and then I said to myself, “Mm,
how would I do that?” And this is what I did: I imagined what it would
2 THE FILM CHEAT
Yet, beyond that cinema is positively filled with people (actors) pretending
to be people other than they “really” are, which is to say, other than
they would be pretending to be (outside the critical view) were they not
acting in cinema. This is the much discussed actor/character formula, the
transformation that occurs inside the work of art. To be prosaic to a fault,
McKellen plays Gandalf quite compellingly but, as he himself knows, he
is not Gandalf. (Actually there is no Gandalf, beyond the word “Gandalf”
on Tolkien’s page and the screenplay, and the figure who moves about the
film thanks to McKellen’s pretending—with a long white beard and a tall
staff, and on a horse.) Cinema is not only filled with such performances and
performers but can be imagined only in the very abstract without them.
However, cinema offers a much-repeated, and fascinating, stretching
of the rules of transformation. Imagine this: for one or another dramatic
reason, there is a moment onscreen in which a character (already the
work of an actor pretending to be the person being portrayed) is required
in the story to act—to pretend to be a different person, not the character
we have been watching the actor achieve but someone distinctly other. In
Following from the enlightening work on “passing” by Harold Garfinkel, I give in An Eye for
1
Two distinct issues of deeper interest are raised by the film actor’s
pretended pretending.
Visible Seams. First, a cool, even, and revealing illumination is spread
across the surface of any one film, and then of fictional cinema everywhere,
showing up the delicate seam between the characters with whom we are
engaged in our watching and the actors we (persistingly) act as though we
do not see. The very idea of acting, of putting on, of pretending is raised
explicitly to view, even spoken about. We can note that these people of the
screen world generally act as though things are quite different from this, as
though we do not see them acting, but in fact we do see. And seeing while
acting as though we do not see we, too, are pretending. As an audience, we
pretend to be “not in the know” yet know that we are very much in the
know. At least when confronted with familiar stars it is virtually impossible
not to see that they are the folk they are while earnestly proclaiming
themselves to be other, Celebrated Other, especially impossible if one has
spent heavy money to see the film—or time downloading it—on the basis
of the actors’ fame. Again, we spy on Gandalf but we know Ian McKellen
is there, too. The performative fiction may be brought more fully to life,
become more electric and more present, when we watch unfamiliars, men
and women we have not already learned to recognize as “themselves.” This
is often the case with children. Christian Bale was only a pre-adolescent
prodigy when he shot Empire of the Sun (1987), amazing to watch yet
otherwise unknown. The same went for Nicholas Hoult in About a Boy
(2002) and Patty Duke in The Miracle Worker (1962). And for Leonardo
DiCaprio in What’s Eating Gilbert Grape (1993).2 With such actors, we can
know superficially and generally that “acting” is going on, without actually
teasing out the actor at work inside the character. With established stars it
is entirely different. To watch Mankiewicz’s The Barefoot Contessa (1954)
is to see not Maria Vargas but Ava Gardner as Maria Vargas, not Harry
Dawes who makes Maria into a star but Humphrey Bogart (who already
is one). At the beginning of Minnelli’s The Band Wagon only a year before,
we had seen the famous movie star Ava Gardner as the famous movie star
Ava Gardner; but that screened “famous movie star” inhabited a different
universe than the woman who was playing her. That diegetic “Ava” was able
to interact with Tony Hunter (Fred Astaire) because she knew that he and
she were both in the entertainment business and had achieved fame there,
but the Ava underneath “Ava” had no truck with Tony, could never touch
him, although she was able to interact with, and make more than one film
with, Fred Astaire (they reunite working together in On the Beach [1959]).
If we are constantly aware of actors putting on their characters, if we
always know there is a seam, and if we can make our awareness routine
2
Bale, Hoult, Duke, and DiCaprio had all done work before these breakout performances, but
not with wide popular recognition.
PREAMBLE 5
few players, all looking different from one another and no one of them self-
identifying as a game player while playing. In sport, all the many players
wear identical uniforms; in the case I wish to point to, there are no uniforms
of any kind. This is the con movie, the film about an ignorant “mark” being
taken in by a group of performers not recognized as such. The donning
of the interior role-within-the-role is very often not shown at first, so that
initially we accept the put-on “characters” as true characters themselves.
Only later, for the viewer’s pleasure, is the con artist revealed to have
scripted, produced, directed, and often starred in a supposed “real action”
that was in fact only a show within the show. In an extreme form, with the
con game being elaborated at very great length and in very minute detail,
the “reveal” might come so late that we barely catch sight of the performers
beneath the “characters” at all. They might seem to be strangers.
At the con film’s crisis moment, some high point of dramatic probability
is reached as we take note of what the complicated charade was all for: a
great deal of money suddenly revealed to have been stolen, a rare museum
piece revealed as a clever forgery, and so on. Our noting suggests that there
has been produced for the film’s audience a moment of stunning awareness
in which the guying-up of performance is put on show for itself, in the center
ring of the circus as it were, with lighting apparently showing all of its parts:
“Look at the little show we have given!!” Now it is undeniable that a trick
has been in progress, a cheat. And not only some of the characters you’ve
watched but you yourselves have been taken in: you, seduced and deluded,
just as they were. In the con film this reveal is central to the emotional turn,
a vital requirement.3 The resolving mechanism is as blunt as it is curious:
seeing that some onscreen characters have been duped, the viewer, feeling
superior because safely outside, presumes that no duping has affected him
or her. One can both know one was cheated and avoid seeing that one was
cheated simultaneously. Perhaps with pleasure, one projects one’s own state
onto the figures of the screen.
* * *
The con film isn’t the same as the heist film. In the latter, the victim typically
does know he has been taken. And focus is given to elaborate methods
of penetrating a defensive shield that is extremely patent to begin with:
3
Erving Goffman’s “On Cooling the Mark Out,” a classic analysis of cons, indicates how in
actual practice the discovery by the victim (the “mark”) that he has been taken in, is potentially
disruptive to success. So a process is put in place (“cooling out”) that disengages him from
social contact with those who have been running the game but in a way that is rationalized
in terms of everyday discourse (someone has bought a house in another city and is moving,
etc.). While cooling out is beneficial for actual con artists, it is inutile in producing audience
catharsis.
PREAMBLE 7
{1} Yesterdays
Facial recognition aphasia; with and without a memory; Oliver Sacks, “The
Lost Mariner”; access to “a past”; character transports
I had lunch recently with a man I’ve known a very long time, an old friend,
who confessed something I had never realized, that he suffered from
facial recognition aphasia, the manifest inability to recognize faces. Not
discriminate: recognize. He could see just fine, but he could not absolutely
be sure he would know what he was seeing. Recognize: to affix a nominal
label to a face one knows one has seen before, somewhere, sometime, and
a face one can certainly tell apart from other faces. He could know with
certainty that he had seen a face but not be able to put a name to it. With
me he had no trouble, he said, but there were many others who would
approach him amicably but leave him confounded, since although he knew
14 THE FILM CHEAT
that somehow he knew them he could not say (to himself) who they were,
could not address them by name.
Many people have trouble remembering other people’s names, sometimes
needing several repetitions (and perhaps even then remaining unable to
retain the information), yet they know that the name is something they
know, even though at the moment it is unretrieved and seems unretrievable.
They have it but have misplaced it. (The mental “room” in which one stores
such things is, apparently, chock full of items of all kinds, so many that
Charles Foster Kane’s Xanadu seems meager by comparison.) FRA produces
a strange, alienating sensation in which a person’s name is not unretrievable
from the vaults of memory but seems instead to be absent from the vaults
altogether. Instead of “I can’t recall (re-call) your name,” it’s a case of “I
don’t know your name.” (I don’t know, I have never heard, your face has
never been associated with a name.) A great deal of what is mentally elided,
then, is the past.
Happily our lunch went; fantastic Cobb salads with cold poached shrimp!
My old friend treated me warmly, as a dear familiar, and we had a splendid
time chewing over our two lives, together. He never once used my name as
here now I, for quite different reasons, step aside from using his.
The peculiar reason I adduce this anecdote is that it illustrates something
far more widely diffused than naming and name-forgetting, a particular
odd interactional situation in which, notwithstanding an aphasic’s (queer,
personal) sense that he himself did not know a person he was recognizing
(from a point of view similar to what would be taken up by others), he could
also present himself openly, dramatically, as someone without a memory:
not only someone who doesn’t know a name that is not on the tongue but
someone who is not knowing something he reasonably should—so very
reasonably should, indeed, that his not knowing is an indicator of lost time,
a horrible gap between then, when the name was on the register, and now,
when it is gone. Let the aphasic protest he is not exactly forgetting, forgetting
is not quite the word: no matter. He becomes a notable case of someone who
apparently cannot delve into his past, cannot travel backward, when any
and all of us ought to be able to do so.
When any and all of us ought to be able to move backward at will.
“Of course,” all normals routinely journey backward, one supposes;
everyone and anyone can (and should show that she can) bring up a
recollection. I remember going to the Museo del Historia Natural y Cultura
with you and eating queso fundido. Such “memoryless” figures as my lunch
partner could be taken to be may well give the appearance of living entirely
in the present, exactly and explicitly because they do not openly stage
retrievals. Note: the open staging of a retrieval. I am reminded some of
Oliver Sacks’s “lost mariner,” victim of a severe Korsakov’s, whose present
was more or less his world: “I wondered, when I first met him, if he was
not condemned to a sort of ‘Humean’ froth, a meaningless fluttering on the
YESTERDAYS 15
surface of life” (39). But Sacks is making a diagnosis, giving the claim to
be looking in. I am referring to the individual’s performance of having no
memory.
Certainly to openly stage a retrieval—I Remember Mama (1948)—is to
identify oneself as having a history (and fake retrievals can be arranged so
as to accredit a newcomer to the game with the bona fides of the longtime
player). Further, one transmits an open signal about such a history when one
gives a notably clear and open staging of retrieval from the past, one displays
knowing oneself to have been placed before, and therefore to be placed
now, in a temporal context. (A) There was a before; (B) I was participant
to that before; (C) I here now point directly to it and thereby (D) credit
my participation then and my pointing now. The facial recognition aphasic
notably fails to give this signal with specific regard to other people, is easily
taken as having no subjectively accessible past in which human encounters
happened. Surely there must be a past, the person could not have been born
yesterday; yet there appears no regard for or access to it. The past has no
present meaning for the being who is ahistorical, and the social past has no
present meaning for the facial recognition aphasic.
Open retrieval of information from “historical” files, the invocation of
“remembered” names, directions, warnings, estimations, preferences, pet
peeves, awkward situations, glorious achievements is a signal feature of what
we call “normal” behavior, and when memory of this “typical,” “everyday”
kind seems to be blocked we anticipate the employment of one of a limited
number of permissible excuses to both explain and bandage the situation.
Momentary confusion, for example: “Oh, sorry, I didn’t quite get what you
asked me”; understandable stress: “Oh gosh, you have no idea how bad this
migraine is!”; not having had coffee yet: “I can’t do anything first thing in
the morning!” Part of what makes for a condition we would call “real” is
a presentation of self that includes actual or demonstrably possible open
retrievals or, as above, reasonable accounts for their absence. Seeming to
have nothing to fall back on, a person could be displaced from the real.
But the everyday, casual reading of others, just like psychiatric and
neurological diagnosis, is similar to watching movies, at least because in
both cases evaluation of a (character’s) personality is tagged to the way he
or she gives patent signals of both perception and memory: the character can
see a red light as a red light; she remembers that a moment ago it was green;
she knows that while then she could have driven through the intersection
now she cannot (i.e., then is not now). Excepting in comedic situations,
and working on the assumption that names have somewhere in the story
already been shared, the character who mistakes another character’s name
signals a quirky, but at the same time symptomatic, relation with the past.
Martin Scorsese plays a marvelous take on this problem in The King of
Comedy (1982) with the receptionist at the Jerry Langford Show offices
(Margo Winkler) who is confronted by Rupert Pupkin (Robert De Niro)
16 THE FILM CHEAT
again and again and again and again and again but can never quite get his
name right. The first time De Niro puts on a charitable smile of toleration,
as though to say, “My name gives a lot of people trouble, has always done
so, and I can remember that, so it’s no surprise it’s giving you trouble, too.”
But also—and here is the charity, “I am telling you this because I also know,
from past experience, that you might get flustered or embarrassed or feel
you have done me an offense, and I want to assure you that’s not the case.”
Yet he is not picking up on the possibility that to her he is a nobody already,
since only people with appointments show up at this desk; one of the legion
members of the great urban crowd, whose name one is under no obligation
to know. Or that she’s distracted. Or that she doesn’t like him for some
reason. Later on, when she persists in niggling with the name, he makes a
correction that is curt and demands to get past her—a clear indication that
from his point of view, she has failed at a crucial task and now, yes, indeed
produced some offense, so that she ought to be, not embarrassed or flustered
but, reproached—not that he has the authority to go about reproaching her.
Note that it is Winkler’s character whose genuineness is dubious, first to us
and not long later to Rupert; the actress is genuinely there throughout.
What viewers calculate about a character is a kind of diagnosis itself,
a positioning of the subject on a scale of believable normality not much
different from the scale we all use in everyday life. The people we meet
within our “reality” are, each, more or less real, depending on how they
seem placed in long time. As we might tag the people we meet with various
identities, surely with the tag we would call “real,” we tag film characters,
and they tag one another. That means that reality is up for grabs here,
particularly the reality of the artifice. The people we take to be present
“really,” to be fully and unquestionably sharing our reality, can show or
recount (and can reveal that they can show or recount) what they have just
finished doing; or what they did an hour ago; or what happened yesterday
or when they were only children (or give reasonable accounts for failures
at this). Winkler’s receptionist isn’t present “really.” Those who are, move
around here and now; but they also dip backward in time. This dipping
into the past and reconfiguration of its content into present anecdote or
reference, embedded in conversation if not in behavior more generally, is
what rounds a figure out as genuine rather than ersatz and simulated. I
exist now, fully and roundly, but I have also existed before, here or in other
places, in like or unlike situations, versions of which I could extract, re-
form, and present evidentially here and now. I can “quote myself.” I am here
because I took a path in order to arrive, and I can recollect at least some of
the landscapes visible from that path. The formula works in reverse, too. If
to seem real a character must share a past in the present, when a character
shares a past he or she seems real: a useful tip for writers and actors, who
might inadvertently focus too strongly on what is to come: have someone
just remember something; anything; just like that.
YESTERDAYS 17
JIMMY: Why do I do this every Sunday? Even the book reviews seem to
be the same as last week’s. Different books—same reviews. Have you
finished that one yet?
CLIFF: Not yet.
JIMMY: I’ve just read three whole columns on the English Novel. Half
of it’s in French. Do the Sunday papers make you feel ignorant?
Because for a character The Past is an actorial and script invention, in plain
fact any character who behaved onscreen as though he or she had no access
to a past would be the realest possible character, but far too real, since our
game of nominating realism doesn’t buy this. We expect that any and every
real present—and the character is really present—has, for those who share
it, a precedent that only the wounded fail to access. The presence of the
character, like the presence of any one of us in a social scene, is modulated,
rounded out, nuanced by memories and hopes—hopes congruent with
memories.
To unmodulated extreme presence, presence in the here and now and
only in the here and now, a kind of unreality, a phantasmal quality attaches,
as was the case with his patient originally for Oliver Sacks.
To some degree I am spelling out elements of a textbook for actors. They
have learned that in order to seem strange and inexplicable they need only
behave as though they don’t have, or cannot access, a past—that is, as though
1
Except in the case of sequels (not so very frequent), where their origins are indeterminate,
being recognized by some audience members and entirely unknown by others.
18 THE FILM CHEAT
they are precisely what they are as scripted, floating constructs embedded
inexplicably in a contrived “present” that has, and can have, no relation to
any other time. Go back for one moment to those lines from Look Back.2
Jimmy was found asking Cliff whether he has read this newspaper every
single time the play ran, night after night, hundreds of times in total on the
West End and then some two hundred and fifty times on Broadway, and,
newborn each time, Cliff said he hasn’t, without any memory of having
been asked before and having given the same answer, verbatim. Here is the
reality of the drama, now. But that each of these can invoke past time brings
on the reality of character. Performance is scripted and carried out with
continual flickering rear views. That a character can seem to have a past is
the cheat of the script. Seem to have a past: give the impression of thinking
back, wondering, trying to remember or speculate, frame an argument on
putatively accepted (earlier) principles. (Interrogation scenes work with this
reaching backward as a fundamental material.)
In most filmic scenes of transport, where a character separates the self
from present diegetic circumstances in order to wonder, to daydream, to
worry backward, to try against all hope to remember what is forgotten, to
reach beyond this—this thing that is the present, this Now—a great deal can
be accomplished by the actor playing with special genuineness two kinds of
scripted lines: (a) those that bring up (supposable) memories; and (b) those
attesting, with substantial reason (we are to believe) that memory is out of
the question (post-traumatic scenes). And ironically, the character who is to
seem vitally and dramatically present will seem to be that way if the script
allows for the actor embedding a present experience in what is to seem,
and what is to be claimed as, a memory—even if later that memory will be
known to be entirely made up and false. “Oh God yes!, I remember now!,”
with the eyes popped wide open. The act of “remembering” itself makes for
the “normally real.”
But the central peg in such a performance, this genuine quality of playing
a truth, this way of making, supporting, modeling, and dramatizing the
simple directness of yes!, having found the lost memory!!!, is finally a quality
that is always, for the actor doing the work, a forthright lie. Owing to the
fact that the actor knows what it is to remember a past—his lunch today, his
rehearsals, a former love affair—he can fake remembering a past quite well.
But the character: no. The character only ever claims to have a memory, since
the character is but surface. And especially in film, where we are separated
by the screen even as we are brought near the screen, the claims as claims are
2
This play was elemental in British “kitchen sink” drama of the 1950s, and is widely credited
with introducing the character of the “angry young man” into culture. In 1959 Tony Richardson
released a film version starring Richard Burton and Gary Raymond as “Jimmy” and “Cliff,” but
the stage play at the Royal Court Theatre, Sloane Square (May 8, 1956), had starred Kenneth
Haigh and Alan Bates.
YESTERDAYS 19
FIGURE 2 Margaret Hamilton (with Jack Haley, Judy Garland, and Bert Lahr in
the ball) in The Wizard of Oz (Victor Fleming, MGM, 1939).
On quite another order than memory is foretelling, the talent for seeing
what approaches from down the road, for helping us “eat the air, promise-
cramm’d.” To represent foretelling visually, David Lean constructs a scene
in Lawrence of Arabia (1962) where his protagonist, led into the farthest
reaches of the shining bleachy desert, stands with his guide near a solitary
TOMORROW AND TOMORROW AND TOMORROW 21
well. The guide makes bold to drink as Lawrence (Peter O’Toole) watches.
Blazing, almost incandescent sunlight, the sands whitened past exposure
limits, indistinguishable from the white sky. (We grasp why someone would
thirst for a drink there; and how disciplined Lawrence is by not going
along.) Suddenly, as he peers off toward the quivering horizon, Lawrence
sees (we see with him) a tiny dot bouncing. Now it grows a little larger and
seems, perhaps, just perhaps, a person. Dark against the white, hundreds of
millions of miles away. But growing larger and larger.
A sharp, sudden, reverberating shot.
And the guide lies dead.
Closer and closer and closer, until the rider can be made out, all dressed
in black, his face dark and glowing (Omar Sharif). “It was my well.”
Seeing what is far away in a future unknown. Seeing it coming. A very
carefully constructed shot, that took time and labor and a film stock with a
wide range of exposure.
Even the Wicked Witch of the West (Margaret Hamilton) does not do this
looking ahead as well with her crystal ball. She stares into it and it sends a
(television) view of what we are to believe is happening now, somewhere far
away. But to be far away now is not necessarily to be in the future of she
who gazes there.
To see and know what will happen. Because canny Lawrence somehow
knows to hold off from drinking.
As with any stage play, the film actor will have been given the script in
advance of shooting; will have been in a position to read it through, to grasp
the many nuances of action he or she will have to embody for the camera.1
In Scene 22 I shall be meeting a person for the first time, in a hotel bar, over
cocktails. In Scene 184 I shall be naked in bed with that person. In Scene 225
that person will put a bullet between my eyes.
Thus, regardless of the order in which scenes are finished in principal
photography, while Scene 22 is being played the actor will act as though
entirely without consciousness of, entirely without regard for—even
without a hint to—what is to be done in 184 and 225. In 225, the actor
facing that gun will be playing a character whose characterological “life”
earlier on, in Scene 22, at that bar, had a certain removed quality (that we
shared), therefore a character, now, who remembers that bar back then,
that introductory moment, that first drink. The performing aspect can be
simple: as memory in action can be shown only through insert shots; the
1
Speaking to Jeffrey Brown about his stage performance as Atticus Finch in To Kill a
Mockingbird (Shubert Theater, December 13, 2018), Jeff Daniels made the explicit point that
after as much as two years’ intense labor thinking through the character, learning all the lines,
imagining one’s way into the story, his method was to jettison all that as he walked onstage.
Éric Rohmer was reputed to use a similar technique when he went on scene to shoot. One has
it all, very securely, very intensively, and then one just walks on without it.
22 THE FILM CHEAT
It is not only the past that believable characters access onscreen. They also
travel forward, relentlessly, and sometimes there is a remarkable occurrence:
the beings we are watching even seem to pass through the fourth wall, cross
the axis, so that they gain a point of view remarkably similar to what has
been afforded to us in our seats. Point of view: knowledge, awareness,
curiosity. Note that a character suddenly sharing a viewer’s knowledge is
not at all the same as a viewer suddenly sharing a character’s.1 We can note
1
A condition outlined thoroughly by Thomas Scheff, and discussed here in Chapter 5.
24 THE FILM CHEAT
the strangeness of the effect when a character seems to have recognized that
in general viewers are jumping from place to place (having been made to
jump), and now, hinting at where he is intending to be, aids us by leaping
ahead, by being prepared to offer greeting as he arrives: we are not following
the action, categorically speaking, because in this case when Joe or Helen
moves from A to B we find ourselves at B beforehand. The character action
is following us. And by rights, as we think, it should: if we have jumped
forward to meet the character on arrival, he or she had best arrive where
we wait. (How wondrous, yet how inexplicable, it might seem if we were to
jump to a location where, next, nothing happened.)
An elegant example of the “transparent” jump can be found in
Michelangelo Antonioni’s Blow-Up (1966). There is a charming old junk
shop in southeast London, full of dusty treasures and enticing darkness.
Outside is a paved road leading up an easy slope toward a park. The
entrance to this park, as we can easily see, has tall trees with slender dark
trunks, side by side. A young photographer who has been scouting the junk
shop goes outside to catch a breath of air and starts, quite naturally for him,
to photograph the place, snip snap, snip snap, slowly backing away and up
the little rise toward the park but without seeing where his body is headed.
Snip. Snap. Snap. Snap.
We CUT.
We are now inside the park looking out at that little street, with the
photographer’s back turned our way and four trees directly in front of us,
separating us from him and the world outside. He turns our way, detects the
park, and walks up into it.
To make a conventional cut here, the editor would have lingered on the
photographer in the street until he stopped shooting and turned around:
turn the other way, see the park, then head up the rise to gain access. At some
instant just before he reached the entrance we would have cut to the inside,
now to be with him as he goes in—cutting inside only on the cusp of his
movement. His motion would lead the cut. Here, however, we see the park
before he does. We see it behind him, dwarfing him, enticing, beckoning. We
are enticed by the beautiful trees, waving in the wind, so green. We want to
go in there. The filmmaker (and his camera) permit us to do what we crave
to do. The character comes to “know” where we are, as it were, and moves
to join us. Our desire leads the cut.
In this way a character can behave as though he knows what we know
about the circumstances—what we know from watching this film of which
that character is unknowingly a part. It is not, after all, because we are
there that we spy that park. In a routine, obvious, and unannounced way
characters very generally open out action in front of audiences who are
watching action open out, and in doing this can be said to share if not
perspective at least sensibility. But here, in a specifically invoked way, a way
“out of the ordinary,” a character has knowledge that seems impossible or
NARRATIVE TRANSPARENCY 25
odd, surely eerie, except for the silent intervention of forces on the other
side of the camera (and the other side of the screen). On the other side of the
screen is to be found that viewer, divided away from the character (so that the
character’s pains do not become the viewer’s). A sharing on the character’s
part of the viewer’s knowledge, an awareness of where the viewer is about to
be, of where he should travel in order to meet the viewer’s (important) gaze,
can happen only if the veil of “the screen” becomes temporarily permeable or,
as I am calling it, transparent.2 Through the screen, as it were, the character
can sense us, see our moves, divine our desires, and sympathize. Narrative
transparency. This is a cheat, of course. Arrangements have been made so
that events will appear to unfold this way. As “our” camera has brought us
forward in space and time, the character “magically arrives” to be met by
us instead of captaining the action; and sometimes this odd dance plays out
when the new (second) location is by no means obvious from the old (first)
one. Blow-Up is a good example. The photographer did not at first appear
to see the park at all, was not enchanted as we were in watching it behind
his back, and could with equal diegetic logic, if he got tired shooting the
junk shop, just as easily walk to his car and drive off. It wasn’t a guaranteed
conclusion that he would head our way. In film the character can always
go “anywhere” but almost always directs herself in a way we must wait
to understand. In narrative transparency, the character seems to have read
the script and thus know in advance: this is transparency because not only
can characters not read the script; they do not even know there is a script.
Wondrously, moving to the spot where we wait presents no difficulties for
her to overcome. Very briefly, perhaps for only a flash, it is as though he or
she knows the audience—knows that an audience is there and knows the
“self” of that audience, but the character must also know that the audience is
watching a movie, this movie. This movie made by actors. Consequentially,
it is as though the character knows the actor who is underneath. Apparently,
both we and the actor—first we and then the actor—moved according to
some plan available only on this side of the camera. We followed a friendly
camera, and the actor knew how to go in our tracks.
Another version:
As part of an unfolding story—say a crime mystery—we are transported to
examine the inside of a character’s house or apartment. Prowling around there
with our chum the camera, we discover all the boring normalities that make
lives interchangeable to some degree: room hooked to room, certain interesting
pieces of furniture, a sofa, a bed, a table lamp. But lo and behold, what’s this?:
a secret hiding place! A little nook behind the sugar jar. Fascinating! But we’d
2
A transparency that goes beyond the organized puncturing invoked by Michel Chion in his
book La toile trouée, a structuring phenomenon that gives viewers intimate access to characters’
worlds. In narrative transparency a character has (appears to have) access to a viewer’s.
26 THE FILM CHEAT
better not linger too long (it somehow being the case that while we puttered
around the kitchen there was no threat of the inhabitant returning but the
moment we set finger into the secret chamber the return is imminent!). We
have discovered the secret spot, at any rate, have gone where no one but the
absent resident has gone before. We’ve made a step. Imagine now that we
leave the scene and the film action continues. Later on, another character,
one we recognize (but who, like a typical character, does not know we exist)
and also someone we know as being a hunter after the secret object, gains
access to the same apartment, on whatever narrative pretext, but immediately
she is inside the door, instead of puttering around drawers and cabinets and
under beds as we did, proceeds straight to the secret spot we found earlier,
the spot we found only after considerable hunting. The discoverer shares our
secret hunting diary, as it were, reads our notes that exist only “out there,
beyond the screen,” all in the interest of moving the story along. The detective
finding the door to the hero’s secret laboratory, just quickly enough to stop
the murder about to take place there but far too quickly for someone who has
never been there before. Take the townspeople in 1931 intuiting where to find
Frankenstein’s monster, up in the rocky crags.
A subtler variation of the narrative transparency cheat is used de rigueur
in chase sequences, all of which, from the Keystone Kops to Bullitt (1968)
and 6 Underground (2019) and beyond, depend on some pursuer P hot
on the trail of some evader E, moving, most often, through a fascinating
warren of architectural forms urban, exotic, or labyrinthine. One need
hardly catalog the celebrated chase sequences in James Bond films, which
form but a microcosm within the catalog. As P(ursuer) races after E(vader),
a number of considerations come into play:
●● Pursuer cannot catch up to Evader too soon, for two reasons.
The catch is the end of the chase, and the pleasure of watching
demands prolongation as much as the proportions of the narrative
can make possible. But also, if P catches E somewhat easily, then E
is evidently not so spirited or talented an evader, probably doesn’t
merit the extravagance of the chase at all, in the audience’s eyes.
This is not a diegetic issue, since in any chase-style diegesis E will
always seem to merit being chased by P simply on the face of it: the
chase is happening, P is eager to have E and shows the eagerness; E’s
flight shows the hunger for freedom (Chuck Jones’s Road Runner
cartoons). For the viewer to have a sporting thrill, P and E must be
reasonably matched. But the catch-up must be held off for a further,
quite dominant reason: because, in the end, the chase is not about
the catch, because the P-E inter-relation is not about the value of E
to P or to the audience, the actual moment of the catch, if it comes,
can be as deflating as it is satisfying (as would happen in Bullitt
without a fireball explosion adding hot sauce to the soup).
NARRATIVE TRANSPARENCY 27
The chase form will work effectively whether or not the purpose of the
pursuit is made clear, whether or not we know which of the two participants,
if either, means harm, or which could do more harm, and indeed whether
or not we are gaining access to the full circumstances. One of the format
requirements of James Bond films is a pre-credit chase sequence of
astonishing speed, athleticism, derring-do, and difficulty placed in one or
more environments of spectacular bizarreness or unlikeliness; the context, if
given at all, will come only (much) later. The chase alone is enough, P after
E, P after E again, P still after E, P closing in on E with increasing odds of
success or increasing odds of failure or no perceptible odds at all. Not P
28 THE FILM CHEAT
after E because; not P after E lest; not in order that, or owing to the fact that,
or even catering to the whims of Z, the powerful third party. Only P after
E, nothing more. Method is relatively immaterial, too. Run by foot, drive by
car, fly by helicopters, ski on a steep slope, what have you. P in pursuit of
E, P wanting to possess E, the formula of capitalism. P after E, P wanting to
do E damage, the formula of retribution.3 A good example begins On Her
Majesty’s Secret Service (1969).
The film chase is a chain of narrative transparencies, typically, since we
do not follow P (and very often not even E) but stand where they are about
to be so that they can arrive after us. (As though they are but pretending to
a chase, so that we can be entertained!) Now a fourth consideration:
●● P and E do the dramatic event no courtesies by disappearing from
view no matter how hard they struggle, no matter how hungry each
is to succeed. We have to see because the chase isn’t for them, it isn’t
for P who needs to corner E, it isn’t for E who needs to evade P, it’s
for us.
And here arrives the fundamental cheat of the form. As far as the
choreographic design is concerned, P’s hunt for E will seem believable only if
E is evasive, in short, if E is given plenty of opportunity to change direction,
find alleyways, jump over fences, migrate through cramped spaces, fling
himself into the air, dart around laundry hanging on the line, all of these
obstacles unexpected and unforeseen by P. But in order that we may see
these escapades, the camera must foresee first. (Foresee position, lens,
lighting requirements, focal problems.) Must establish us there before the
character comes. Must force the character to intuit where to be next (to
peek at the script).
One can twist this examination yet further. Even in scenes that are not
chase scenes, just simply dramatic encounters running one after another, the
elements of the film are arranged in something like a chase, events constantly
being pursued by characters, and here, too, we must always be placed for
an ideal view. As Donald Crafton writes, it is possible to be “using the
term Chase metaphorically, suggesting the linear trajectory of the narrative
in general, not a specific instance” (111). One could argue it is through
narrative transparency that we manage to see all of the cinematic story, since
we are enabled to leap ahead of the action without noting the cheat: the
action seems to be cannily following us. The pursuit sequence models what
normally happens before the camera but with all the stakes raised, all the
conditions extrematized for high visibility.
3
What Kenneth Boulding called the exchange system and the threat system (Personal
conversation, October 1966).
NARRATIVE TRANSPARENCY 29
Before any character “knows” how to commit an action (to the extent
that we can imagine a character knowing), knows where to sit, knows
what to eat, knows what street to walk or race down, knows what flight
to take to Tijuana, the camera must know because the camera will be there
first. But no sign will be given of this foreknowledge, save that it will result
in the successful vision. No character will acknowledge a bond with the
camera, even in face-to-lens moments such as abound in Alfie (1966) where
the (Michael Caine) face is aimed only at a non-lens or with Matthew
Broderick’s categorical adorableness in Ferris Bueller’s Day Off (1986), but
character thoughts can never seem bonded to production contingencies. The
script must cheat the fact that it is always one step ahead.
Without being one step ahead, it cannot function as a script. And
without being one step ahead the camera would show nothing but a kind
of afterimage.
By contrast, if we know the camera is one step ahead, if somewhere it
actually tells us it is—Hello! Watch how I always know where to go!—the
tension and thrill are leached out of the film.
The more elaborate the territory, the more pitfalls it contains, the more
apartments are in the corridor, the more narrow the transoms above their
doors, the more restricted or even obstructed the alleyways with barbed
wire fences at the end, the more contrived will seem the camera’s canny
placements, and thus the more artificial will seem our easy ability to see
clearly—always to see clearly, even too clearly—how the character daringly
moves. Yet without elaboration, territory becomes flat and tedious, fades
off, and the strength of the character(s) takes over. In this light compare
District B13, with David Belle’s fabulous precarious parkour maneuvers
and Manuel Teran’s marvelously sentient camera, with Cornel Wilde’s
The Naked Prey (1965), where in an extended and breathless sequence an
almost naked victim must flee barefoot across the African landscape while a
group of marksmen, ceremonially clad and bearing sharp spears, chase after
him as their prey. With both, the P-E shot sequence model is fully in use,
especially involving a “sentient” camera that always knows how to signal
the character where it will be, but the dangerous eccentricity in B13 signals
the technique spatially and the signals in Prey are characterological.
As any instant of narrative transparency could easily be a dangerous
reflection of the audience to itself (the character playing to a camera; the
camera rendering the picture to the viewer), it is typically edited with
distracting visual discontinuity and accompanied by pulsing and exciting
musical cues, also composite elements of the cheat. The character’s “reading
the production from behind” functions unceasingly while being unceasingly
out of view.
4
The Cheating Cut
moves, that is, through some effect of the filmmaking. A camera-eye that
moves, which is to say, a mechanical and logical arrangement for moving
the camera, some invisible and tightly planned production involving such as
shots, lights, ancillary personnel, a divided script, a developing character—
all the things we would prefer to claim we have no truck with while we
watch and become caught up by the film. Not only that editing is set to be
invisible (as it is); but that editing-set-to-be-invisible is invisible. And finally
the moving camera—its being, its motion—is read onto the character. And
actors are aware of this.
Almost all narrative film is edited, made up of numerous shots that
are hooked together (on historical variations in the length of shots, see
Bordwell). The shooting script is a kind of manual for fashioning the various
parts that will be collected to make the film.1 In watching a film we agree
to move discreetly and unconsciously from one isolated shot to another
and in moving to understand the character as moving and being moved to
move. Discreetly and unconsciously, as in “without acknowledging our own
action” (as it is prompted and made possible by what shines on the screen
to be seen). We effectively move through the story, but we move thinking
ourselves stationary and imagining that it is the story that moves. The fiction
of cinema demands that we digest and neglect our own motion without
comment, even when, as with the Moscow chase in Paul Greengrass’s The
Bourne Supremacy (2004), the shot transitions are lightning fast, even in
some instants unperceivable (quarter-second) blurs. In refusing to comment
on our own motion we deny it. As long as we seem ready to play by the
rules of this game of secrecy, editors can reasonably expect us to put up with
any transition however outlandish, our only alternative being an open (and
sullying) doubt as to how one could get there from here, so quickly and with
no obstruction, no traffic jam.2
Of course the cheater who behaves with extravagant panache will not
only go scot free but also gain immense credibility as a genius, the unnoted
discontinuity he or she may have presented, the chasm across which one
leaps, showing off as a kind of triumphant battle scar after the unforgiving
turmoil of creative work. Three marvelous edit cheats, forward motion
accomplished so effortlessly it seems as natural as rain, with each of these
standing upon, evidencing a script built to support it and give it display.
One can write for cinema with full knowledge that the camera’s jumping is
a standard possibility. One can write with the invisible pen.
1
The “Building an Interocitor” sequence at the beginning of This Island Earth (1955) is a
chilling, but also wholly entertaining comment on breakdowns and constructions, multiple
parts for making unified wholes. Underneath both this rendition and the studio process itself is
Durkheim’s “organic solidarity” (Division Ch. III).
2
Excepting the one the diegesis imposes, of course at a critical moment. See The Taking of
Pelham One Two Three (1974).
32 THE FILM CHEAT
But that apparently unobtrusive cut from the long shot of Kane walking
away from us and down the corridor, his tiny reflection stalwart if wooden
at right, to the shot of him stumbling forward toward the camera which will
discover the hall of mirrors: the cut that confers upon Kane the inevitability
of his multiplicity, that shows him marching toward a future—that cut is
telltale, outlandish. Why? Because it is another thing altogether to offer a
straight continuity of motion, a pickup of the moving man to follow him
stepping along, and indeed the promise of “straight continuity” is what
operates as a pretext for the cut. Kane moves, stay with Kane. Keep following
3
Interestingly, perhaps strangely, this recursion was pictured as well, and in the same year, using
Joan Crawford, in George Cukor’s A Woman’s Face (with cinematography by Robert Planck);
then paid homage by Jean-Pierre Melville using Charles Vanet in his L’aîné des Fercheaux
(1963).
4
Yet at the same time a scathing Wellesian reference to Triumph des Willens (1935) and thus
allusion to the model for his character, William Randolph Hearst, as a Nazi sympathizer.
THE CHEATING CUT 33
him, see what he becomes. But here, the second shot is a whole new world,
in effect a whole new destination, as though in a new dimension, something
marvelous in itself, something unexpected and unexpectable, calculated
to give the viewer a chill and a thrill: quickly, blatantly, with quaver and
reverberation. The shots until this have been cut together to follow action
and characterological feeling: Kane amok in the bedroom, Kane stunned in
the doorway, Kane jerking away from the scene of the crime (this bedroom
has been his trysting place with Susan, no doubt), Kane dropping away
from the servants down the vacuous hall. Complete coherence, even logic,
and aesthetic sensibility, too. Then suddenly a jump to a perspective that is
nothing short of galvanizing. An entire camera and lighting crew, among
many others, had to be at work in order to effect this magic, and for the
editor Robert Wise still more work, to effect the transition in such a way
that no one would notice.5
Galvanizing from Luigi Galvani (1737–98), who was fascinated with the
body’s transmission of, and susceptibility to, electricity. Bioelectromagnetic
pioneer. Feeling and sentiment, the muscles (of expression) as electrical.
Medical electricity. The Galvanic idea is that electricity is resident in the
body itself, whether or not the body is stimulated from an outside source.
Seeing the Kane-mirror shot we have a frisson of pleasure and wonder, a
jolt, and so we can say the shot is galvanizing. Yet our principal character
Kane is clearly on the verge of a fugue at this point, rigid of posture, robotic
even, and silent because all his language (he was a newspaper baron) is now
swallowed in catatonia. The galvanization is in the viewer, not the character.
Kane in the bedroom, Kane in the doorway, Kane in the corridor . . . all
electrically disconnected, but then, in a cut that audiences accept without
questioning, even without detecting for what it is, Kane as the depleted and
progressively shrinking doll, our doll, the doll that with a jolt jumps away
from, and into, itself. A focus of vision, surely; but in the mirror shot there is
no one to look at him but the viewer outside, who looks at the whole.
An ominous musical cue helps create the ersatz effect of the earlier
shots being blended, through transition, into the mirror shot, but while
it develops the action, while it expands and enriches our sense of Kane’s
world, nevertheless that mirror shot is not about Kane as much as it is about
our thrill in observation. It works as what Tom Gunning, writing of early
5
I can only notice in the way that legion scholars and cinephiles notice such things nowadays,
freezing a frame to study it, repeating a movement over and over and over, reading about it
perhaps, certainly not being forced by circumstance, as the viewers in 1941 were, to grab
whatever I could get as the movie rolled on, rolled even away from the theater and into what
would have seemed then like obscurity. After initial screenings and subsequent B-exhibition in
smaller venues months later, the form was that a film would simply “go,” and viewers had no
way at all to retrieve it until the videotape revolution of the 1970s, if then.
34 THE FILM CHEAT
6
For discussing punch lines with me I am grateful to Alex Clayton and Tom Hemingway.
THE CHEATING CUT 35
If the onlookers laugh when the clown suddenly finds himself falling like
a stone it is because they had all along been projecting their musculature
and sensibilities sympathetically into his walk and now find that their
leaning into his anticipated conduct, into the anticipated guidedness of
his doings, their framed prediction of what is to come, is disordered.
(Frame Analysis, 381)
How does the character manage to travel to the punch, the new location
apparently unplanned and unforeseen at the beginning—but still, of course,
intensively planned, intensively foreseen, for the benefit of the actor and that
of the camera, which must permit the audience to be there to receive the
character when he arrives? This is where the narrative transparency comes
into play. The character must somehow be reading the audience’s mind (the
audience/the camera), the traveling mind that lets the camera ride away with
it. The camera is the script, so, weirdly if unnoticeably, the audience has
access to the script. But now, apparently, so does the character.
As is known albeit forgotten: while actors have deep access to the script
the characters they play have none. For the characters, indeed, there is no
script; no camera; no audience; only plastic space and time. This is a space-
time in which it is not so very easy to believe. Our thought keeps dropping
back to the actor with her script, with her plans, with her foreknowledge of
the scene, and must be cheated if pleasure is to ensue.
The character’s apparent foreknowledge (assuming that we can
countenance a character having knowledge of any kind!)—the impression we
could have, were we to consider the situation quite fully, that the character
had somehow read the filmmaker’s mind, because at some punch line even
if the floor is pulled away from the character still the character found that
floor first—might reveal itself in numerous ways beyond his or her appearing
in a distal location to be met by the camera. A character could appear in a
proximal location, even in the same location, but, time having passed, in a
way especially idealized for camera, posing as she would never have posed
in other circumstances. The change of state, as it were, is the jump forward.
And in that renovated pose, a character could deliver an action not only
fresh and unheralded but one that the camera was ideally placed to see, an
action that would lose all its oomph were it to be seen from any other place.
The pose-to-camera is found through transparency, but more: when we see
this climactic pose, when we respond by exploding into a laugh or a gasp,
the thing as a configuration and a design will seem quite inevitable, although
previously it was unimagined, improbable. Improbable inevitability.
The telling case is Desi and Lucy. Desi Arnaz and Lucille Ball, two
catastrophes waiting to happen, as viewers in the 1950s happily knew.
An urban couple, they have acquired a long, long trailer and set off to see
the majestic countryside. They know nothing of maneuvering a trailer,
and little more about driving altogether. Many hilarious and precipitous
36 THE FILM CHEAT
escapes line up (Vincente Minnelli going over the top with set-up jokes),
including one in which Desi goes apoplectic trying to back the trailer into
a suburban driveway. Finally, thrillingly and relievedly on the road, Lucy
has decided to make a fancy dinner while he drives. Beef ragout, some kind
of white cake iced with gentility, a Caesar Salad (in a huge bowl: “You
don’t cut the lettuce, you tear the lettuce!”). She is dressed in a lovely dark
green full-length dress, looking a little like a Caesar Salad herself—a nifty
foreshadowing. We know things have to go wrong—this is Desi and Lucy!
He is up front idiotically singing: he believes himself an operatic tenor, and
is bellowing nonsense news: “We’re having beeeef ragouuuut! And Cae-e-
e-e-esar Sal-l-l-l-l-l-l-ad!” The road is bumpy, the trailer rocks, left right, up
down. Lucy is challenged, to put it mildly. The lettuce is flying out of the
salad bowl, especially when, having cracked in two raw eggs, she makes
to toss it by hand. Soon it is on the floor, and also on her head, and the
cupboard door has flown open so that all the foodstuffs are flying out,
unlimited quantities of white flour spraying all over her and mixing with the
salad moisture to make a kind of sticky dough that clings to her hands and
dress as, with increasing desperation (and increasing energy), she careens,
slips, twists, jerks, and collapses around the trailer. (Nobody but Lucille Ball
could do this so magnificently, not even, I beg to say, Chaplin.) But now for
the silent punch. The camera “discovers” her in a tableau moment, body
dumped up against a corner like a sack of flour itself, shoulders slumped in
vivid now-splotched green, legs spread helplessly, head dangling as though
from strings: she is a giant marionette. Her eyes look into the lens beckoning
and surrendering (as in a Warner Bros. cartoon). And the body is positioned
perfectly at frame-center, a frame in which the food detritus is reduced so
that only defeated, deflated Lucy is visible as content. It is as though she has
collapsed with intent here, just in order to be seen this way in a feature shot.
The feature shot is the joke’s payoff.
But there is more:
As we look at her in pity, from screen left the trailer door flies open and
Desi pops in to say, with exquisite inanity, “Is everything all right, Lucy?,”
whereupon with her left hand (screen right) she quite suddenly plants what
looks like a cream pie in his face. (We realize it is the remainder of the cake.)
Not only was the scene constructed for a beautiful (and beautifully messy)
portrait of (beautifully messy) Lucy, it was constructed ideally to show the
whipped-cream gag from the perfect angle—one that gives complete access
to not only the goo but also Desi’s stupefied surprise. A payoff’s payoff.
Here again, choreography is kept out of view and beyond suspicion.
Were viewers to see arrangements, the sort of arrangements necessary for
setting up this long final shot with its two-beat conclusion, the delightful
haphazardness of the action would dissolve. It is Lucy’s foibles apparently
occurring without (or against) plan that makes them funny. What is cheated
is the arrangement of action for camera, not some aspect of the action itself
THE CHEATING CUT 37
(since the moment we see Lucy with food we intuit that she is going to
become food). The scene is a little dance, with the finale chord being the
concluding pose. And the camera, we see too late, was dancing, too.
●● 2001: A Space Odyssey (1968; ed. Ray Lovejoy). One of the
supremely celebrated and much-recognized edits in cinema history,
for which almost no description is required. In prehistoric times,
Moonwatcher (Dan Richter), a violent ape who has just picked up a
tapir bone from a skeleton and brandished it as a (first) weapon now
hurls it up into the sky, and just after the white rectangle reaches
its apogee and begins its descent POOF! it magically turns into a
white rectangular spaceship against a black star field. Robert Kolker
describes it vividly:
The bone-white spaceship falls gracefully in the interstellar ballet
that synchronizes its movements with that of the space station.
Johann Strauss’s waltz “The Blue Danube” plays on the sound
track—nineteenth-century music accompanying twenty-first
century space technology. Death (the bone) seems to give way
instantly to life—the exciting future of space travel. (611)
* * *
following one another more or less as the movement within them dictates,
notwithstanding that inserts can be added. A character reaches a stairway;
the character is seen climbing the stairs; the character reaches the top
of the stairs. With each successive shot added on, there is instigated no
particular surprise that the character having been located in the previous
shot now appears in this one: the action itself is taken to make a dictate.
With narrative transparency, ensuing action is not logically probable and
so when the camera jumps for a position to see, it jumps as a result of the
director’s dictate, and the character’s arrival is finally, effectively, in response
to the jumping camera. This, simply, is why I see it as a situation in which
the character sees through the production wall to the camera itself. The
editing in narrative transparency hides, as it were, beneath the grammar of
conventional sequential editing, which shapes most of the film space we see
and also our steadily ongoing expectation.
5
Narrative Opacity
FIGURE 5 Outside London’s Royal Albert Hall in The Man Who Knew Too Much
(Alfred Hitchcock, Paramount, 1956).
All of the clues in the Albert Hall sequence are double clues, then, directed
in two separate vectors at the same time, one vector aimed toward [A] Jo on
her Buchanan hunt, another toward [B] the musically informed viewer (one
toward an observer who knows what the future will bring, “what will be”;
one toward an observer who does not1):
●● [i] When, in Kensington Gore, she moves past the poster into the
lobby [A] Jo (the American tourist who, even earlier in life, as a
famous performer, never gave a show here) is certifying to herself
that yes, this is the Royal Albert Hall, the place where Buchanan
will be; whereas [B] oblivious to Buchanan we are noting that this
is the place where the cantata will be sung (and even, thanks to
Hitchcock’s considerateness in showing the poster, the names of
those who will perform it).
●● [ii] When in the lobby Jo encounters the Assassin (whom [A] she
knows to be a strange man she saw at her hotel room door in
Marrakech, but not an assassin, while [B] we know him for who
he really is because we watched him “rehearse”) and he threatens
her with the life of her son, [A] she is made especially desperate to
find Buchanan; whereas [B] we confirm to ourselves that the man
who practiced with Drayton, and smirked intelligently at the man’s
condescension, is now here in front of us, fully equipped and ready.
●● [iii] When Buchanan makes his (grand) entrance along with
the portly visiting Prime Minister (Alexei Bobrinskoy) and his
Ambassador (Mogens Wieth), [A] Jo thinks, “Oh yes!, there is
Buchanan now! Maybe I could signal to him?”; but [B] we think,
“Ahhh, that plump man in Buchanan’s care is the target. Alive now,
dead soon.”
●● [iv] When the music begins, [A] Jo is swept away by the flow
of it, and more deeply anxious about her son and the fact that
she couldn’t talk to Buchanan, while [B] we are on track for the
assassination shot, listening through the score (the script) for
the right moment. Jo is not listening for a cue; she is listening to
the music integrally. Were she as aware as we are that a killing is
planned here, and that this cantata will trigger it, her lack of action
1
An underpinning irony being that Jo McKenna (Jo Conway, the famous singer) is musically
informed, thus a very particular member of this audience, perhaps even more knowledgeable
than the viewer of the film, yet Hitchcock makes her musicality seem irrelevant for the moment.
When the cantata begins, her response as a listener (to the orchestra under Bernard Herrmann
and the singer Barbara Howitt) becomes far more sympathetic, far more musical in the quality
of its sensitivity. The many other patrons are carefully shown sitting expressionless as statues
(the intended victim notably included).
42 THE FILM CHEAT
overhear the rehearsal earlier, where we learn about the cantata for
the first time and from which she was utterly excluded).
●● She would have to have been much more suspicious of the man in the
tuxedo. Not just a memorable face (an unforgettable face, Hitchcock
knew) but a face from where? The only thing Jo ever saw this man do
was politely speak at her hotel room door. Nor just politely. Exquisitely.
●● Regarding Buchanan, she would have to have made some attempt to
get the man’s attention, rather than just timidly watching him ascend
a staircase. “My son is in danger! There’s going to be a killing! I’ve
just seen the killer!”—all of which we fill in, and inaccurately. Her
son is in danger, yes, surely, but not here. She knows there will be a
killing in London but not here. She knows the gaunt-faced stranger
is bizarre-looking, yet he is also a textbook model of etiquette and
only we know he is the killer.
●● And when the music started Jo would have to have attempted to
do something to stop the proceedings, instead of riding along with
the melodies as she does. Yet, do what? She has not put the pieces
of the puzzle together, nor would we have done so had we not been
treated to that “rehearsal.” (Again: treated as Jo was not treated.)
And in assembling the puzzle she would have to have been willing
to sacrifice Hank, dismissively, coldly, because at least ostensibly
she would have more care about the prime minister of a country
she does not know. None of this is conceivable, given the details of
Hitchcock’s demonstrated logic.
Jo’s being kept out of the picture cognitively and physically is an essential
aspect of the film’s composition.
And positively,
●● The ironic thrill we obtain as the sequence rushes to its cadence
partially grows out of our sudden awareness that Jo now knows
what we knew all along, that the concert, Buchanan’s presence, the
assassin’s shot, the intended victim (and the openness of all this to
our sight) work together in a tightly composed and unbreakable
knot, a knot threatening, with mounting amplitude of voice and
quickening pace, to come apart. To our delight she is sharing our
rung of the ladder, but has very little time to rest there (the editing
shortens the shot lengths as the cantata finale approaches). Were we
to have known from the outset that Jo either already knew all this
or would soon enough discover it, that her awareness and ours were
matched all along or very soon to be matched, all this excitement
would escape like air from a punctured life raft, and the music itself,
nine minutes and more of it, would have been little other than a
tedious delaying mechanism.
44 THE FILM CHEAT
2
As in the family scene at the detective’s house early in Nicholas Ray’s On Dangerous Ground
(1951).
3
For the reader born in the twenty-first century: he is using a 33 1/3 rpm vinyl recording on a
turntable connected to a rudimentary built-in speaker. Such devices were almost as routinely
available as laptop computers today.
4
Miles shows exquisite musicality, because his downbeat is executed with the cleanest
professionalism, although this moment is cheated, of course, since the music track can be back-
synced to coincide with his downbeat—the very opposite of what is happening “live” in the
Hall, one might think (but, of course, what we see there is not “live” performance). As creator
and director of London’s Mermaid Theatre, founded in St. John’s Wood in 1951 then shifted to
Blackfriars, he had in fact given the “downbeat” for numerous productions, not least of which
was Treasure Island in which he played a memorable Long John Silver. The Assassin’s putative
musical denseness is another private joke: Reginald Nalder had been a singer and dancer in
Vienna before emigrating to the United States. We do see his sensitivity as he listens in the
balcony later, curious to glance at his companion’s pocket score.
6
Our Faithful Friend
FIGURE 6 The precarious sound stage in The Day of the Locust (John Schlesinger,
Paramount, 1975).
though no one gazing at this incredible world ever blinks.1 As John Belton
has made crystal clear, sound after the early 1930s was, and now remains,
recorded so as to make the space of the picture acoustic, not to be faithful to
the shape of the diegetic space. In a related way, the picture is recorded so as
to make logical the world of the story, not the world in which the recording
was made. The presumption we make in being transported through filmic
narrative—arrangement is made so that nothing in the film will contradict
the movement that is accorded us—is that no key event will be omitted from
the story, no event of significance will take place somewhere we cannot see,
no significant character will fail to appear, no meaningful utterance will be
unhearable. We are not only embedded in the ongoingness but embedded
with a completeness and totality in which we can have faith, placed as far
inside as one can be without breaking through the wall of the skin. This is
a special view, and we have been accorded it not because we can rightfully
claim to be worthy but because a filmmaker we do regard as worthy has
made the decision to grace us that way.
When I watch Kenneth Branagh’s performance of Hamlet (1996) or of
Hercule Poirot (2017) I do not suffer the same nauseating doubt or intrigue
we are to presume is inside the character, yet this doubting Hamlet and the
intrigued Poirot are my closest chums as I watch. In the omniscient narrative
that I know intimately—whatever “intimately” finally means—what they
experience I share, and since I would not wish to feel nauseating doubt or
intrigue myself (a little doubt or intrigue maybe, but not the Full Monty) I
tell myself to remain calm and let them “carry” me and, as loyal chums, they
remain calm and do just that: we go on and on. Even quintessentially private
moments between characters—Hamlet confiding to Horatio (Nicholas
Farrell); Poirot questioning Princess Dragomiroff (Judi Dench)—moments
such as I would never be able, or ask, to see outside of cinema, are shown
openly and with a tickling casualness, as though, like an invisible phantom I
inhabit (and properly should inhabit) the secret space containing the action.
Lovemaking and murder are two rich examples of this effected intimacy.
When either occurs onscreen I am not afforded a view so very involving
that I wonder whether I am somehow naked or covered with blood spatter,
yet I do sense myself to be privy to something others are not, and would
not be, privy to, and something, further, that I should see from up close (see
Chapters 19 and 47). Others: even all the people sitting around me in the
same space, who, though what I see is light coming from a screen, somehow
do not, as I believe it—as I require to believe it—see what I see the way I see
1
Rule-proving exception: Blow-Up (1966) features a marvelous nocturnal moment with David
Hemmings skimming down Regent Street in his Mercedes with the top down. Suddenly he
thinks he sees a familiar woman on the sidewalk and quickly halts, but the camera, following
our delight in the movement, keeps tracking ahead until suddenly, realizing the car is no longer
at its side, it turns and looks back at him looking back.
OUR FAITHFUL FRIEND 47
then this “voice” of cinema to which I refer, the “person” not in but of the
film, the presence revealing presences to us, is an acousmêtre’s acousmêtre,
a spirit behind the puppeteer. When, to introduce whole films or specific
scenes the camera, elevated, swoops over a strange and notably fascinating
territory (New York City’s Spanish Harlem from high above when West
Side Story [1961] begins; the solarized “mindscape” during the star voyage
of 2001: A Space Odyssey [1968]), we immediately accept and adopt the
required point of view as offered by a flying cicerone who loves us and out
of love has given us to see. We immediately agree to find the vision valuable,
even indispensably so, and sense a thrill at having this particular—this
particularly entertaining—exposure to something we might not ordinarily
glimpse now opened up by someone so estimable (as to find us estimable),
so kind, and so careful not to drip the tea. Yet the system of service works
only when it can be known in advance how the motor of our satisfaction
works, known how we can be tickled, known how to afford a view beyond
the apogee of our imagination, and known that good service will pay off.
Instead we could be watching something cryptic and fail entirely to be
touched.
As to the location of the drama as set onscreen: if the camera is indeed a
“magic carpet” of sorts, we are willing to let it take us anywhere, anywhere
in space and time. (H. G. Wells’s time machine could move through history,
but always and only at one particular place; in David Lowery’s A Ghost
Story [2017] these constraints are relaxed, with profound results.) For
Hamlet, we are swept off to the parapets of the Castle of Elsinore, hundreds
of years ago, hovering in the Danish shadows there so that we can watch
48 THE FILM CHEAT
the night watch. “Answer me. Stand and unfold yourself.”—but not bloody
likely. Far, far, far more entrancing, at any rate, than most day trips from
Copenhagen. For Good Will Hunting (1997), a corridor at Harvard where
a janitor stares at a math challenge scribbled on a blackboard (a challenge
intended to stymy any member of any audience). For Titanic (1997), a pier
at Southampton, 1912, a pier like any pier in a place like any other place,
except, of course, not. For Star Trek VI: The Undiscovered Country (1991),
the Starfleet Academy somewhere in the general vicinity of San Francisco
(like Lucasfilm!), hundreds of years in the future, everything clean and tidy
and sensibly ordered.
Wherever we go and whenever we presumably go there, being given to
see by means of whatever delicious movements, we trust implicitly that the
narrator is wise, capable, informed, and forthcoming. And not forgetful.
And having our best interests at heart. Also, if the film is indeed true to what
cinema is and can do, a narrator who manages to show things, not just use
words to refer to them. This “voice,” as I call it (perhaps it is more a hand
opening out); this personality: it is friendly because nourishing, ceaselessly.
Nourishing, responsive, considerate, loving. Generally the narrative has no
motive to trick us, at least finally, to make us dupes of Cartesian deception.
To keep a secret, yes, as long as that secret is either finally revealed or finally
left for a rather easy evening’s homework. When at film’s end there is a
radical, shuddering turnabout, we feel we ought to be able to look back
over the thing in memory and discover how, very close to the beginning, and
with an insouciance immeasurable, the secret was tossed upon the table.
Generally, anything and everything we would need to know we may glean
from what we see; and anything and everything that we need to see our
narrational chum openly, unabashedly shows. Bernardo Bertolucci’s The
Dreamers (2003) has Matthew (Michael Pitt) staring in excited amazement
at the vagina of his new friend Isabelle (Eva Green), and because we are to
affiliate with his moment of enlightenment we must stare, too (the filmmaker
paying homage to Gustave Courbet’s L’origine du monde [1866]). Later
Isabelle will stare with a matching amazement at his penis, and we are given
her point of view, too. If in the story there are vital secrets they will be
fashioned to appertain to some character(s) wanting to keep things away
from others, but we—oh, no no: we will not be left out; by means of Scheff’s
“ladder of awareness” we will know what is “not known.” Or else, finding
out later, even too late, we will know that, and how, we did not know.
But while we are tacitly let into the “interior” of the film’s habitation
the hand holding open the gate is entirely concealed from us, so that in
being admitted we have the feeling of entering of our own volition. Indeed,
more: we have the sensation, having divined the combination to the lock,
of sneaking in transgressively out of hunger and desire. An interesting case:
Clint Eastwood’s Sully (2016) puts us in the cockpit with the pilot and co-
pilot of an aircraft that after taking off from La Guardia must make an
OUR FAITHFUL FRIEND 49
into the light. Consider a very complex narrative space where it is necessary
to leap around and see many facets of a situation before it can be fully
understood: say, the soundstage catastrophe scene of John Schlesinger’s The
Day of the Locust (1975), where first we are brought into the Napoleonic
Wars, and up very close, but then pulled back to see that it was only a
simulation on a movie set, then taken further backward to see the director
with his megaphone upon a crane dolly, high in the air with the soundstage
ceiling and lights above his head. Hundreds of busy extras are being halted
at work so they can do another take and get it right, damn it!, and then,
under the scaffolding of the constructed redoubt we see not only the way
the carpenters’ 2 x 4s have been arranged but also how the “DANGER”
signs have all been binned. Now the face of the designer (William Atherton)
standing in frozen fear and panic as he notices. Back to the view from the
top of the redoubt with extras racing up only to plunge into nowhere when
the set (now, predictably) gives way. The camera is never not in the perfect
position to see what must be seen2; nor is any logic implied or interposed to
explain our power to hop from position to position.3 We of course accept
this offering of power, but the camera quietly empowers us to accept it.
In scripting these jumps, the filmmakers know that any explanation, not
of the cluster of places to which we must move but of our easily moving
there, would draw the magic curtain away from the production machine,
would permit us to “see that man behind the curtain,” even in the ironic
case where, as here, what we are seeing is exactly the men behind a camera.
Note the non-replication of our everyday experience. Were we to be present
on the soundstage like that designer, we would stand at every moment in one
particular spot there, or at least one area, more or less frozen, incapacitated
to see (even if urged to imagine) a great deal of what was happening. Always
in life we are unable to see a great deal of what is going on. There are hidden
actors, actors we hear without seeing, events of which we get a bad view,
movements that are sloppy, rumored happenings that we do not catch, and
so on. The ideally aimed and cultured vision blocks our attention to the
fact that in the story world are hidden actors, too, ones we hear without
seeing; there is sloppiness; there are events not quite in view. But we are
happily swept away with the generous, the exciting, the unfamiliarly violent,
with the exceptionally sexy peephole a film does manage, contrivedly, to
provide. Cinema will persist in seeming not only an eye but a magical eye,
that goes far beyond what the human eye can do in framing and seizing a
“world.” Anything that would dissipate the magic will be blocked away. For
2
Or to hint at, if not exactly configure, what remains out of frame but for the viewer is resonant
with what the screen shows. Offscreen space, the subject of fascinated rumination, speculation,
wondering, and desire is not random.
3
This “hopping” (my language) is a key feature of “intensified continuity” as discussed by
Bordwell.
OUR FAITHFUL FRIEND 51
Schlesinger, the cohort of assistant directors hidden all over the set, some
conceivably even in costume, massing, herding, urging, moving the army
of extras playing the army of extras (and the assistant directors) in this
way not that way, and in so many directions to boot, so that the effect of a
catastrophe can be generated. The “director” in this sequence barks away
through his megaphone, but his “assistant directors” are invisible until one
of them leads the charge up the redoubt to his own peril. The director is
scripted to bark, “the way directors do,” as if out of his lungs comes control
of everything.
One goes forward not only trusting the friendly “maker of displays”
but also believing in what the displays offer, with unquestioned and
unquestionable acceptance, as in a dream, where we take what we see and
hear as absolutely given and, regardless of how twisted it may seem, given
for the Good. We are trusting, even loving, because the narrator of our
dreams, although hidden, is a goodly (if not Godly) narrator who merits our
full commitment of respect. As Walter Benjamin suggested, the dream has
no outside (839).
More. The friendly narration, configured if not actually embodied,
has identifying characteristics, so that its presence and its workings, if
unrecognizable themselves, have recognizable effects, telltale stains. We
notice and affirm certain narratorial characteristics without wondering how
these might work to enchain us: roughly the age (perhaps older than we are
and wiser as with Kane in Citizen Kane [1941]); perhaps younger and more
innocent as with Scout in To Kill a Mockingbird (1962)]); roughly the social
class and technical knowledge (Heywood Floyd on the moon voyage in
2001). Narrational tics become evident as the narration acknowledges certain
realities rather than others, notices some things rather than overlooking or
avoiding them. More importantly, just as the narration acknowledges social
realities it also staunchly avoids claiming acknowledgment but treats them,
instead, as only, merely, naturally, simply, obviously present to the narrative
eye because there is no other way for them to be but present, and as though
any other reality isn’t real. Read through Henry James’s What Maisie Knew
(1897) for a study of social knowledge openly accessed by adults but artfully
concealed from a child who is in their presence:4
I am grateful to Nellie Perret for pointing the way to both What Maisie Knew and its author.
4
52 THE FILM CHEAT
and holds back and to the kind of social access one is presumably afforded
through its agency. In Stephen Frear’s The Queen (2006), we are accustomed
to going into the sitting room at Bucks House, as it’s called on the inside.
We see the telephone in her hand. In Empire of the Sun (1987), we are
accustomed to being sequestered in a prison camp by the Japanese. In The
Queen we are not so blinded by opulence, nor in Empire so overtaken by
shadow, as to have our view compromised.
Feeling accustomed to friendly narrative, we feel the comfort that comes
with custom. We can relax our hold on the reins of thought. Striking us
when we are relaxed this way, the writer’s cheat comes as a shock and a
triumph at the end of two valuable films. As they progress, The Go-Between
(1971) at Brandham Hall, an English country house late in the nineteenth
century and Atonement (2007), some decades later in a similar place, we
have the sense of a love story being spelled out phase by phase. In both cases
there is a kind of awkward (unstable) triad.
(1) The Go-Between. Young Leo (Dominic Guard) is the eponymous
go-between, invited to a seat in the English countryside and then expected
to shuttle back and forth between the entitled Mary, Lady Trimingham
(Julie Christie), and the farmhand with whom she is madly in love, Ted
Burgess (Alan Bates). It is a glorious summer, a time of brilliantly sunlit days,
bleached haystacks, shadowy barns, trickling rivulets, emerald swards, and
taking off one’s clothes. For Mary the world is enchanted by her passion,
but she and Ted are caught in a mad, transgressive affair, in a cultural setting
and at a time when social-class boundaries were rigidly observed and a girl
like her could have no purpose in cavorting with, or even acknowledging the
presence of, a boy like him. For navigating assignations messages must be
carried back and forth, and Leo is the innocent messenger. Things turn out
badly, Mary being led to marry a man of her class and “having a son with
him” (secretly a son by Ted). By the film’s end a great deal of time has passed
and we learn from Leo’s mouth how, Mary’s husband having died in the
war, he was asked once again to be a go-between for her, revealing the secret
love to the son. However, this forthcoming Leo of the finale is more than a
neutral, disembodied voice. Our faithful friend brings us to see him sitting
behind a window during a heavy rainstorm, a very old man now looking
back through the long inverted telescope of cinema and of life, decades upon
decades back, to the time of his own childhood when for him everything
was brave and clear and sun-drenched and utterly not understood. The
writer’s cheat here, that provides a thoroughgoing pleasure for the viewer,
lies in giving full information about the narrator only after it is too late
to imagine anything being done to mend the tattered situation he helped
rend—in revealing only at the film’s end that the entire film was being told
from only the film’s end. While the film was progressing the audience had
intuited itself at Brandham, in the days of the affair, and had felt a continuity
of presence there and in succeeding actions elsewhere. Suddenly it becomes
OUR FAITHFUL FRIEND 53
shockingly clear that the whole thing was a living memory, experienced
now somewhere else, in the rain, and so long afterward that it is impossible
to find certainty about anything. While the film does begin with the adult
Leo, we are not given enough information to position him temporally or
to come quite to the realization of who he is or what his involvements will
now be shown to be (that is, to have been): he is made, when first we meet
him, forgettable, so that as the alluring and complex story unwinds we find
ourselves fully present with Mary and Ted, oblivious, just as they are, to
what is beyond themselves.
There is a verbal irony here, of course: Mary and Ted are cheating with
their dalliance, in order to make life especially delightful; and the script is
cheating their cheating, to make it especially delightful for us. The principal
power of the cheat is in abeyance until we are confronted with the shocking
irony of Leo, our Leo, having aged; of much time having passed, without
narrational comment. The friendly narration has jumped us through a
lifetime but makes no claims to having done so; or to having the power to
do so; or to having considered the kind of effect such a charge might have
on us. It is as though we must of course have known where we would be
headed; we must of course have seen it all coming. Any other presumption
of our presumption would draw attention to the radical alteration in setting,
costuming, makeup, and tone, so much attention that, swept away at the
finale by our own gasping grasp that we swooped forward we would fail to
catch the strange pain Leo is trying to give over.
(2) In Atonement we find ourselves witnessing the feux d’artifice of love
between Cecilia Tallis (Keira Knightley), a girl of the upper class, and Robbie
Turner (James McAvoy), far from a nobleman but the object of her passion
nevertheless. Their trysting is accidentally witnessed by Cecilia’s thirteen-
year-old sister Briony (Saoirse Ronan), who in her consternation tells her
parents that Robbie is a thief. He is cast out of the family circle, away from
the estate house, away from Cecilia. Five years pass. We meet Briony (Romola
Garai), conflicted and anxious in regard to her past. Robbie becomes caught
up in the war, is wounded on the beaches of Normandy, and dies a horrible
death there while she fails at nursing him. It is only at the end of the film that
we meet the figure who, it turns out, has been revealing this whole fabric
to us, Briony (Vanessa Redgrave) as an aging author looking back on her
childhood with deep regret at having destroyed her sister’s chance at love.
A similar cheat works here: the intelligence, sensitivity, and point of view
being employed in recounting the tale is that of a very mature and reflective
woman, in this case even a magician with words, but the imagery puts us
so close to Robbie and Cecilia, so close to Briony who is perforcedly so
close to them, so close to all the family and their friends who circulate like
butterflies around the Tallis brilliance, that we feel ourselves embedded in
early twentieth-century history, even suspended in time—as becomes evident
with the wounded Robbie (helpless Cecilia resting by his side)—imprisoned
54 THE FILM CHEAT
* * *
As to the cheat of the “friendly narrative,” as I am calling it, one more word:
The “faithful friend” was intentionally spawned for, and has been much
cloned in, commercial cinema, certainly cinematic narrative, in which a
certain interpretive binding holds the viewer’s consciousness in registration
with the imagery. In life as we know it there are very few such considerate,
outgoing, unstinting, kind, and all-knowing companions who would arrange
to give us boons of experience (ideally staged) without letting us see the
gifting as well as the gift. Parents, siblings, spouses, lovers, perhaps. But
surely not scriptwriters. It is just because the camera is no friend of the heart
that all its many boons must be offered while we are unconscious.
7
Bridge from Nowhere
FIGURE 7 Leroy Daniels (l.) with Fred Astaire, doing “Shine On Your Shoes” in
The Band Wagon (Vincente Minnelli, MGM, 1953).
that we know such results have come previously from “causes” such as this
“cause”; given that our theory of the world incorporates flows like this one;
given that we have no reason for doubting whether an outcome such as this
outcome could result from a cause such as this cause; given all of this, when
we think back on the cause we do not doubt the effect as effect. The forward
flow will always be a flow, but it can also be an effective flow.
It is widely understood by those who have experienced their culture that
a very broad range of possibility exists as to event-to-event flows, some
events being capable of leading to (preceding) virtually anything within
reason, reason, of course, being a set of known and accepted formulae for
limiting probability in a local setting. The final determination of cause-effect
relationships is open to negotiation socially. I snap my fingers and the sun
rises, but only in a relatively primitive culture (not my own, I suspect) would
any credibility attach to that pairing as cause-and-effect. I say a primitive
culture: certainly, let us agree, a pre-modern one. Moses stretches out his
rod and the waters of the Red Sea part . . . If I had a rod to stretch out, and
I stretched it, waters would not part anywhere.
Contiguity and likelihood, then. In the typical film musical, which
replicates the structure of a dream more than it does the structure of the
everyday (to which, thanks to designers and performers, it very often bears
some resemblance), there is the scantest imaginable contiguity between
events for very good structural reasons. When, say at the Freed Unit at
MGM, a decision is made to produce a show, the first step is the assembly
of a contractually feasible group of musical items, these very often selected
from the studio library (where on most items the studio owns copyright)
or coming from the catalog of a musician (and producer) like Arthur Freed
himself. The songs will be “lined up” in some way that makes for an arc of
musical phrasing, rhythm, and harmony, one number seeming appropriate
as a kick-off and another as a finale, etc. Then a story structure is made
up that will weave the songs together, or more properly, that will narrate
between the songs in what seems a forward-flowing chain of contiguities,
which amounts to a continuity. The narration serves to build bridges. Each
narrative bit has as its primary function making the song that preceded it
and the song that follows it seem more or less contiguous; and making the
second song seem as though it flows from the narrative, too. But no part
of this is anything but constructed, by which I mean not always already
socially understood and accepted normatively (as in the “social construction
of reality” [see Berger and Luckmann]) but literally put together (with art
and arbitrariness) like the pieces of a kid’s Lego set.
The sense viewers would have that one sung moment fluidly (inevitably)
leads to another is thus an induced sense, and the manner of inducing it is
a grand cheat. With certain sorts of characters—the ones who overpopulate
Freed Unit musicals!—the everyday they inhabit allows for almost anything
to happen, and so the writers are in a position to invoke almost any
BRIDGE FROM NOWHERE 57
integument to bind musical numbers together and make the binding seem
indubitably real. But a very nice example of the fragility and artfulness of
this kind of cheating is to be found in the opening few moments of The
Band Wagon (1953), one of the really glorious musicals of the Hollywood
golden age.
In a little gestural moment Alfred Hitchcock neatly reprises this scene in Torn Curtain (1966)
1
the Welcome Show. “Tony. Hunter. Sis boom bah!” The three do a
happy-smiles routine, Tony assuring Lily, “You’re much too pretty to
be married to that!” Lester: “There’s work to be done. I have here a
script. . . . Smell it, you can smell it’s good! There’s a great part in it
for you and nice little parts for Lily and me.” Dissolve past nocturnal
street traffic to a medium-close of the three of them talking in a
sidewalk crowd.
[6] Lily and Lester are trying to persuade reluctant Tony to get in on
their new musical which will be directed by the fabulous Jeffrey
Cordova. But, “What’s happened to 42nd Street?” he wants to
know, “This used to be the greatest theater street in the town. The
New Amsterdam, I had one of my biggest successes there. . . . Noël
Coward and Gertie were here in Private Lives2. . . . First show I
ever did was at the Elgin and . . . and I don’t believe that’s even here
anymore.” Key action: a cigar-chomping drunk (Cigar Reprise) steps
on Lester’s foot. In agony, he pays the man and apologizes (typical
Oscar Levant self-deprecation: “I can stand anything but pain!”).
Tony sees his pals off in a cab.
[7] He is in front of an open arcade (where, had the threesome kept
walking, he wouldn’t be), filled with notably goofy automata, such
as a fortune teller, a weight machine, a baseball throw, and a mystery
machine dominating the space but all closed off. Here, and weaving
among the adults and young people populating the place, and while
acquiring a hot dog he doesn’t want and a collection of doubtful
looks from strangers, Tony performs Schwartz and Dietz’s “Shine
On Your Shoes” (1932), dancing through the number, as he sings,
in the classic Fred Astaire fashion (the classic Tony Hunter fashion,
as we are to imagine), in this way quickly showing us (but not the
people around him, who seem oblivious) that he is back (tastefully
mismatched socks and all). The number—one of the really beautiful
musical numbers in the Hollywood canon, given the lilting tune,
the vibrant color, and Astaire’s debonair smoothness taken to an
extreme—ends with him duetting with a shoeshine man (Leroy
Daniels, also wearing, in the Astaire tradition, vibrantly colored
socks) and finally kicking the mystery machine into life.
Two songs, then, “By Myself,” which is soft and slow; and “Shine On Your
Shoes” which is more rhythmical, jazzy, upbeat, and promising. Between
them the intercession of Lester and Lily, their goofy show idea, Tony’s
2
A flicker of researched realism: original production of the Noël Coward play, January 7, 1931,
Times Square Theatre, starring Noël Coward (1899–1973) and Gertrude Lawrence (1898–
1952).
BRIDGE FROM NOWHERE 59
[A] Fictional space. Both the station and the sidewalk on 42nd Street
are jammed with people heading in all directions, dressed in all
colors: a twittering kaleidoscope. Yet the closeness of the shots in
both locations, centering on the trio, lifting them away from their
background, makes the planet of Grand Central and the planet of
42nd St. seem to fade away while a bubble of private, joking, ultra-
friendly human relationship looms forward. We had a tiny hint of
this spatial division on the station platform when, leaning close to
her old pal Tony, Ava Gardner made a subtle comment “only to
him” about how trying the “business” is, a comment only he would
understand, as her confiding smile telegraphs. Tony is worried about
the wounded Lester, and helps to get him into a cab with Lily, but
at the same time he is caught in his own reverie, thinking about his
past, the old 42nd St., the glittering distraction of the present, and
generally “going his way by himself.” In one pair of spaces, then:
the old and the new; the more private and the more public; buoyant
energy and patient reflection; the general crowd and the special
talent.
[B] Talk. Beyond saying how happy they are to see him, the Martons
are giving Tony a sales pitch. (The sales pitch is an elemental aspect
of entertainment production, and this film will focus on it later, with
some sharpness.) The pitch falls flat, maybe. But a telling query: is
Tony-starring-in-a-new-musical, as a conversational subject, linked
to what came just before (his solo train voyage in dismay) and what
could come after (beginning with his play at the arcade, then his
sliding into song there, then his spirits lifted, then his participation
in the musical)? At least for the viewer, the pitch works as a promise
of refreshment and rebirth for the admirable, the handsome, the
debonair, and the sweet-voiced Tony, especially welcome for the
somewhat sad Tony singing “By Myself” because he knows the
adulation he got while being famous is all gone. The promise here is
that Tony will be famous again, albeit his confidence isn’t presently
up to it. (Hopefully if Tony tastes the flavor of fame, so will we.)
As he wanders among the arcade machines he is at play, and the
dance-song that comes out of him is unreflective, almost unthought,
a genuine show of a talent that is inherent in the personality without
effort or intentful control.
“Shine On Your Shoes.” Just as it seems natural his getting off the train in
loneliness to sing “By Myself,” it seems natural for Tony to have his friends
meet him and shepherd him away, and natural for him to want to be alone
and find himself at play in the arcade. Natural, too, if it is Tony (Fred)
playing that a shoeshine turns into a dance display. Happenstance, if we
insist; but unquestionable happenstance.
Plain. Ordinary. Although there is no rule saying our trio must find
themselves on 42nd Street.
Ordinary. What might be true for anyone.
Anyone might feel lonely and sing “By Myself” if she knew the song.
Anyone might wander among the crazy machines, snag a hotdog, start
dancing. What anyone would not do is perform with the elegance, the trim,
the practice, and the extraordinary fluidity of Astaire/Tony, but by setting up
the former star, Star and only a Star, as the subject of concern, the filmmaker
solicits our tacit agreement to bond with this paragon of talent. This is
true from the first shot, where near the desperate auctioneer is the giant
photograph, a smiling, entirely benevolent, wholly lovable Tony Hunter,
Tony Hunter the Famous, As Was and Ever Will Be. We may be told Hunter
has aged, but to look at Astaire is to doubt that.
The sales pitch/chummy chat between the Martons and Tony is a major
cheat here. It gives the impression of artlessly bridging the railroad platform
moment to the arcade moment, since what would our focal hero do but
emerge from a platform and what could he do meeting the Martons but
go along, with them nudging their script all along? But there is no such
thing as an artless bridge. The apparent artlessness, the “obviousness” of the
connection, is what is cheated, what I am putting into question. Levant and
Fabray must play the Martons as literally exploding with excitement to see
their friend, quite as though they have been talking over the idea of snagging
him into their project until they’re blue in the face. They burst upon him,
and all the eventfulness they suggest bursts too—makes a forward motion
probable. The film is filled with interstitial linkages, keeping in relation to
one another songs that are in actual historical and performative fact quite
self-standing: “Triplets,” “Louisiana Hayride,” “Stairway to Paradise.” We
will be guided to feel that a man who was sad a few moments ago, and who,
because of that, turned down a prospect of work, has now found renewed
energy and hope. We can reasonably anticipate that very soon, very very
very soon, Tony will be onstage again, doing the material Lily and Lester
have fashioned for him to do (since if he’s going on Broadway what other
material could he possibly use?).
The interstitial dialogue in a musical such as The Band Wagon functions
somewhat in the way printed text cards easeled before the audience
functioned in a vaudeville show, as overt indicators that one act was closed
and another about to begin. But in vaudeville the signal system was part of
BRIDGE FROM NOWHERE 63
FIGURE 8 Alida Valli in The Third Man (Carol Reed, London Film Productions,
1949).
Every story comes to an end. And yet if the writer’s job in fashioning a script
is to arrive at an ending that seems logical, replete, appropriately sonorous,
and more or less conclusive it is true, too, that no construction functions
automatically as an ending, and that no matter the ending one creates there
is always something that could come afterward if one wished it to. Always
AND HERE ENDETH MY TALE 65
1
Note that while this phrase comes near the end of Hamlet it is not, actually, the last thing we
hear from the stage.
66 THE FILM CHEAT
Readers who are fans of music will want to listen to Malcolm Arnold’s “A Grand, Grand
2
Overture Op. 57” (1956), which nicely poses the problem of coming to conclusions.
AND HERE ENDETH MY TALE 67
FIGURE 9 Max von Sydow (l.) and Robert Redford in Three Days of the Condor
(Sydney Pollack, Wildwood/Dino De Laurentiis, 1975).
Since Fritz Lang’s Dr. Mabuse the Gambler (1922), a broad array of
films about institutionalized villainy have been made to popular acclaim.
Mabuse (Rudolf Klein-Rogge) reappears in The Testament of Dr. Mabuse
(1933; Rogge again) and The 1,000 Eyes of Dr. Mabuse (1960; Wolfgang
Preiss), in all three films a consummate criminal mastermind who sets in
motion complex and fabulous misdeeds and perplexes the forces of law and
order. The idea of the criminal confounding authorities stems from Poe, of
course, but Mabuse’s telltale characteristic is the megalomania behind his
enterprises, his penchant for the grand scheme (that we see partially echoed
today in heist films). Two aspects of Mabuse, the character, were central:
first, his overall heavy negativity and secondly, his capacity for disguise. Not
only a villain but a powerfully theatrical one, who could masquerade as just
about anybody. Evil dressing up as Good.
ONLY PRETENDING 69
The James Bond films, beginning with Dr. No (1962), extracted the first
of Mabuse’s evil traits, expanding and aggrandizing it in the character of
the mysterious supervillain, a figure with a diabolical plan to, effectively,
take over the universe. In comedic form this same trope appears in many
superhero films as well. It would be characteristic of a descendant of Mabuse
to inhabit a secret lair, to have capable assistants very often not publicly
visible, to lead a virtual army of clearly uniformed serflike myrmidons who
run some vast, highly technologized facility containing the superweapon he
intends to unleash. Like Mabuse, the Bond supervillain is very, very, very bad,
calling up the sharpest and most intelligent—not to say costly—of civilized
resources aiming to bring him under control. Most filmic supervillains do
not emulate Mabuse’s theatricality, however. The Bond villain blatantly (and
super-civilly) presents himself, very often inviting Her Majesty’s noble spy to
sit at the table, supping him with elegant and expensive foods, and chatting
away with cultivated aplomb. In effect he is making the statement, “I am not
hiding,” whereas Mabuse was a genius at hiding, like Doyle’s Moriarty. He
could be standing next to the chief of police in complete safety.
This second strain, villainy in disguise, deeply structures a great number
of late-twentieth and early-twenty-first century films about pernicious
corporations, pernicious government agencies, in general the apparently
normal and sleek but actually lethal social world. A purely Adornian
critique, pointing to myriad ways in which our capitalist development
taken to a high level compromises ethical concerns, human health, dignity,
community, the sense of beauty, and other estimable aspects of our lives
together. And one of the principal and notably recurring elements of these
films is the arch-villain who, we learn only too late, has been hiding all
along in the skin of a character introduced early on as powerful, dignified,
wealthy, noble, charitable, and fine, in short an epitome of the species. Or
else as a completely boring bureaucrat stuck behind a desk with nothing
interesting to recommend him at all. We come finally to discover a blazing
truth, that the “bad guy” is not the good leader with the benevolent smile,
as seemed, but a warped, very often profoundly psychologically damaged
monster whose smile was only a mask. We can take Martin Vanger (Stellan
Skarsgård) in The Girl with the Dragon Tattoo (2011), ostensibly a dignified
head of a family empire but latently a sadistic torturer and murderer. Or, in
The Fugitive (1993), Dr. Charles Nichols (Jeroen Krabbe), on the surface a
meticulous medical researcher heading a dignified and multivariate project
but really a malevolent crook scamming a false drug trial and willing to
arrange for the murder of innocents in order to succeed. In Spike Lee’s Inside
Man (2006) the ostensibly austere and dignified Christopher Plummer is a
soulless Nazi exploiter. Examples of this script maneuvering are legion.
A number of “games” are in play here. The scripter (and/or script
doctor) who uses the “civilized villain” trope (“uncovering of evil”) is
making a more or less clear statement of the audience’s foreknowledge and
70 THE FILM CHEAT
may say, of Yuri’s life do not, in the film, seem equably extensive, flowing
to culminations at the same rate. His arrest by partisans late in the film
happens in what seems a blink; his studious regard at his mentor’s side as
an attempted suicide has her stomach pumped, much earlier, is slow and
methodical. This elasticity of narrative time is one of the features of cinema
as art, as Victor Perkins taught in Film as Film. The motion within which
one feels oneself caught up is variable.
Plenty of other films accomplish a character’s “aging” or “development” or
“transition,” yet not so repletely as Zhivago. In The Magnificent Ambersons
(1942), for a classical and wonderful example, arrogant Georgie Minafer
(Tim Holt) grows into repentant George Minafer in a swift editorial flare.
In Welles’s Citizen Kane (1941) the eponymous protagonist (Welles) surely
ages, and visibly so, but we met him already in late childhood, and then with
only the briefest moment to examine him, swiftly, through a window. As we
watch Zhivago, what can we think time to be, that a poet’s more than five
decades might pass before us, contracted entirely within only three hours of
our lives?
Contractions involve anticipations, a sense of phrasing. As one begins to
be enraptured by a melody the ending hints itself, more and more firmly.
Well thought at least since Aristotle is the capacity of fiction to embody
and compact time, and all the rudiments of cinematic shooting and editing,
the grammar of film, afford opportunities for speeding up time (Fellini
Satyricon [1969]), slowing it down (Umberto D. [1952]), bringing it to a
halt (Murder on the Orient Express [1974]), making it seem not to exist
(One From the Heart [1981]). Life is fictionalized as a malleable material
that can be drawn and squeezed, cut apart and put together, shaped and
re-shaped. And there are several ways a transition can be effected from one
piece of film (showing one diegetic moment) to another (at another time). As
John Carey nicely showed, changing conventions have existed in cinematic
history for detailing to an audience the “fact” that story time has passed.
We experience film moments and passages by way of their occupation of
time, their procession. But little attention has been paid to the tempo of the
movement, an element that is central to our filmic experience.
The filmmaker can cause some moments to pass very slowly and others
to race, all without using those (cutesy) conventional effects: pages of a
calendar flipping quickly to show months elapsing, dates flashed onscreen
to show years going by, newspaper headlines flying past, or blunt references
to significant cultural events or changes of fashion. If we compare, say,
the voyage into the future in the 1960 and 2002 versions of H. G. Wells’s
The Time Machine, a fiction explicitly about temporality, we find that the
earlier film satisfies itself with scenic change and some slight lighting effects,
whereas the later film uses a full-scale computer graphic sequence to show
buildings shooting up and falling down in mere seconds, wars evaporating
in seconds, inventions flashing on and off, day turning into night over and
74 THE FILM CHEAT
over and over and over as with a strobe. The implication here is that were we
to have access to a Time Machine, and were we to ride it into the far future,
our optical experience would be something akin to this effect produced by
(the time machine of) cinema. Or for an example very different: in Easter
Parade (1948) there is a musical number with Fred Astaire dancing in front
of a chorus, all this watched in stunned admiration by Judy Garland in the
shade of the wings. Suddenly, we see something new. Astaire is dancing at
half-speed in front of the chorus continuing to dance at full speed.1 Consider
as well slighter variations, subtle modulations of tempo, adjustments of the
story clock that are cheated, produced in such a way as to carry action
forward usefully for the storyteller but without the audience being let in on
the curious stretchings of the taffy of time.
Tony Richardson’s The Entertainer (1960) offers a double metronome, a
parallel (ostensibly simultaneous) pair of dances, running against each other
at different tempi (as with the Easter Parade number). We are probing the
life of Archie Rice (Laurence Olivier), a washed-up song-and-dance man
at the end of his sad career. To regain some chance of pocketing enough
money to pay the tax man, he is putting his aging father to work, Billy
Rice (Roger Livesey), former mega-star now in his dotage but feisty. He
believes he can still catch an audience. As he gets dressed backstage Billy
doesn’t stop muttering about his routine and his illustrious past. We cut
away from his blithering to the hot-lit stage nearby, where a salacious and
notably rhythmic routine, “Put Me Among the Girls” (by Johnny Wakefield
and C. W. Murphy) is in progress. Jump back to Billy coming into the
shady wings, still without his jacket. Archie and the loving but exasperated
daughter Jean (Joan Plowright) are both hunting around for it. Back to the
stage, “Put me . . . among the . . .” Back to the wings, Billy getting his false
mustache on—it’s enormous, preposterous—trying faces with it. Back to
the stage, “Put me . . .” Now in the wings, however, Billy is having trouble
breathing. Back to the stage. Hot, hot lights. In the wings Billy is having
serious trouble breathing. Archie tells the stage manager to signal the singer
to stall and we catch her from the wings dancing offstage, a false smile on
her lips, quickly demanding what’s wrong. “Billy isn’t feeling well, you have
to go back and do another verse. Go back. You have to go back!” She goes
back onstage and picks up a reprise, this time almost doubling the tempo,
“Put me among . . .” Backstage Billy has collapsed. Back to the singing.
“. . . among the girls! . . .” Billy is in his final moments. Billy dies. All of
the cutting here is designed to give the impression that the many events
occurring in different visual fields—the stage, the wings—are in a single
temporal space, yet if we consider each side of this twinning alone we find
the clock ticking by, the “downbeats” of expression, not matched by those
1
For a discussion of this routine, including a technical explanation, see my “Bells Are Ringing.”
KEEPING MINUTES 75
on the other. The stage song is jerky, frenetic, wild, mechanical. What’s in
the wings is somber, vague, stuttering, like a candle flickering out. Billy dies
between two visual phrases of the onstage song. His anxiety and palpitation
is brought on, we are given to suspect, by fear of the stage moment, which
for him, through the whole sequence I’ve detailed, is coming closer with
more and more rapidity. That is: as time runs out (on his reprieve from the
audience) it seems to pass more swiftly. This is a standard parallel editing
situation, originated in 1911 by D. W. Griffith for The Lonedale Operator
but here, thanks to performative talent on both ends, there is a distinct
quality of variation between what the singer is doing (with false gaiety) and
what is happening to Billy. The moment of Billy’s death can be imagined to
be a race for him, while for Archie the future is opening up to a bald and
salted field in which no happiness will grow. The future opens slowly, as
though tiers of curtains are being drawn away from Archie’s eyes when he
sees his father expire, but the song he cannot help hearing in the background
has an unrelenting tempo.
But it is our proceeding through the film I wish to examine. Not the death
scene alone, but how we move away from it into what happens next. The
speed of happening. We move (instantaneously) to the funeral scene, on a
hilltop under a gray sky. The transition is through a normal dissolve, taking
about a second or two. We feel ourselves moving now as in conventional,
unmanipulated film narrative, at an even and uninterrupted pace. No matter
the events being narrated, the film is giving them over . . . the film is giving
them over . . . the film is giving them over. But since there is a relation
between diegetic events and the extra-diegetic editing pattern, we can watch
how the film gives things over. Billy dies → We are at Billy’s funeral. No time
seems to pass between the two events, no distinct time: a mere inhalation.
No time for Archie to sit at a table and think. No time to mourn. No time
to make funeral arrangements. The film could linger over the absence of
the fondly remembered Billy, or over the anxiety of nervous and nervous-
making Archie, but what it does instead is direct our attention to its own
forward flow through the ether.
If we think of the temporality of the backstage sequence in The Entertainer
(wings >>>>> stage >>>> wings >>> stage >> wings > stageWINGS) and
then of the temporality of the shift to the funeral, death |---| funeral, we find
that felt, known, experienced, and depicted time is handled in two different
ways, first in (increasingly swift) metrical steps and latterly in a leap across
a gulf. Once again: not what is happening, but how it is that, in seeing what
is happening followed by what is happening afterward, we breathe our way
forward. In the stage sequence of The Entertainer and in the large arc of
Doctor Zhivago, the underlying assumption is that so many things happen
in a life, even in a few hours of a life, that each and every one of them cannot
be shown onscreen: some (artful) elision must occur. But beyond elision is
secretly accelerating and decelerating elision, making patient (tranquil) and
76 THE FILM CHEAT
anxious (jerky) elisions. In the end, elision is the control mechanism for
the advancement of what is to come. It is possible to cheat the fact of the
modulation of elisions.
Elision and holding off oncomingness are intrinsically and very profoundly
musical. In his autobiography, Little Did I Know: Excerpts from Memory,
our greatest contemporary philosopher, whose life was devoted to both
thought and harmony, writes of the signal part played by anticipation in, as
he says, “our need for music” (Cavell 400). Stanley Cavell was remembering
a traumatic moment when he first came to consider this, but the nub of his
suspicion was that the musical interval, a fundament of musical form, was
tied in its power and effect to the very human experience of waiting for a
release yet to come. It seems a wholly musical aspect of cinema, then, that
scenes might move differently, some promising resolution swiftly, here, now,
here, now, here; and some implying that time and life move in an adagio,
that change will surely come but one must be patient for it. One thinks of the
spluttering, egotistical Italian music teacher in Kane (Fortunio Bonanova)
pressing Susan to get a phrase right---NOW! Her lack of vocal talent will
become clear to everyone, but not quite so swiftly as that. By contrast, if we
watch Baby (Ansel Elgort) sitting at the wheel of his robin red getaway car
while his associates hit a bank in Baby Driver (2017), sitting at ease with
his headphones on, singing along with the music, using the steering wheel
as a drum set, twitching and gyrating in his seat all the while keeping his
calm, steady eye on the doors to the bank, we see a progression that could
well be an unbounded wait. In fact, he is so appealing to watch waiting
that we wish the moment could go on for the whole length of the film, and
feel irritated when it is interrupted by the thieves racing back with the loot.
Anticipation is variable, as musical tempo is, but it is always the extension
of form through tempo, the placement of event in a phrase of anticipation,
that builds the musical character of a drama and fills its heart.
Audiences sense this if they do not explicitly know it. They do not expect
diegetic movement to be uniform. In Baby Driver, immediately after the
bank heist, and its culminating, very long, unbelievably catastrophic and
near-catastrophic road chase—a prestissimo staccato adventure if ever
was—we see Baby cruising happily and in an idiosyncratic little dance down
a sidewalk to fetch coffee (more on this later). The pace is all new, but the
shift away from a prior pace to a present one is part of the music that is
expected in cinema. The building up and cultivating of this expectation,
however, is a cheat: a mounting of cultivation that occurs while the viewer
is blocked from noticing that she rides in a vehicle driven by someone whose
foot presses down upon, then pulls away from, the accelerator.
Beyond all of this rests a still more colossal cheat.
Regardless of the tempo at which a scene’s or moment’s “melody” is
struck, regardless of the number of beats to the minute it has (a metronome
marking of sixty meaning that there is one beat every second), regardless of
KEEPING MINUTES 77
the stretch of action, the actual minutes of clock time, always quietly present,
move by without tempo. Tempo is an artifice laid over time. The clock has
no tempo, but it is through tempo that we experience what it registers. (By
altering some of the words in a sentence, or its length and placement, a
writer can affect the reader’s sense of tempo in reading. But the ethereal
page is always underneath.) Ingmar Bergman illustrates this paradox in The
Touch (1971), where Bibi Andersson slowly walks around the thoroughly
objectified body, stilled upon the bed, of her recently deceased mother. On
the wall we see the hand of a clock jigging along in its mechanical life. Tick-
tick-tick, time goes by as one is frozen in the face of the living and non-living
bodies together.
However it is that time passes--if we can say that it actually does pass-
-as far as we are able to surmise it passes uniformly. Yet even this cannot
be established. If we can presume—as we do always tend to presume—that
there is one time and only one time, and that it has a certain precise density,
we must see that through any pair of film scenes, any dramatic processes,
where a figure moves ahead through anticipation to some resolution or
partial resolution, first to one destination and later to another, through
all of this sped-up or slowed-down movement time itself is uniform. The
expectation of an event coming after this event produces an interval, but
intervals are superimposed on time. When we go to the movies, we spend an
hour and a half or two hours of our lives looking at the screen, no matter
how fast, and across what time frame, creatures on the screen appear to
move. In musical terms, when we listen to two movements of a symphony,
an adagio and then an allegro, even if the first seems reflective and swellingly
slow and the second brisk and urgent the clock ticks on, through both.2
Filmmakers are obliged to cheat this truth, and anyone’s acknowledgment
of it, by concocting, just as composers do, variable scenes, slow, fast, fast,
faster, faster still, very slow, stationary, fast again. Failing to do this would
leave the audience open to seeing how artificial even accidental scenic
rhythms are; how filmic “time” and time are not the same. At that point the
screen’s precious illusion is broken. The changes in tempo, the accelerations
and decelerations, keep us awake and waiting for what is to come as though
it really is what is to come rather than only “what is to come.” Our actual
wait as cinemagoers must be the wait we endure as human beings, because
it is (only) as human beings that we are cinemagoers. We wait through the
drumbeats for tomorrow, knowing that Time makes dupes of us all.
2
And the conductor can tell you how many minutes and seconds that movement will take. But
that clock: I forbear here to include discussion of Einstein’s dictum that the issue of whether
one is moving with the direction of the ether, against it, or perpendicular to it actually affects
the clock in use.
78
Of Performances
{11} Monster!
Lon Chaney; The Phantom of the Opera; The Unholy Three; The General
Died at Dawn; latex; Akim Tamiroff; Predator; Alien; Jacques de Vaucanson
{13} Pain
Montgomery Clift; Judgment at Nuremberg; Jack Nicholson; Chinatown
{14} Measuring Up
Dustin Hoffman; Marlon Brando; Christopher Walken; Christian Bale; Sean
Astin; Robert DeNiro; Vincent D’Onofrio; Jaws
{15} Privacy
Animal Kingdom; Psycho; Elephant; North by Northwest; Alien: Covenant;
Blow-Up; The Forsyte Saga; Taking Lives; Atonement
{16} Dance
Kramer vs. Kramer; Annie Hall
{17} Keyed Up
Hercules; Samson & Ulysses; Casablanca; Remember; An American in
Paris; The Big Store; The Birds
{20} Surrender
Edward Scissorhands; A Ghost Story; Alien
80
11
Monster!
FIGURE 11 Raymond Massey in Arsenic and Old Lace (Frank Capra, Warner
Bros., 1944).
Manifesto:
It is never wholly salutary to launch an attack on other people’s
fantasies, though in the case of politico-military fantasies taken to extremes
in everyday life (the dream of the Master Race) such attacking has more
than once proved necessary and effective. But the imaginative, fabular,
82 THE FILM CHEAT
mythological fantasies that distort for thrill, that effect some telltale frisson:
these live within our darkest thoughts in a logic none of us can control
or find the origin of. If conscience doth make cowards of us all, so does
consciousness. In film stories, the character of the monster is everywhere,
chilling, terrifying, awakening, warning, provoking us through the mask of
characters’ engagement.
Monstrosity is not always biological or corporeal, yet in film, which
must relentlessly make shows, the body warp is the least ambiguous way
of suggesting it. While in the real world there are no twistings, meldings,
hypertrophies, absences, duplications, and miscolorations of the body
that lack a medical explanation of one kind or another,1 usually in film
narrative the scientific rationale for monstrosity is either only hinted at or
vaguely circumlocuted, or skipped entirely in favor of a disarming depiction
floating without rationale. When we see disfigurement in the everyday, and
without an explanatory rationale, it can be powerfully disarming, and this
happened to me many decades ago when I was brought face to face with
the residents of a retreat for the bodily disfigured not far from Chicago.
The faces I saw there I had dreamed, or seen, onscreen dozens of times, yet
I knew those cinematic faces were accomplished with makeup, while these
were not. Misshaping, duplication, swelling, and, perhaps most disarmingly,
misplacement of facial elements were legion, among these mostly quite
young people who got along with one another effortlessly but seemed wary
of outsiders coming in to visit, even with the kindliest intention.2 If there
were explanations to be had in every case, one did not have them, they
were not provided. In cinema the explanation is often not provided, surely
not with any accuracy of detail. Stories instead labor to regale us with the
“magical potion,” the “experimental technique gone awry,” the “chemicals
inadvertently mixed up,” the “mad scientist,” the “curse,” and so on.
Monstrosity onscreen is typically produced by means of an actor
transform, and Lon Chaney (1883–1930) is widely considered to be the first
performer who accomplished this in a prodigious, elaborate, and brilliant
way. His mutations, as the monster in Frankenstein, as the Phantom of
the Opera, and as legion others are Hollywood legend, particularly since
he designed and almost always single-handedly applied his own makeup.3
While the general proportions of Chaney’s face remained more or less
constant through his work, the qualitative modulations he produced in his
eyes, nose, mouth, ears, hairline, cheeks, and jaw were so radical that his
1
A medical explanation that vitiates the chill of encounter, according to Fiedler.
2
David Lynch’s The Elephant Man (1980) will give plain illustration of the sort of kindly
intention that has no weight in such circumstances.
3
See Matthew Solomon’s analysis of Herbert Brenon’s Laugh, Clown, Laugh (1928) in
“Laughing Silently.”
MONSTER! 83
creatures gave all signs of having genuine physiognomies of their own, and
he became known popularly as the Man of a Thousand Faces.
Chaney’s tricks usually included some combination of three main features.
He would use tiny wires to pull or twist skin or musculature (painfully), thus
producing ricti, uncontrollable slobbering, the twisted gaze (as he told me
in 1986, Dick Smith used a similar technique for removing Frank Sinatra’s
jowls in The Detective [1968]). Secondly, Chaney would use make-up paints
to color and miscolor parts of the body, always with a view to what the
effect would be on black-and-white film (where color contrast does not
function); and he would wear wigs, rings, distinctive costumes in general.
Thirdly, he would use performative techniques: grimaces, postures, limps,
stooping, and so on. His last film was Jack Conway’s The Unholy Three in
1930. He died at the age of forty-seven, before the era of latex.
For Lewis Milestone’s The General Died at Dawn (1936), Charles
Gemora invented a liquid latex application for producing slanted eyelids
on the Caucasian actor Akim Tamiroff (1899–1972), celebrated later for
his work in Dragon Seed (1944), Touch of Evil (1958), Ocean’s 11 (1960),
and Topkapi (1964), among many other films. The latex eyelids permitted
Tamiroff’s Genl. Yang to appear on camera without the actor experiencing
notable discomfort (as was Chaney’s lot). The success of Gemora’s
application promoted its use more liberally in The Wizard of Oz (1939) for,
among many other demonstrables, the Wicked Witch’s extensive nose and
much of the Cowardly Lion’s adorably cowardly face. Gemora (1903–61)
had been a Hollywood stand-by for populating the famously popular gorilla
suit (partly because he was not tall); he worked that way with Chaney in
Unholy Three, Béla Lugosi in Murders in the Rue Morgue (1932), the Marx
Brothers in At the Circus (1939), and many other films, before leaving the
suit behind and turning alien, beginning with War of the Worlds (1953).
Latex applications are made after a face mask is taken of the actor, baked
to hardening, and then used as the substrate upon a copy of which the artist
applies the monster “flesh” using soft, moldable clay. When the copy and
the original are superimposed, blank spots will show wherever the build-up
is found and from these blanks, separate latex partial masks are fashioned.
Ron Miller astutely notes how these partial masks are used even when a
whole face is to be refashioned, since one of the telltale giveaways that
makeup is being used is a rigidity of expression, and multiple partial masks
allow the actor much more muscular flexibility. (It goes without saying that
actors develop a particular facility in using the musculature of the face.) The
partials are applied to the actor’s face using spirit gum or other adhesive,
having been fashioned in the first place with extremely thin edges so that
make-up paint applied on top can blend them smoothly and imperceptibly
with the actor’s (normal or painted) skin. There are so many cases of supreme
latex effects in Hollywood cinema it would be impossible to construct even
a short list, especially considering the bizarre creatures in George Lucas’s
84 THE FILM CHEAT
Star Wars (1977), the Gary Oldman transform as Dracula (1992), the water
creatures in Hellboy (2004) and The Shape of Water (2017), and one of the
most celebrated makeup jobs in Hollywood history, Dick Smith’s aging of
Dustin Hoffman in Little Big Man (1970).
As legion movie fans know, from having grown up with the relative
normality of “monstrous” configurations on their favorite screens, latex
applications painted with extraordinary artistry can be used to turn any actor
into virtually any sort of being or thing, as long as the producer is willing
to spend the money and time and can find the make-up artists to do it. The
turning is affected, however, by whatever knowledge, or half-knowledge, lies
latent in the viewer. While most who watch films do not know precisely how
disfigurements are created, they do know that disfigurements are created,
and that as they watch the unspeakable movements and actions of screen
monstrosities they are seeing tricks.4 (A neat evasion is to avoid gaining
knowledge of the cast in advance. With Bong Joon Ho’s Snowpiercer [2013]
the benefits can be delightful.) Whereas with stage magic prestidigitation was
a central, perhaps the central, technique—keep the hands moving so quickly
nobody can see what they’re doing—with the “magic” of screen make-up
the artist using latex and paint is not at work in front of the audience at
all. The process can therefore be as slow and methodical as production
schedules allow for. The chief skill involves hand-eye coordination: having
deft skill cooking and baking the latex and then a keen eye for figuring the
precise colorations to apply in blending it in (with a view to photography
under specific light temperatures and against specific backgrounds).
But as in stage magic, the essential problem of cheating appears and
reappears: something is being done that must be made to appear as something
else, or as nothing. The latex pieces must not be seen as latex (Andy Serkis,
Lord of the Rings: The Two Towers [2002]); nor the paint as paint (Judi
Dench, Shakespeare in Love [1998]); nor the dental implants as implants
(Jerry Lewis, The Nutty Professor [1963]); nor the special contact lenses
as contacts (David Bowie, The Man Who Fell to Earth [1976]); nor there
being a point where the bald cap or wig attaches to the skull (F. Murray
Abraham, Amadeus [1984]); nor the actor’s technique in modulating vocal
and muscular movement (John Hurt, The Elephant Man). With the screen
“monster,” a sharp professional eye is turned not to what has been done
with the body but to how this change will look once photographed, and so
the make-up test is invaluable. Nevertheless, the screen “monster” walks a
very thin tightrope in performance for many reasons:
4
The education of many viewers, especially young ones, has been fostered by Mission Control
Media’s television show Face Off (2011), featuring Michael Westmore (of the Westmore
dynasty), Ve Neill, and other artists.
MONSTER! 85
The “discharge” proved most popular, most tellingly evidential of the trueness,
the naturalness, and unaffectedness of the thing. How, if it does this, could it
be constructed?5 With the alien in Alien, two discrete tricks are used to cheat
the audience’s attention. First, we never see the entire thing top to bottom
until the very end of the film—and then only far too briefly—so it is left to the
imagination to specify magnitudes (as with the shark in Jaws [1975], where the
trick is taken one step further in that the entire creature is never quite visibly
shown, unless it is underwater and thrashing, at which point the thrashing
action distracts us). The second is that the innermost mouth is geared and
powered to run over with distracting drool when—so unbelievably swiftly—it
snaps to produce death.6 The monstrous body is doing Show Business. Before
one can stand back for serious evaluation, the “show” is over.
The actor playing the monstrosity finds in the mirror that a trick of a
different kind has been played, because inside the appurtenance the self is very
hard to find. The movement of the face must be relearned to fit the moldings.
Movement on land and in the water must be naturalized to the species—
the “species”—of the thing instead of to the needs of the performer. And of
course working conditions deteriorate almost always, because one is locked
into gear that limits muscularity, produces sweltering heat under film lighting,
is hard to eat through and so on. The point here isn’t that the “monster” is
uncomfortable for the performer to act but that the discomfort is a distraction
and being “monstrous” in front of a camera requires intense concentration of
effort, all of which must scrupulously be hidden. The monster is the veritable
star of the film, and when it is onscreen audiences do not back away from
inspecting its smallest features, like nineteenth-century nursemaids picking
lice from the head of a child. The telltale small feature is one of the cheats of
the monster trope: it distracts attention from the thing as a whole.
With monstrosities, the viewer is positioned in two discreet atria, one in
which is exhibited nothing but technique, strategy, know-how, manipulation,
and craft, and the other a cavern of fear and disorienting “ugliness,”
misshapen abysm, horrifying excesses and absences. We see the special effect
we have paid to see, surely, yet are shocked by sights that go far beyond
what we knew to want, sights that disarm, terrify, and rouse other screen
characters just as they do us. If in this delicious and elaborate cheat our
foreknowledge fails to salve, is this because in some grand Schadenfreude
only the thought of destroying our knowledge through exceeding it, brings
release?
5
The Eating Machine at Hobart’s Museum of Contemporary Art works in a cognate fashion,
although with literal transparency.
6
A derivation from the snap of the animated crocodile in Disney’s Peter Pan (1953).
12
A Star, Not a Star
presence onscreen. Stars thus play key roles. Character players are cast as
eccentric sidekicks, bizarre villains, personable henchmen, and the like. The
problem that produces the relevant cheat here is one that becomes clear
when we note the differential optical allure of both types of actors.
The star must shine, indeed must appear to be the source of light that makes
the whole screen shine. No matter the character in question, the star beneath
has the viewer’s commitment of love, and must therefore be manifested in an
unquestionably recognizable way.1 There are few exceptions to this formula.
Not only will the star appear to dominate the story, he or she will on every
appearance dominate the screen. But often a scene must be played with
a partner who is a character actor, a persona comparatively enshadowed.
Character players, in role, are as often undetectable as detectable, as
often marginal as nearly central, as often accompanied by a team of other
character players as alone. These actor types, stars and character players, are
effectively statuses that attach to persons in an ongoingly negotiable way.
In a film like Murder on the Orient Express (1974) (reprised in much the
same form in 2017), many former big stars—Michael York, Wendy Hiller,
Jacqueline Bisset, Jean-Pierre Cassel, Vanessa Redgrave, Anthony Perkins—
are relegated to character-player status, albeit “star character-player” status,
against the repeating (but in this case marginal) domination of Albert Finney
(latterly Kenneth Branagh) as Hercule Poirot. However, given that the star
is central and the character actor only (but fully) adjacent, how can the
difference between their statuses be reconciled with (a) the need for the
fiction to elude viewers’ consciousness of status difference as such, (b) the
director and cinematographer’s need to compose shots including both at
once, and (c) the ongoing requirement that no matter what happens, all the
players onscreen should appear to belong in the same package, the same
“world,” yet at the same time belong there in different (classed) ways?
Return with me to Akim Tamiroff, born of Armenian descent in Russia, a
student from 1918 of Konstantin Stanislavsky. A consummate professional,
he was noted in America for his character parts, playing always against a
dignified, handsome, or flamboyant star (Anthony Perkins, Frank Sinatra
and Dean Martin, Orson Welles). The thick Slav tongue, the pouting eyes,
the extraordinary bejowled cheeks made possible a kind of expressive
plasticity, to which the actor’s off-kilter English added tang. Like so many
character players in Hollywood’s golden age, Tamiroff found himself cast
many times over in the same sorts of roles, it being a production practice
trusted and true for directors and heads of casting departments to look at
1
Although in this context, it is wise to consider Noa Steimatsky’s inspired confusion watching
Michelangelo Antonioni’s Il provino/Prefazione (The Screen Test/Preface, 1965): It was
impossible for her to know “at what level of the re-enactment we stand. Fiction and actuality,
action and re-enactment, person and role are compressed” (183).
90 THE FILM CHEAT
actors by way of clips from previous films, often and easily borrowed from
any studio (nowadays, eager actors seeking work provide their own “reels,”
which are typically high-definition disks containing scenes from the films
they’ve made). The prosthetic eyes he wore in The General Died at Dawn
(1936) attracted attention in their own way in a white-dominated culture
that doted on caricaturing other cultural types—in her book Romance
and the “Yellow Peril,” Gina Marchetti gives a critical view of this kind
of colonization, commenting, for example, on how the Swedish actor Nils
Asther (1897–1981), a notably handsome face in Hollywood from 1926
through the mid-1950s, played Frank Capra’s The Bitter Tea of General Yen
(1932) in “grotesquely designed” makeup (50). Asther had no prosthetics
there, but he did sport sharply defined and outrageously angled eyebrows,
which consistently brought attention to his eyes. As to the easily converted
Tamiroff, in the mid-1940s, when Harold Bucquet and Jack Conway were
preparing Dragon Seed at MGM, they would have been familiar with
Tamiroff’s work in General Died and possibly even have cast him because
of it. The cheat of the latex was therefore helpful not only for establishing
a precise (and peculiar) caricature but also for furthering an actor’s career.
The character player is faced with the challenge of unendingly transforming
the self for camera, so as to be able to play one distinct type, say, at Warner
Bros. for three days’ shooting and a quite different one at Fox just afterward
for two days’ more, and so on. Make-up, hairdressing, the manner of carrying
the costume, vocal modulation, quirky facial expression—all these features,
taboo for the star who must always be a Self—aid in the changes. While
one will find the star’s portrait photograph a fairly accurate representation
of the being one has been seeing on the screen, the character actor’s might
be unidentifiable, posed as it is in unaffected clothing, without makeup for
character, and in less sculpted light. In fan magazines and other publicity, the
star’s head shot will gain a different kind of prominence, showing him or her
off as a blemish-free, intensely expressive point of contact. Stars typically
don’t need to withdraw prosthetic masks for such “everyday” photography
because as a rule they don’t wear prosthetic masks in the first place, they
show and sell themselves as being what they “actually are.” In the case of
Gary Cooper, a photographer will take care to light the facial bone structure
prominently, to have bounce light emerge from the eyes. And assistants will
see to it that the hair is not only impeccable but also harmoniously singing.
Cary Grant will look debonair and relaxed, as though the camera is his
mother. Joaquin Phoenix—who started out playing characters and became
a star, yet maintained a preference for odd characters to bear his stardom—
appears on a cover of Vanity Fair (for October 2019) standing at the lip
of a swimming pool in a white shirt and black tie, but he is in the pool,
having been doused, and is sopping wet: adventurous, daring, over the edge,
serious, sincere, and calm, with dark penetrating eyes. Marilyn Monroe is
photographed by Richard Avedon in a tight-fitting black spangled dress
A STAR, NOT A STAR 91
with an extended V-neck. She is fully made up but her hair is in shambles
(the Hangover look) and she gazes slightly off-camera with her eyes half
drawn in what seems like sadness. For Bert Stern her platinum hair explodes
in waves, her eyes beckon, and her smile tickles amusingly, as though she is
having a dirty thought.
All actors’ head shots are cheats—they must be; their function is not to
tag but to flog the person—but the star shot is an elaborately fashioned
one. Studio executives don’t cast on the basis of this sort of thing, since
stars are either on contract with work routinely assigned or else independent
contractors desired in advance by the producer. But for both the glamour
figure and the character figure, advertising photographs and narrative
cinematography both work to create two bonds: one of the actor with her
diegetic character, the other between the characters themselves (the relation
between the actors being almost always of no account on set). The identity
of any actor as employee is wedded to the identity of a character and also
to the ensemble of personae to be found inside the narrative. Each character
abiding there must fit. Yet at the dining table of labor, only some sit at the
head.
But the star’s centrality and the relatively peripheral placement of
character actors work together to fashion a complex cheat upon the
audience’s knowledge. The screen must be composed with fields of relative
importance so that the viewer can have assistance in swiftly focusing and
following the details of a story. This is one good reason why star players
constantly have more intense lighting. But the lighting of character players
in the star’s surround must seem to logically derive, to be related in intensity
if not to match, and all this irrespective of the “natural light” that is being
simulated in the “place.” Lighting does a lot to bring actors’ work in line,
to affiliate characters while maintaining bright star centrality, and thus the
lighting hides actual working relations in a very particular way. In the world
of film labor offscreen, however, hierarchical distance may not exist between
workers or may exist very acutely, it being possible for a star to attend the
same synagogue on Rosh Hashanah as the character actor he played with
yesterday, or play poker with him on an off-work weekend, or refuse to be
in the same room. Yet at the same time, and completely covered over by
both script and light, one performer may be separate from another—even
when both are stars, or both character actors—for reasons audiences do
not surmise. One example: in Sweet Smell of Success (1957), Burt Lancaster
and Tony Curtis share star billing, and both feature as centerpieces of any
and every shot that includes either of them. But Lancaster’s company was
producing the film, and in effect he was paying Curtis for his labor. There
is a power split between the two onscreen but it has nothing to do with the
power split behind the camera. Harry Carey and later his son Harry Carey
Jr. were intimate friends of John Wayne, but in John Wayne’s westerns they
again and again played subsidiary character parts to his star turns.
92 THE FILM CHEAT
show. One is overcome by the sense that if there were any way for him to
do it, Clift would cover over his scars and his reshapen face and resort to
only performing a character’s grotesquerie, yet also that any cover-up would
bring him closer to the looker’s attention not further away. The only solution
is willing (even proud) acceptance of the blemish as, now, an intrinsic part
of identity, a feature that belongs where it is, and hoping that the viewer will
make the necessary allowances. Nor is serious wounding always a strictly
visual matter. When we have a performer with a broken voice, we hear the
break in every syllable of dialogue, but make allowances (Jack Krugman,
Julie Andrews after her Broadway run in Victor/Victoria), fully aware that,
unlike a false limb but very like a tortured face, it cannot be hidden. Erving
Goffman notes in Stigma one of the effects of body repair: “Where . . . repair
is possible, what often results is not the acquisition of fully normal status,
but a transformation of self from someone with a particular blemish into
someone with a record of having corrected a particular blemish” (Stigma
9). Clift’s “blemish” not only resulted from but was the accident itself; his
history and his presentation of self in Nuremberg is an indication of a repair
dutifully and successfully undertaken. Goffman goes on:
The matter of Petersen and Clift together on the witness stand complicates
analysis. Petersen has been disfigured in an invisible way, but his wail renders
the sterilization at least conceptually visible; at the same time Clift, who
is Petersen at this moment, carries a very visible and totally unchangeable
stigma. Between the audience and the character, between me and Petersen as
I watch his torment (and perhaps think of it as a remodeling of his torment
in the car, as Clift), there is a relationship of intimacy, “public intimacy.”
We are always intimate with the characters of the screen but this peculiar
intimacy is touched by the touch of fate.
The structuring of Rudolph Petersen as a man whose sex has been
maimed and, more chillingly, as a victim at the hands of the Third Reich,
gives him a stigma not only ineradicable (like Clift’s facial trauma) but in
a way pendulous, of great gravity. The male can think of himself as “the
same” (but altered) if his face is reconstructed surgically.1 But if his testes
are removed surgically or blocked chemically from functioning his self-
1
This applies to Mark Hamill’s transformation and to Ann-Margret’s after her stage accident
in September 1972.
96 THE FILM CHEAT
FIGURE 14 Jon Voight and Dustin Hoffman in Midnight Cowboy (John Schlesinger,
Jerome Hellman Productions, 1969).
“We already and from the first discern him making this thing other,” writes
Norman O. Brown (8). This thing, the whole thing, the central thing as he
must know it, himself, yet also the self as entity, his body. The body as sized.
The body as a performance in itself.
Acting is more or less one or the other of two possibilities, in practice.
It is being, which is living, in its fullest essentiality, such as is seen with
Kristen Stewart in Personal Shopper (2016) or Elliott Gould in The Long
Goodbye (1973). (The camera catches it all. You cannot lie to the camera.)
And this is metamorphosis. (Metamorphosis – Becoming – Transformation
– Hiding.) As there is never anything onscreen but truth and whole truth,
MEASURING UP 99
what was complete and real at the moment the aperture was open. In this
sincerity of the flesh there is constant metamorphosis in that as time passes
life flickers and develops and no two moments are the same. The actor must
authentically feel his presence in his moment, and must negotiate secretly,
that is, privately, with the character in order to give the character openness
to, and access to, that mutability. In such acting one does not play a scene,
one plays a life.
On the other hand we have construction, masquerade, where the character
is a device the actor literally or metaphorically puts on. Anthony Hopkins as
Hannibal Lecter, Mary Astor as The Princess Centimillia in The Palm Beach
Story (1942). One finds here a notable constancy moment to moment, the
constancy (almost rigidity) of a portrait in a frame, because the mask is not
alive in itself. Also a strange quality of presentation: metallically articulate,
burnished, intensified beyond human limit, not what we find in people but
what we find in people represented.
With both kinds of acting the performer has no choice but to be, finally,
in self-knowledge as well as in presentation, a body, this body and not that
one, and whether the body is expressed without reserve (Brando in Don
Juan DeMarco [1994], playing a toss-and-catch-the-popcorn game in bed
with Faye Dunaway) or is affected through contortive manipulations (John
Hurt as Merrick in The Elephant Man [1980]) still the camera cannot but
show it, there being nothing else of the performative self to show. And what
the camera shows must stand, hold itself, breathe, and get dressed. What is
it that happens onscreen with the actorly body as the camera team contrives
to shape, arrange, and show it? Especially in regards to a key aspect of
the actor’s body, something no actor and no person would go through life
without both sensing and recognizing: size. Toooo large. Tooooo small.
Jusssst right!
As to corporeal girth, overall weight (involving bone density), or bulk,
essentially horizontal displacement, impressions are not difficult to manage.
Pads work very well (Orson Welles as Falstaff [1965], Angelina Jolie in
Regression [2015]) and are nicely concealed, but lens choice can be easier
still, wide-angle lenses (below 50 mm) tending to spread space laterally
(permitting a more closely-positioned camera) and spreading body elements
(facial elements notably) outward from the center of the screen. Dream
sequences, drug hallucinations, memories, and so on are very frequently
established through extreme wide-angle photography, 18 mm or 20 mm.
On the contrary, the longer the lens the more the body will withdraw.
Clothing may hide a body the camera finds oversized in relation to others
in the scene, in construction but also in fabric texture and color in relation
to the texture and color of the props and set. Color affects us strongly
through contrast (on which see Albers). Coloration can cause a garment,
and therefore the body encased in it, to apparently recede into or spring
from the background, as a shot or character placement might require. The
100 THE FILM CHEAT
1
My gratitude to Dan Sacco for this and related observations about actor size.
MEASURING UP 101
The star close-up will very often take an actor’s face and magnify it so
that it fills the entire screen. Spread poster-like before us will be the well-
known features in sympathetic array, the parts bearing relation to one
another in a predictable and pleasing manner. But in the real world, close-
up lenses missing, we do not have opportunity to view the star, or anyone,
with this kind of proximity mixed with sharp focal clarity. The performer
is of necessity smaller in reality. On the street one can perhaps recognize
the performer (there is a delicious scenic moment in The King of Comedy
[1982] about precisely this: “When it’s him it doesn’t look like him.”). But
the comparison between screen persona and real personality, as embodied,
goes far beyond the simplicity of measurement. For the viewer there are
subjectively felt components of any perception. The screen body has a
plasticity actual bodies do not present themselves as having; it seems to
float in space rather than being gravitationally bounded. Onscreen there is
no gravity. The screen body travels magically, is cut apart and apportioned
magically (medium shots, close-ups) then magically reconstituted (long
shots), touches the objects in view in an only barely discernable way. The
actor’s everyday body, should one encounter it in the everyday, turns away
in privacy or modesty or distraction and does not present, “face-on,” that
recognizable star hieroglyph.
●● Nor is there recognizable pathos in the screen body itself, outside
of what a scripted moment might inspire us to read or imagine.
The actorial face that is scarred, blemished, misshapen—all
medical contingencies—is made over so that the character face
can harmonize with other character faces. Extra lines are filled;
pimples are covered; scars are painted just as sometimes for good
dramatic reasons scars are painted on. The character body is
entirely fashioned in coherence with dramatic requirement, and
at the expense of the producer; but the performative body is kept
in reserve—it operates through a history of employment. We must
always remember that in the golden years, actors on the studio
contract found that the way they appeared, both onscreen and
offscreen if they were in public, literally belonged to the studio.
●● Further, although we come to know the character in her diegetic
surround, become able to effect recognition in a flash, we tend not to
know the actor at all, except as a result of work. She offers a routine
presence behind characters roughly like this one (like: recognizably
covering or based upon the same actorial persona). The face goes
with a name, if only a name attached to a face. We don’t know
MEASURING UP 103
Wash
In Animal Kingdom (2016), teenaged orphan Josh (Finn Cole) has taken up
residence with his grandmother, her chum, and her three sons, who range
PRIVACY 105
in age from their mid-twenties to late thirties. One of this crowd, Shawn
(Andrew “Pope” Cody), is fresh out of jail, and eager to help the other
three with a heist job. He is assigned to find a getaway car and wishes to
commandeer the help of the young visitor. At the moment in question J.—as
he calls himself—is in the shower. Important to be clear: (a) a young actor
at least appears to be in front of us, completely naked, self-cleansing; and
(b) a script has specified that in this scene the character called “J.” will be
showering. Earlier moments have explicitly not identified J. as mudstained
or uncomfortable physically, that is, desperately in need of a shower, and
nothing in the immediately ensuing action dictates that J. should be recently
cleansed. We have to find him somewhere, and the decision has been made
to put him in the shower.
Our camera is both inside the shower stall with J. (a cursory half-nod to
Psycho [1960]) and malingering on the wafer-thin border between the stall
and the bathroom, where Shawn makes his entry and presses J. to hurry up
and get dressed so they can get going. In the shots of their interaction the
camera is cranked up so that the images are uniformly chest-up on both sides,
eyeline match being established with some care since, again as per the script,
it is to be signaled to the viewer that the sudden intruder is not looking, just
as the viewer is not looking (has not been given to look) at J.’s body, only
at J.’s receptive face. The sound of the running water is continually present.
There are intermittent, and rhythmically edited, de rigueur shots of nude
J. running hands over himself as he listens (that is, Cole gives a believable
show1).
This little scene figures for me here because it is a notably clear and
uncontaminated example of a much replicated trope in contemporary
television and film work. Some character of interest, alone or with someone
else, is in the process of showering or taking a bath when the camera
discovers the action and attends it. Eric Deulen and Alex Frost in Gus Van
Sant’s Elephant (2006) tellingly cleaning each other, an erotic and revealing
moment if at the same time cheated through (typical) genital masking;
Daniel Craig and Olga Kurylenko in Marc Forster’s Quantum of Solace
(2008); Virginia Gardner showering behind a heavy (but not heavy enough)
curtain in David Gordon Green’s Halloween (2018); Keanu Reeves with Ana
Ularu in the bathtub in Matthew Ross’s Siberia (2018); Scarlett Johannson
simulating Janet Leigh in Sacha Gervasi’s Hitchcock (2012); Matt Damon
fingering the warm green water as Jude Law bathes in The Talented Mr.
Ripley (1999); little Jack Dylan Grazer showering with his favorite clown
in Andy Muschietti’s It (2017); teenaged Gabrielle Anwar sucked under the
1
Believable: he follows a series of steps that could be taken from a Shower Manual that all of
us possess and use religiously, as though nobody could be in any doubt as to what some other
person would do in a shower.
106 THE FILM CHEAT
for recuperation [that never comes].) Why would it not be sufficient for the
showering character to say, “I’m going to shower,” and then emerge cleaned
up and in fresh clothing? In what way can we understand it being necessary
that the shower be evidenced? Leaving aside the nonsensical speculation that
we find the character inherently false and want to get underneath the clothing
to find the true identity—since there is nothing inherently true about skin,
in performance—can we think we understand ourselves entering the shower
because we doubt some situational sincerity and ingenuousness, suspect
the character is really using the shower or its sound for a purpose quite
other than cleansing, and one we should discover (Roger Thornhill [Cary
Grant] slyly deceiving Eve Kendal [Eva Marie Saint] in North by Northwest
[1959])? Or do we imagine there is some important piece of information that
can be conveyed only in the shower/bath situation, a code to be discerned
in the grout between tiles? Regarding that last possibility, it’s important that
we keep in mind a simple fact of visual narrative: that the tiles would gain
attention. No matter the content of the dialogue in a shower or bath scene,
the fact of the naked body in a warm and cozy circumstance will override it.
Do we enter the shower because, as the filmmakers have correctly presumed
of us, we are eager to see the actor without clothes and the shower or bath
is the perfect (and perfectly conventional) pretext? Thus, in watching the
shower/bath scene, or at least in watching ourselves watching it, are we
made conscious to some degree of our own desire to strip the performer?
Do we have to make some particular self-identification in order to accede
to this hypothetical situation, a self-identification that is a potential self-
incrimination, and does the setting of the shower or bath assist us, prime us,
in doing that? Because stumbling into a stranger bathing can be a cause of
shame or embarrassment, a cheat is required in the cinematography so that
we can preserve our self-esteem, and that cheat is the odd framing. Is cinema
perhaps always everywhere about stripping away coverings, so that a desire
to see people without clothing is no different, really, than a desire to hear
them tell the secrets of their heart? What are we presumed to want always
and already, that we can relish being given such spectacles?
A certain realism is built up by masked shower/bath scenes. We are
systematically brought close to a stranger’s body—speaking in terms of the
intimacies we all allow, both the character and the actor are in fact strangers
to us—and allowed, even encouraged, to participate in two optical fictions:
(a) First, that this stranger, while being rather fully unknown, is
nevertheless, somehow, not quite a stranger. Not only can we apply a name,
in fact two names, but this person is sharply and instantly recognizable as
belonging to a type we have learned to recognize already: not only a female,
say, but a female of a certain race and age, who does or does not have a
job, and if she has a job who works in one kind of occupation rather than
another; so that altogether she belongs on a kind of “team,” containing
not only her but others as well. She is an exemplar. We establish a relation
108 THE FILM CHEAT
that is typical rather than personal, encountering and swiftly accounting for
aspects that accord with our general expectations of people like this. And we
neglect, if we even detect, quirky, idiosyncratic, personal tics, gestures, and
features such as birthmarks, scars, flab, tattoos, all of which could be used in
typification but tend not to be, yet at the same time help mark this body as
foreign, belonging to someone with whom we might form an idiosyncratic
personal bond. The birthmark or tattoo at the top of a bicep, gleaming
now with water, becomes only “a birthmark,” or “a tattoo,” which is to
say a singular example of the broad category of colorings we would name
“birthmarks” or of the broad category of designs we would call “tattoos”
in full knowledge that a legion human beings have similar ones and scrub
them in the same way, yet also, to some little degree, this birthmark or this
tattoo, drawing us in a little or nudging us away. The shower is not the
place we zoom in for deciphering. In the shower/bath we are presented with
singular examples of types, but not individual people. Not fully and only
this mark, this tattoo, this positioning, this body, this arm, this man but
Mark, Tattoo, Posture, Person. This cataloging is a form of cheat, in that
the peculiarities, the puncta, that describe a single unique embodiment are
flattened and subsumed under types so that we can operate as though we do
not see the actual solitary nude human being in the frame.2
(b) Secondly, that we are performing the gaze upon this body strictly
in accordance with well-accepted conventional norms of behavior in such
places and such company. There is a proper way to watch someone shower,
and we know and obey the rules. We look at the head, the head and shoulders,
the shoulders and back, even the feet, even the hands using soap upon one
of the body sections just named; but we do not look at the genital area, the
buttocks usually, the breasts, the armpits, the lower belly. This allows us to
think of ourselves as modest, polite, authentic, and sincere rather than being
forced to recognize ourselves as eager to see other people’s privacies. But
this opportunity to confer nobility upon our own gaze is afforded by the
camera’s careful placement and framing, not by our self-discipline (which
in this case is a mere follower), and so it is an ethical cheat as well. We are
never shown something from which the genteel person we would claim to
be, would humbly turn away.3
The underlying question here, the question that brings the cheat into
focus, relates not to our own prudish reticence to look at the naked body
2
By virtue of its identificatory clarity the cinematic nude shot, notably in bathing, differs from
the painted nude discussed by Kenneth Clark.
3
The keyword here is “shown”: we can much more easily be told, especially in printed fiction,
since, first, the verbal mode allows full disbelief and secondly, the words on the page are not
in public display—we are not seen seeing them, so that “turning away” is hardly requisite or
useful. See for a particularly interesting example Bret Easton Ellis’s Glamorama 382ff. And
thanks to Jason Jacobs for pointing this out to me.
PRIVACY 109
(the naked Star Body, indeed) or admit that we would like to, but to the
persistent peeking that is arranged for us, and that we gleefully accept in
the face of that reticence; in short, we have a hungry reticence that models
itself as abstinent reticence; a reticent curiosity that insists on denying how
curious we are. The requirement to direct one’s emotional commitments in
two opposite directions at once produces the requisite cheats that we find—
cheats that help us: heavy glass shower stall doors and walls (easily penetrated
by brutish tongue, as we see with Alien: Covenant [2017]!), extremely misty
weather conditions, flagrant shower heads, copious lakes of bubble bath, or
neatly positioned bodies or body parts. The neat positions work beautifully
for camera, but no one would wish to suffer one of them in real life. All
this notwithstanding the extreme care with which a cinematographer can
compose his frame, using (very typically) the bottom cutoff line to dissect
the bathing body. That cutoff line is an “offside” over which a hand or two
can easily stray, as in grasping a bar of soap or other accoutrement that
might attract attention; or as in reaching up to smooth water away from
the eyes. The actor’s face, a notably expressive zone, often acts as a body
covering: that is, covers up the fact that the filmmaking team is covering up.
The expressive face is endlessly fascinating, and also endlessly distracting if
it belongs to someone on the marquee. It is because covering up must itself
be covered up that cheats become fascinating.
There is nothing particularly new about prudery, modesty, or lascivious
curiosity. What is worth attending to is the structural arrangement by
which curiosity about the body and its private functions is partially but
only partially satisfied, the limitation on satisfaction imposed in the name of
some noble protection of vital interest, some show of diminishing the very
curiosity motivating the style of the presentation in the first place. Without
a presumption of curiosity about the body, there is no sense in visiting
someone in his or her shower in the first place. Taking a shower does not
beg accompaniment: it’s too wet for a secret phone conversation, too humid
for typing a code, too soppy for inscribing codes onto the tiles. And truth is,
there are very few people who sing in the shower so well we would feel we
were at a concert were we there listening to them.
At the beginning of the twentieth century, when John Galsworthy
published The Forsyte Saga, civilized people repressed their curiosities
about other people’s naked bodies, sufficiently satisfied (at least as far as
they felt it was acceptable to demonstrate) by the kind of hints that clothing
could provide. Nowadays while curiosities of this sort are still repressed,
guarded against, actively fought, there lingers a common pretense that they
are not; that glimpsing, peeking, openly seeing are all commonly possible
and socially acceptable exactly because they can be done. The camera’s peek
is taken not to compromise modesty because (only because) modesty can
systematically not be admitted to. Thus, when the camera creeps down a
hallway into a bathroom facility, and thence into a shower stall, where the
110 THE FILM CHEAT
water is running and a naked body is present alone or with another naked
body (or, as in the case of Starship Troopers [1997], a platoon of them),
nothing is marked in the screen image as untoward, strange, perverted, wild
even though we are looking in the manner of those who are not looking. If
the curiosity the camera addresses is considered a wild extravagance if not
a transgression, the camera only marginally gives this the nod. Metonymic
redemption: a body fragment sufficiently rounded and glistening to stand in
(secretly) for the (imaginary) whole.
Copulate
Consider a relatively superficial cheat. Two naked bodies are writhing on
a bed, steamed in the throes of lovemaking. By convention, one tends to
hear an underscore heavy on strings and light on brass and woodwinds, a
score absent the hyperbolic accents of percussion: violins as heartstrings.
Or violins as nerves pulled to the breaking point. Usually in contemporary
film at the beginning of the twenty-first century, the bodies and bed are
photographed in color, although not a great variation in color is actually
to be seen—high color contrast would separate out the bodies, give them
roundness—amber light very often flooding over a bed with rumpled pink
or amber sheeting and casting gleams over amber bodies. There may be
a vocal track of moans and squeals, but they would be minimized in the
mix and the scene would “read” just as clearly without sound as with.
There is sometimes shown a (relatively swift) mounting toward climax,
sometimes not. One is regaled by a virtual Kama Sutra of variant positions.
And with some regularity one or both of the participants rises afterward
and goes about doing something else. In all of this, the body as visualized
is used as a self-cover: intertwined legs symbolize (stand in for, mask)
the linked genitalia that, present or impending, are rigorously not shown
and rigorously motoring the action; torsos overlap; arms interconnect to
form bizarre glyphs as if while copulating the team are sending off coded
intelligence. Parts of heads are visible, or whole heads severed from bodies,
just enough to make sure the viewer can identify the characters and be
pinioned to the drama. Of course the body parts we can see mask over the
body parts we cannot. As to the point of view: the camera seems to rest just
beside the bed, or perched on the sheets to the side of the bodies in play.
We are there.4 Sheets and duvets will decorously cover, and then salaciously
uncover, parts of lithe, pink, undulating bodies, making a beautiful abstract
4
A very popular weekly television series commencing in 1953, narrated by the prestigious
Walter Cronkite, You Are There episode by episode posited direct narration of a celebrated,
important historical event (the landing of the Hindenburg, the Gettysburg address, and so on)
PRIVACY 111
composition that can be viewed from on high. When the upper erogenous
zones of either lovemaker are shown they are used as sculptural forms for
creating such abstracts, and for cheating the absence of the lower regions.
Even the presentation of buttocks, seen from the side, can work as a tidy
cover (the ass not as a thing to be figleafed but as figleaf itself).
Frequently climactic moments are covered over by lap dissolves, which
can be multiplied to create a kind of alternating rhythm between dreaminess
and awakeness in the characters and for the benefit of viewers. It is easy
enough, too, to have the camera suddenly transported to another zone
so that the orgasm is merely a sound effect from the distance or, indeed,
substituted for by a telephone call or crowd cheer at a football game.
In cases of frenetic sex (increasingly popular after 2010) where very
shortly after meeting for the first time the (entirely overwhelmed) characters
race to disrobe in some private space and then conjoin vertically, say against
a wall, there being no time to wait even for lowering the self to a bed, the
camera dutifully shows the speedy dispensing with trousers, panties, skirts,
in order to suggest boldly that erotic action is in play below the waist and
of such urgency that decorum of any kind is out of the question. Urgency
becomes the compositional form. The urgency is almost always further
cheated through the actors’ guttural expressivity. An example accomplished
with some style and recognition of class priorities involves Ethan Hawke
and Angelina Jolie in Taking Lives (2004). Another is the library lovemaking
scene in Joe Wright’s Atonement (2007), where we have Keira Knightley in a
floor-length forest-green satin gown and James McAvoy in a full tuxedo. As
their passion comes to the point of overflow, he has her pressed up against
a burnished wooden bookcase, floor to ceiling, softly illuminated. It seems
a simple—because exceptionally swift—matter for him to have her panties
off and the brilliant green dress sufficiently hiked up, and his own fly (at
this time in England he would say “flies”) down, so that in a breath there
is, presumably (because of her [virginal?] gasp), penetration: litany in the
library. What we see is two otherwise dignified people, each representing a
principle gender, standing and spasmodically jerking toward each other if at
the same time maintaining cool British composure, all this more or less in
full clothing (depending on the angle of view).
In the case of this film and this particular scene, the voyeurism
conferred upon us is significant narratively, thus philosophically, because
we are not the only lookers-on. A thirteen-year-old sister, Briony (Saoirse
Ronan), garbed entirely in angelic white, has wandered in and is standing
in frozen fascination, her eyes pried as wide open as clamshells. She will
not turn out to be silent as a clam, however. Her report about Robbie and
with the audience “in direct attendance”; we were there. This was obviously an advertisement
for television’s ability to, as we were meant to sense, take us around the world.
112 THE FILM CHEAT
Cecilia, however confused (we do not hear it, and have no reason at all
for supposing she knows what she has seen with any exactitude), leads to
Robbie being banished from the house and the love affair being destroyed.
As the film progresses, this single instant has the deepest conceivable
moral and emotional implications. Robbie’s banishment and the tragedy
of the broken love affair both expand in volume and meaning because of
the authenticity, read compelling heat, of that lovemaking. Yet it was an
authenticity that begged our belief, that demanded vicarious participation
to be fully comprehensible.
Two frequent assumptions leading to cheats:
●● That the personnel who make movies are the sorts of people who
would believably engage in sexual activity whenever and wherever
possible, with insatiable and inordinate appetites. The sex we see
onscreen, therefore, leans toward the real, has a tendency, barring
obstructions, to seem journalistic and hence believable; actually
happening. BUT: we know, and can be presumed to know, that what
we are watching cannot actually be happening. This verisimilar
behavior is, and can only be, faked. And since we are known to
know this (that we are knowingly looking at acting, after all), some
trick must be pulled to con us out of that knowledge, to suggest that
here, finally, and, thankfully, visible to us in perfect composition,
is a moment of sexual presence. Actors, many fans assume, would
always automatically want to have sex; the film system would be
designed to facilitate the preferred view that they are doing so
when they are not; and then finally the system would be designed
to inform us that actors are not sexually active in the manner that
we think them to be. The absence of the giveaway shot is direct
evidence of this last contrivance, because it is a discernable absence.
Even a central absence. We are openly shown that a culminating
truth is being kept away from us, and in being shown that,
something else is also kept out of view but not in such a way that
we are aware of. That something is our shame, our overriding sense
of propriety now violated with our participation. Since the orgasmic
truth must be omitted, there is a sense in which we shouldn’t have
been there at all, not for any part of it. In Atonement, young Cecilia
is frozen to the spot out of astonishment, curiosity, the hunger for
experience, and shock; she cannot bring herself to leave. Neither
can we, yet we feel we should, and when the sex builds we feel
the cloister more and more. We want to see, quite desperately, but
are surprised, even shocked, to note that we can see. This desire,
fostered by what is onscreen, cheats the moral code we know we are
violating. Our violation is one that, because of the helpful cheat, we
need not atone for.
PRIVACY 113
There is a far less superficial cheat about filmed lovemaking scenes. They
systematically beg a certain provocative, deeply troubling question that
surpasses the nature of the narrative itself and goes to the center of our
film-viewing experience. We are always, by agreement, stood in for by the
camera. The camera is our factotum and our simulacrum, our friend and our
distanced eye. What is the camera—and what are we—doing in this place?
We come to be near the bed because the camera merely moves to be near
anything at all “of interest,” yet how and why is this “of interest” and how and
why does the camera move to it with such apparent casualness?5 Casually,
as though there is nowhere else the viewing eye could reasonably be at the
orgasmic moment, nowhere any viewer would prefer to be. Even Lawrence
Durrell’s fascinated narrator, confronting the lovemaking moment, has a
greater degree of modest self-consciousness as he finds himself describing
“an indistinct mass of flesh moving in many places at once, vaguely stirring
like an ant-heap”:
5
Apparent casualness, note. Since late in 2018 “intimacy coordinators” have been employed
on-set as intermediaries between actors and directors, and choreographers of ideal sexual
representations. More on the problem of achieving “comfort” in intimate scenes in Chapter 16.
114 THE FILM CHEAT
feeling thrilled. The thrills pass into and out of us too quickly to be known
as thrills while they are there. Our excitements are unnameable and invisible
until seen in retrospect. The objectivity we find in Durrell—“They lay there
like the victims of some terrible accident, clumsily engaged” (187)—is
forever part of his textual narrator’s talk and consciousness (the narrator is
a long way off), however the very present film camera in lovemaking scenes
has not penetrated, like the narrator in Justine, by accident. Could not have.
Can do nothing by accident. Yet because of the cheat of the scene, accident
seems to be everywhere.
As we pattern our interpretation of the lovemaking scene, in framing a
reason for the camera’s presence we also frame a reason for our own. How
is it possible, how can it be rationalized, how can sense come of the fact
that we are here watching this now? Watching directly, without mediation.
As it occurs. Who could we claim to be, or not to be, in gazing the way the
camera allows us to gaze? That the onscreen lovemakers were showing off
to a third party (Georg Simmel’s tertius gaudens) for augmentation of their
own pleasure, and that the camera might silently be occupying the stance of
this third seems a rather far-fetched consideration. Similarly disregardable
is the thought that as watchers of this, we consider lovemaking—bluntly,
sexual action—as no more interesting in itself than, and in fact not especially
different from, any other perfunctory action, such as doing the dishes,
cooking a pot roast, having an argument, making a bank deposit. It is simply
behavior, that only, and we are simply observers, here and everywhere. This
scene isn’t special.
But hardly so. The special lighting, the artful compositions of form, the
peremptoriness of the dramatic action all suggest this is not something
quotidian at all. And, we must recall, even Durrell’s narrator, adopting a
quotidian point of view in order to “surprise the truth of [his] own feelings”
(186), uses language with a kind of awed hesitation, as though he is aware
that suddenly he is faced with something distinctly not banal.
It may well be with a kind of transgressive, even somewhat ashamed
daring that we permit ourselves to be the seers the camera must be imagining
it is photographing for. In the Durrell, the viewer-narrator’s self-conscious
reaction is produced by the lover’s startled awareness and response; whereas
in the cinematic scene the lovers have no such awareness to pique us. Indeed,
the viewer who has lapsed into a thoughtless sleep while watching may well
have no self-consciousness at all, but merely drink in the vision of naked flesh
in the same way as everything and anything else onscreen. A true imbibition.
A soporific dullness prevents even the elementary consciousness that certain
truths, certain pleasures, certain eventualities are being systematically
denied in the process of showing; denied without proclamation. To be
offered a piquing sight and denied fullness is, after all, both an insult and a
demeaning. For this to happen without indication, quite as though it is not
happening, is an outrage.
PRIVACY 115
Arise
Getting out of bed brings us from one world into another. There is narrative
cogency: the character getting up is a person, persons sleep, when they have
slept they get up. A character who remains alive but doesn’t get up fluidly
is either not well or very tired, neither condition generally useful for action
narrative. Getting up is topically irrational: when we see a character do
something, we do not need to be told that the night before doing it he was
asleep. Principal in depictions of getting up is a coherently designed bedroom
space, accurately reflecting either the private tastes of the sleeper or else
those of the person whose bedroom is being shared (even if the space is a
hotel room). Standard items of composition: rumpled sheets (almost never
blankets); naked or semi-naked body(ies); evidence somewhere of sleeping
habit (nude, shorts, pajamas); demonstrative semi-conscious attitude. By
attitude we read the character’s drowsiness on being drawn out of sleep,
slowness to adapt to waking conditions (often by sitting up in bed for a
few seconds or by sitting on the edge of the bed). And also first tasks: to
march into the bathroom to pee, to march into the kitchen(ette) to put on
the coffee maker (film characters almost never have their first coffee of the
day at an outside emporium), to march to the window, draw the drapes, and
peer outside (into the street; into the sky; into nowhere). The wake-up scene
is almost always followed closely by a business scene with the character now
fully dressed, fully awake, and fully aware at a workplace or else making
way to some important destination; we pick up the action as he or she
moves into it. We could also have picked up the action without the wake-up
scene that came before.
Of this (very typical) get-out-of-bed construction, we can note two
important features that seem to define narrative bounds and possibilities:
[1] A temporal shift. As the preceding scene will conventionally have
taken place at night (often very late at night), thus in darkness, the morning
wake-up is given in order to inform the viewer that time has passed, a spate
of time, indeed, during which the character in play has rested safely and
been entirely uninvolved in relevant action, in short, a rest period in every
sense, a time-out. Extra-diegetic narrative time has passed, we are moving
forward in (ordinary) diegetic narrational time, what we are about to see is
to be taken (either fully or provisionally, until subsequent confirmation) as
happing after what we saw happening before. We are awakening to a new
day. “New,” meaning: unplanned developments may occur; we may travel to
a new location; we may meet unknowns. All of this is a nice reflection on the
filmmaking process itself, since when a cast and crew awaken after sleeping
off one long day’s work and head off to a new work call, they, too, will enact
new developments (unexpected by the viewer), will do this in a new location
(even if the same set, still the same set later), will encounter strangers. One
could see that in the moment of awakening and crawling out of bed, the
116 THE FILM CHEAT
character is most closely affiliated with the actor beneath. Yet, not to forget:
in such scenes, actors are not actually awakening from sleep, and the sleep
we see at the introduction of the scene is mere “sleep,” the play sleep every
one of us learned to perform in childhood. The producer cannot afford for
the actor to actually sleep during a “sleep take.”6
[2] Preparation for the day’s action. Consider the difference between (a)
having a narrative move from any nocturnal scene A, where something of
interest happens with the protagonist, to any morning scene C in an action
setting, where time has passed and some ongoing continuity of action is being
established (reflection, ensuing behavior, discussion with others); and (b)
making that narrative move but inserting a transitional scene B, a morning
scene in which the protagonist from the night before now awakens in bed
and goes off to get ready for C. What is added logically by the addition of
B, aside from humanization of the character—he or she has trouble waking
up, just as I do; he or she takes a shower; he or she gulps down a cup of
coffee—and a pointer to the character’s design taste (which could easily
have been effected already in other previous scenes). What is the narrative
value of the oft-witnessed scene of a character “opening the eyes”? Do we
need to see that the character sleeps, else we might fail to believe? Scene B
gives evidence, yes, that the character spent a night sleeping; but there are so
many bodily functions we do not appear to need evidence for, that are also
real: the character checks a small pimple on the cheek in a mirror, applies a
little alcohol; the character takes a half-open book on the coffee table and
either puts it back in a bookshelf or decides to leave it alone; the character
picks up the telephone, then thinks twice and decides not to make a call. On
and on. Perfunctory, everyday, trivial things. How is the character rolling
over in bed, sitting up, and walking off (with a small ballet of body moves
to keep vital areas from showing to camera) substantially different? Won’t
the viewer make the assumption, all else considered, that in any scene the
character comes into action prepared (in an embodied way) to do what he
or she does?
Is the moment of sleeping in a bed an especially private moment, more
than, say, going into one’s safe deposit box or dropping a letter into a
mailbox or receiving a telephone call? Is it somehow primal, elementary
beyond elementary? And if it is this, what exactly is established by our being
given access to the elementary-beyond-elementary? Surely that the character
is just like we are--albeit that the character is not just like we are--at least in
some respect now demonstrated before the camera: human in the same kind
of way, vulnerable, feelingful, desirous, fearful exactly as could be anyone
watching. Such a demonstration would of course contradict a number of
scenic imperatives of cinema, including a belief carefully established and
nurtured in viewers that the characters are entirely special, entirely worth
watching in some charged, elevated, transacted way. We paid to see them
wake up in bed (in the way we know we wake up ourselves in bed), paid to
see evidence of the everyday. Watching them behave at first light is higher,
better, more delicious than going into a public square and watching strangers
feed the pigeons.
In many ways, then, the bodily exploration we can make as we watch a
character get out of bed is a narrative cheat in total. Artfully replicated from
the real, effectively staged and photographed, emphatically timed, it almost
always nevertheless takes place without performing a narrative action of
significance. The scene of awakening is a filler: the shot of the character with
eyes closed and head on pillow; the shot of the character groaning; the shot
of the nude or semi-nude body appearing out of the sheets and standing;
the shot of the stumbling action that comes next. All this is perfunctory in
the extreme, narratively speaking, with only rare exceptions. A significant
exception, yet one that is handled very swiftly onscreen and entirely
without titillating ornamentation, is the photographer’s (David Hemmings)
awakening in London the morning after the pot party at the end of Blow-
Up (1966). Here we are to feel—and the filmmaker and cinematographer do
make us feel—that a vital change has taken place while the character slept.
That the world he is awakening to is a different world (for him). He goes to
sleep in a tumble, fully clothed, and when he comes awake it is merely by
popping his (all-seeing) eyes open in morning light.
Douche
In the opening episode of Granada Television’s The Forsyte Saga (2002), we
are made privy to the bedchamber of Soames and Irene Forsyte (Damian
Lewis, Gina McKee) as, early in their marriage, they engage in lovemaking.
This is a double cheat, first in the way that all lovemaking scenes are
cheats, as I discuss above; but secondly in that the diegetic logic would
have us believe we are in the Victorian era, when marital sexuality was kept
entirely out of strangers’ view. The bedclothes are pulled over Soames and
Irene, and both are clearly dressed in white muslin sleeping garments the
lower parts of which, we are to presume, have been pulled aside to make
genital engagement possible. The man is atop the woman and is thrusting
rhythmically, then more and more quickly, then arching in an abrupt halt.
Again, a series of gestural (body-gestural) moves intended as a chain of
signals or indications, all this based in a gestural language ostensibly shared
with the viewing audience: the thrust from above, the variation in speed, the
intensification, the halt as climax. Gestures are here aimed to signal action
at a distance (a distance from the perceiving eye), a fundamental function of
the gesture broadly speaking.
118 THE FILM CHEAT
The morning after a certain night on which Soames at last asserted his
rights and acted like a man, he breakfasted alone.
...
He ate steadily, but at times a sensation as though he could not
swallow attacked him. Had he been right to yield to his overmastering
hunger of the night before, and break down the resistance which he had
suffered now too long from this woman who was his lawful and solemnly
constituted helpmate?
He was strangely haunted by the recollection of her face, from before
which, to soothe her, he had tried to pull her hands—of her terrible
smothered sobbing, the like of which he had never heard, and still
seemed to hear; and he was still haunted by the odd, intolerable feeling
of remorse and shame he had felt, as he stood looking at her by the flame
of the single candle, before silently slinking away. (509–10)
That single candle and that silent slinking: the first finds its way, filmically,
into her hand, in the toilet, where instead of covering her face and producing
PRIVACY 119
first part of the scene be certain that the bedclothes are pulled up and in
the second part that the camera never shows any truly informative details?
Although in the Victorian era many husbands, prudish, personally modest,
would have penetrated their wives beneath the bedclothes, those bedclothes
are cheated as covers for penetration now, in a distinctly non-Victorian era.
The answer that will be forthcoming is, needless to say, “realism,” as though
Damian Lewis and Gina McKee are otherwise perfect representatives
of the Victorian person. If it is argued that the filmmakers wished to be
authentic to Victorian tradition rather than to contemporary practice, one
would have to ask whether in Victorian tradition people did what we are
doing, sneaking into a private bedroom for an entertaining surmise. The
point about Irene’s douching is that she would have hidden her device and
its usage from Soames; that it is the man’s eyesight from which this little
performance is being masked away; and as the camera now masks it away
quite efficiently, we may presume the contemporary camera is picking up the
Victorian man’s dominating viewpoint.
Yet why any viewpoint? A quite realistic approach would have been
to avoid showing anything at all with respect to conjugal sex; to have the
whole thing intimated, circumlocuted, altogether distanced. Here it seems
necessary for the filmmakers (possibly because they sense that it will seem
necessary to their viewers) to show what goes on during the sex; yet also,
and crucially, to avoid showing it, because, owing to our own prudery, the
offering of an actual sight would be a violation of sensibilities—-not Soames
and Irene’s sensibilities, but ours. It is quite all right for us to be peeking in
on the activity in bed, peeking and, indeed, holding ourselves there until the
culminating moment and even afterward; and quite all right, too, for us to
visit the secret toilet facility; but in both the bedroom and toilet we should
have our eyes either closed or turned away, or blindered, or be able to claim
that we did.
Here, then, is an open demonstration that persists in being entirely closed.
A closed “open,” which is to say a complete cheat, itself covered up by the
details of set design and actor behavior so as to seem anything but what it
actually is. Peter Gay quotes a comment in the Saturday Review’s evaluation
of George Eliot’s The Mill on the Floss: “There are emotions over which we
ought to throw a veil” (Heart 250).
16
Dance
FIGURE 16 Woody Allen and Diane Keaton in Annie Hall (Woody Allen, Jack
Rollins & Charles H. Joffe Productions, 1977).
Take the case of an actor, let us call him Joe, who (a) has filmed more than
ninety percent of his shots for a picture (and who is therefore, from the point
of view of a producer watching a budget, almost impossible to replace);
DANCE 123
(b) is now and has always been the favorite choice of the director and the
producing staff for the role he is playing; (c) is obliged to film a scene in
which, as the script dictates, his character “masturbates”; and (d) indicates
to the director, privately, that, although he knows full well the framing will
be cut off at chest level and no genital configuration will appear onscreen,
still, for his own comfort he desires to be naked and to masturbate actually
(say, because he was trained in the Method Acting tradition). This is not
the kind of “comfort” that would be typically assumed and negotiated in
filming, although here as elsewhere, the filmmakers would try every trick to
satisfy the actors they wanted to work with: yet, “satisfy,” not satisfy. What
if the issue is important enough to the actor that he will walk off the picture
if forbidden?
●● The screen images of so-called “sexuality” will not only be separated
and distanced from moments of real sexuality in the offscreen world.
They will be proclamations of being separated in this way. Here is
what was done, here is what was agreed to, here are the lines we
promised not to cross, here we are—watch carefully!—not crossing
them. Sex becomes, in effect, talk and also a record of talk. Sex is
words.
here. Money is more crucial, and every pause, every retake, every gaffe costs.
The scene must be prepared. The workers must know, each, what the others
are doing now and are planning to do next. She is standing there, and she
will walk to here. I am here, and I will walk to there at the same time. She
will move more quickly than I do. I will spit out a line of dialogue as I cross
past her.
How and why do negotiated preparations make their way into filming?
And by what cheat are they erased, camouflaged, tucked away from the
audience’s view? In general here, as with so much else in our experience of
cinema, we know a great deal that we disavow; we accept and believe so much
that contradicts what we know. The delight of participation is unthinkable
otherwise. Are we helped somehow—and if so, how—to conceive the action
we see as spontaneous and original, not negotiated and rehearsed?
[1] Gravitational Tricks. A glass containing liquid is knocked by a
character’s hand so that it falls off a table and smashes on the floor. No
matter the choreography of the scene, for an actor to make a move like
this very convincingly sells the spontaneity of the character’s action. The
legendary case is the restaurant argument scene between Dustin Hoffman
and Meryl Streep in Kramer vs. Kramer (1979). He has a tall glass of some
delicious-looking French white, perhaps a Pouligny-Montrachet—the
character’s money appears to have been spent. They are fighting about the
custody of their child. Heat mounts. Finally a point comes (apparently so,
because we are in no way given preparation for it) when Ted (Hoffman)
loses his composure entirely and with a spasmodic, violent, explosive gesture
smashes the glass off the table and into the air. The wine, the glass all go
into oblivion, loudly, visibly, in a gasp of complete gaucherie. What has been
said many times about this scene is that Hoffman did not tell anyone he was
going to do this; and in fact it would not be difficult to imagine that he did
not know himself, until he felt the action. The shock of Streep’s reaction is
stark. This cheat toward spontaneity is effected by breaking the rules. Yet:
breaking rules inside a very tightly drawn boundary—everything must be
in frame, for instance; everything must be lit;1 no harm can come to Streep
from Hoffman’s maneuver; preparations must either be in place or possible
in the event the shot has to be re-taken, and so on. Was it a real glass glass,
or a breakaway? Was she sitting exactly in the right place and posture not
to be hit by any of it?
[2] Population Tricks. As characters in narratives populate spaces together,
when any one of them takes a position it will be necessary to ensure (a)
that he or she does not block our view of any other character important
1
Alfred Hitchcock on light in film: “We must bear in mind that fundamentally, there’s no
such thing as color; in fact, there’s no such thing as a face, because until the light hits it, it is
nonexistent” (Truffaut 183).
DANCE 125
at the moment or any important object, and therefore the actor’s position
vis-à-vis the camera needs to be worked out; (2) that no person or object
has already been positioned in such a way as to block a key actor’s stance
or move. Consider a much-celebrated comedy scene. Alvie Singer (Woody
Allen) and girlfriend of the moment Annie Hall (Diane Keaton) are at a
Long Island summer rental, standing in the kitchen, trying to cook lobsters.
Part of the joke is that Alvie being Jewish, he doesn’t know lobster from
pinochle; when he holds up one, he extends his arm to keep it as far away
as possible, as though it is a monster. Another part of the joke is that Annie
is from the Midwest where they ain’t got no lobster. Another part of the
joke is that they are trying out domesticity. Another part of the joke is that
the lobsters are having a revolution and seizing power, crawling all over the
floor. The two people need to jump around the kitchen space, jump around
one another, and jump around the lobsters without inadvertently stepping
on any of them, all with rhythm and pacing to keep the scene moving.
Allen and Keaton had to know where they were to stand and move,
how many beats to take on each line, and where the partner would act
as well. Considerable staging, measuring the distance from each character
to the lens to establish proper focus, making sure the lighting was right
were all called for. Letting the character breathe, each actor tacitly follows
a set of choreographic commands. The positions here had to be learned and
retained without aid, because since a white floor had to be laid in order that
the lobsters not disappear against the terra cotta tile floor that was part of
the kitchen, and since there would be medium-long shots showing most of
the room and notably that white floor, marker tapes for the actors could not
be laid down.
In this scene, the untrainable lobsters crawling around throw the switch
for definitive spontaneity, realism, uncontrivedness; and all the actors need
to do is appear to be reacting to creature movement they cannot in fact
predict.
[3] Display Tricks. Not only are objects touched and grasped before the
lens in such a way as to make them sufficiently visible for telling the story,
but actors in role make themselves sufficiently visible as workers, too. This
process occurs through a translation: Actor A is playing character X; B is
playing Y. In order that A get necessary exposure in a scene he sees to it
that X is exposed to the right kind of light, and B counterposes by worrying
about Y. Standing at a certain distance from the lens, making the smallest
gesture of the head or body while not speaking, knowing how the color of
one’s garment will show in the scenic composition, and so on: all these tricks
help actors have their characters get primal exposure; or, more importantly,
not be overcome by other actors working to do this. “If you stand just there
like that, you’re blocking my key light a little.” The director and surely the
cinematographer will be conscious of such things, but actors have their own
professional reasons for caring, too, and for looking after themselves. But
126 THE FILM CHEAT
One often sees a character sit to play the piano, but there are relatively few
performers who know how to do it. And the piano opens itself to much
deception, chief among instruments, since anybody can place hands upon
a keyboard and almost anybody can move fingers one or two at a time.
The illusion being created in “authentic” screen pianism, as we sometimes
sense it, is that not only the character but also the actor beneath abounds in
1
A small part of Chapter 17, “Keyed Up,” was presented in a different form as “Shoot the Piano
Player” at the Society for Cinema and Media Studies, Seattle, March 2019.
128 THE FILM CHEAT
musical sensitivity and talent, is richly filled with the desire to express, and
doesn’t mind putting on a show. To stick the label “musical” upon a person
is to perform a strange elevation, as though he or she now approximates
some Olympus of high sensibility, tasteful refinement, and especially melodic
desire, not to say athletic capability (because to play the piano is athleticism
to be sure). The played tune is a kind of utterance or articulation, and in
using the hands to produce it the character is making a speech beyond what
words or tongue can muster.
Another feature of musical instruments, generally, is that in direct
presence, the use of them cannot be faked—anymore than the use of a bat
can be faked on a baseball diamond. You can either play or you cannot.
Were the viewer to become aware of a character merely “playing the piano,”
not really playing the piano, were a viewer to notice during a musical scene
that the body onscreen isn’t doing what one is supposed to understand it
doing, the only resolution would lie in finding reason for the character to
be dramatically cheating—a cheat inside the story, a fictional cheat—but
almost always such a reason is absent. Further, as actual piano playing
cannot be cheated the character—living in a reality—cannot be presumed to
be cheating it, and since the actor is closely allied with the character, here by
way of arms and hands, we have a tendency to believe the actor isn’t cheating
either. Musical cheats are thus in a special category: easy to accomplish in a
way that much else isn’t for film, in the sense that the audience is unlikely to
pick the cheat up, and this because it is notably unlikely to try. Yet cheating
there must almost always be.
pressure: an outside production again, although in this case one far less
frequently to be heard, since the cost of acquiring the services of a first-rate
musician is far greater than the cost of getting a performative filler. Touch
works upon the action of a piano—the ease with which a finger might
depress a key.
[c] Musicality is essentially the marshaling of enthusiasm: causing the
piano to speak or sing on behalf of both the composer and the performer
at once.
Only the very greatest masters of the piano are extremely technically
adept, possessors of a perfect touch, and intensely musical. While some
actors can play piano, there are no actors one could call great masters of the
instrument; they are great masters of another instrument, that substitutes
onscreen. It is worth noting further that the display onscreen of profound
musicality could be overly absorbing for the audience, draw attention
from the characters, the story, or the moment. Competence is required, but
serious musicality could ruin a scene. In the same breath one should say that
“serious musicality” must frequently be performed.
While the puppeting of the onscreen musical moment is essentially
an off-camera matter acoustically—no matter what is happening on set,
the actual sound is not the sound we are hearing—the added sound must
be aligned with the photographed image in order to give the complete
effect. Any sound dubbing moment at all will present the same kinds of
challenges, except that with piano playing, if we are seeing the keyboard,
there are ten sound effectors moving alone or in groups slowly or
quickly at each instant and the sync has to match all of this. As with
more conventional forms of the maneuver, successful puppeteering means
hiding the puppeteer. Thus arise the many cinematic gestures of revelatory
concealment: showing disembodied hands, or arms and hands, and adding
in pre- or post-recorded piano sound; substituting the expressive face or
upper body for performing hands; moving the camera to such a distance
that the operation of fingers on keys cannot be ascertained; or, in an
extension of puppeteering that seems to bring the puppet alive, giving very
brief shots of a performer actually playing a short—and easy—passage
carefully learned out of musical context: a few chords, a small scalar
passage, and not necessarily something from the music we are hearing
as long as there is a match. This kind of “vérité” passage will be intercut
with disembodiments and expressivities to lend the impression of a holistic
performance. David Sudnow recollects a process like this in learning to
play the piano: “For the most part, my practice sessions were given over to
playing a handful of songs, doing my improvisations. Fluent manipulations
of these pathways produced a semblance of competence, and I was able
to sustain long playing sessions” (35). We can see the same “semblance of
competence” employed in filmic depictions of painters at easels, where the
combination of expressive and highly skilled bodily action and technical
KEYED UP 131
Screen performers who were off-camera painters themselves (Vincent Price, Tony Curtis,
2
Anthony Quinn) tended not to play painter characters for the camera.
132 THE FILM CHEAT
performer of exceptional sensitivity and talent to yield to the music and then
quickly regain star stature at the keys: we see this with Christopher Plummer
playing Wagner in Remember (2016). But the least effortful procedure—as
in the least expensive and time-consuming—is to use the inexplicit view and
the ventriloquizing offscreen musician, even, sometimes, substitute models
for arm and hand work.
Most inexplicit views take up camera positions similar to what audience
members would have at a concert if they did not occupy the precious few
seats that afford a direct, close-up view of the keyboard. A number of
energizing cheat routines are conventional:
●● Spasm. As we see it rendered, musical passion makes (carefully
cultivated) long (“authentically musician-like”) hair shake, elbows
pump in and out like bellows, shoulders desperately hunch with
the strain of concentration. Musically untrained actors can perform
expressive gestures like these quite easily, more easily than they can
display artful flexibility with their untrained hands. A glance on
YouTube at Daniil Trifonov playing a concerto will quickly show the
folly of such “emoting.”
●● Spontaneity. We witness a production of musical performance
happening, as it were, on the spot, out of a flush of momentary
spirit, with no history, since the moment of pianism is very often
inserted into the film arbitrarily and without build-up. Yet no one
but the savant merely plays the piano, it is necessary to practice
long and hard today in order to give a good show tomorrow. Scales,
arpeggios, chords, close finger position, octaves, not to mention
fragments of a piece played over and over at different tempi—six
to eight hours a day: all of this is elided in screen representation.
Except in cases where, themselves the subject of drama—Madame
Sousatzka (1988), The Piano Teacher (2001)—piano lessons are
substantially ornamented with emotion and conflict, practice
is treated as a boring and pointless, or conflict-generating, time
waster. In An American in Paris (1951), the concert pianist Oscar
Levant, who in his real life practiced substantially, plays a character
named Adam Cook who again and again merely sits and plays with
aplomb. The pianism “slumbers” in his hands and need only be
“awakened.”
●● Centralized maneuver. The pianist’s feet are kept out of camera
frame, while, as anyone who plays the piano knows, the instrument’s
pedals must often be involved in performance and cannot be
managed other than with the feet. Upper bodies dominate the screen
as much as arms and hands. Thus, screened pianism is an “upper”
business, coming from the torso (the heart) and its extensions, the
KEYED UP 133
●● Tic. The arm muscles, very frequently the objective center of a piano
shot, need not come into use in order to mobilize the muscles of the
hand. To play a perfectly fluid scale (a difficult challenge) covering
three or more octaves; or an arpeggio over the same range; or a
chord progression or octave progression, it is not necessary to lean
over one way and the next, or to wave the arms; it is not required
to pretend one is on a cricket pitch. Everything happens in the hand.
In effect, much of what is seen onscreen when the hand is concealed
amounts to a kind of actor’s tic. Were a character to tic this way
without a piano, he might be read as a ticquer.3
●● Cubism. Attending a piano performance in the everyday world, one
need not see anything. It is quite sufficient to listen. And those whose
pocketbooks can afford only the cheapest seats may well be placed
where no view is afforded. But if one does wish to gaze, the most
productive target is the hands upon the keyboard. The power and
the capability, as well as the tenderness or ferocity, are in the hands.
Wherever one is placed, however, that is where one is. Cinematic
pianism invariably makes the piano experience cubism by cutting
(delicately!) from angle to angle, as though what is happening has
so many facets it takes numerous camera positions to gather them
all into one vision. The impression the editing tries to foster is that
as the camera positions change we move closer and closer to the
sacred fire at the heart of the music. But since it is the sound of
music that rules, and the showing of piano players is a matter of
arbitrary concession, the particular choreographies one finds in
filmed piano scenes are telling in themselves rather than reflective of
the music. The screen is made continually interesting as a vision, so
the problem faced by cinema is the conversion of the sound of music
to the look of music, or at least the look of what can be sold as the
sound of music.
●● Musical interest. As normal citizens, do piano-playing characters
onscreen ever even show themselves interested in music, do they
talk about it or worry or plan, do they have favorite composers, or
favorite pieces to play, or favorite techniques to chat about? In much
3
Here as in so much else of cinema we gain a clear view of Kenneth Burke’s act-scene and act-
agency ratios, the bias in reading an action that is given by the place in which the action is made
or by the tools that are used to make it. Take a person making a repetitive movement with one
hand while holding the other palm-up and it is easy to make the reading “mentally unstable,”
or “hallucinatory” (as we can see in Frank Perry’s David and Lisa [1962]). Put a wooden spoon
in the first hand and a bowl in the second, and place the whole thing in a kitchen, and you have
a diligent cook.
136 THE FILM CHEAT
Workers are often shown one-sidedly this way. But in The Man Who Knew Too Much (1956),
4
Hitchcock interposes a short but telling scene in an embassy kitchen and the corridor outside,
where slaving laborers are seen on a break, being only people with one another.
18
Don’t Believe It
FIGURE 18 Singin’ in the Rain (Gene Kelly and Stanley Donen, Paramount, 1952):
Jean Hagen is at the front microphone, here suddenly revealed as a mouther only, as
we find Debbie Reynolds dubbing her from behind.
1
For a thorough analytical discussion of which, see Ryave and Schenkein.
DON’T BELIEVE IT 139
2
In their analysis of first films made by Navajos given only the scantest instruction on camera
loading, Sol Worth and John Adair found that walking was a signal aspect of narrative
construction and cultural meaning for the filmmakers, a telltale authenticity they felt the need
to explore.
140 THE FILM CHEAT
3
For more on film sound more generally, see Altman; Beck; Chion, Audio-Vision; Eyman; and
Weis and Belton.
DON’T BELIEVE IT 141
as many as seventy or eighty times to get a good take (and since nobody
producing a film takes for granted any actor’s physical tastes or allergies).
The tactical point of the filmic cheat is to overcome the viewer’s resistance,
his or her proneness to considering an act incredible by conveying it in a
credible mode, or by erasing features that lend toward the incredibility. The
meal: the actor can’t eat all that much food over and over but actually we
don’t see any actors eating, we see them passing food around, hear them talk
about food, watch them fork food up and move it toward the mouth before
a cut switches us to another diner. The production problem lies in having the
food on the table diminish as the scene proceeds.
In a way, the enhancement of credibility through substitute action is a
kind of stunt, and anyone on the crew might be converted into a momentary
stunt person. Here are two fascinating stunts, one secretly disruptive and
one openly kept from view:
Stunting voice. When he was shooting The Hospital (1971), Arthur Hiller
told me,4 he had a scene with George C. Scott, head of a hospital in which
patients are systematically being killed, now utterly frustrated and a physical
wreck for lack of sleep. The character was to stand up, walk to a window,
open the window, lean out, and say in utter exasperation, “Jesus . . . Christ!”
Take after take after take after take after take Scott leaned out the window
and said, almost sotto voce, “Jesus Christ.” A meek whisper.
No matter what he tried, Hiller could not bring the actor to change his
rendition. So in the editing room, he went to another part of the picture
where Scott was railing and said “Jesus . . . Christ!!!” He snipped that out
and edited it into the other scene. When we see the film, albeit the character
puts his back to camera when he leans out the window, nevertheless we take
his expostulation to be wholly credible, to be emanating from this body we
see from behind; when in fact it is wholly faked, ironically with his own
voice and without his intention: unwitting self-mockery, entirely guised.
Stunting expertise. It goes without saying that whenever an act A is to be
substituted by another version B, a version accomplished more inexpensively,
more accurately, or even accomplished at all when the actor working to
produce A simply cannot do it; whenever a cheat uses extraneous footage
to make credible what would otherwise be open to question, the viewer’s
presumption, quite naturally, is, that the substitute performer is an expert,
sufficiently to do handily what we see being done. When a character has to
do something physically taxing, so that in watching we might be filled with
doubt about the actor and think him “dubbed in” by a stunt person who can
manage more easily, we take this stunt person to be notably expert at the
activity: driving cars, leaping from heights, recoiling from gunshots, even,
as in the case with body models, standing (or lying) in for the star during
a lovemaking scene. Not only expert but more expert than the actor being
replaced. The replacement is taken to be working, in fact, only because the
actor is in some particular way relatively incompetent or blocked. And once
people have seen quite a few filmic examples of such transfers, they come to
automatically expect certain kinds of stunt substitutions—that is, they know
their credibility is being poached. What a lovely challenge to rationality, then,
is the physical stunting of Burt Lancaster’s characters, almost invariably
performed by Lancaster himself even in conditions of danger as in The
Train (1964) and The Gypsy Moths (1969). As long as we are ignorant of
Lancaster’s stunt work, we read the character as amazingly accomplished
and presume some even more amazingly accomplished stand-in has worked
to convince us: sliding down a high ladder against the clock in The Train,
for example—a trick the actor would have learned much earlier in life as an
acrobat. Producers and actors know that the perception of “credibility” or
“incredibility” is rooted much less in the accomplishment of action before
the camera than in the viewer’s knowledge, and the expectations that flow
from it.
19
“I Love You”
FIGURE 19 Charlize Theron and Johnny Depp in The Astronaut’s Wife (Rand
Ravich, New Line Cinema, 1999). A tiny homage, perhaps, to Edwin S. Porter’s The
Kiss (1900).
The kiss, even in action stories that ostensibly have nothing to do with
human passion, devoted instead to showing how a heroic band struggle
against an assembly of social forces, against gravity, against the limits of
their own endurance, against anything and everything to redeem some vital
treasure. For the Good, one finds, ultimately, the hero and heroine bonding
with an embrace, the two chums striding into the night, the galpals swept
away from the everyday, albeit in an embrace that is played sometimes for
comedy. Always, finally, the union:
and calmly walks away. The proximity must bring on the meeting of lips,
the meeting of lips the opening of mouths, and the opening of mouths a
coupling of more severe contingency in a planet far, far away once the lights
have come up.
That kiss:
There are probably no living persons who have not taught themselves
how to perform it through some reminiscence of what was seen onscreen
(the motion picture operating essentially as a mannerist textbook). Getting
the right interpersonal distance, as measured in inches or centimeters.
Angling the head. Moving one’s mouth forward at some calculable speed.
Actually aiming for the partner mouth, locating it with the very blind lips
(since way down there and from this angle and proximity the eyes cannot
get a view). Moving into, not back out of, the touch. Deciding when the
moment is done, that is, knowing how long to engage, how long and with
what ornamentation. Pulling apart slightly, what to do with the eyes, which
now gaze longingly into the other’s eyes gazing longingly into one’s longing
gaze. What to say, if anything, since whole architectures have been known
to collapse on a word. And then continuing to operate with what is now not
only knowing but knowing-oneself-to-know more than can be known from
exterior viewing alone.
The kiss! . . . . .
Onscreen it cannot but be summative. It cannot go wrong. It cannot be
obscured. It cannot be scenically mishandled. And the building hunger, the
itch, that is initiated and grows monumentally—this must seem actually
present, which is why one speaks casually of the good or bad “chemistry”
between actors. When there is “good chemistry,” the two major stars appear
to yearn for each other’s nakedness and desire, but for real. Legion are the
studio publicity stories concocted about one contracted star beginning an
affair with another (even while shooting a film), these putative escapades
functioning as spurs to audience belief in the chemistry which, like all
chemistry, is quite beyond sight.
Onscreen the kiss, something affected as natural and easy to do—when of
course it is neither—betokens the joining of the stars, a culminating moment
for the drama but also for the stargazing experience. As long as the mélange
of feelings is orchestrated as a finale or cadence the success of the film can
depend on the accuracy of the kiss, its believability even if all else seems
bogus. This is the supreme bodily touch (censorial restrictions of the times
notwithstanding), the link that brings the actor and character together in
their own internal “kiss,” as it were. The bond that weds passion to action.
But the problem here, here and always, is the conundrum presented by
what the social theorist Georg Simmel called the tertius gaudens. The Third
who Watches. As voyeurs in reality, we would have the same difficulty as the
camera has: obtaining, from any conceivable viewing position, a perspective
in which the action of each party is visible wholly and fully at the same time
146 THE FILM CHEAT
as the action of the other. As viewers of intimacy we can but seize an illusory
angle, something that charges us to imagine the coupling beyond our limiting
frame. And when we look at the camera as a tertius, noting that it is wearing
(as both enabler and prophylactic) a lens, we must see that angles become
expressly, overwhelmingly important. And in physical fact it is not the case
that the angle one person requires in order to do mouth-to-mouth with a
second is the same angle that a camera requires of kissers in order that a
sight be made of it. Displacement, refraction, warping, misalignment—all
these potential grenades—always threaten to exaggerate features of the kiss,
throw the act out of proportion, make what is intended to be graceful and
accomplished look sloppy, amateurish, and hopeless, even grotesque. Actors
learn, for instance, that in extreme close-ups with one another, and varying
according to the size of the lens, they must not look into one another’s eyes
or onscreen their gazes will fly past each other. In Virtuoso I quote Peter
Lorre revealing a lesson he gave Bogart about choosing one eye to focus on,
but not both (267–8) and those two had only dialogue together. Physical
engagements are more complicated still.
Mouths will frequently not touch in the way that it appears they are
touching. Aimed targeting might bring a modicum of pleasure to the actors
but the characters would appear to be misaiming. All this warping is because
the clarity and proximity of focus most desirable for kissing scenes requires
an aperture of f.2, perhaps even f1.2, and not more than f.4. At f.2 the linear
depth is foreshortened intensively, the graphic planes of space are brought
together. For the kiss as kiss to be discernable it must be shot in profile, or
“cheated toward” the profile, and this means that the depth between the side
of the actors’ cheeks near to the viewer and, say, the distal side of their noses
is contracted. When people kiss in reality they physically negotiate a space
that is not contracted in this way. As well, when characters talk to each other
certain slight angles must be interposed in the actors’ body placements, in
order that the alignments of the bodies look as though they match.
Beyond being cheated optically so that it seems optically right, the screen
kiss is cheated symbolically. The character never—but never—openly makes
statement about that kiss, what it felt like exactly, whether or not it seemed
acceptably good, or, even more, precisely what sensations affected various
body parts. “Gosh, when I kissed you my lower lip, toward the left side,
felt as though it were being eaten alive.” After the kiss comes silence. In
that way, the kiss can be taken to be culminatingly informative, to speak
the speech in the fullest, least ambiguous way, leaving “no stone unturned,”
no hint undelivered. There is an electrical cheat as well, almost always: the
kiss moment summons and delivers extraordinary illumination, as though
the mouth-to-mouth is actually running electrons through hitherto hidden
lightbulbs. A glow in the eyes. A glow on the cheeks. The world opened
in wonderment as a visual entity. Except in the rarest of circumstances, in
everyday life when people kiss the lights do not come on except, perhaps, in
“I LOVE YOU” 147
the dark cave of the imagination, and the cheat in film here as elsewhere is
to make the luminosity in that cave tangible. Key lighting helps a lot.
The screen kiss also cannot fail. No character can say, “Golly, I have been
thinking for some time how wonderfully attractive you are, and I have been
desiring beyond desire to plant my lips on yours; but now that I have done
it, I have to confess it wasn’t as wonderful as I hoped it would be, no offense
intended.” Nor can a character tell a second character, “Gee, yes I would,
yes, love to kiss but I have a bad tooth infection.” Or, “Gee, I’m a vegan and
you eat meat so if I kiss you am I eating meat, too?” Or, “Kissing you was
actually not so much at all, because in my dream last night I was kissed by
an angel.”
The kiss has to seem to be the universe in a grain, everything here and
now, all possibility contracted into this blaze of shining penetration. If one
kisses with spontaneity and release, nothing of the sort can happen on
camera, since for the screen kiss, considering focal distances and hot spots
of light, angles of bodies and timing, make-up and the grace summoned for
movement, there is enormous work to be done. The kiss as architecture.
148
20
Surrender
with the accompanying obligation to restrain one’s actions in line with the
limitations and capabilities of the effected character. Is one subsumed by one’s
makeup, or does one make a distinct point of emerging as a performative self?
The actor and character are in a face-off.
In diegetic surgeries, battles, alien encounters, plague outbreaks, and
other like situations, the actor will typically be smeared over with an entirely
artificial sheath, a suppurating make-up wound, a latex facial substitution,
a scaly alien skin; or confined to a wheelchair or stretcher or bed or other
mechanical device (as in torture chambers or, for Andrew Garfield in Breathe
[2017], an iron lung). Such transformations can be felt as reductions of the
self just as much as aggrandizements, aides to the creation of, as it were,
monstres par défaut as much as monstres par excès (see Fiedler 20ff.). And a
construction might bring experiential traumas. Actors who must wear full-
body suits (Haruo Nakajima playing Godzilla in 1954 and onward, Bolaji
Badejo towering in the Alien costume for Ridley Scott) or actors wearing ape
costumes (David Warner in Morgan!: A Suitable Case for Treatment [1966])
or being locked in rubber (Johnny Depp in Edward Scissorhands [1990],
Ricou Browning in The Creature from the Black Lagoon [1954]), or being
turned into a kind of flexible figurine (Tilda Swinton in The Chronicles of
Narnia: The Lion, the Witch and the Wardrobe [2005], Boris Karloff in
The Mummy [1932], Cate Blanchett in Elizabeth: The Golden Age [2007],
Helena Bonham Carter in Alice in Wonderland [2010]) may find it difficult
to do the things most people don’t think about at all, like sipping a glass
of water, chewing a sandwich, using the toilet. The point of the taxation
through confinement is only the producer’s profit, in that taking the make-
up off and putting it on again is an expensive process and producers would
prefer to have it done only once in a shooting day.
More difficult than tolerating the get-up, however, is working with it
expressively, because the actor feels a need to be seen as himself, not only as
the character, and the laid-over character tends to dominate the performative
self, even obliterate it. Once the studio system dissolved, actors could not count
on the seven-year contract (which, a kind of imprisonment itself, did offer job
security for a time) and found themselves, in many cases, continually reaching
for a new job in the knowledge that “Look at me, look at what I can do!”
isn’t something producers would take to heart if it came from the mouth of
a character instead of the mouth of an actor who could make characters. The
best path to a successful performance in masque is to hold back from fighting
the conditions, exactly as in coming to terms in everyday life with a debilitation
like a broken leg. Let the mask take over . . . entirely. Become the mask, though
hopefully not to the point that the mask becomes taken as the performer, that
is, will not come off. One recognizes that it is the mask affecting the audience’s
sensibility and thought, and one’s job is to service and support the mask. If
it is sometimes necessary to go to extreme lengths in providing this support,
one must always avoid openly competing with one’s own character, however
SURRENDER 151
ersatz that character might seem. The more one competes against it, tries for
characteristic personal expressive signals and permits tics, the more and more
constructed and arbitrary seems the character mask. The more arbitrary the
character mask, the more arbitrary the film altogether.
In this odd case, then, the actor’s supreme cheat, his or her way of turning
the viewer’s critical mind away from the thought that the character is an
artful and made-up creation, is to do nothing but play the lines and move as
the constraints permit. For self-advertisement one must trust to the publicity.
There are delightful, deeply engaging moments in Scissorhands when one
senses the actor becoming acutely aware he cannot move his hands because
his character has no hands to move, and Edward’s little looks of surprise
and wonder are telltale in convincing us of his sincerity, since the “scissor
hands” fell to him, far from being a result of his will and operation. I am
here, I am trapped in here, there is little I can do but I will throw myself
into doing at any rate. Johnny Depp sacrifices his personality entirely here,
disappearing inside Edward.
But throwing oneself into doing: there are ways of doing that, and ways
of doing that. David Lowery told Eric Lavallee at the Fantasia International
Film Festival the ironic story of shooting Casey Affleck in a ghost costume
for his film, A Ghost Story (2016). The principal actor is in the costume for
the entire movie save the opening few minutes:
It was very clear that it was him—and it was almost surreal how much the
sheet exaggerated his physical traits, because he has a very specific way of
walking, a very specific way of hanging his head, he slouches a little bit,
and the sheet just magnified all those things so even though we didn’t see
his face it was very clearly him. But the other thing that happened was
that it was very clearly an actor with a bedsheet over their head. And it
felt too corporeal. It felt very clunk and, to be honest, quite silly. So from
that point forward we started refining the way in which the costume was
utilized and the way in which he acted underneath it. And by and by we
just sort of removed every bit of his body, which—and every bit of his
performance, and once we had done that it became clear that we could
put someone else under there, which we did do from time to time.
A case of the self effusing through the costume and making a leakage that
threatened the continuity of the viewer’s belief. It was necessary with the
camera and costume together to “just sort of remove” every bit of his body,
and then every bit of the performance that was his. Not the performance
the actor was giving, but the performance that, intentionally or not, he was
appropriating.1
1
I am grateful to Brandon Cronenberg for pointing me to this interview, available online at
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=0YJ08840jhY
152 THE FILM CHEAT
{21} Corral
Richard Chalfen; Pillow Talk; Bullitt; Poltergeist; Who’s Afraid of Virginia
Woolf?; Funny Games; The Guilty; The Bourne Ultimatum; The Circle;
Zabriskie Point
{22} Show Me
Wolfgang Schivelbusch and light; Impressionism; Nestor Almendros; Claire’s
Knee; Pauline at the Beach; Rebecca; Greta Garbo and William Daniels;
Suspicion; Day for Night
{27} Moving On
Panoramic perception; the coup d’oeil; Baudelaire
{29} Peek-a-Boo
Psycho; Mon oncle Antoine; The Lady in the Lake; The Naked Kiss; Up in
the Air; Alfie; House of Cards; acousmêtre/optimêtre; Walker Gibson
154
21
Corral
FIGURE 21 Kristen Stewart and Jodie Foster in Panic Room (David Fincher,
Columbia, 2002).
The camera’s biography is simple: it has always been able and ready to
go anywhere the light is sufficient, has always been a creature of curiosity
preferring not to face obstructing walls. And yet, regard! There are walls,
and the camera cannot go everywhere. When, as in Pillow Talk (1959) and
Grand Prix (1966) and The Thomas Crown Affair (1968) the editor makes
use of optically printed camera mattes to create the “multiple screen” that
at first enchants by the multiplicity of its views, by the hint that we can be in
more than one place at the same time, we realize too soon that every looking
requires a boundary, and we cannot apprehend without some selectivity of
concentration. One is reminded of Richard Chalfen’s curious dictum that we
can photograph anything anywhere anytime, but we don’t.
156 THE FILM CHEAT
The camera does not see everything that takes place in the realm of the
narrative:
●● It cannot see—and so we cannot see—at one and the same time both
the outside surface and the interior wellspring feeding it; and in fact
we do not see that interior quite generally. It is well known that
surfaces can be misleading, that appearances do not always convey
or completely convey motive. It is the surface that makes it possible
for us to discern an objective form: a leaf on a branch, a rolling ball,
a body in conversation. Everything seen by the camera is a surface
except that:
●● The shadow is neither surface nor interior.
●● The camera, and we, not only can see but must see. Since we must
see, we must be enabled to see. The camera is there to see, and
therefore no action that does not have a clear visual component can
be subjected to it. Make the implicit explicit. The camera cannot see
(a) belief, (b) fear, (c) adoration, (d) fascination, (e) meditation, (f)
forgetting, (g) excitement, or any other emotional state that humans
claim to be feeling. It cannot see someone’s anticipation or drawing
to a conclusion. What the camera can see is movement, action, and
gesture that can be claimed to be pinned to some internal state: a
sign of belief, a sign of doubt. The camera does not see happiness
but when a little girl is giggling with her eyes atwinkle we can say
we are seeing it. Running to, running away—the camera can show
these, although in point they look exactly the same (like sunrises
and sunsets) unless some further information is given by editing.
Chewing we can see, digesting we cannot.
●● Thought we cannot see, but words inking their way onto a page
we can.
●● The camera is always pricking or pinioning the viewer’s
consciousness. The bathtub dialogue in Pillow Talk (between Rock
Hudson and Doris Day) is an attempt to articulate both sides of a
telephone conversation at once, the speaking face on one side of the
screen and the receptive hearing face on the other, and then the two
persons switching.1 As we do not with surety determine motive as
the conversation gets underway, both faces are incessantly puzzling.
1
As in the conversational behavior with “flappers” using “bladders” that Gulliver describes in
regard to his voyage to Laputa (Swift 172): “It seems the minds of these people are so taken up
with intense speculations, that they neither can speak, nor attend to the discourses of others,
without being roused by some external taction upon the organs of speech and hearing . . . [the
officer makes] gently to strike with his bladder the mouth of him who is to speak, and the right
ear of him or them to whom the speaker addresses himself . . .”
CORRAL 157
The framing may include at its margins passages and spaces to which
the narrative does not explicitly take us—the dark alleyway—but the
cinematographer can have his gaffing team light these spaces in such a way
that they pass essentially unnoticed in a shot centering on something more
brightly lit (and therefore more dynamic). The set designer can collaborate
by planning and building a story space where some aspects are toned down
through coloring or embellishment and some are keyed up. The screenwriter
will take caution about mentioning places we do not see, so as not to permit
distracting disappointment in the not-seeing. The point is that generally
speaking we go where the story makes us feel the need to go, and our
attention, satisfied, is drawn away from otherwheres. In Who’s Afraid of
Virginia Woolf? (1966), a drama taking place largely in a domestic living
room, there is a point when one resident prods the other about the bedroom,
and in fact this bedroom is “upstairs,” in a zone to which we have hitherto
had virtually no access; but in a subsequent scene we do go to this bedroom,
and we can even recollect how we did swiftly and casually go there near the
beginning of the film to watch a woman changing but were so fascinated by
her (Elizabeth Taylor at her frowziest) we may not have paid much attention
to the space.
The camera is summatively generous. No treasure is hinted at that the
camera does not hold out for us to grasp. The camera itself is never (never
to be seen as) held away from treasures available somewhere within the
diegetic world. The camera is free. The camera is supple. The camera is
magical.
To put this obversely: an Aristotelian unity holds sway, in that all the
nooks and crannies opened to our view turn out (magically) to be important
for the story (and what is not important is made to seem nonexistent). But of
course this is a grand cheat, a method of reducing the potential complexity
of a tale to the more limited range of what can be shown: what the producer
can afford to show, what the designers can manage to configure, what the
viewer can be presumed willing to tolerate.
●● More than uniform diegetic importance, the various visible endroits
in narrative space must compose and hold, together, a certain
uniformity of reference. The designer knows that once he or she has
commenced imagining and drawing out plans for any set at all, that
set will offer certain reference to a fictional “reality,” whether that
reality is intended to be phantasmal or reportorial, whether of a
CORRAL 159
(a) ideal for the event that is to take place there—that is, nobody
feels cramped or swimming in the sea unless the cramping or
extreme openness are intended (the red room in Red Desert
[1964] is a tight space but excitingly so);
(b) elegantly designed to hold and feature that event, a space that
for the characters must be an optical wish fulfillment (as it is
for us), regardless of how “shabby” its surface;
(c) uninteresting in itself as a narrative space anticipated by a
character for later use, excepting for meticulous inspections
that are part of the dramatic construction, as when Michael
Caine visits Laurence Olivier’s labyrinthine lair in Sleuth
(1972) or when Vera Miles visits the upstairs bedrooms in the
Bates house in Psycho (1960). Characters very often tend to
move into a space and relate to other characters as though
the space itself has no vital qualities that touch or distract
them: we can be touched and distracted while they pay no
heed; or they are sent into a space with spectacular visual
qualities and forced to exploit these as part of the action,
exploit them immediately on being present (Harold Lloyd and
Jimmy Conlin on the skyscraper with the lion in The Sin of
Harold Diddlebock [1947]; Audrey Hepburn fearful at the
Palais Royal in Charade [1963]; John Alexander repeatedly
chasing up the staircase (à la Teddy Roosevelt) in Arsenic and
Old Lace [1944]). However it gains use or attention, the space
in which we linger to watch the action is put forward as the
singular and only space appropriate, available, and existent at
this moment. There is no need, and no urge, to peek around
and find attached secret spots, improvements, unless, again,
that very peeking around is the substance of the drama. A
limiting case might be My Dinner with Andre (1981), in which,
aside from a very brief opening and very brief closing phrase,
both involving the streets of Manhattan, we are settled for the
entire film at one table in a corner of one restaurant, listening
to two people converse; yet we are made to feel absolutely
comfortable, quite as comfortable as they are with their roast
quail. Indeed, many viewers of this film swear they have
journeyed to the sites mentioned in the tales that comprise the
conversation.
●● Narrative space shows dramatic coherence, in that whatever we see
happening here is just the sort of thing that could happen in a space
like this, or else, with an irony the film intends us to receive and
enjoy for its own sake, just the sort of thing that would never happen
in such a space (a direct inversion): the gigantic Waterloo station at
CORRAL 161
rush hour is exactly right as the place where Jason Bourne (Matt
Damon) would flee and hide in The Bourne Ultimatum (2007). Or,
in a flipped situation, without knowing where he is Jerry Lewis’s
nerdy yet very male Jerome Jerome arises, gets dressed, and goes
to breakfast in a gigantic girls’ sorority house in The Ladies Man
(1962). These are examples of Kenneth Burke’s “scene-act ratio.”
The action must not be such as to compel presentation of some other
space, to which we do not go. But the naturalism of the fit between
action and place (the straight fit/the ironic misfit) is a cheat against
our virtual confinement where the action is. The appropriateness of
setting is so rich we do not notice how it is our cell.
●● All of these principles, including the cheat mechanisms, can
themselves become the substance of dramatic exploration, as
happens for instance in Noises Off . . . (1992), theatrical characters
fleeing from our sight but then suddenly appearing backstage, and in
Synecdoche, New York (2008), where filmic fiction is the subject of
the filmic fiction. In The Magus (1968) domestic environments are
lifted away in an elaborate fabrication.
●● There are three kinds of fictional spaces, and film constructions
work by invoking and arranging them: (i) places a character desires
to visit: idylls; (ii) places a character is forced to visit: dungeons;
(iii) public spaces that people move through both conversationally
and physically in order to get to (i) or (ii): neutrals. All these have
corresponding cheats.
Typically (i) the happy destination, the idyll, will be set up as the solution to
an apparently irresolvable problem that confounds characters for whom we
have already been made to feel an enthusiastic affinity. They are not quite in
the “right” place, but if they can find a way to get there all will be resolved.
The earlier moment—a passing phrase, a whole scene—establishing the
character(s) as lovable, and the attached moment in which the problem
is presented in all its daunting complexity work together to make travel
to and arrival at the esteemed destination a matter of course. Often we
will be brought in during the journey (for instance, in Michael Haneke’s
American remake of Funny Games [2007]) to find people (played by star
actors we already know and love, Naomi Watts and Tim Roth in this case)
on the road in their car, chatting, joking, or arguing about the problem they
need to solve. The set designer and cinematographer might collaborate on
the characters’ arrival to show the destination as architecturally notable,
marvelous, special, ideally located, and so on. But what does not happen,
what the cheat makes unnecessary by framing the place as a mere waystation
on a longer route, is any pointed reference to the place of arrival as a
singular destination which is itself the whole subject of this film. We merely
162 THE FILM CHEAT
arrive there, merely make ourselves at home but not with such imbrication
as to block us from proceeding with ongoing action. The arrival of Aziz
(Victor Bannerjee) and Adela Quested (Judy Davis) at the monkey temple in
A Passage to India (1984) is, at first, a similarly wondrous, promising event
showing off a space that is marvelous. Dr. Meecham’s (Rex Reason) arrival
by auto-piloted aircraft at the research facility in Georgia gives a warm,
welcoming tone near the beginning of This Island Earth (1955). Dorothy
landing in Oz (1939), amazed Anna’s visit to the palace of the King of Siam
(1956), the travelers’ chancing upon the hidden Shangri-la in Lost Horizon
(1938) . . .
Clearly the idyll can function in romantic and in terrifying films, in
fantasies and in nightmares, as long as it presents itself, at least initially, as
a happy find. In Ransom! (1956) an idyll is converted by the action into a
dungeon as a cozy home becomes the inutile haven for two people whose
child has been abducted, and then reconverted to an idyll at the conclusion
when he is returned safe and sound.
Or:
(ii) Characters suffer capture, imprisonment, debilitating discomfort,
torture, degradation. The cheat here is doubled. The script implies over
and over that there is another place we are not seeing, the normal zone of
freedom outside these constricting boundaries, the “better place.” In prison
escape films, we are given references to a “world outside,” and prisoners use
the word “inside” to define their cloister, the prison. Beyond this general
reference to a freeing exterior we have little or no time to take note of the
space itself as a space because of the horrifying, wounding, or nauseating
events that take place here and, for the information of the viewer, negativize
it. Nor in the face of the horrors do we calmly examine the creatures who
by making an appearance constitute an event: Jabba the Hutt in The Empire
Strikes Back (1980), Col. Saito (Sessue Hayakawa) in The Bridge on the
River Kwai (1957), the giant spider in the terrifying dank basement of
The Incredible Shrinking Man (1957), or the horrifying kidnapper (John
Goodman) in 10 Cloverfield Lane (2016). As to unpleasant events and
unpleasant spaces, it is especially interesting to consider how a thoroughly
confining and undesirable situation can be produced in a routinized working
environment. The Guilty (2018) posits an emergency call center where an
operator (Jakob Cedergren) trying too eagerly to help a young woman
phoning in becomes embroiled in something shockingly bad. In Panic Room
(2002), Jodie Foster and Kristen Stewart escape home invaders in what they
believe is a specially designed safe space, but because it is insufficient to
their needs they are forced to visit the outside, that is, their own (fancy New
York) apartment and thus the invading thugs who are lurking there with
extreme malevolence.
(iii) A neutral space can be immense with respect to the size of the
protagonists who go there (the cornfield in North by Northwest [1959]) or
CORRAL 163
cozy and gemutlich (the restaurant in Little Italy where Michael Corleone
carries out an assassination in The Godfather [1972]), but it is always used
by the characters without belonging to them. It can be painfully nondescript
(the nocturnal plaza outside Lincoln Center where Laurence Olivier stabs
Roy Scheider in Marathon Man [1976]) or so elaborately filled with event
that it merits a special set piece inside the film (the rainy square filled with
umbrella users in Foreign Correspondent [1940]). The protagonist will
be split apart from the space, briefly or totally, either discernably edging
through a crowd there or engaged in a special way that makes the place
irrelevant (Dustin Hoffman’s Ratso Rizzo limping through the streets of
midtown in Midnight Cowboy [1969]). The public neutrality leaks into
the diegesis as diegetic neutrality. Hotel rooms are particularly useful as
public spots—spots that only some character(s) can be found in, but that
anyone can theoretically rent and visit—and when significant action takes
place there it is the action and the actors committing it that gain attention,
not the room itself (even, finally, in a setup where the room gets explicit
identification, as in the two adjoining hotel rooms we finally visit in The
Conversation [1974]).
In the idyll, a key cheat is the act of rendering the space instantly, naturally,
unquestionably hospitable and right, even more for the characters than for
the viewer. The character does not have to take dramatic time to make the
place comfy, so that if we see a character actually taking time for this we
know that the activity itself has, or will have, signal dramatic import. In
the dungeon, the space provides an ominous pathetic fallacy, oozing with a
foreboding darkness or “darkness” that acts as an unrelenting warning yet
not actually warning the viewer to “stay away” by shutting the eyes. Neutral
spaces are carefully constructed and photographed so as to give signs of only
appropriateness, never welcoming warmth or ominous darkness, so that
the action can stand out. If we watch a film like Spielberg’s The Terminal
(2004) we see the enormous lengths to which the visionary filmmaker, the
scriptwriter, and the key performer must go in order to make rational a
distinctly individualistic and much extended use of a space intended for vast
publics and speedy movement.
●● These spatial types are not fixed in a drama; a fictional
development or turn can metamorphose any of them into one or
more of the others, as with Ransom!. The space capsule in Apollo
13 (1995) begins as an idyll and becomes a frightening dungeon, as
does the Chunnel train from Paris to London in Personal Shopper
(2016) or the 15:17 to Paris in Clint Eastwood’s film of the same
name. For a few very piggish little folk, Willy Wonka’s magical
chocolate factory becomes anything but a wonderland. To reverse:
Lord of the Flies (1963) concludes with a warming transformation
of a war-scarred island into a haven of safety. A computer hacker
164 THE FILM CHEAT
FIGURE 22 Jacqueline Bisset and Jean-Pierre Léaud in Day for Night [La nuit
américaine] (François Truffaut, Les Films du Carrosse, 1973).
1
A thorough discussion of camera movement and of film lighting can be found in two books
by Patrick Keating, The Dynamic Frame and Hollywood Lighting from the Silent Era to Film
Noir; and in John Alton’s very helpful Painting with Light. Nestor Almendros’s A Man with a
Camera is eye-opening.
2
Including, Kino Flo, a high-output fluorescent system designed for Robby Müller by Frieder
Hochheim and Gary Swink in 1987.
SHOW ME 169
3
For a clear comparison between patterned shadows created for single-source lighting and the
same created for noir expressivism, see first Alfred Hitchcock’s Suspicion (1941), the opening
train sequence or the shots inside the new atrium of the Aysgarth home, and then John Huston’s
The Asphalt Jungle (1950).
170 THE FILM CHEAT
●● Speed. In the late 1950s and early 1960s, new and considerably
faster stocks made it possible to shoot on the street with available
light, even at night (on technical matters such as this, see Salt). All
the potentially expressive glare, and the detectable formal sculpting,
of artificial light is banished in the name of situational realism.
Where are we? What does it really look like here (really: not in
a movie)? Using available light, whenever possible, is a boon to
filmmaking for other reasons. The production becomes a smaller
picnic, with fewer pieces of bulky equipment to move around, less
reliance on electrical sources. Nestor Almendros’s nocturnal street
photography for Paris vu par . . . (1965) is a good case, as is Raoul
Coutard’s shooting for À bout de souffle (1960). Shooting with
available light can produce more splotches of darkness in scenes,
relaxing the designer and decorators’ need to fill in all the spaces.
As well, the available light cheat might lead viewers to associate
more comfortably with screen images as similar to what they see in
the everyday, with, among other effects, the result that personalities
teasingly remote from their audiences (Gloria Swanson’s Norma
Desmond in Sunset Blvd. [1950]) are now lowered from their
heights, brought close, brushed up against (Monica Vitti’s Giuliana
in Red Desert [1964]).
●● Arcs. The arc lamp, invented early in the nineteenth century by
Humphrey Davy, operates through an electrical current leaping from
one rod to another, in filmmaking rods made of carbon. The light
is extraordinarily bright (thus, if not modified by filtration or other
tactics, something of a giveaway), very useful in noir cinema for
giving the harsh highlights needed to make the contrasting shadows
especially ominous. It also produces a very high-temperature blue
light equivalent to daylight, thus being exceptionally useful bare,
or suitably filtered through gels, for simulating outdoor sunlight on
an indoor shooting location. The “outside world” is a generalized
cheat in cinema, almost never being a true outdoor space. Space
outside the window(s) of a room or a car when we see action inside,
is created by either arc lamps or skypans aimed at flat-lit painted
backings.4 Arc light angled through a built window-frame on a set
will photograph as daylight.
●● Barn doors. The various forms of tungsten (yellow-balanced)
light used on sets can be fitted with metallic “barn door” shutters
that allow for precisely directing the angle of incidence. As we see
For an exceptional case of lit painted backings used as the “outside world,” see my The Eyes
4
the world “naturally,” all objects are lit with angularity, so that
uniform lighting can look false unless distractions are provided by
subjects with interesting features or those engaged in dramatically
vital activity. The screen world seems molded and shaped, because
objects are not uniformly lit. This is just one type of mechanism that
provides for precision in lighting control. It is one thing to supply
light to a scene, another entirely to sculpt it so the right things
(including actors’ faces or parts of them) are “properly” heightened.
●● Cookies. Decorative or especially evocative shadows are created
by a device known as a “cookie.” This is a piece of cardboard or
Styrofoam that has been cut into a particular shape and then affixed
to the end of a long slender rod of some kind. A stage hand holds
the cookie up stationary or with movement between a light source
and the scene itself, thus effectively sculpting the shadow. Examples:
light flickering off the windshield of a “moving” car (shot on set
with a breakdown vehicle on gimbels); or the notable shadows
of noir, trees, poles, silhouettes, which have invoked such a wide
appreciation among fans and critics. To see astounding and very
beautiful, very large and complex cookie shots, made to emphasize
single-source lighting, see the “West Wing” sequence of Hitchcock’s
Rebecca (1940).
●● Bounce. As with diffused light, reflected light casts no shadow, and
can thus be very helpful in bringing soft and uniform illumination to
the star face in a portrait shot. Selective reflection, carefully aimed,
can help a cinematographer create the roundnesses and contours of
the celebrated star face, as William Daniels did with Greta Garbo.
A sheet of card stock or other pallid substance (nowadays often
Styrofoam) is held by a camera assistant below the performer at
such an angle that light from above aimed down at it will bounce
back into the face. This “bounce light” is singly responsible for much
of the celebrated star images of the classical age, a significant part of
what made the star seem to be beyond the human, closer in form to
a Greek sculpture.
●● Radiation. Photographing the close-ups of Grace Kelly for Rear
Window (1954), George Barnes created a variation of a trick that
had long been in use: rubbing a thin film of Vaseline on the lens in
order to obtain a diffuse, softened shot of the female face. Instead
of doing that, he stretched a nylon stocking over the lens and then
burned a tiny hole in the center with a lit cigarette. The light on
Kelly’s face (considerable bounced light) now gave crystalline focal
clarity directly in the center in a very small area, and then spread
radially with more and more diffusion. The stunning facial portrait
as Lisa leans over Jeff to awaken him shows the effect.
172 THE FILM CHEAT
●● Taking sides. There are no humans whose left and right sides are
perfectly isomorphic. Any one of us looks like one person when
photographed in right profile; and like someone else shot on the
other side. This effect is modulated considerably when the camera
shoots frontally at an angle. For profile shots, performers may have
sound professional reasons for wishing to avoid certain possibilities
and may even, as did Claudette Colbert, insist on contract clauses
which would stipulate profiles from one particular side only. But
the script supervisor has to keep careful notes of the angles used on
principal players, so that shots taken at different times but meant to
be edited together will match. The matching of two shots, discussed
in film theory as “suture,” is part of what conveys to the viewer
the illusion of being enmeshed in a coherent multi-dimensional
space where moments are real, but this conveyance depends on
film being shot in such a way that an editor can piece it together
reasonably, much later. The matching of shots can’t be created in
the editing, then, if it is not effected before the lens first. The “fit”
has to be arranged in principal photography, through pose, through
positioning, through camera placement and movement, through lens,
through lighting, and through careful notation.
●● Keys. The “key” light is a tightly focused and intense light (usually
tungsten-based) that concentrates on a principal object or on
some especially important feature of the performer’s body (almost
uniformly the star’s eyes, producing that telltale twinkle). I was on
a set once where the lighting of each shot took an extraordinarily
long time. The scene was “the Oval Office.” A long table with chairs
all around and papers, both crumpled and flat; coffee cups; pens.
I was told by an insider that the Japanese crew was using normal
Japanese lighting techniques: first bulk-lighting the whole area, then
spot-lighting various key areas where performers would be standing,
and then carefully keylighting every single object that would be in
frame, with a separate keylight for every single crumpled piece of
paper, each keylight separately controlled for intensity, coloration,
and sharpness.
●● Props. In two ways most set lighting in cinema is arranged to be
invisible as such, with the exception of “practical” lights such as
table lamps, candles burning in candelabras, chandeliers, and so on,
which typically do not actually light the scene. Light sources are
hidden off-camera, but also the light produced by the light sources,
fashioned to seem only realistic for the scene, has no more discrete
visibility in itself than any light does for us when we use it. Light
is noticed when it gets in the way: a reading lamp too glary or
not angled ideally. Sun coming through a window and getting in a
SHOW ME 173
Aside from specialty cases such as the milk glass above, where a light
effect is designed to be expressly visible as part of the storytelling (the
studio catastrophe scene of The Day of the Locust [1975] is another good
example), it is more generally the case that lighting is subjected to a blanket
and paradoxical cheat: nothing will show without it, yet it is always effected
so as not to show. Not only could a glimpse of a lighting fixture at the edge
of the frame ruin a shot and dispel the narrative illusion but so might a too
noticeable splotch of light inside the scene, something that seems not to
accord with the place as posited. In what follows next, I address one special,
and especially tormenting, lighting situation for filmmakers.
23
On the Road
FIGURE 23 Tom Cruise (l.) and Jamie Foxx in Collateral (Michael Mann,
Paramount, 2004).
Particular camera, lens, and lighting problems are posed by the narrative
trope of characters driving in cars, a feature that goes back to before the
1930s. In Sergei Eisenstein’s Strike (1925) we see a dark car moving through
the rain, with the driver dimly lit inside. The central function of the car
shot or sequence is social realism, the depictive recognition that we live,
and dramatic events occur, in a world filled with automotive transit. That
people use their cars in many ways, inhabit them, furnish them, perhaps
most importantly relate to other people in them. It is rare that a car
sequence appears depicting action that could not possibly have been shot in
a stationary location elsewhere, and indeed the most typical use of the car
in our culture, a means of getting from one place to another (as is shown
climaxing The Graduate [1967]), is among the less frequently depicted uses
ON THE ROAD 175
onscreen. In movies, things happen in cars, and in such a way that they seem
heightened for being placed that way.
Here are some of the problems in car shots:
●● The car interior is relatively cramped as spaces—certainly typical
diegetic spaces—go, and must now fit two or more characters,
a camera operator, and perhaps an assistant, as well as all the
necessary lighting equipment. Bus interiors, such as we see in Speed
(1994), have more room but it is almost impossible to get a clear
shot that blocks off the lighting fixtures.
●● The car interior is dark on the face of it. For night shots it will
seem cavernously so. The cinematographer does not want to ruin
the realism by bringing in too much light, but unless there is light
nothing is going to be seen.
●● The world outside, through which the car is passing, must look crisply
focused and colorful, sufficiently that it does not seem to exist on a
different planet from that of the interior. The story will sometimes
depend on some particular person or object seen outside, from within
the vehicle. But: too much clarity can produce too much interest, so
that as the vehicle passes, a distal place or object suddenly becomes
more pressing to the viewer than a character speaking a key line of
dialogue up close. Elia Kazan manages the crucial back-seat-of-the-car
conversation between Brando and Rod Steiger in On the Waterfront
(1954) by eliding views of the outside altogether, and replacing them
with flashing light (as from other cars).
●● For action scenes the car must appear to move quickly through
space. 6 Underground (2019) is a paradigm. Often precarious and
aggressive action is required as well, such as a character in one
car attempting to kill a character in another at full highway speed
(Bullitt [1968] or some of the cavortings in the early car chase
of Baby Driver [2017]). There is considerable inspiration for the
photography of such activity—with sharp axle blades anticipating
the guns of oncoming “millennia”—in the stunning chariot race of
Ben-Hur (1959).
●● Sometimes very precise control of star lighting and sound recording
are required while the set (the vehicle) is “in motion,” and outdoor
location shooting is out of the question for getting precision shots
of this type. Further, sound stages, even back lots, are not large
enough to accommodate fast-moving cars, although of course there
are legion film moments where slow-moving cars have been filmed
indoors. Nina Foch’s green limo in An American in Paris (1951),
Fred Astaire and company showing up at the log cabin in Swing
Time (1936), for just two cases.
176 THE FILM CHEAT
1
Steve McQueen did almost all his own stunt driving in Bullitt, however.
ON THE ROAD 177
either have larger softer tires than most vehicles, or be traveling on a special
track, or have a camera setup on gimbels, so that bumps in the road do not
affect the shot. Usually for a driving sequence it is not necessary to have the
driver or passenger visibly identifiable in every shot of the group, as long as
key shots make very crisply focused reference to the stars. Stand-ins can be
used for distant shots.
In place of exterior shots, or used intermittently to accompany them,
are shots from within the vehicle where the outside world is seen to pass
by the windows. When a lot of traffic is involved, the assistant director will
be completely in charge of all the personnel and vehicles and will more or
less direct the movement by which cars on the road creep up and pass the
central vehicle or lag behind, or whatever. In driving emergency sequences—
Baby Driver has extraordinary footage of this kind, as does The Bourne
Supremacy (2004)—the A.D. has a crew of stunt drivers, and the action
is broken down into tightly choreographed very small shots where, with
the help of catapults, springboards, and pull-aways vehicles and bodies can
seem to twist, spin, flip, and fly through space catastrophically.
The most frequent technique for capturing the outside world through
which a car moves is rear-projection photography, in which footage of the
scenery, from some particular point of view meant to simulate a position
in the vehicle, will be shot considerably in advance and then, on a special
soundstage, projected from behind on a screen outside the window area of
the partial car rig. That vehicle is most likely to be only a “car,” nothing
more than a cursory frame, steering wheel, seat, and window structure,
often on gimbels, springs, or moving platforms. Process plates (as they are
called) need to be made early on, and are usually effected by a special effects
camera unit on a location. Views through the back window or the windshield
of the car, angularly through the rear windows, or laterally through the side
windows need to be shot with the special-effects camera car moving at a
different speed for each (sixty percent of forward motion for lateral; eighty
for angular; one hundred for full rear).
Rear projection can lose effectiveness the more it diverges from the main
photography in terms of image quality: focus, saturation, illumination level,
and blur. Yet it need not. What makes rear projection difficult to achieve
with brilliance is the fact that there are legion difficulties inherent to the
process no matter what kind of film story it is being used to fake. With
cars, a poor quality rear-projection screen can diffuse light badly from the
center to the margins so that there seems to be a hot spot (Lady for a Day
[1933] gives a good example). The film stock used for the plate will affect
the saturation and brightness, not to say the color balance. But the most
perplexing of problems is the maintenance of dramatic balance, since the
better the rear-projection plate, the crisper, the more colorful, and the better
lit, the more clearly audiences can see outside the vehicle as well as inside,
and the more likely, then, that their attention will be taken up by some
178 THE FILM CHEAT
2
See further Pomerance, “Bells.”
ON THE ROAD 179
is devoted to them at the expense of the scene. The less they talk, the more
we fixate on the scene. And the longer we fixate on the scene the more likely
it is that we will see some slight disjunction between the background and
the foreground—a disjunction that in non-vehicular scenes we are less prone
to seeing. One of the cheats of car scenes is to keep the protagonists talking
enough to be a distraction in themselves.
But linguistic utterance need not be articulate. In the downhill car scene
of Hitchcock’s Family Plot (1976), where Bruce Dern and Barbara Harris
are trapped racing at about forty-five degrees downhill, inside a car the
brakes of which have been tampered with, we find intercut with the driver’s
point of view and external shots of the car on the road dozens of shots of
Harris trying to climb on top of Dern to save herself and Dern trying to
throw her off so he can keep eyes on the road. Many of the close-ups—his
foot interfered with on the brake pedal—are made in studio. The shots are
cut together rather quickly, so that the viewer, like Harris’s Blanche, bounces
around desperately (a carnival ride). Artfully intermixed here are perfectly
lit shots of the car interior seen from below and beside the driver with rear-
projected outside, and location shots of a stunt vehicle. The vocality is so
aggravated and fearful that it takes our attention from the seam that joins
the rear plate photography to the live footage.
Photographing car scenes faces a far different challenge today, as the
car culture has become more rabid and where the car shot signals, among
other things, the regularity of the everyday. Sometimes an action, especially
a dialogue, heightened in believability because vehicular, will be diminished
in dramatic power exactly because the car is a casual, almost too casual
conversational setting, the sort of place where people go to “just talk.” In
police procedurals now—typically cop duo films—much more attention is
paid to the types of conversation and the conversational content inside the
police car, between partners, than to the car as an agency of travel: in fact,
it is taken entirely for granted as an agency of travel, but the quirkiness of
the partners inside it is demonstrable most succinctly through their banal
conversations. The car would seem to transform all conversation into
banality.
In the classical era the car signaled social class and functioned principally
to convey class-bound action forward. Car scenes today are ornamental to
the mechanism of the story and do not move the action forward as much as
they imbricate us with the action. The realism of car shots, a popular myth,
dissolves some in actual viewing. When we see people driving cars on film
we know full well they don’t really look like people in real life who, driving
cars, don’t tend by posture or gesture to proclaim that they are doing so.
If on the road today one finds plenty of rude, aggressive, and incompetent
driving, when any of this kind of thing is performed on film it is carried
to an extreme, becoming almost comedic (Margot Winkler does a notable
car-bound riff in New York, New York [1977]). As it is not troublesome to
180 THE FILM CHEAT
discern how unlike the everyday a car routine is, car scenes must be cheated
through the inclusion of brazen distractions inside and outside, no matter
how dramatically probable. Driving down an expressway on the wrong side
of the road and heading the wrong way . . . driving near a precipice . . .
driving next to a car that is trying to bump you off the road. Driving with
gunshots fired. Driving wounded, as one bleeds. Driving against helicopter
pursuit. And on and on. All of these eccentricities of staging wrap us so
deeply into the momentary action we forget that we are being steered.
Steered, too, onscreen, and in a way that no one could accomplish if the
world were caving in. Perhaps the ultimate car-in-extremis moment comes
with John Cusack in his limousine in Santa Barbara in 2012 (2009), racing
to save himself as the urban geography comes apart under his wheels. An
ultimate moment of a more tightly composed, and entirely parodic kind is
the ambulance chase in Frank Tashlin’s The Disorderly Orderly (1964), one
of cinema’s great action choreographies involving Jerry Lewis putting his
foot to the floor.
Substitute driving is but one of the attractions of car scenes. A tender
moment, designed for romantic flavor, can be worked by means of a car, too,
and through an interesting substitution. There is a culminating brief scene in
Parker, where the eponymous hero, an action figure with a strict moral code
and a thoroughgoing sense of decency (Jason Statham) is parting from Leslie
(Jennifer Lopez), a young real estate agent in West Palm Beach, who has
been helping him revenge an especially filthy crime debacle. They are in a car
together, she at the wheel. He patiently explains what she must do with the
huge cache of jewels he has stolen from the robbers, and that in following
his instructions she must be very patient. She listens. It is a quiet Florida
night. He looks at her and gives a respectful nod. This could have been,
perhaps even should have been, a smashing romance, but he is with someone
already (she is not, haplessly) and love isn’t in the cards. As he stands on the
pave looking through the window she gives him a genuinely tearful smile
of goodbye. He responds with a tiny, but genuinely profound nod. The car
draws away, and we can see the regret, the release, the Weltschmerz in her
posture and touching expression. CUT TO: a shot from behind as Leslie’s
white car disappears into the night. The scene works only if we accept the
offer of sense and sensibility that is being offered onscreen, namely, if we
continue to feel Leslie moving away, moving away forever, into the long
dark night of time—and this after a very involved and swellingly sincere
relation with the person being left behind. Parker gets it, as we see from
his pose. And we get it, too. But a little cheat is in progress. Lopez is at the
wheel as in the lateral shot she moves the car away from him, off right. In
the ensuing long shot, the money shot, it is a stand-in driver. Yet we feel her
there. We feel what we wish to feel, yet at the same time the wish will have
to satisfy on its own.
ON THE ROAD 181
FIGURE 24A (Top) Big Basin State Park in Vertigo (Alfred Hitchcock, Paramount,
1958). Photography by Robert Burks; (Bottom) Amanda Langlet (l.) and Arielle
Dombasle in Pauline à la plage (Éric Rohmer, Les Films Ariane, 1983). Photography
by Nestor Almendros.
“GOOD CINEMATOGRAPHY!” 183
Viewers who are not in the business of making pictures often credit a film
they have seen with having “Good cinematography!” The images brought
pleasure. The images had clear (enough) focus and interesting subject
matter. The pictures taken as a whole gave the viewers a “good” feeling,
morally speaking, and through their appraisal the goodness of the feeling is
projected outward as a feature of what is on the screen.
{READER ALERT FOR THOSE WHO BELIEVE IN SANTA CLAUS}
Virtually everything that cinematographers do—all cinematographers—
has elements of the extraordinary, and the fastest way to learn this
is to take up a camera and try to make beautiful pictures of the world.
Yet, to win accolades extraordinary accomplishment is not required of
cinematographers: an astutely written, or exceptionally witty script can do
the trick; or a set of well-crafted performances; or someone’s celebrated
stardom plainly shown; or eye-catching set design and decoration, a haunting
musical accompaniment, an editor’s genius. Good producing is almost never
credited, like good hairdressing or good continuity, but it’s amazing how
much a producer can do to foster the development of a film (or to stifle
it). Viewers may be struck by a director’s infusion of pace, the feeling that
events are rhythmically ongoing. And as to the cinematography, it may be
evidence of nothing more than the most routine aspects of professional
accomplishment on the part of cinematographers, camera operators, grips,
and gaffers. Providing adequate lighting, handling the camera in movement,
undetectably getting and shifting focus, using a film stock that will ideally
capture the situational light and movement: all these are the bread and
butter (gluten-free or not) of picture-making, and virtually any filmmaking
crew will manage the challenges at all times, whether they are doing “good”
work or not. What is difficult involves variables most viewers neither notice
nor think they care about: depth of field, lateral movements, eccentric
camera placements, focus maintenance in motion, and sometimes the color
of lighting (for a startling example of which see Coppola’s One From the
Heart [1982]).
The “good cinematography” cheat, fostered in informal discussion, in
media reviews, and officially by the Academy of Motion Picture Arts and
Sciences by way of the Oscar competition (the World Series of film), often
offers a sense of Marvel!! and WONDER!!!! at what cinematographers
would consider normal for film, the day-to-day that goes along with the
territory. An equivalent posture might be raving ecstatically about a RADA-
trained British actor’s crisp enunciation, or giving immense admiration to a
concert pianist moving her fingers very rapidly upon the keys to play, say,
Chopin’s Grand Polonaise. If you can’t do fingerwork like that, you don’t
play Chopin. If you can’t enunciate you get off the stage.
The presentation of an Academy Award for cinematography (since
1927) is a firmly grounded incitement to audience admiration, yet admirers
often neglect to take into account the salient truth of the Academy Award
184 THE FILM CHEAT
2003: Russell Boyd for Master and Commander: The Far Side of the
World [landscape (seascape), archaic situation]
2004: Robert Richardson for Aviator [script, characters, powerful
central performance]
2005: Dion Beebe for Memoirs of a Geisha [script, situation]
2006: Guillermo Navarro for Pan’s Labyrinth [script, surreal effects]
2007: Robert Elswit for There Will Be Blood [script, characters,
powerful central performance]
2008: Anthony Dod Mantle for Slumdog Millionaire [script, “exotic”
situation, and setting]
2009: Mauro Fiore for Avatar [effects, (CGI) landscape]
2010: Wally Pfister for Inception [effects, (CGI) landscape]
2011: Robert Richardson for Hugo [effects]
2012: Claudio Miranda for Life of Pi [effects]
2013: Emmanuel Lubezki for Gravity [effects, situation]
2014: Emmanuel Lubezki for Birdman or (The Unexpected Virtue of
Ignorance) [witty characters, situation]
2015: Emmanuel Lubezki for The Revenant [landscape, situation]
2016: Linus Sandgren for La La Land [characters, “behind the camera”
landscape]
2017: Roger A. Deakins for Blade Runner 2049 [effects, situation]
2018: Alfonso Cuarón for Roma [characters, rare b/w]
(and at what cost); the sophisticated challenge of lens choice, given all the
variables effective with this one or that one; the nightmare of focus pulling,
especially in very long or in moving-camera shots; the relationship between
technical equipment required and physical location, with its restrictions
and limits (for The Player [1991] schlepping cameras, lights, dollies, and
other equipment up the vertical slope that leads to Whitley Heights); special
working demands of the director or performer; the need to make visual
continuities within each shot (this happens, then this, then this, then this)
so that later on shots can be cut together by someone else.1 How to balance
the aesthetic demands of the shot with the labor demands of the producer
and the unions, since everybody working to achieve the moment of aesthetic
beauty is a contracted employee with guarantees and obligations arranged
in advance.2 All of these technical contingencies point to a working
environment much more than to a magical one, all would show a canny
audience that what is onscreen results from a complex and sophisticated
arrangement of labor and does not spring spontaneously out of the blue. But
audience engagement—which sells tickets—is favored when attention is kept
away from the technical, and the celebration of “good cinematography” is a
useful way of setting this distance.
For just a few examples: When Emmanuel Lubezki gets the (much
deserved) Oscar for The Revenant, nobody says in public that almost
the entire live-action portion of the film was shot with available light, an
achievement that put onerous demands on both crew and performers. When
Vilmos Zsigmond is rewarded for Close Encounters it is not part of the
publicity that he had ongoingly to make live location shots that would work
in combination with extremely high-resolution and high-illumination effects
mattes; that the human characters encountering extra-terrestrial life should
not diminish in stature visually when they did. What we see touted instead
is Leonardo DiCaprio struggling in the wilderness and looking dirty; and a
visit to earth of a cool alien starship that perfectly calls up 1970s lightshows.
To illustrate extremely difficult work finely done I choose three examples
(none of which earned an Academy Award), knowingly passing over a very
great deal of material that could just as reasonably capture our attention
here.
1
It is well known about Alfred Hitchcock during his combative days at Selznick International
that he retained artistic control (in the face of the aggressive and manipulative David O.
Selznick) by “pre-cutting” the film; the shots were planned in advance then made in such a way
that there was only one way to cut them together into the final sequence. For more on this see
Leff.
2
One example of the constraint placed on cinematographic work by collaborative labor
arrangements is Cary Grant’s standard contract (he was an independent contractor): it
mandated that he would leave the set promptly every day at 6:00 p.m. no matter what, and this
sometimes meant working very quickly to complete a shot on time.
“GOOD CINEMATOGRAPHY!” 189
onto the lenses of the eyeglasses Lancaster wore, so that his lighting would
produce some glare and bring emphasis to his eyes as agents of a surveilling
gaze. Since J. J.’s dialogue was written to be sharp, pithy, and aggressive,
hearing the voice speak it while being unable to take one’s gaze away from
those glary eyes made for an unforgettable effect. But at the same time
the camera and lighting rig had to move with the character in such a way
that no light would fall extraneously on the surround. The film needed to
look expressionist, without ever going so far in that direction that it veered
detectably away from realism—even though the Manhattan being portrayed
was more a fabular than a realistic Manhattan. One could watch this film
being wholly impressed by the play of power without giving a thought to the
cinematographer’s inventiveness.
As one can see by the awards given over the past ten years or so, a taste
has developed for cinematography that points to itself in some way, as the
recording of elaborate visual effects surely does. This kind of flashiness is not
a guarantee of quality, but it does ensure the viewer’s non-stop excitement,
especially if CGI artists can manage to produce an explosion, a wound, a
fragmentation, a firestorm, a whirlwind, or a crash freshly every second.
25
“Picture This”
In making this pan shot the cinematographer (Daniel Aranyó) has this to
consider:
●● Every object across which the camera passes—not all of them
at the same distance from the surface of the lens—must register
clearly as itself, and must do so quickly enough that in the camera’s
glide it does not vanish offscreen before being known, in this way
depositing in the viewer’s mind the trace of a disturbing blur, a
“what-was-that?,” and “I’m-not-absolutely-sure.” Consider that
in the finesse of viewing, any “What was that?” would obstruct
sight by turning the reception, the viewer’s alert sense, backward in
time toward a vision, already gone, of something that was not only
not lit or focused sharply enough in the first place but also is now
recognized in retrospect, swiftly, as being deficient this way. Every
object must register instantly and clearly as itself. This means that
the rapidity of this pan—let us say, how many seconds it takes us to
travel through an arc of ninety or so degrees—is part of the shot’s
“equation” and is to be calculated in advance. Once the speed is
known, or known roughly, the objects in the room can be placed
in such a way that the amount of motion-time resting on each will
be known. While we have come to learn of the flash-pan, in which
space will appear to blur, by design, as it flies by until we hit upon a
desired object of focus, this is not intended to be such a thing at all,
but something else. Something meditative, relaxed, and dreamy.
●● Dreamy, that is: we are already, as viewers, mentally occupying
the state of mind we will soon discover our subject is occupying.
Perhaps he is taking the lead from us, through some kind of
sensation because, as we shall discover, his eyes are closed.
●● As this room is a normal room (a normal-looking room of its
sort), it is imperative, too, that a proper appearance be given. The
place must look (very much) like what it is in the story, a cozy den:
there has to be enough light on the set, correctly modulated in
every possible nuance, for showing this: showing, that is, making
discretely visible. A tiny lamp could be glowing golden on a simple
shelf. A healthy fire could be ablaze in a welcoming hearth. A man,
presumably at home, could have dumped himself into his favorite
chair, and from where we are positioned he would have gained
light on only half his face. The composition begs for rational
construction of this kind but, as well, the viewer has no problem at
all constructing it.
●● But it is also true that this picture looks like a picture, and while
every shot in cinema is in fact a picture only some are “pretty as a
picture” and of these only a small number, usually, are intended to
“PICTURE THIS” 193
declare themselves as such. This shot I point to, its resolution upon
the detective at the end of the pan, this shot that is starkly pictorial,
is not pretty, however. It merely looks as though some force has paid
attention so that the place will show itself, and anyone in it, off well.
This task no user of his own den would set for himself in the real
world. One would be comfortable, but would not strive to give off
the appearance of being comfortable. (We can think back to neurotic
Larry Renault [John Barrymore] arranging a dramatic light upon
himself before committing suicide beside a fireplace in a hotel room,
in Dinner at Eight [1933].) Had we magically found ourselves in
this man’s den with him, very nearby so that as he slouched in his
chair before the fire we could share his peace and his daydreaming
state of mind, were we to be inside that space, it is interesting to
note that we would not see such a contrast in the fire-lighting with
our eyes, the hot, hot, hot glare on the fireplace side of his face
and the shadow over here. Our eyes would adjust to even out the
discrepancy between the two sides of the face. Given a second or
two, the eyes always adjust. The far side would be the brighter still,
but not nearly as much more than the near side, as we see in the
picture. The camera can be spoken of as analogous to the eye, it can
be called The Eye of the Story, it can be thought an “optical” device
(not only a device aimed at our eyes but a device that is itself eye-
like), but it is not. It does not make this adjustment.
●● In order to expose the film stock without adding bounce light to
even out the scene, the cinematographer has to take note that the
flames will overexpose in relation to the shadow areas; that if one
lights and focuses to obtain a clear and realistic portrait of the face,
the flames will take over the shot, both being slightly out of focus
and being so very bright they offer luminous threat. The shadow
areas would be overwhelmed. In this case it would be the fireplace
getting the attention (for its brightness), with the result that the
man in the chair, brightly enough lit to be visible, would also be
insignificant and not so inviting.
●● Our picture here looks like a picture because it looks as though an
artful accommodation has been made by the cinematographer to get
a reasonable rendition of the person (detective = central character) in
line with a clear and rounded representation of the (difficult) room.
Vermeer was an expert at this. Gainsborough.
●● However, the cinematographer has used a signal cheat. He has seen
to it that the film plays not to our knowledge of the world (our
knowledge of what we would see were we there) but to our myths,
myths that can be seen to organize our expectation and perception
far before we experience:
194 THE FILM CHEAT
Writing of the Dutch still life, Erika Langmuir is brought to consider the
height from which objects are seen: “Someone who ‘looks down’ at us is felt
to be supercilious; we ourselves feel superior to whoever ‘looks up to us,’
while ‘to look someone straight in the eye’ is to demonstrate sincerity and a
desire for intimacy” (54). The cinematographer’s so-named “Dutch” angle
is not really Dutch but somehow “Dutch” is easier to say than “Deutsch.”
German Expressivism used this technique frequently, and so when it came
into American usage the German word for “German” became part of it. But
word pronunciations are brick walls all over the world. In practice now, the
“Dutch angle” encompasses a wide range of camera placements in which
the world appears to be twisted, flipped to the side, in some other way
disoriented, or seen from very high above or below (tilts). When characters
are seen through twists, we have through our own projection a sense that
196 THE FILM CHEAT
them in diegesis because singular for us, has been manipulated without their
apparently knowing so that it will play “naturally” both with and around
their bodies. This needs a little slow unpacking:
●● We have a perception of every scene from without. We are looking
at the dramatic space from some point of view, in the “Dutch”
cheat typically from way above or way below. The action spreads
and looms up there or down there, a thundercloud or a Lilliput of
possibilities. But at the same time:
●● We recognize the characters as they have been spelled out, and part
of the spelling is their social status relative to one another. In Clover,
we know Plummer’s Raymond Swan is the studio head and Wood’s
Daisy is his creation to be used—he thinks--as he pleases, so as we
look upward and see him dominating her we also get a social view
that accords with the expectations we have borrowed from him and
from the Hollywood system.
●● Daisy, however, operates differently. She may be a studio
employee—a salaried worker—but she is also a major star. She
doesn’t kowtow to Swan when she interacts with him, she faces
him and has at it directly, as does he with her: directly—she being
a little shorter (as we are shown it) turning her chin up; he being a
little taller turning his chin down. For Daisy, Swan is automatically
and naturally the man that the camera with its angling has led us to
know, the Big Man, whom the system that is exploited in the diegesis
has privileged. Yet she is not quite obedient, not quite his slave, not
quite not-herself.
ourselves loom and teeter or shrink helplessly. In the skewed stairway shot
in Rebel Without a Cause (1955) where Jim sees his mother upside-down
as she comes downstairs, we share his confusion, disorientation, imbalance,
and vulnerability.
The Dutch shot does some of the performer’s work, in that striving with
tone or posture or elocution to establish deference or dominance isn’t really
necessary if the image does that for you.
27
Moving On
In the train one could see neither where one was going nor where one had
come from but only, instant by instant in an unbounded fragmentation, what
was here now. “The dissolution of reality and its resurrection as panorama,”
Schivelbusch writes, “thus became agents for the total emancipation
from the traversed landscape: the traveler’s gaze could then move into an
imaginary surrogate landscape” (64). The signal argument in Schivelbusch’s
book relates train travel and its mode of perception to modernity itself.1
Film is, in a way, like a train;2 and as we watch it (cinematographers all
know) no matter our construction of the experience we actually see without
recognizing a beginning or an end but only a fleeting ongoingness.
Given that we are not fixating on the image but only glancing at it, the
image may work quite well if it contains less information than is supposed
by the viewer. A single telltale feature, nicely lit, may suffice entirely. The
cheat, then, is that the images invoke, imply, or suggest a field and mode of
attention they do not take pains to serve with detail, that they seem to offer
a picture of things while in fact offering a glance. Instead, the onward thrust
of the story’s increasing probability sweeps us forward on a kind of hunch.
●● II. The coup d’oeil. Ortega discusses the act of looking in modo
obliquo, rather than in modo recto:
1
I am grateful to Ann Kaplan for pointing me to Schivelbusch’s book in London in 2005.
2
François Truffaut to Jean-Pierre Léaud, in Day for Night (La nuit américaine, 1973): “Les films
avançent comme un train, tu compris?, comme un train dans la nuit.”
MOVING ON 201
vision, those side-views “from the tail of the eye” which represent the
height of disdain. Thus, the third dimension disappears and the field of
vision tends to convert itself entirely into surface. (123)
FIGURE 28 Two lap dissolves. Above, Gregory Peck with Ingrid Bergman in
Spellbound (Alfred Hitchcock, Selznick International, 1945), effect by Jack Cosgrove.
Below, Jessica Tandy in The Birds (Alfred Hitchcock, Universal, 1963), effect by Bob
Broughton.
BEHIND THE CAMERA BEHIND 203
The optical printer was developed by Linwood Dunn. Taken at its most
essential, it is a pair of devices fixed near one another in absolute registration
within a solid, metallic frame structure. One of these is a standard camera,
typically 35 mm although other devices can be subbed in. The second is a
projector. The lens of the projector is pointed straight into the lens of the
camera. What the projector projects, the camera can record on film. And
the two devices can be regulated to operate at variable frame rates—24
fps, which is the Academy norm; 36 or 48 or higher fps for producing slow
motion; 18, 12, or lower fps to produce speed-up—as well as being set to
count frames; to easily shift movement forward or backward one or more
frames at a time; and to accept inserted blocks ahead of the film plane, such
as black cards.
Fade. If as film unspools in the projector—any scene at all—the aperture
on the camera side is made to close in a smooth progression through the
frames, until it is completely closed, what is recorded on film is the fade to
black. Clearly, this can be done swiftly or slowly, as called for. A fade-up
would be made by starting with the camera’s aperture closed, turning on the
units, and as the film unwound ahead slowly opening the camera aperture
(again, at variable rates).
Here and in other maneuvers with the optical printer special care will
be taken to meticulously clean the two lenses, that of the camera and that
of the projector. In final effect, what is produced by the camera is a second-
generation record, a film of a film, and it is sometimes possible to see the
shift of generation onscreen at fades and so on, since only the tail end of the
outgoing and incoming scenes need be used to make the transition and in the
print the recorded transition will be spliced in. With optical printer moves
that were worked through at the Technicolor laboratory, the transitions
were made in the original black-and-white records so that in the final print
there was no perceptible shift. With Eastmancolor films processed in studio
labs (DeLuxe, Warnercolor, Metrocolor, and so on), this purity was absent.
Dissolve. Scene A is optically printed as though for a fade (see above). The
system is stopped. Both the camera and the projector are wound backward
to the starting point. Scene A is removed from the projector and replaced
by Scene B. Now a fade-up is made on the same receiving stock. The effect
will be a dissolve from A to B. By varying the rate of film movement in the
projector, or the rate of aperture closure or opening, the disappearance of A
and appearance of B can be symmetrical or skewed either way. Hitchcock
took pains to arrange for dissolves that would remarkably add layers of
implication to his stories.
Split. The scene being projected onto the film stock can bear manipulation
at the hands of the operator (and many operators in the studio era were
exceptionally accomplished). A small black card can be inserted in a slot
between the passing film and the lens. The operator can make the card block
any part of the frame, and as the projected image moves forward the rate
204 THE FILM CHEAT
can be controlled, even to one stop-frame at a time so that the card can be
adjusted. In this way, only half of a scene can be recorded. When camera
and projector are rewound, on a second pass the operator can block the
other side. To make films in which a performer exists beside himself or
herself onscreen, “double” films, two pieces of film are used in the projector,
A with the performer on, say, the right side of the set; B with the same
performer, perhaps costumed differently, perhaps not, on the left. When the
film is shot on set, clearly the camera has to maintain strict alignment for
both sequences A and B, keeping an exactly measured distance from the
performers. The material on the set that will appear in the very center of the
frame is important and will typically be some kind of vertical structure that
is built into the setting, such as the edge of a bench or a tree trunk.
Design. By affecting the projected film with a variety of blockers of
different shapes, and controlling the blockage one or two frames at a time,
an effect can be created of scene B moving into A and taking over by means
of circling, dropping, popping up, arriving through venetian blinds, and a
very large array of other possibilities.
Given that both the projector and the camera can be set to turn at variable
speeds, and that both have apertures that can be opened or closed to whatever
degree, the final effects on the recording film are consummately varied and can
be achieved with great clarity. All of this constitutes a cheating mechanism,
technical in its base yet used by artists of extreme skill and inventiveness
to produce effects that can only be called creative in their falsity. In the
dissolve, for example, the viewer is intended to actually “see” one scene
wiping, fading, or dissolving into another as though in a world of the dream,
where images can transpose in such irrational ways. The cheat is necessary
here because although the experience of watching film is dreamlike, it is not
a dream. Part of the delight of watching film comes exactly in unpredictable
transpositions, and in our ways of interpreting these transpositions in line
with our appreciation of the whole. Digital transpositions have their own
variety of flexibilities, but both digital and non-digital forms come to life
especially in color shifting or grading, such as we find in the Lord of the
Rings films (2001–03).1 Optical work allows us to unknowingly see more
than the pictures shot by the cinematographer, and although their names do
fly by in the credits (usually under “Special Photography”) the matte artists,
optical printer operators, and color specialists who fabricate what we call
“the film” from the filmic materials originally shot, tend to go unheralded
and unknown, if they are not simply forgotten.
I discuss one very complicated visual morph effected through non-digital color control in
1
FIGURE 29 Audrey Totter in Lady in the Lake (Robert Montgomery, MGM, 1947).
Perhaps no screen myth addressing the story or the labor behind it is more
prominent and also more taken for granted than this: figures of the screen
do not know the audience is there watching them. They act, as it were, in
a world cut off, a private and untouchable zone, a territory into which we
peek at our peril and for our pleasure. The “invisible” effect, if we might
call it that, is produced by actors maintaining sight lines that are generally
guided away from the lens. When the actor doesn’t see the camera, the
character doesn’t see the audience (whose camera it finally is, by adoption).
206 THE FILM CHEAT
to theater. The tension is hard for Montgomery to keep up, and without
the murder-divorce-duplicity story and its peculiarities the gazes do not
work to fashion a new engagement, except perhaps with the screen bodies
taken in themselves. Le Trou (1960) commences with a very brief address to
the camera by Jean Keraudy about his friend Jacques Becker’s film (telling
a “true story” in which he was involved); that film we are about to see.
Samuel Fuller’s The Naked Kiss (1964) is structured conventionally but at a
climactic moment a central character, Kelly (Constance Towers), confronts
the lens and dramatically removes the stunning hair that has captivated us
all along to reveal that she is in fact bald. Something of an homage is given
by Steven Soderbergh in his The Laundromat (2019). Jason Reitman’s Up in
the Air (2009) leaves us with the principal character standing at loose ends in
front of an airport departure board unsure where his future lies. Swiftly, in a
half-blink, he looks at us for guidance. Lewis Gilbert’s Alfie (1966) is a first-
person narrative in which our beloved (and belovedly naughty) hero Alfie
tells the story by looking into the camera and addressing us, with a tone of
great personal warmth and confidentiality: the confiding is conspiratorial,
and from the outset we are cozily wrapped into the conspiracy. The same
intermittent cozy attachment is shown in Tony Richardson’s Tom Jones
(1963) by Albert Finney. An even more conspiratorial, and finally diabolical,
affiliation with the audience is produced in the original House of Cards
(1990) by Ian Richardson as Urquhart, winking at us sideways, smirking
into our privacy as he makes defamatory comments about other characters
strolling blithely around him. It can hardly be that as these characters “see
the camera” they also “see us watching,” since even if one passes from the
character to the actor one can admit only that the actor knows what a
camera is, and can have no expectation of meeting any one of us in the dark.
This is, then, a curious, even idiosyncratic form of affiliation: the character
recognizes himself or herself as a character, not a person; a being put on by
a person who works to a camera. That person, as far as we are concerned,
recognizes only the “form of” the audience, the audience as a construct.
How can the character’s confrontation be understood in light of the
tension between our presence and our absence as viewers: between presumed
innocence of the production on one side and the production’s explicitly
catching our eye and ear on the other? If the fleeting knowledge of actorial
presence—of our presence onlooking the character’s1—swiftly flies away
in most cases, how can we entertain the experience suggested in the films
above, where such flight doesn’t seem to happen at all?
The answer to the dilemma is both simple and profoundly troubling.
The onlooking character, that screen figure who “turns to the audience”
and winks, emits in seeing us a kind of transubstantiating ray that converts
1
On the audience member’s capacity as “onlooker,” see Goffman, Frame Analysis Ch. 5.
208 THE FILM CHEAT
us, not only as we watch and listen but by virtue of our watching and
listening, into someone else, another character in the screen extravaganza
but one who goes without a name and without an image, one who is a
participant not a mere outsider/peeker-in. I might coin a word to match
Michel Chion’s acousmêtre (which functions in the sound by speaking and
audible speech from off) and suggest that the viewer becomes an optimêtre.
Sound is something we should not produce in any event, as it would be
unconscionably (impossibly) rude to interrupt the proceedings. But we
can stand silently and nearby, the servant who makes entrance with the
Queen. As optimêtre we have full rights to inhabit the place of the drama,
to position ourselves anywhere and to move in any fashion, and this, surely,
with any filmic arrangement, yet somehow much more particularly, more
intelligently when a character gives us the eye. The recognizing, approving,
welcoming eye. The optimêtre knows what it is to be there, through the
secret illumination that comes to him and to all characters by virtue of their
placement in the drama. When I am an optimêtre, the Queen can talk to
me, can confide in me, can whisper endearments or scathing critiques to me,
can use me to share her ribald jokes. Because in sharing herself this way the
Queen has identified the proximity of her confidant(e), that charged and
eager watcher knows her as no other character does, sees and hears the
silent soliloquy hiding in every comment she makes.
When one character speaks privately and directly to another character,
makes a kind of “inside soliloquy,” the same charge is not invoked. We are
special, as we watch.
The difference between the optimêtre and the onlooker:
The onlooker is part of the actor’s world of awareness, a creature invoked
by the performance, akin, in a direct way, to Walker Gibson’s “mock reader.”
The “mock reader” is a persona of the reader’s, someone I become when I
approach a text; and in order to make such an approach I act as though the
language of the writing is familiar enough to me, as though the presumptions
made by the author can be taken by me for granted, just as required, and
as though my fascinations are those implicit in the textual address. As to
the onlooker, who exists in the act of cinematic spectatorship, the character
neither knows him, nor recognizes him, nor sees that he is there, nor believes
in the possibility of him, nor admits him to citizenship in his world. For the
character, it happens that, without consciousness of it, he lives his expressive
life in register with the onlooker’s knowledge and expectations: again, by
happening but not a happening of which he is aware. If he were asked
about it (but who could ask?) the character in all sincerity would be entirely
oblivious to how this happens. The actor, however: well, she does know
how this happens, being in league with a writer and aiming her performance
to a viewer’s reception. The actor knows she has created the onlooker, in
a way, and created, too, by invocation, another character who is not in
the know about onlookers. That character, the optimêtre: this “person” is
PEEK-A-BOO 209
known to the character, likely very well known, known and recognized as
known, although a being to whom, until the moment of the direct gaze to
camera, when the figure of the optimêtre is expressly summoned, neither the
character nor the viewing audience gives a thought. He is one of those who,
in Starobinski’s words, “can see to it that his name no longer designates
himself. Rather ingenuously he dreams of placing himself in the position of
one who sees without being seen” (81), ingenuously because also hopelessly,
since at the moment of the character’s gaze to camera it is evident that
trying to peek without being seen peeking is doomed to fail. The optimêtre
is a bunkmate, a bosom pal, no matter the tone adopted by he or she who
looks straight forward to address him or her. Not a creature who is involved
in the action of the drama but a creature in whom the actor’s character can
confide. The confidant(e) has been in the room all along, silent and standing
to the side, and now that he or she is invoked by that character gaze there
is felt and assumed a response, an attitude the character can have predicted.
(Certainly not an attitude that could shock the character looking out at it.)
When I say “invoked” by that character gaze I am of course tilting the
scale a little toward the character as active being when, of course, it is no
more than a put-on. Michael Fried writes in Absorption and Theatricality
of a shift
{35} Heist
Moral implications of watching
{37} Stand-ins
Barbra Streisand; Rebel Without a Cause; F for Fake; Kevin Costner
FIGURE 30 Daniel Radcliffe in Harry Potter and the Prisoner of Azkaban (Alfonso
Cuarón, Warner Bros., 2004).
Either by extraction from the flow of the normal, or by artful concoction, film
is made in the stream of everyday life, sometimes secretly on a soundstage,
and sometimes relatively openly on location (if with direction signs for the
cast and crew that have fake titles on them). Quotidian routine is an essential
element in the prepared broth: routine that is either filmed directly (sidewalk
crowds, trees in a park) or “directly” (as in documentary—an epitome being
Frederick Wiseman’s High School [1968]), or imitated for fictional realism
(JFK [1991]), or used as a substrate on which some fantasmal invention
rests (Marriage Story [2019]). But sometimes a filmmaking team will need
to realize an image that cannot be made in the stream of everyday life, a
picture of something fabulous and mythical, else a picture in a dangerous
circumstance, else a picture of the actor’s body yet showing a body that does
not look like the actor’s actual body to fans who recognize it. And many
other things.
214 THE FILM CHEAT
sky—all these are matted in. Daniel is not above or even near a Loch, he is
in a soundstage near London, in the air but not necessarily far off the floor.
A by-product: if he is a child actor, he is most likely having the time of his
life “flying” in the green world.
The two motives for matte usage are these:
Special visual effects are no longer the public secret they once were. Books
are in print detailing them with splendid illustrations that will call up
fond memories of screen moments one had thought to illustrate one thing
when in fact they were based on quite another. The matte technique has
been explained in detail, and nowhere better than, in Raymond Fielding’s
The Technique of Special Effects Cinematography (1965). But after 2000
public interest really peaked. From Mark Cotta Vaz and Craig Barron’s The
Invisible Art (2002) to Richard Rickett’s Special Effects: The History and
Technique (2006) to Editing and Special/Visual Effects, ed. Charlie Keil and
Kristen Whissel (2016), and much more, effects techniques such as mattes
are explained, illustrated, discussed, and mused upon. Everyday viewers,
not making claims to professional status, continually voice opinion about
effects and claim to see failures. They look back with hollow charity on the
now disregarded early techniques with which they grew up.
What the matte cheat finally provides is one or the other of two opposing
results: a coherent, apparently seamless, aesthetically unified image in which
the protagonist seems perfectly to fit and harmonize with the space, quite
without the effort of any special construction; or only a hapless attempt to
convince viewers that the protagonist perfectly fits and harmonizes with the
space without the effort of special construction, hapless because a canny
audience, already appreciative of the delicatessen affectionately known as
sfx, search for, measure, evaluate, and compare the technique they claim to
see in use: see baldly for what it is. When the matte works, the character is
there. When the matte doesn’t work, the character isn’t there. But in both
cases, regardless of the success or failure of the technique, one finds a place,
a there, to experience and point to.
They are really there, they aren’t really there.
But . . . where is there?
There is no there. In front of us is only a “there.” Yet the inducement to
accept the true thereness of the “there,” to think of a there there, is the cheat.
And this is, of course, the same cheat as applies in filmmaking that does not
use the matte technique, filmmaking altogether, albeit the matte technique
218 THE FILM CHEAT
when discovered as such raises the cheat to our observation most distinctly,
most blatantly. In cinema there is never a there there but to follow along we
must surmise that there is. When we watch it is impossible to see the image
without conceiving of a there that is not there, without falling for the effect
even if one thinks one is watching the magician employ it.
31
Where Are We?
FIGURE 31 Grace Kelly and Cary Grant in To Catch a Thief (Alfred Hitchcock,
Paramount, 1955).
were oriented skyward, to the sun, moon, stars, and other hierophanies
of the sky rather than, as in Neolithic times, downward to the spirits
of the earth. With the ritual center, and later the city, human horizons
220 THE FILM CHEAT
expanded beyond the local and the fleeting to the cosmos and its orderly
cycles. Not only that, priests and kings believed that they could mediate
between heaven and earth, impose the former’s stabilities on the latter’s
propensity for chaos. In form, these cities were rectangular, with the four
corners oriented to the cardinal points, as with Dur Sharrukin (721-705
BCE) and Borsippa (604-561 BCE), or with the four sides oriented to the
cardinal points, as with the historical cities of China. (114)
Our cities and our landscapes, our religions and our sciences have all
pointed themselves with regularity in the same “cardinal” ways. More, in
The Return of the Vanishing American, Leslie Fiedler uses the northern, the
southern, the eastern, and the western as the four principal narrative forms,
at least in American literature.
Yet cinema is different. It is always a case of, “Where are we? Here.” And
“Where are we going? Onward.” “Where are we coming from? Before.”
There are no cardinal points, the left and the right of the picture are vacua,
above and below simply do not exist and never did, behind the picture is
nowhere and in front of it is the unspeakable us.
At the same time, those who view renditions on the screen finally leave
the theater and go off to live conventional lives, in which they have dutifully
learned the rigors of conventional geographies, a learning by means of
which they traveled to the cinema and then traveled home again—even
though the map that connects “home” to the “screen world” is nonexistent.
When space is designed to create a cinematic place, a setting for a story,
homage must be paid to the everyday grid, notwithstanding that shapes
may be freely reconfigured to slide away from the limitations of that grid.
(Designing The Cabinet of Dr. Caligari [1920], Walter Reimann and Walter
Röhrig built city sets in modulating proportion, so that buildings would
seem to stretch away from the eye.) When we dream, we enter and move
through a space that is more like the space of the screen narrative than the
space of the territory outside. When we watch film, we move through a
space that is like the space of a dream.
Two cheats become evident as laws of design. First, any set design that
is intended to call up—to summon—thoughts of any realistic world known
or knowable to the viewer will include, however minimally, some tag that
connects to everyday perception. A highway marked with road signs. A
bathroom with a roll of toilet paper next to the toilet. A conference room
with a telephone. A kitchen with a frying pan. We are very often so swayed
by the pungent realism of this tag that we neglect to see the plasticity of
the overall design: a highway with no vehicles on it (shot on a location, by
the aid of a police license for stopping traffic flow); a toilet with an odd
figurine standing on its basin (shot on a soundstage, with the help of an
artist’s construct); a conference room with picture windows giving out upon
a prospect of the stormy sea (a stage set, with a stunning rear projection
WHERE ARE WE? 221
or CGI ground); that frying pan sitting on a stove that has no power. The
real tag signifies a real place. When the real tag is withheld from the design
we find ourselves in a purely fabular place, somewhere we can admit only
through imagination, somewhere we can travel only by imagining. A good
example would be that cityscape in Wiene’s Caligari. It is possible to strike
a dramatic unfolding that hovers between dreamscapes and reality, either
by using a realistic design and structuring unrealistic action there; or by
using an unrealistic design and having characters behave in an ordinary,
recognizable way. In Caligari, for example, the characters have conversations
which model, in their form, their tone, and their linguistic structure the kinds
of conversations people have all the time everywhere. In The Adjustment
Bureau (2011) we move from one to another very precisely photographed,
realistic Manhattan location, following people who behave as people do on
the sidewalks of New York, while entertaining the thought of secret agents
moving through secret doors into secret tunnels that magically connect
distant points as though they are adjacent. It is easy enough to see the trouble
expended in mounting believable signs over banks, restaurants, hotels, and
the like; in painting up police cars to look as though they properly belong to
the NYPD, the LAPD, and so on; in decorating the building fronts of studio
backlots so the street will not look like only a “street.”1
In a scene with characters, how do we find ourselves, self-locate as the
being we must become to apprehend and appreciate what is shown?
Those characters we follow are in front of us only because they are being
screened, occupying there what is depicted as a recognizable sort of place,
behaving in a way consistent with at least our imagination of how people
like that would act in a place like this (not that we base that imagination on
knowledge). The actors are using their bodies persistently to aid in shaping
the place, producing angles, stretches, extensions that match the lines of the
design: thus, while in an actual setting such as this people might use their
bodies much more haphazardly, paying less attention, here the body of the
actor is treated as part of the scenic design. The actor as a presence never
disrupts the image design. (For an elaborate demonstration, see the ballet
sequence in Singin’ in the Rain [1952]).
And there is to be seen a responsiveness—perhaps even an odd
responsiveness—to the qualities of a place in the specifics of performance:
a character not just turning off a table lamp but standing beside it for a
moment to let a dramatic beat emphasize the gesture, or resting a hand
upon a doorknob to give weight to the instant of turning it and walking in.
The characters not only fit the place, they become of the place, relating to
the locus, local. We sense appropriateness, belonging, order. A very extreme
situation, where, miraculously, there is still fit: in Cries and Whispers (1972)
1
Usually the giveaway is the kerb, not forefronted in the shot.
222 THE FILM CHEAT
2
The ticquer can be thought of as a person who makes numerous inappropriate indications, as it
were signaling out of context and for no appreciable reason. In carefully designed “catastrophic
situations” (such as in A Night to Remember [1958] or World Trade Center [2006]) people
frantically gesturing do not seem out of place.
WHERE ARE WE? 223
The fireworks are not only white but also purple, suggesting that
the purple in the room comes from some slowly dying ember of
passionate radiance that flew off the explosions.
●● The fireworks function diegetically as well as aesthetically, and
so the open French doors through which we can fully see them
and the explosions themselves were requirements, given the story.
The Bataille is in progress not so far away. The fireworks are in
celebration of that, and thus work to evidence the geophysical
setting of the story. Much else in the film works to do the same, as
though constant reiteration of our presence on the Riviera is part
of the deeper meaning here. The Riviera as The Riviera is a central
player in the film (from the opening shots onward). The Riviera
= glamour = wealth = sophistication = exclusiveness: Francie and
Robie, glamorous, wealthy in their two ways, sophisticated beyond
belief (especially from the cinemagoer’s point of view), exclusive in
that they are exclusively ours, just as this room is.
* * *
I have argued above that in watching a film scene like this one from To Catch
a Thief the viewer becomes an onlooker. I ask now, how has the place been
arranged to help the viewer in her effort to become that onlooker? It is clearly
a transformation that has to be learned, and that bears constant support and
incitement. Here the viewer is an onlooker floating on The Riviera, a peeper
who has crept into a private hotel room, a seeker after romance. We need
hardly stress that this onlooker is not attending the Cannes Festival while she
is watching this film; she is not on The Riviera at all. Three obstacles must
be cheated successfully, or the love duet—that is floating near us—will ring
entirely hollow from start to finish, top to bottom.
[1] Stolidity. The viewer is and remains comfortable and satisfied to be
here, both “here” as an onlooker watching and here as a cinemagoer alive
in the theater showing this film. There can be no anxiety stemming from the
lack of a compass. Bringing a self to the theater, the viewer did not at any
point expect to take, and did not make necessary preparations for taking, a
voyage to the South of France. (We see the large colorful travel poster in the
travel agency vitrine, but we do not have our passports.) We are “staying
put.” We wish to be in France watching all this happening in France, but
basically not be in France because that would be troublesome and expensive.
We are reticent to move, in a certain sense. Our reticence to move must be
addressed, and it is addressed, by virtue of the seductive glamour with which
the shots are composed. (Of all the opulent settings we see, this is by far the
most opulent.) At this moment, however, the viewer has been infected with
no realistic need to be shown a hotel room in turquoise and/or purple light,
WHERE ARE WE? 225
with mysterious shadows. A hotel room could have any kind of light, any
kind of furnishing, and the scene could be late in the afternoon. Further,
sexy as Kelly and Grant are together, this story could be told with any two
actors if they were sufficiently competent. Kelly and Grant bring value-
added allure.3 And the romance being sparked here, possibly, is something
we are not just eager but very hungry to see, so that we are willing to be
where we must be to catch the action from the beginning and willing to stay
with the characters, follow their actions, to see what will develop. We come
to cinema with a stolidity, an idea of a compass, but the film cheat must
tease us out of it. To tease us to feel at ease shifting around without palpable
direction. As we sit looking at the screen, where is France, after all?
[2] Modesty. It is unconventional, to say the least, to sit in observation of
two people in an actual or potential lovemaking situation. Desire to see as we
might, we really tend not to put ourselves in the embarrassing situation of being
caught peeping. Conversations, glances, mutterings, and gestures like theirs are
considered private. While it is the case that in some ways the entire depiction
onscreen is a privacy opened to viewer inspection, this scene is a privacy within
that privacy and, again, a privacy without shape, with no up or down, no left or
right. But the glimmer and glamour seduce the eye, so that reticence flies off. We
can feel reason, in fact, to believe something else is happening with these two in
this place, and it is entirely reasonable, not to say sensible, for us to pay it heed.
The fireworks alone are a spectacle we yearn to watch, and for doing that this
room provides such an ideal vantage point. Or the jewelry, especially against
that exceedingly idealized Kelly skin. The calm sophistication of the dialogue
and poise of the postures, a nice lesson for the imitative spirit. Not to say the
much noted (and much exploited) screen modesty of these two stars, who by
this point had teased audiences plenty of times so that audiences got used to
leaning forward and entering the tease. This scene might get sexy, even naked,
with some actors, but with Kelly and Grant in 1955 there is no way it will be
anything but properly dignified and properly filled with implication. It is safe to
be here watching. We are in the presence of those who observe Decorum. But
that presence: where in space is it?
[3] Class. These are exclusive coordinates: Cannes, the Bataille season, the
Carlton of all hotels in the world, a huge suite inside it, two rich American
women visiting France, a suave man who knows how to handle himself
anywhere. The entire construct here is beyond the class of most film viewers,
who are principally working-class and middle-class citizens of modernity. The
very rich, like Francie’s mother or the aristocrats she is imitating, don’t go to
see movies like this. The Carlton they know inside and out because that is
where they stay. They know the Riviera altogether, in the 1950s haunt of the
3
For Kelly’s last time onscreen, since while shooting this film she met, fell in love with, and
subsequently married Prince Rainier of Monaco (but a short hop from Cannes).
226 THE FILM CHEAT
jet set and the mega-rich, Juan-les-pins, Antibes with its yacht basin, Cimiez
high above Nice. The chic clothing: Grace Kelly ain’t wearin’ schmatas. The
knowing dialogue. The jewels. The casualness of the seduction, as though it
were part of a repeated routine. Here, as in other depictions of wealth in
movies, we will be known to be watching out of a kind of resentment, a
paining regret that we don’t have the resources these two do.
But in the avidness of the watching, cannot our being lost in space be
cheated in itself? Is there a doorway out of here? If so (and we don’t see
one), where does it lead? How far off, and in what direction, is the lobby
and the hotel’s front door? Does that door face the Mediterranean or away
from it? And so on.
Seeing Francie and Robie occupying this room as they do, we have nothing
but a firm conviction in their belonging here, nor anything but the very
firmest conviction in the fullness, the completeness, and the unquestionability
of this here. Her hand comfortably, possessingly on the wood framing of the
loveseat, his graceful body leaning toward her amicably, the opened French
doors behind them, the sparkling tranquility—all these are made to appear
not so much fabulous, exotic, and exclusive as natural and right and proper.
The designer, J. McMillan “Mac” Johnson, has made certain that his hotel
room set will have just this kind of space, extending on both sides (but to
where?); room for just this kind of furniture as placed by the decorator Hal
Pereira; and a coloration scheme that when lit with color filters will produce
an ineluctable attraction to the eye.
If, by sharp contrast, we examine the design of a film like Alfonso Cuarón’s
Roma (2018) we find a domestic residence that sprawls shapelessly and in
which the camera—the narrative—will be (will have to be) in very constant
motion. The home is filled to overflowing with objects appropriate to the
bourgeoisie, continually speaking a motto, “Wealth, Privilege, Possession,”
but the film is about the characters only, mostly servants, this place and its
design being onscreen only to identify some of them and designate their
social positions. We move from character moment to character moment,
passing through the carefully packed and rather generally lit domain but
never really taking it in as a domain except in the most general way. The same
kind of optical unconcern attaches to other film places designed to show off
wealth, the home-castle in Firewall (2006), the cabin in the woods in Leave
Her to Heaven (1945), the actress’s home in Imitation of Life (1954), the
New York apartment in Rosemary’s Baby (1968: our protagonists live in
The Dakota!), the Minifer residence in The Magnificent Ambersons (1942).
These depictions contain in their design an implicit axiom, that we already
know the kind of life represented here, know it and are eager to see it, so
that in effect it needs only the most general kind of representation, only a
cue. In To Catch a Thief, the design is the film; the place is the action, yet
east and west, north and south are utterly confounded in the image. We can
know the directions, perhaps, but we cannot see them.
32
Walk on the Wild Side
FIGURE 32 Two angles from the restaurant scene of The Man Who Knew Too
Much (Alfred Hitchcock, Paramount, 1956). Cinematography by Robert Burks.
Design by Henry Bumstead.
228 THE FILM CHEAT
The narrative and physical attractiveness of the two stars is plenty of reason
to concentrate on them at any rate, but if we need more reasons we can
count on (a) Day and Stewart holding principal status in the Hollywood
constellation; (b) Stewart’s magical show of stumbling, almost tripping, as
he steps over Day with us looking between his spread legs, as well as his
innocent Midwest, drawled bumbling as he moves; and (c) the magnificent
white and teal dress and matching cape Day is wearing out tonight. We are
concentrating on them, nice tidy shot, and thus taking the setting more or
less for granted once we quickly verify by sweeping inspection that it is the
Moroccan restaurant we have been promised.
Very pleasant. Some slight education about foreign climes. A private
entry to this tight American marriage.
A little time goes by.
Now the McKennas, our new friends, meet another couple who are sitting
back to back with them, the Draytons. Rather than trying to converse by
twisting their backs out of shape, they invite the Draytons to turn around and
take their seats, and they move across the table, now occupying the position
that the camera (that we) occupied previously. Sharing with strangers—the
epitome of hospitality and friendship. The two couples chat amicably.
But . . .
In order to get a better view, to see one couple at screen left, the other at
screen right, all in profile and all cheery as pie, we suddenly move to take
WALK ON THE WILD SIDE 229
up a position where just earlier we saw a tile wall. We become, in fact, that
wall, and from the position of the wall look down the length of the table
to see the McKennas at left and the Draytons at right. Fun to watch them
break the bread, try to eat the roast squab in the tajine. And the Draytons
are as thoroughly British as the McKennas are thoroughly American, so this
is a friendly trans-Atlantic summit.
I here forego all discussion of the content of the discussion and what it
might come to reveal in turning the plot of The Man Who Knew Too Much
(1956), in order to focus on the subtle shift of perspective that has occurred,
already, twice in the scene. In the first instance, the camera traded places
with two characters. In the second, the camera is trading places with the set.
But in both cases we are implicated.
In both cases we are both viewers who can see and viewers who are
blocked from seeing. Early on, watching Ben and Jo, we cannot see where
Ben and Jo are soon to be sitting. Later, watching Ben, Jo, Lucy, and Edward
(“a big noise in agriculture”), we cannot see the restaurant wall that defines
the limit of their space.
As to that wall: when the camera (when we) become the wall (take up
the position where the wall was) we are caught in a conundrum, because
as agents of the film vision we can appreciate the shot composition but
as onlooking believers in the restaurant construction we are momentarily
stymied. Being positioned where we have just seen a tiled wall we are
obliged to occupy its dumb, uncalculating attitude, to be as neutral as it
was. Yet because a vision is offered to us here, by the camera, we must also
occupy the onlooker’s consciousness. Thus, we see (objectively) and we see
(personally, because we know the McKennas) simultaneously and at once, in
a puzzling stance that opens us to a wholly non-rational, wholly equivocal
kind of sight. Four tourists in Morocco; or two people with whom we have
bonded and the strangers they have just met. As to the soft divan: when
the camera (when we) occupied it and got a long shot of the restaurant
stretching past the McKennas, we used our eyes to see the full frame—as
much as the film camera ever allows viewers to see. But then the McKennas
take up our seat and we must “hop” to the wall (the aisle on the far side
being for the waiters to use, not for us).
The view to which we move is produced through a particular design cheat
called the “wild wall.” When a wall in a set is “wild,” it is built so as to be
completely, or partially removable, so that the camera can be placed where
that wall stood. There are other distinctive “wild” shots like these restaurant
shots to be found in Hitchcock, another in the Marrakech hotel room when
Dr. McKenna begins by unpacking clothing from a dresser backed up
against a wall and continues his action as perceived by us from that wall.
The legendary Rope (1948) is substantially dependent on wild walls that
are on rails, able to “swing back,” as Hitchcock said, “And the furniture
was mounted on rollers” (Truffaut 183). When a filmmaker expressly wants
230 THE FILM CHEAT
to work without wild walls, as is the case with Clint Eastwood, the camera
team must figure a way to use squeezed positions and wide-angle lenses to
shoot scenes inside small rooms.1
Another feature of the wild wall is that it claims a double identity. As a
floor-to-ceiling array of decorative tiles, for example, the restaurant wall is
part of the story-scene, an element in a setting declared openly by the story
and one that is shown to “establish a kind of realism,” inspiring the viewer
to think of what she is seeing as a representation of an actual place.2 At the
same time, and in a wholly contradictory way, the array is a pre-designed part
of the production, present to the view at one instant while always prepared
to be removed at another, but removed not only from view: removed also
from story-space and re-placed in production-space. When it is moved the
wild wall is part of the production, invisible to audiences. This wall is thus,
at each moment whether we are seeing it or not, both present and absent,
both a challenge to us and nothing at all. These antinomies make for a very
confounding, not to say disorienting mode of vision, and the secrecy of the
wildness helps audiences slide (wrongly) to the side of believing they are
simply always placed in the ideal position for taking a view.
To be noted: When first we see the tile wall—more accurately, when first
we are exposed to it—it functions casually and entirely unobtrusively as
a highly ornamental part of a highly ornamental interior design, a story
element helping to identify our surround. We do not gaze at it, but we do
recognize it instantly, and it belongs to the world of the story, the Marrakech
world, the exotic. But when, having taken the second camera position, we
think back in realizing that we are positioned where the wall was seen, it
has become something that could be manipulated at will, something to do
not with a story but with a set design. The divan that the McKennas move
over to occupy began for us, an assumed if not quite a presented audience,
as a camera position and became the McKennas’ seat. As in retrospect we
realize that this is where we were positioned to look at the restaurant the
divan becomes, now, a signal of the production of the film.
Why, one might reasonably ask, does the viewer typically not pause to
see this “many-sided” wall, not pause to consider how the story and the
production of the story are intertwined? Because a cheat has been made
to glide over the duplication of tasks. But how could such a cheat have
worked? To answer this we must briefly look at the restaurant as a good
example of Kenneth Burke’s grammar of ratios. Here is a scene in which
1
I am grateful to the late Henry Bumstead for sharing some of Eastwood’s preferences with
me, in 1998.
2
The restaurant, entirely fabricated on a Paramount soundstage, was intended to reproduce
an actual Marrakech restaurant and, secondly, all the tiles were hand crafted by the designer,
Henry Bumstead, after local patterns. More on the film can be found in my The Man Who
Knew Too Much, and the arrangements for the restaurant are described in detail in DeRosa.
WALK ON THE WILD SIDE 231
some vital act takes place. We are thus confronted with a scene: act ratio,
for Burke a declaration that this act is (always already) properly the kind
of act to be observed (set) in a scene like this one; and that this scene
is (always already) properly the kind of place in which one easily and
reasonably finds such an act. A unity of movement and place. But the Burke
scene: act ratio is not even-sided. In a story film, especially a suspense film
like The Man Who Knew Too Much, action must always be set in the right
place but also always take precedence over that place in the perceptual
routine. The place is quickly registered and laid away, so that the behavior
can take the spotlight; indeed, the action becomes dominant in this scene,
and after we register the identity and nature of the restaurant as a space
we dismiss the place from attention. Filmmakers know this pattern. When
he designed the restaurant for Paramount’s Stage 1, Henry Bumstead was
fully aware that he could make a wild wall for Hitchcock, and that if the
wall as an object would at first be enticing yet soon it would recede, taking
its wildness with it.3
Were viewers fixated on cardinal directions and the absolute definition
of diegetic space, they would have to map out that restaurant, and the wild
wall would be impossible as part of that map since features on non-fictional
maps do not toggle between appearance and disappearance. That tiled wall
is only to Ben and Jo’s left (which is nothing but screen right) and then their
right (nothing but screen left); screen right and screen left, not right and left.
And then it vanishes, and then it is nowhere.
3
The restaurant sequence was made June 27, 28, and 29, 1955, the first days at the studio after
a substantial filming voyage to Morocco and London.
33
Happy Trails
FIGURE 33 James Mason (l.), Christopher Olsen, and Barbara Rush in Bigger
Than Life (Nicholas Ray, Twentieth Century Fox, 1956).
So compactly and coherently are filmic action and filmic setting unified,
when the artists at hand are expert, that one thinks of the two as being
not only interrelated but mutually generative in an ongoing way. When, at
the end of Bringing Up Baby (1938), Cary Grant’s David has finally found
his cherished dinosaur bone and is climbing up a scaffolding to place it
in the culminating position on that massive skeleton, the massive skeleton
happens to be there waiting for him, and so does the scaffolding: the latter
looks just flimsy enough to give us the barest hint that it might not be as
sturdy as poor David would like, and the former looks like a catastrophe
waiting for its moment. When, in Six Degrees of Separation (1993) Flan
(Donald Sutherland) wants to impress his guest Geoffrey from South Africa
(Ian McKellen) by taking him aside and showing him a transparency of a
Cézanne he intends to have, the warmly lit study is there for them to be
HAPPY TRAILS 233
alone in, a haven, silent, plushly lit, and the Cézanne transparency, provided
by props, looks perfect when held up to the light in this place: so perfect,
in fact, that when Flan says he plans to have it and turn it around for a
quick sale, anybody who loved Cézanne would be chagrined. When, in The
French Lieutenant’s Woman (1981), the nineteenth-century Dr. Grogan
must be presented in his private study, the study is there for Leo McKern to
walk into, jammed with skeletons, glass cases, weighty tomes, magnifying
glasses, and such like, and all of the furniture looking as though it has been
there forever inside these sanctified walls that, bordered by nicely painted
trim—trim lit by candles—treasure the deepest past. One has the feeling of
the designer and the director confabulating in a corner, the actors fully made
up in role standing by patiently yet with extreme eagerness to inhabit the
scene, though of course the confabulation happened long in advance of the
actors’ presence, possibly before they were even hired.
What could it mean to speak of a unity of action and scene, in film?
Proportion, for one thing. That the space in which characters move seems
to fit them, and they it; trees larger than humans, but not so much larger
that the humans become insects (unless, as with the Vertigo forest, that is
the effect). Rooms appropriate to a social class. Modes of transportation
believable for the characters at the moment, containing within them a
believably sized space. Further, spaces that are “designed” in the diegesis
should fit the character’s apparent taste. All of this is carefully done in such
a way that it is clearly and variably photographable, in short no touches
that cannot show up on camera. And a scene, as well, magnificent enough to
apprehend, so that it captures the viewer’s attention; yet not so magnificent
that it abstracts the attention away from the character at a key moment. A
character can stand at a plate glass window, for example, looking out upon
a splendid lake with mountains and a sunset, but all of the terrain must
recede when we see the side of the gazer’s intentful face.
A collaboration of filmmaker and film designer. But this collaboration is
largely cheated. Audiences are not to detect it. The scene is “naturally” this
way. The character is here, but the here is merely present for the character to
inhabit. Nor the place itself but its face. Not the redwoods as used for Kim
Novak and James Stewart but the way those redwoods are made to look,
since, like a place, a scene is not a space (see Tuan, Space and Place). The
awesomeness of the Vertigo redwood forest is distinctive, even unforgettable;
but it is not the same as the awesomeness of the actual redwood forest, what
Novak and Stewart would actually have experienced in making Madeleine
and Scottie experience the “redwood forest.”
In practice, the director-designer arrangement tends to work this way:
Having carefully read, annotated, and thought about the script, the
designer knows what diegetic “locations” will be needed. Let us take Nicholas
Ray’s Bigger Than Life (1956). (1) An elementary school classroom where
Ed Avery (James Mason), finishing up a day’s teaching with a sweet but slow-
234 THE FILM CHEAT
witted student, prepares to leave; also set here will be a night-time parent-
teacher session later on. (2) The teachers’ lounge in the same school, where
he meets a few colleagues and reminds them about the party at his house
tonight. (3) The Avery house, with a front yard, a back yard grassed over
(in which some action will occur), a living room, a den, a kitchen, a hallway
with a staircase up to the bedrooms, an upper landing. (4) The Averys’
bedroom upstairs. (5) The upstairs bathroom. (6) The taxi depot where Ed is
moonlighting. (7) A medical consultation facility with, among other things,
a fluoroscope. (8) A doctor’s office for discussions. (9) A department store
where Ed can buy his wife an expensive dress she protests she does not need.
(10) A church for a Sunday morning service. (11) A hospital room where
Ed, seriously overdosed with cortisone, lays in agony and finally recovers.
(12) The hospital corridor outside this room. The designer is getting a rough
idea of places, not exact behavioral movement that will occur in them and
how broadly that will be choreographed. He will build every space to be a
choreographable space and the director will use it as he will.
The designer is thinking, which of these are interior spaces and which
exteriors? Translated: how many scenes can be shot on hunted-out real
locations, how many will require sets to be built on soundstages? And
regarding the latter, which soundstages, that is, which studio? The designer
is familiar with all the soundstages at the major studios and many at the
legion minor studios in the Los Angeles area, the New York area, the London
area, the Vancouver area, and so on, and what he doesn’t know he can
fairly easily learn, since the studio will offer up a map with specifications
for each stage: height, length, width, grid structure, whether or not there is
a removable floor, whether there is a pool. Bigger Than Life is a Paramount
production: will the set-building be on-lot at Paramount (5555 Marathon
Street, Los Angeles) and if so, which exact stages will be rentable for the
designer’s use (the designer will have preferences)?1 For each interior “room”
in the diegesis: is it connected to any other space and must passage between
the spaces be possible for the actors or will those movements be handled
through matching edits (in which case the two sets can be miles apart)?
For making exterior shots that include part of the house, how much of the
house will have to be built, and what arrangements made so that this part
matches against interiors built elsewhere?2 How big will the location appear
to be in the story, measured, say, in feet, and how big would the set have to
be so that the camera could give the impression of that diegetic size, using a
1
The floor being removable there to yield an extra ten feet of height, Paramount’s Stage 18 was
ideal for the single set of Rear Window (1954) and later for the sorority house of Jerry Lewis’s
The Ladies Man (1962).
2
In North by Northwest (1959) the memorable Vandamm house (in the Frank Lloyd Wright
style) is a matte painting. The on-set build included the very lowest beams only and a separate
piece for a balcony and a railing. Cary Grant never gets very far off the studio floor here.
HAPPY TRAILS 235
3
MGM’s “Munchkinland” occupied only one corner, about one sixth, of their Stage 27. The
village of Brigadoon took up the whole place.
236 THE FILM CHEAT
for the storytelling and the cinematographer and costumer in terms of colors
and textures. Then calculating the time required in the studio’s carpentry
shop, the materials, the labor for building, the labor for delivery to the stage
and erecting, and also the labor for striking and removing when the shooting
is done. Is it possible that all the scenes of the classroom can be shot at one
time (regardless of cast), so that after a few days that set can come down and
be replaced, on the same stage, with another one?
But now a more delicate, more penetrating problem, once all of the
carpentry cheats have been accomplished, all external locations have been
spotted and legally arranged for (a written contract for each one with
the owner or supervisor of the property). Where will the director put his
camera? What will the camera see and not see of this interesting place? That
is, what has to be made perfect for camera, what can be left undone? (Will
the bedsheets be pulled down?) Sets can theoretically be built only partially,
to work for the scene the camera will frame. (Most Hollywood sets are
built without ceilings, for just one example, but doorways can lead nowhere,
tables have nothing in their drawers, the kitchen cupboards, like Mother
Hubbard’s, be bare.) Some set designers work with meticulous knowledge
of where the camera will be for every shot made on a set they are building
and what will and will not be seen there, the director having thought this
through long in advance and given consultation. In other cases the director
comes onto the set, often alone, and figures out what will be done today,
and how, right in the space itself. On top of all this, if painted backings are
to hang behind portions of the set (viewed through windows or doorways,
for example: an extremely typical tactic, used considerably also in television
and made-for-tv movies), what colors will the scenic painters use for those
backings and what adjustments to the colors on set will be needed—or, for
economy, will preexisting skyscraper or other backings be used? Such things
are available. What film stock will the cinematographer be using and what
will that stock do to shift the colors as finally printed: Technicolor (before
1956), Eastmancolor, Fujicolor, Agfacolor—these all work differently.
Some designers work on the basis of an overriding principle: that they
do not know now, and will never know, what the director will want to see
or what the actors will want to do, so the entire set must be made for show,
including the backs of doors, the area behind furniture, the inside of desk
drawers! Nothing—but nothing—left out. The director has freedom to go
where he will, show what he desires, no limit. The designer knows that he
will not be at the director’s side.
He will not be at the director’s side because he is several days to a week
ahead of the director all through the production, busy planning, making,
and setting up designs that won’t be used until later, by which point he
will have moved on again. The director and actors, the cinematographer,
the support crew will arrive for work early one morning and find the story
HAPPY TRAILS 237
world they need ready and waiting for them to inhabit. It will be built to
work, and they will work it.
So effectively will the designed world seem to have been arranged, so
considerately designed, so artfully crafted, so tastefully surfaced and
textured and painted, and so easily will the characters move about there as
we watch, that the thing seems nothing less than real, and real, too, seems the
characters’ involvement with the place. In The Courtship of Eddie’s Father
(1962), a kitchen with paneled cabinets filled with tea cups and food items.
In The Manchurian Candidate (1962) and E.T. (1982), a kitchen equipped
with a modern refrigerator that will teem with food and drink when the
door is dramatically opened. It is certainly part of the actor’s talent to give
the impression of comfort and ease in a place never known until now, and
she will walk around and rehearse if necessary in order to “learn” the place;
but unless the place is designed to offer comfort first, the actor cannot do
the work.
North by Northwest is an excellent example of set cheats, because
Robert Boyle, the designer, had a keen eye for realistic detail and because he
intimately knew Hitchcock’s framing. The lobby of Roger’s office building
on Madison Avenue, a built set. The Oak Bar of the Plaza Hotel, a built set.
The Townsend mansion interior, a built set. The Plaza Hotel’s room 796, a
built set. The lobby and delegates’ lounge of the United Nations, built sets.
The dining car of the 20th Century Limited, a built set. Eve’s sleeper, a built
set. Parts of the cornfield recreated on the rear-projection stage. The Shaw
& Oppenheim auction house, a built set. The interior of Midway Airport, a
built set. Portions of the Mt. Rushmore monument, a built set. The interior
and close-up exterior of the Vandamm residence, a built set. The viewing
platform and visitors’ center of the Mt. Rushmore monument, built sets.
Roger’s hospital room, a built set.
The cheating designer, hard at work building what will seem a real place
of one kind when in truth it is a real place of another, must have fidelity, and
show that there is fidelity, in two matters:
First, making the specially built nature of the set disappear behind utter
conventionality of design, so that instead of looking like a design the set
looks like an actual place: in short, faking style. In Billy Wilder’s Sabrina
(1954) we are treated to an executive boardroom with attached kitchenette
and high windows looking out at the Hudson River. Hal Pereira and Walter
Tyler give us a mammoth polished table (ideal for William Holden to
go sliding on after Humphrey Bogart lands him one on the kisser). The
kitchenette is used briefly, but not centrally in frame. The window plays
urgently, but we never get a good enough look outside to determine the
fakery of the painted backing that hangs there. The whole place is dressed
“expensive,” as it belongs to a corporation run by a fabulously wealthy
family and they apparently spare no expense: viewers have likely never been
238 THE FILM CHEAT
in such a place and so if it is large enough to hold the action, the engaging
action by major movie stars who take our eye, it will be fine.
Secondly, the designer is completely covering up the fact of the faking, a
matter of key importance, just as actors cover up the fact of the acting. The
picture in all its aspects seems to flow off the screen in a golden aura of not
just authenticity but spontaneous authenticity. Albeit there are times when a
film set looks somewhat like a film set, because it has been designed to look
precisely that way: one will find this frequently in the Hollywood musical,
where ongoingly the set supports the action and the action is more oneiric
than practical.
34
The Thing
It may well be that the fighting forest in Baum’s The Wonderful Wizard of Oz
(1900) gave inspiration to Walt Disney for his 1932 animated film Flowers
and Trees, but it certainly led to the forest sequence in MGM’s 1939
film. The inanimate (or imperceivably animate) becomes—surprisingly—
animate. The trees sprout mouths and make language of a kind, using
their branches as arms to encircle our friendly quartet. Here is a primary
example—though, given Lang’s Metropolis (1927), not the first example—
of the object becoming characterological. Think of The Mummy (1932)
rising from the dead, the dinosaur bone at war with the terrier in Bringing
Up Baby (1938), the controlling, perhaps malevolent power of the “dingus”
in The Maltese Falcon (1941), the unholy power of the box in Kiss Me
Deadly (1955), the living playroom in Tom Thumb (1958), the mobilizing
force of the slab, a font of intelligence, in 2001: A Space Odyssey (1968),
the creature disguising itself as conduits and storage space in Alien (1979),
240 THE FILM CHEAT
the talking stone wall in The Princess Bride (1987). I avoid mentioning the
numerous occasions in the Harry Potter saga when some thing behaves as
though it is an embodied consciousness, a significant object upon which
canniness, motivational design, and purpose have been inscribed. The thing
made “flesh.”
Less disturbing somehow but equally products of the systematic animation
of matter are robots, advanced computers, and alien tools: HAL in Space
Odyssey, Robbie the Robot in Forbidden Planet (1956), Gort in The Day
the Earth Stood Still (1951), the velocitor in This Island Earth (1955), R2-
D2 and C-3PO, bless them. A smartness, a power, and a plan that gain
dramatic potency by apparently superseding what human agents can do.
Achieving the hybrid characteristics of these creature-devices, these
device-creatures, requires a design cheat. The object in question must
be made to look on first examination like a product of human or alien
engineering, and this examination, as choreographed in the flow of narrative
cinema, is not likely to be slow and patient. A surface of metal, usually
polished (a signal that atmospheres will offer no resistance). Controls, often
illuminated (the power room of the Krell in Planet is a spectacular array
of lights). Mechanical (rhythmic, unstoppable) agencies: arms, grapplers,
magnets, emitted rays, moving parts (Robbie the Robot being quite hilarious
because of the contradictory direction in which some of his parts move
simultaneously—a sign of delightful confusion). Essential is that the Thing
be conveyed as fully and swiftly as possible in the form of the inhuman,
a being that was born of no mother—this orphanage, so to speak, being
the root of the affecting pathos in the finale of 2001 when HAL sings his
“kindergarten” song and introduces his “parents.” No human birth, at least
not a normal one, yet also nothing spiritual in the sense that we accord in
legends of Jesus, also not born of mother in a normal way. This inhuman
birth makes for a coldness and inhospitability, a calculation, a mathematical
soul. The thing as machine, then. The machine as un-alive.
But also the Thing as touchingly animate. A discernable personality, a
spirit of good or evil to mobilize action, a ferocity or gentleness that sensitive
human characters find affecting. Also, a diligent capability that trumps
human skill: objects can be hurled at greater speed and frequency, chemistry
can be converted, sinews can be manipulated, a ringing metallic voice can
issue commands impossible not to follow. To get at this we must see some
simulacrum of the dominating face, or an arrangement that we can willingly
and pleasurably choose to interpret as a face. By presenting the mechanical
surface first, and in some telling detail, the photography allows for the
animated qualities—the suddenly appearing control surfaces—to be seen in
light of mechanism, thus, not life per se but a machine that seems “alive,” as
well as seeming to seem. Yet also consider the formula exercised in reverse,
something first seen in light of the fully human, a person who turns out—
that turns out—to be a machine. Consider the death of the science officer
THE THING 241
Ash (Ian Holm) in Alien, as, his head struck off by a fierce blow he continues
to flail, finally making it clear that he was, all along, (only) robotic. This is
a human become mechanical, a degradation. The machine become human,
like the animal become human(oid) (Caesar in War for the Planet of the
Apes [2017], who, as we all know, is mo-capped by Andy Serkis), is climbing
the “ladder,” doing what evolutionary theory tells us we all did a long, long
time ago. Doing what we did, the Thing becomes like us, conspecific in a
way, recognizable. “This thing of darkness I/acknowledge mine.”
The animate mechanism as graphic subject runs the risk of bringing
laughter or dismissal. Robbie the Robot works powerfully because, although
his plexi head allows us to see desperately whirring mechanisms (puppy
learning new tricks) he is still a major player in more than one scene of
violent aggression where he shows amazing brute force. But the animus,
the spirit of what had been a stationary, immobile thing is tricky because
it can seem to come out of nowhere, which means, of course, out of some
designer’s toolbox off-camera. If sympathetic characters fall under machine
power and are threatened there; or if they accept benevolent but “living”
machines as friendly forces, we can be persuaded to take the things very
seriously indeed: this happens over and over, both for good and for trouble,
in Jurassic Park (1993) and its sequels. It is a recurring trope in war films
where an endangered flyer seizes the controls of a damaged aircraft and
saves the day (this apotheosized by Luke in the starfighter at the climax of
Star Wars [1977]).
What considerations come into play when mechanism or solid objectivity
comes “alive” believably onscreen?
●● In effect, the now living thing will become a character, like all other
characters in a fictional zone. One danger is that, only because of
its physicality, it might come to seem much more interesting than
human characters, more compelling even than the stars of the film.
The viewer is therefore, quite intentionally, given limited access to
this Thing, and access only at dramatic points when the involvement
of the creature is central to the story either as action continuity or as
comic relief. The Thing is given an introductory scene of its own, so
to speak, but then relegated to secondary status. Even in conflictual
conclusion sequences, where a heroic human must battle the Thing,
the human gets more camera time, which means that the shots of the
Thing must be very carefully calculated to be specially informative.
Arnold Schwarzenegger concluding his battle with the alien in the
finale of Predator (1987).
●● But what we will be encouraged to forget or dismiss as irrelevant
is this: that before it was characterized, the Thing was part of the
setting, a kind of mass ornament, mass in the sense adduced by
Kracauer describing telltale cultural formations (as he writes, of
242 THE FILM CHEAT
Weimar culture) that arise but not from the people and are without
a “current of organic life.” There is in the character-object a kind of
“linearity”:
FIGURE 35 Anne Bancroft and Dustin Hoffman in The Graduate (Mike Nichols,
Lawrence Turman/Embassy, 1967).
[2] Another argument is that nobody takes any of these direct intimate
scenes, as they are portrayed on film, the least bit seriously in the terms
they offer. We recognize that we are being given only passing nibbles,
leading us to a sensible moral resolution in which the good will end well,
the bad unwell, and the world will remain intact. We must witness a very
dirty moment indeed so that the hero can be in a position to appear heroic
by making things clean. This is essentially a dramaturgical argument: the
violence is structurally necessary as a set-up for the sanctified retribution.
Sanctification, order, permanence—these are the principal targets, not
characters, feelings, or storylines. And not hidden drives or pathologies.
[3] A third argument, very popular in the second decade of the twenty-
first century, is that sex, violence, hard language, wounding, death, and
rampant crime are quotidian attributes of the world in which we live.1 The
world has become this way, wake up and try to smell the artificial roses.
Back in the 1920s and 1930s and 1940s the world was an entirely different
kind of place (say viewers too young to have been there). The film is merely
reaching for realism in the spirit of not hoodwinking its audience, telling
a truth, revealing the everyday to us in a light that will help us see it more
clearly. Call this the pedagogical argument. Without scenes of hardness and
cruelty, without dark penetrations, a film would be only juvenile fluff, indeed
hype. Fluff, I should add, as abounds, these critics claim, in purportedly
discardable Hollywood films of the 1920s, 1930s, 1940s, and 1950s. Fluffy,
nonsensical, unreal.
Unreal city,
Under the brown fog of a winter dawn,
A crowd flowed over London Bridge, so many,
I had not thought death had undone so many.
(T. S. Eliot, “The Waste Land”)
These three arguments about the depiction of the secret, the blistering, the
agonizing, the violent, and the private onscreen can all be countered, and
without making roundabout voyages.
• The educational argument [3]: First, the world in which we live actually
doesn’t look as things do onscreen, not at all. The participants are far less
ably choreographed in everyday life and far less distinctive to look at, since
unlike screen performers, who must labor to be where they are, the folks
we see on the street haven’t worked with a choreographer and haven’t
1
A world, Bertrand Russell told Romney Wheeler in 1952, in which (already) it was very
difficult for an old man (he was approaching 80) to live. He said, too, that he thought no one
who was born after 1914 could possibly understand what it had been for him to grow up (in
the late nineteenth century).
248 THE FILM CHEAT
sat in the make-up chair. Further, everyday action is subtler in most cases,
harder to grasp quickly and easily (as we must be led to do by the cheats of
the camera). Action is subtler, more unresolved, often unresolvable, often
unclear, but onscreen each instant must have clarity, even the instant of
narcotized unclarity. Another way to put this: the viewer must never be lost
at the point of the punch line. But then the punch line and what cacophonies
lead up to it are not so very much like our lives. The images of life given on
the daily news are constructed to appeal the way film images do, directly,
bluntly, in high contrast. Life is not life dramatized.
• The dramaturgical argument [2]: Taken alone, this is not off-center
but is finally too simple. Film stories don’t follow a single roadmap, nor is
the screen giving over only a story. A film can be structured in many ways,
including a hypermoral situation leading to a criminal one, not the other
way round. Nor, in cases of holy retribution, is our nobly vengeful hero
ever shown to experience serious pleasure, release, or moral contentment
for having erased the dirt. That the hero would redeem a sacred world in
eliminating evil—that the dirty evil is placed in the film to permit this—is an
assumption that makes for a difficult reading of, say, The Godfather (1972),
or even, examined closely, The Wizard of Oz (1939).
• The psychoanalytical argument [1]: The proposition that we gawk only
or principally because we deeply want to see what we “should not” has a
deep (yet untestable) logic, but those who support it make the mistake of
taking representational realism as a given, the dirty image onscreen as a
double for some dirty display in the everyday. Their case always rests on the
idea that outside the theater, just as inside, violence and darkness are what
we secretly wish to look at, that going to the movies only heightens, polishes,
and extends the action in which we are already always engaged. But the
screen image isn’t quite a window on things, and the relentlessness in the
presentation of screen violence belies a social world in which many kinds of
activity take place, not all of them enticing our secret desires. If scopophilia
is engendered very deeply in the human condition, this insatiable craning of
the spirit toward sight, it is hardly directed only at the taboo, only at the
prurient, only at the shameful, and is therefore hardly always problematic.
The hunger for vision applies to even the most casual and peremptory
seeings, the ornamental lights in the lobby of the movie theater, the screen
depictions of grass growing. Yearning to see is not elementally bound to the
urge to discover what has been held back.
What if we acknowledge that as settings for film stories, violence and
sex are fake, and palpably so? Either viewers in the know see the open
duplicities, or ignorant viewers realize that what they see is part of a film.
No one watching a murder onscreen, for instance, believes (a) that a real
murder took place before the camera and therefore that (b) they are, by
watching, accomplices. No one watching what is purported to be sexual
intercourse feels moral qualms, thinking that what’s onscreen is reality, since
HEIST 249
the framing, the timing, the rhythm, the musical treatment, the lighting, and
the specific viewing angles are far too contrived. What if instead of claiming
to be hoodwinked by the fake, taken in, robbed of the real by illusion, we
confess that we know all along we are getting paste? More: getting a paste
is what we adore. Then:
Secondly, what if part of the appealing fakery, as we see and appreciate
it, is the very sophistication of its production, the sheen, the high-resolution
frame captures, the gorgeous lighting? What if we come to believe we are
seeing not merely a fake but a fake of the highest quality, the kind expressly
designed to deceive hapless others who do not have the perceptual acumen
that we do? It is a deception, but for them. We are not deceived because we
would not fear deception. In this way we become virtual appraisers of art,
priests who offer (or hesitate to offer) authentication. Knowing the screen
image is fake, but also recognizing it is such a magnificent fake we have no
compunction admitting to being pleasured seeing it, we become cognoscenti,
true connoisseurs of the new visual high cuisine. Yet this is cynical. It is
possible that in accepting the cheat for what it is we are making a profound
acknowledgment, coming to a fuller appreciation of the cinematic process.
A third term in the equation. We not only know fakery when we see it,
and have learned to appreciate first-class fakery, but then, growing into film
watching by way of screenings and discussions online and offline we come
into the desire to catch the best fakes possible, like getting the best pizza in
town, snagging the put-up shows that come closest to what we call “the real”
without actually going all the way. We are not only connoisseurs; we are like
art thieves whose great pleasure it is to nab from the grandest museum, in the
thick of night and amid confounding truckloads of buffoonish police, some
utterly refined sculpture that is the museum’s great treasure, worth a fortune
but also—and only we have the advantage of knowing this—a complete and
utter fake, made originally as such and placed on the pedestal to replace an
actual treasure so priceless no one is given access to it. This action is spelled
out through the mythology of “the story” in William Wyler’s How to Steal a
Million (1966), but the assumptions behind it, the way it mirrors a possible
general attitude, is left unexplored there.
What if cinema has made all of us appraisers, specialists with an eye for
fakes and especially brilliant fakes? Or if not an eye, a heart?
If the cheat is a theft of credulity, a kind of heist, rather than clinging
to “the authentic,” whatever that is, we can admire the cheat; become
aficionados of all those delicious heist movies with an adorable crew—not
only George Clooney but George Clooney and Brad Pitt; not only them but
also Matt Damon; and also and also—aiming for the gargantuan gleaming
emerald, the last painting of the great French Impressionist Henri-Charles du
Parc de la Vallée, the contents of the casino vault, the storehold of the Bank
of England, the night’s take in Las Vegas’s five biggest casinos all at once (as
in the original Ocean’s 11 [1960]). In fact, we can come to see, by way of
250 THE FILM CHEAT
admiration for the skill involved in cheats, that all movies are heist movies.
And that authentic treasure, that treasure that was authenticity, stored by so
many viewers diligently in the secret vault inside the vault inside the vault,
has no ultimate value at all.
The cheater’s greatest challenge: images that only look as though they are
only trying to look real.
36
The Reality Effect
doubt or wonder, that originates beyond mankind and has affected Cavell
and me (two students, at different times, of the same teacher)—is this: not
“What is reality?” but “What is it that motivates, urges, presses us to consider
certain qualities and experiences ‘real,’ in the first place?” James wanted to
know under what conditions we call things “real.” I want to know, with
Cavell, what moves us to do so, conditions notwithstanding. For James, we
do not consider something real because it is real before we consider it. What
it is, is indeterminate, and we sometimes use the word “real.” If the name
sticks (if many others use the name this way) a thing becomes real, at least
to those who speak about it, and the world that subtends it becomes reality.
Names stick when they are applied by the forceful, the deeply respected, the
dominant agencies of power.
But why do we find it necessary or helpful to use the word “real,”
especially when we think of film? Surely the candy can be sweet, the poison
bitter, no matter how real. “Everyone,” writes James, “knows the difference
between imagining a thing and believing in its existence, between supposing
a proposition and acquiescing to its truth” (283). What is the profound
ontological pleasure that flows our way when we aver that something we
see onscreen bears a striking resemblance to, copies, faithfully represents
“reality”? It is to be presumed that when we see something unworthy of
this claim—take as a good example Mickey Rooney cavorting in the spangly
ferns as Puck in Max Reinhardt’s A Midsummer Night’s Dream (1935)—at
least the sane among us would grasp that it is not to be called “real” and
that the world of the film is not to be believed as “reality,” yet does such a
categorical denial actually describe, arrange, clarify matters in some vital
way? Our seeing “reality” in movies is not as simple as film reconfiguring
onscreen, to some marked degree of exactitude, what we have already
configured somewhere else in the eye, both because much of film is not for
the eye alone and because only using a 50 mm lens makes it easy to roughly
approximate the form of normal ocular experience. To pin everything of
film to our prior experience is to take ourselves more seriously than the
films we watch and also to not carefully watch those films. Further, finding
“reality” in experience would seem to privilege the experience of the finder,
if it is indeed worthwhile to make such a call; and once the privileging is
in place, once we find reality on the front lawn, claiming the existence of a
replicating agency, film, is wholly unnecessary. In Bob Rafelson’s Five Easy
Pieces (1970), we can see Jack Nicholson’s “smartness and sarcasm” at a
diner table when the waitress won’t bring him whole wheat toast, but as I
have sat at such a table and had trouble getting whole wheat toast myself,
the “reality” of his experiencing the problem is not value-added for me, does
not elevate what I see by likening it to my own experience. And surely my
experience is my experience whether we call it “real” or not.
What I have called “the reality effect” sums to our accepting and labeling
depictions as “real,” as well as our fierce penchant for doing so, with all
THE REALITY EFFECT 253
the circumstance that flows after. “Reality” is a hot topic. There are legion
films now where some character’s “sense of reality” is seriously challenged
(he suddenly awakes to find that he is not where he thought he was, and
so on), sometimes by means of mechanical arrangements that are arcane
and indescribably complex, yet always the resolution of the riddle is the
“ground” of the everyday, always he finds where to put his feet in a world
that is called “real,” and furthermore, usually at the point when he finds this
“sacred” ground, the story is over. Why need that ground be “real” in order
for it to be resolving or culminating or apotheotic? Why the apparent need
for a double tag, “real ground,” when one might think “ground” would be
sufficient in itself? Why does a place need to be real if it is to be somewhere
that, when a person can neither remember nor find it he searches through
legion difficulties, and finally, with a glow, “really” discovers again? That is
a serious question, but it misrepresents the query I pursue. That question
stands upon the presumption that something can be—is—real, that such
a condition as reality exists, and asks why the label tagging it should be
applied in a present instance. I am not interested here in whether reality
exists or not. I want to know why we wish to use the word (as though it
does) and what the outcomes are.
I am not meaning here to follow strictly in William James’s steps and
ask of the attributes of the “real,” the features of an object or situation that
would lead us to place it in the category of the “real,” which category we
already believe in, fundamentally. I mean instead to ask how it serves to
believe in such a category enough that we will speak of it. How by virtue
of belonging to the “real” an experience gains elevation and importance it
apparently did not have to begin with, quite as though experience is not
enough. What I am calling the “reality effect,” then, is not an attribute of
things or happenings that leads us a certain way, but a condition of our own
experience, a kind of addiction to a form.
Do we believe, as Cavell has suggested, that we have a wish to be
present—not only present, I might add, but authorial!—at Creation?
Cavell’s Cartesianism: when we are present at Creation, we believe in it
fully, we acquiesce to its truth, because, like Descartes (and Cavell would
agree, I think) we do not think a Great Deceiver has constructed a Great
Deception in order to waylay us. James was meticulously describing a
kind of “mechanism of realization,” the operative psychological gearing,
whereas Cavell seeks the spirit within, our reaching toward occasions we
can understand as real. We can note that at least in popular discourse to
see a filmic moment as real brings a special treat: not only, perhaps, that a
moment of creation is before us and we are, as Cavell suggests, present but
that this present moment is made special by being thought, not creation
alone but, “real” creation, so finely danced, so sumptuous, so radiant.
(For instance, the “real Creation” at which we might be “present,” a
purity of purities, would not be a movie set.)
254 THE FILM CHEAT
(Once again, every single one of these elements is worked at least partly
through a cheat.)
The moment brings a certain satisfaction, a certain doubt, an eagerness
to keep watching, a keen attention to the setting, a matter-of-fact acceptance
of the maneuvers made upon the car’s steerage. “Yes,” we can say with
enthusiasm, “a car scene!”
THE REALITY EFFECT 255
Yes, a car scene. Yes, a conversation in a car. Yes, two people conversing.
Yes, the car moving forward. Yes, the sun setting. Yes, the steering wheel
controlling the car.
We can see, approve, even find some delight in this. Certainly the humdrum
normalities of car driving do not surprise or engage us in themselves, not the
way they did the very first time we were taken somewhere in a car.
But given the scene in Detour, so fulsome, so present, so detailed, so
engaging, so exciting, so mysterious . . . then . . . then . . . why do we take
one step further and claim it all looks “real,” and then, thinking through
the manner in which it has been made to look this way, think to ourselves,
“It was the cheats that made for the look of ‘reality.’” The word “reality”
couched in such a shroud of sanctity the word “cheat” now looks abysmal.
Why does the cheat achieve “reality” rather than a pleasurable delusion?
Pleasurable—more pleasurable, considerably more, than would be possible
without the cheat. Thanks to the cheat, this is gorgeously fake. The driver, let
us say: he sits woodenly at the wheel doing nothing and saying nothing. We
get it, he’s there, we’re there with him. But somehow if he turns the wheel a
little, stares through the windshield, talks to the passenger, we like it more.
Do we (have to) like it more because now it seems real?
Do we not trust our liking, in and of itself?
Consider the driver’s action here—I hope it is clear that each element
of this exemplary picture could be examined this way. The driver’s action
brings delight, and we could examine the mechanism of that transaction,
his movements, our experience. The moving body portends a future, we are
more easily wrapped into an event when we think it is going somewhere. If
the hand moves the wheel the driver is gesturing: presence, thought, reaction,
sensation, even desire. Seeing this movement we see ourselves. We have come
to the birth, the creation of the gestures, the moment of their inspiration
(and then perhaps the moment of our own inspiration, too). The humanness
and the impending futurity the performer suggests by “acting like a driver”
bring a peculiar thrill of recognition, a release of doubt, a quickening of the
breath. Let us go so far, even, as to suggest we might come to feel fear, chills
up the spine, desire for union, eagerness to find a coffee shop, anything at
all. Feeling, emotion, commitment, and delight. In a package.
In a unified package.
But how does it add to think of that package as “reality”? Everything
we see of the driver is what it is, surely, yet by invoking some “domain of
the real” and positioning our current experience there, do we add a layer
of identification, a bringing the driver into our presence and a bringing of
our presence toward the driver? Even if we know we are watching cheats
artfully applied, still we are brought to yet another, higher-order “reality,”
the truth behind the false image, and like other “realities” this truthful one is
worth a visit. How and why? For whether we name this place of residence,
256 THE FILM CHEAT
where the image shines and we are shined upon, “reality” or “unreality,” the
same cheats brought us there. We could call it art.
Once we have raised up the “reality” tent, regardless of how deliriously
colored its stripes, the guy lines assume command: proper dispensation of
resources, of living beings, of space, of time. Inventive transformations—
dirt roads into railways. Proper enunciation of principles, reasons for living,
pathways to success, what to hope for After. Another tent will go up nearby,
to be sure, and soon enough we will have struggles of “reality” facing off
against “reality,” struggles followed by skirmishes, skirmishes followed
by wars, all in the name of whose “reality” should be officialized as truth.
Breakdowns in the method for examining reality: chemical reality, historical
reality, dramatic reality, political reality, psychological reality, biological
reality. And we have indices and representations, which by our compulsion
to adhere to the structures of “reality” use “proper” proportions, in order
to acknowledge instead of expressing. Hence the weight of (“unreal”)
caricature to dismember elites and forms and institutions that could be
called pernicious. And the desire for a glowingly “true” and “real”—as we
take it—vision of the way things are.
Reality gets in the way of experience, however. Cheats could be understood
as leading not to something pretending to the real but to something avowing
the beautiful:
FIGURE 37 Barbra Streisand with chorus in Funny Girl (William Wyler, Columbia,
1968).
but she is also not the person Fanny Brice who is being mocked up by that
character. Of course neither was Fanny Brice, the performing phenomenon,
this or any character or person, as Fanny Brice, because historically she was
a woman named Fania Borach. “Fanny Brice” was a product she sold, a
substitution with which she came to identify.
In substituting one shooting location for another, filmmakers need only
take care to ensure that any specific reputation attaching to the substitute
does not read over into the drama, or a quality of the actual place leak
through the curtain of the substitution. Caution will be exercised in
proximity to recognizable landmarks, lest they creep into the shot. Or, by
contrast, caution will be exercised to include the landmark if it can help
seal the identification of a location that is actually disconnected from it
(against the dictate of the fiction). In Rebel Without a Cause (1955), for
one example, the concluding sequence calls for the three protagonists to
assemble at night at a huge mansion adjacent Griffith Park and within short
running distance from the observatory. But the sequence was shot at the
Getty Mansion at 6th and South Irving, quite a long way off and with no
particular view of the observatory at all. But thanks to careful framing and
careful editing the diegetic connection can be made. The edit as a geographic
join is all over cinema.
When the viewer experiences an accomplished substitution—one place
for another; one person for another—the principal effect is an unrecognized
but calculated misdirection. One could gain considerable insight here from
a viewing of Orson Welles’s F for Fake (1973). The ersatz is exchanged as
the authentic, a situation considered seriously problematic in the economy
of material acquisition (the art world) but somehow not only permissible
but entirely regular in the economy of fictional transaction (the world of
film). In watching film, we never really expect the goods on offer to be what
they claim to be, indeed the irony produced by the gap between what they
seem and what they are (what they are identified as elsewhere, by those in
the know) is a major source of our thrill. We relish fabrication, knowing all
along that it is fabrication but being held away from a view of the technique
in the wings. “I am fooling you,” is a trumpet call we love to hear, but “Let
me show you how I’m doing it” is a threat of ruin.
An elementary question: How is it that we can entertain such pleasure at
the patently inauthentic? What is the relationship between our consciousness
of inauthenticity and our devotion to the presence of the moment?
The conception of a visual narrative is a process different from its
reception and appreciation, in that a different scale of values is invoked and
a different mode of consciousness implied. The material effect being worked
through in both production and viewing is the same effect: a showing of
the crowd of the everyday, the myriad minute articulations that are life
itself (as “conceived” by the characters) at the same time as they are the
substance of rational cataloging (for those seeing the surface). In the act of
260 THE FILM CHEAT
1
The ease of recognition is profitable, and the ease of replication is cost saving, two principal
effects of genre filmmaking in the 1930s and onward. See Schatz.
2
As used here, the terms “specificity” and “diffuseness” are borrowed from Parsons.
STAND-INS 261
The actor must do the same. By virtue of infusing generalized thoughts about
a character’s type with his own spirit of temporal presence, his pulse of
sensitivity, a spirit he always carries about, the actor jettisons the technical
categorization scheme out of which he began to fashion the character and
now by both reaching and relaxing brings the character to life. That is,
“life”: fleeting sensibility with all its foibles and snorts.
We are enthused by performance because of this liveliness, exactly. We
accept our knowledge of its categorical construction, but then eclipse that
knowledge by touching the manifest expressiveness of a being who is tasting
time.
38
The Superuniverse
FIGURE 38 Christian Bale in The Dark Knight Rises (Christopher Nolan, Warner
Bros., 2012).
1
Reflecting on the casting process for Six Degrees of Separation (Vivian Beaumont Theatre,
November 8, 1990) John Guare wrote, “We used that time of casting to discuss the play, to
understand the rhythm of the play, to hear what the play wanted to be. All I knew about the
play was that it had to go like the wind” (xi).
264 THE FILM CHEAT
{39} Believe in Me
King Kong (1933); King Kong (1976); The Seven Year Itch
{41} Sequitur
Edit as cheat; spatial/temporal transitions and continuous or discontinuous
movement; Hitchcock and Kuleshov; the cheat of causation; Rear Window
{46} By Contrast
Complexity and simplification; The November Man; resolving moral
muddles; resolving resilience muddles; Shane; Body of Lies
* * *
268 THE FILM CHEAT
1
A July 2019 conversation with Kat Zabecka prompted this meditation on Kong.
270 THE FILM CHEAT
As this creature gazes down at her she is a Lilliputian daydream, save that,
being no Swift reader, he has no education to help him recognize Lilliput
or to imagine whether instead he might be in Brobdingnag. She is both
small and quaint and delicate, let us say a kind of doll, yet alive. (As with
George Lucas having his Princess Leia emerge from R2-D2’s projection,
a holographic miniature, this is something of an homage to the projected
Altaira in Forbidden Planet [1956].) Dwan excites Kong’s curiosity, even, if
it would not be too bold to imagine this, his quasi-scientific curiosity—and
why not fully scientific curiosity—because he concentrates on her frame,
her movement, her coloration, her size as though she is a specimen he has
recovered. With the other hand he stretches out an index finger to feel her
butterfly surface. The fiction of the tale (here and in the earlier King Kong
[1933]) is that capitalistic adventurers have journeyed to the hidden, remote
island where Kong lives in order to follow hints of a mysterious Other; but
here it is evident Kong himself is journeying to follow at least the smell of
his own mysterious Other, that he is as bent on discovery as his pursuers are.
He teases her by bringing her close enough to a waterfall to get soaked. To
him Dwan is ineffable.
Are we to suspect, as pop theorizing insists, that he is harboring a
throbbing sexual motive? The wild beast and the tender maiden, the
nouveau dragon and the princess? He would have to come down in size,
an unthinkable challenge not only because of his nature but also because
the story of strange monumentalism would collapse if he did. It can only
be a fascination that leads to Pure Love, the love that brings adoration and
surpasses the flesh, a sanctified dream. She has become his beckoning spirit,
although it is clear enough that from her point of view beckoning is quite
out of the question.
Now, a coup de grâce. The ape exhales, and his warm breath shudders
downward and flutters her clothing so that we have a brief echo of Marilyn
Monroe (another blonde) in The Seven Year Itch (1955). Monroe is on a subway
grating, Lange is on a leathery palm; for Monroe the air comes from below, a
subversive tickle, while for Lange it drops from above, something of weather. The
breath, the flutter, the contact, the deep and unforgettable knowledge.
How on earth did they persuade Jessica Lange to stand in the palm of a
giant ape this way? Without visible fear, with only hesitation. How did they
find an ape, indeed, whose hand was so large—the palm alone about six feet
long or more? Where could such a creature be found? (We might remember
with ironized pleasure that the hunters in Kong are seeking to make a movie,
too; so the thought of our own movie-makers seeking an exoticism for their
camera to eat is not such a strange thought.2) The answer, of course, and in
a word: cheats.
2
The eager, hungry camera is taken to exciting extremes in Pirandello.
BELIEVE IN ME 271
This is not Kong’s palm. (An incredible statement, because this is Kong,
always forever, and here we have his palm.) It is not any kind of palm,
medically speaking. It is a large plastic and fabric device with an internal
system of hydraulic tubes all powered from without, puppeted. The fingers
twitch on command. As she stands there, she is in a set, not a hand. The
wrist, the forearm extending upward are parts of the mechanism. There is
actually no Kong face exhaling Kong breath. A fan flicked on and off will do
the trick, Lange will competently fill in with the appropriate response. Today
a realistic palm would be created digitally, and the Lange image matted onto
it. In 1976 such a process was as yet unperfected and the mechanical palm
was a crest-of-the-wave effects form. A special-effects hand, at any rate,
masquerading as a living one. Not so very hard to do, assuming the audience
is unfamiliar with giant apes and their hands.
The potential trouble with such a cheat lies in a bent for denial
confronting any viewer’s deep conviction and belief in the story—the
willingness to believe is part of the lure that brings viewers to the theater—a
denial insistently affirming that in our world, the world pictured onscreen,
there are no giant apes and Kong is nothing but a fabrication for narrative
purposes. This hand we see cannot possibly be a real ape’s hand. Yet at the
same time the viewer takes the position, easily and without consideration,
that the girl is a real girl, youthful, vivacious, hungry, radiant. Thus a reality
and an unreality are combined for view, the oil not quite mixing with the
water. A jarring dysjunction keeps separating the female figure from the
mechanical support. She is effectively jolted into hyperperception with every
tiny indication falsely imported to the hand: the line of the hand embedded
in the leathery “skin,” the thing’s magnitude and its radical disproportion,
even the caution with which the fingers move in a kind of robotic learning
curve. How to overcome these subtle yet not so subtle challenges?
The shot will not be long enough to permit objections to mature into
arguments. Here, on the page, they can mature a little, but the shot doesn’t
even last as long as it took you to read these two sentences. Also, Lange’s
clothing will be designed not only to feature her admirable body but also to
appropriately cover it, to offer rags that seem, in their weird way, fashionable
upon her at this instant, and also teasing, both a revelation and a secrecy. She
will become, for only the spate of Kong’s breath, a fashion model, a figure
who arrests the eye and brings focus.3 Next, the “breath” fluttering that
garment will seem to touch her skin, too, a thrilling glaze, and any reaction
to this on the viewer’s part will take attention away from doubt. The same
can be said for the marvel of the disproportion as it fully hits, since in all
of the interaction between Dwan and the ape we have never yet seen a
measurable comparison like this. And then a factor that effects artists can
3
Not strangely. In the early 1970s, Jessica Lange was a fashion model in New York.
272 THE FILM CHEAT
always knowingly count upon, that a voice inside the viewer beckons her
to go along with the story development no matter what, to move forward,
to push aside any looming obstacles to such motion, else the pleasure of the
entertainment will be hopelessly lost. Believe in Kong. Otherwise the dark
tunnel of doubt that leads to the depressing daylit realization that one was
a fool buying a ticket to be here. One can see easily that with the advent
of widespread and intensified exhibition outside of theaters, on a basis that
does not call for quid-pro-quo payment film by film, the problem of belief
and denial is exacerbated, and effects must be hyped.
Indeed, all of King Kong requires that we believe in Kong. Wonder
about him, love him, care for his future. Consider now, just for a quick
juxtaposition, the final moments in the 1933 original. Having escaped
from the Broadway stage(!), the ape has rampaged through the city (fifteen
blocks in reality) and climbed the tallest tree he can manage to find in this
jungle, which is, of course, the Empire State Building.4 Perched at the top
vulnerably, proudly, in torment, he can do nothing but succumb to the air
force. And although when he falls the long shot utterly fails to mobilize
sympathy, since it is only a scientifically calculated demonstration of an
object taking a long fall through space, the body upon the ground stirs us
to the heart, not just because Kong has been killed by modern civilization
(what else could happen?) but because here and all along he was our pet. We
were attached to him, artificial as he seemed, and so we believed. We loved
the artificial-and-living Kong, or the toy that simulated life, much as when
we are children we loved our own favorite mechanisms and endowed them
with both life and consciousness. Speaking to our toys we believed in them,
and when he lies dead we finally speak to Kong. When he lies dead, having
returned from the dead and died again, we speak to Kong.
4
In the 1976 film, the setting is updated from the Empire State Building to the World Trade
Center, a technical problem for Peter Jackson and crew making another remake in 2005. They
again used the Empire State Building as a model of triumphalist height.
40
Over Thames
FIGURE 40 Aerial view of the Thames over Waterloo Bridge in Survivor (James
McTeigue, Millennium, 2015).
Edmund Husserl wrote of time in 1905, the year Einstein published his
Special Theory of Relativity:
From an Objective point of view every lived experience, like every real
being [Sein] and moment of being, may have its place in the one unique
Objective time—consequently, also the lived experience of the perception
SEQUITUR 279
Françoise Dastur observed that for Husserl, time “constituted the most crucial
problem for philosophy. This problem marks the limits of its enterprise of
intellectual possession of the world” (179). As we attempt to apprehend
cinematic time, thinking back to Husserl, we can note not only that the
cinematic work is ongoing in its essence but also that within it, through
editing, various manifestations of contextually external time are offered for
consideration. One is causality, in which some B eventuating after some
A is considered to result from it, to be caused by it, even to be impossible
without the prior eventuation of A. There is an instant in Jim Jarmusch’s
Dead Man (1995) when William Blake (Johnny Depp) is struck in the chest
by a bullet, and what happens thereafter is a sequence of journeys he makes
into the wilderness that end with his expiration. Here is a separation of A
from B by an intermediate parade of events, but we never have doubt that
his death, B, eventuates from his being shot, A, although the intermediate
events accrete upon one another in fascinating arrays and overlayerings.
Causality may come up as a thought, then. That B comes from A. And this
can be nicely confounded if by means of a flashback technique we do not
actually see A until after we have seen B. In diegetic exposition B leads to A,
but we take the exposition to be in reference to an Objective time in which
A of course preceded B. Mervyn LeRoy’s Random Harvest (1942) gives a
very beautiful example. But causality is a relatively determinate calculation,
a thought that has limited utility.
Eventuality itself is another possibility. The arrival of things after things,
the ongoingness of the world. When Merleau-Ponty writes,
If time is the dimension in accordance with which events drive each other
successfully from the scene, it is also that in accordance with which each
one of them wins its unchallengeable place (457)
he does not specify, but with his antimony clearly means, that the placing
of events is provisional, that any event winning an unchallengeable place
will later be driven successfully from the scene by another event winning
another place. The ongoingness of cinema, perpetual, is its sense of time,
its acknowledgment of eventuality. That B appears after A, and that in
seeing the movement from A to B thanks to some method of editing we
can have the sensation of a flowing forward, with or without causality. It
is the “afterwardness” that strikes us, the sequentiality. Time in the film
seems to be unspooling just as the film itself does, moving forward so that
280 THE FILM CHEAT
events precede and then flow after each other. Rick (Humphrey Bogart) and
Renault (Claude Rains) stride across the gleamy tarmac by night, heading
for a new friendship, and this happens, this can only happen, after Rick puts
a bullet into Col. Strasser (Conrad Veidt) who is trying to make a phone call
(Casablanca [1942]). Sugar Kane (Marilyn Monroe) confides to Daphne and
Josephine (Jack Lemmon, Tony Curtis) in her train compartment after she is
seen by them striding down the platform to get onto the train (Some Like It
Hot [1959]). Even two eventualities posed as “temporally contiguous” need
not bear an implication of causality yet there is flow: spoiled Veda (Ann Blyth)
doesn’t want her mother Mildred (Joan Crawford) to kiss her goodnight,
“It’s sticky,” and then she turns away to sleep but with her eyes hungrily
open (Mildred Pierce [1945]). And when in a diegesis a configuration is
put forward of two eventualities happening “simultaneously” in different
locations (the desperate radio conversation at the beginning of Stairway to
Heaven [1946]), there is no way for cinema to offer the simultaneity other
than a flowing forward, excepting arbitrary use of effects (like split-screen)
seen through the viewer’s knowing assumption that without them, simple
forward progression would have been the only way (Pillow Talk [1959]).
Even in the split-screen, the sides of the “simultaneity” have to be optically
curtailed, one following the other, to aid focus.
Yet also, the production of editorial sequencing, indeed of filming itself,
occupies a time quite separate, a time lived in the editor’s or cinematographer’s
experience and quite prior to the existence of the filmic sequentiality that
can affect us. When we watch a film, we do so without consciousness of the
temporal relation between watched eventualities in the Objective time of the
filmmakers. Which scene was shot before which scene. Which scenes were
cut together before which others. Which performer, indeed, was hired before
which other performer and was waiting on the set to give a welcoming hello.
Our opportunity while watching film to assess temporal flow, sequence,
eventuality, even causality, is all produced through a cheat.
Every edit is a cheat of sorts. It is a way of joining two pieces of film,
which amount to two fragments of experience, so as to make them seem
intrinsically bound in a continuity which stands upon a unity. Even the
tactic of cutting across space and time, as cinema is so pronouncedly
capable of employing, brings together vastly separated zones into what is
felt as a harmonic and fluid march. Film’s unspooling makes every advance
a continuity.
Every discontinuity a continuity.
We have all heard the Hitchcock hymn to Kuleshov:
You have an immobilized man looking out. That’s one part of the film. The
second part shows what he sees and the third part shows how he reacts.
This is actually the purest expression of a cinematic idea. [Vsevolod]
Pudovkin dealt with this, as you know. In one of his books on the art of
SEQUITUR 281
Here, speaking into the ear of François Truffaut, Hitchcock is being puckish
as well as informative. His clear fascination is for the exact effects a filmmaker
can cause through shot manipulation by editing: the placement of shots in a
linear row, one before another. Eyes>>baby>>Eyes: Eyes>>soup>>Eyes for
Kuleshov (fond, perhaps, of babies and soup) and Stewart>>doggie>>Stewart:
Stewart>>half naked girl>>Stewart for Hitchcock (fond, perhaps, of both
doggies and half-naked girls). What Hitchcock does not trouble to elaborate,
but what calls urgently for elaboration, is the very principle implicit in the
forward movement of the edits.
This is a matter of huge interest to those who make and those who
study “slow cinema.” A subsequence can seem no different than what it is
subsequent to.
Normally we are given to read any B as ensuing from, reacting to, even
caused by an A that preceded it, even when B is a retreat to an earlier diegetic
time and therefore diegetically the cause of A. (Coming diegetically first, our
B is truly an A.) As we read forward, all the words that emerge from the text
refer back to, take their meaning from, and keep the rhythm of the words
that came earlier. The Kuleshov “experiment” works exactly because we
are prepared, or willing, to think that if we see a man looking and then see
an object, that object is the thing that man is looking at. Immaterial that a
crafty writer-editor team can fool the audience’s calculations by breaking
that formula sleekly; the point is that there is a formula to be broken.
There is a formula dictating that one thing leads to another. One thing
has been led to by another.
(Continuity is a requirement for cinema because frames come one after
another.)
1
Hitchcock is here chatting with Truffaut about Rear Window (1954).
282 THE FILM CHEAT
Except that one thing does not lead to another. Experience is hardly so
simple. In the realism of cinema we reduce experience to simple, digestible
arrangements. A woman reaches out to a door handle, turns it, opens a door
and walks forward. After a cut we see her emerge from a doorway (from
the other side of that door: that door, the door I have just mentioned) into
another space. The rationale of editing would teach us that the two rooms are
contiguous, that the door leads from Room 1 to Room 2 straightforwardly;
but also that in making that move, nothing at all is happening for the woman
beside taking herself out of one place and inserting herself into another.
Since movement is all we see, movement is all there is. Cute narrative games
can be played here. When she arrives in Room 2, looking the same, in fact a
year has passed and all the conditions of her existence have changed. Or in
Room 2 she loses her whole memory of Room 1 and cannot figure out how
and why she is here. A forward edit: being somewhere, then later forgetting
that one was there. Or in Room 1 she forgets why and how she is there,
but she reaches forward, turns a doorknob, and moves into Room 2, where
suddenly she remembers being in Room 1.
The logic of the forward edit is meant to apply to the viewer more than
to the character. When in Rear Window Stewart looks out of his window, we
look out of his window. And when “Stewart sees” a half-naked girl dancing,
we see that girl. We look, we see. As though nothing else intrudes, nothing
else is subjected to consideration, no daydream, no reflective thought, no
sideways glance, no retrieval of memory. Look>>see>>be. We look before
we see. Or do we see before we look? Is it possible to look without having
seen?
Considerable work has been done by filmmakers who are broadly
considered “experimental”—Stan Brakhage, Paul Sharits, Maya Deren,
Michael Snow, Hollis Frampton, R. Bruce Elder, to name only some—to the
end of producing cinematic motion with edited pieces but without building
in the essentially formulaic dictate of causality, eventuality, process; or,
more broadly, to the end of invoking a greater process, more poetic and
less journalistic, more natural and less arbitrary. But the narrative edit is
always a kind of cover blinding us to the world of happenstance, reflection,
consideration, dream, by offering a direct map to eventualities, forthcomings,
finales. A map cheat.
Hitchcock uses Rear Window to explore its own system of cheating at a
crucial moment when Jeff (James Stewart) becomes so enraptured watching
Thorwald (Raymond Burr) across the courtyard (a man he suspects strongly
of having butchered his wife) that he takes his eyes away from another
apartment down below, where Miss Lonelyhearts (Judith Evelyn), a middle-
aged woman he was spying on a moment before while she was disappointed
on a date, has now apparently downed a bottle of pills. Hitchcock’s point at
this instant, yet also throughout the film, is that many things are going on at
the same time all around, the apartment structure (elaborate and expensive)
SEQUITUR 283
mainly a mechanism for setting before the camera (before Jeff, who uses a
camera, too) a manifold spread, manifold but at the same time a spread only
a part of which can be taken in at any one moment. With every act of gazing
we may establish connections, discover clues, as Jeff does; but with every act
of gazing we are taking our eyes away from something else, possibly equally
potent, possibly dire. To do otherwise we would need a greater eye, the eye
that is shown in close-up (to our horror) in The Fly (1958).
Anyone would know that the solitary reality under consideration at
any moment is not the only reality, that one’s logic does not stand alone
in the world. And yet the cinematic process, by way of the editor’s cheat,
makes us sense ourselves bearers of such an omnipotent logic, sole, solitary,
independent, floating, unless (as with Rear Window) some direct notice is
given that we are not. Always, with or without notice, something vital is
happening here, now, that I do not see.
42
Veni creator spiritus
Anna is gone.
Where can she be, Anna? Anna? Anna?1 An aggressive search, every
crevice, every sea-washed nook, the foamy waters all around, the blazing
sun. Can she have gone into the water to swim away? Away where? To
death? Is there a hidden cave?—no, there is no hidden cave. Anna has gone.
This is early in the film, within the first twenty minutes or so. The story
continues for about another two hours. Anna never reappears. Is Claudia
concerned all this time? Is Sandro always everywhere endlessly searching for
Anna, no matter what else comes into his life?
Might Anna have been an illusion in the first place, an illusion considerably
more potent than the illusions of cinema, even? The film seems grounded in
the practical, not in illusion. Sandro has his feet on the ground, physically
if not morally.
We ride the boat. We come to the island. We hop onto the rocks. We
explore. We laugh. We tease. We run and we climb. Always forms, shadows
from the hot sun, glare, more forms, old forms, rocks from a billion billion
years ago, the sea, the everlasting sea. Where and when can she have
disappeared? She was here, before our eyes, and now she is not here.
There is, then, a Force beyond the social forces at play in the story, the
class, the attitude, the aspiration, the regret. Name the force Antonioni;
name it God; name it Creator Spirit. Veni creator spiritus! This force is in
action over and above—entirely independent of—our seeing the results; it
causes happenings and it erases happenings; it places before us, like so many
gifts to the emperor laid out on a fabulous carpet, all the creatures we need
to see, with their anxieties, their questions, their hopes, their abject fears.
Vitti’s character (as so very often in Antonioni’s work) is a notable case of
pent-up anxiety covered over by smooth grace. Everything is forcefully (if
calmly) laid out, all the conditions carefully spelled, the whole temperature
of the afternoon’s fun dictated firmly by the quality of the sunlight and the
forms of the rocks. If everything is here, if everything has been given, then
...
Then Anna’s absence is also here.
The emptiness is also given.
But here Antonioni executes a masterful plan. He does not play with the
conventions of the edit, the way one shot leads to another, the way we are
led first to feel expectations mounting and then to make a detection on the
basis of those expectations. He simply waits for a shot to terminate—any
good reason: the film runs out, the sun hides momentarily behind a solitary
cloud, a wind comes up blowing the women’s skirts, anything—and when
1
“Massari suffered a heart attack and was unable to complete a swimming sequence. The
assistant director, Franco Indovina, pulled on a petalled cap and bikini to double the passage
between pleasure boat and shore” (Sinclair 107).
286 THE FILM CHEAT
the camera is off he simply rescues Massari from the film. Ultimate Force,
he reaches into the narrative ongoing before him and he withdraws one of
the beings, simply. “Grazie. That is all for you.”2
Anna/Massari vanishes not behind a rock, not in the waves, not on the
far side of the island, but in a pause made by the Creator Spirit, a pause
placed off-camera. Her vanishing makes us starkly aware of the camera, the
island as setting, the Creative Force operating all this while at the same time
lingering before our sensibility like a vagrant perfume. So: not everything
that happens in a film needs to be seen happening. Not everything we see is
a happening. There are two worlds, one before the lens and another behind
it, two worlds, two horizons. Anna not only exists in both; she moves from
one to the other. And for the filmmaker, conscious of the twinning of his
world, she never dies.
2
“And please remain nearby for twenty-four hours so that we can be assured no re-takes will be
necessary before you fly off,” would be the typically understood farewell on a real set.
43
“Bite the Dust”
When the action gets swift the body almost always disappears. The editor’s
problem when the story launches into a hot-blooded pursuit, a precipitous
dangle, a fight, a horseback chase, an extra-vehicular activity, the climbing
of a construction crane—the problem and the challenge is to find a way
to do two things, apparently at the same time, although in practical effect
different shots are made and very skillfully cut together. First, quite beside the
long shot that will show the terrain, the complexity, and the challenge—why
fear has a place here—be certain to feature the principal character, clearly
identifiable, and heroic in deed. Next, keep the actor who is playing that
character from having to do anything at all, since a recognizable character
doing something is intrinsically interesting in herself but here it is the pulse
that is important.
Why must the actor be kept out of the stunt shot? A question that has
become too innocent for words in the wake of the 1983 death of Vic Morrow
288 THE FILM CHEAT
while filming Twilight Zone: The Movie for John Landis (and not staying
out of a stunt shot). Stunt work has a dangerous edge. While it is true that
in any movie shot accidents can happen, in stunt shots special safeties are
put in play:
●● Stunt performers are expert at what they do, and can be
differentiated according to expertises with different kinds of action.
They have performed the actions in question more than anyone else
on the set; they have learned the inside tricks.
●● Stunt performers work with directors and cinematographers to plan
out the precise action of every single shot, so as to place maximal
advantage on their own safety.
●● Crew members are generally sensitive to stunt work and its inherent
difficulties, and work hard, if necessary with numerous takes, to get
a shot right, injury-free.
●● Stunt performers are insured differently than actors are, and part
of the complexity of the stunt shot is the producer’s need to have
it accomplished with no untoward extra costs to the production,
beyond the specialized equipment needed.
●● Given the planning, the detailed labor, and the knowledge involved,
generally speaking stunt shots are not at all as hair-raising or life-
threatening as they appear onscreen. Much (cheated) exaggeration
can be produced through lens choice, camera speed, and filming
angle; as well as through sound editing. We tend to see what we
hear. Sound editing is a fascinating aspect of the driving shot,
because cars move much more slowly than they are posited as
moving in the story. The sound of revving motors covers (cheats)
the actual movement. Where there is no reason for diegetic sound, a
music track works effectively as cover.
character moving through quick action and courting danger. The courting is
performed by a stand-in, that is, comes from the behavior of not an actor/
character but a stranger/character we can reasonably believe to be the actor/
character; yet at the same time reasonably hope is not, since the actor would
get hurt and this stranger is inviolably magical in talent and stamina.
While the action flows—and typically the editing is accomplished with
very short pieces of film, running as briefly as a quarter of a second—we feel a
certain comfort in relaxing away from the screen and mapping the movement
(for which process designers assist us by dressing the protagonists in either
especially visible colors or easily detectable body suits). We sit back, we
ease into the rhythm of the action, we generalize the antagonism, drawing it
further and further away from Hero/actor vs. Villain/actor until it is wholly
morphed into the moral panorama of Good vs. Evil. As long as we find
ourselves watching a competitive “sport” between two discernable teams,
and as long as we are comfortable rooting for one of them, we can lose our
anxious fear that the hero will be hurt as an individual. Any wound produced
will be diegetic, a “hurt” that facilitates the plot (Luke Skywalker losing
his forearm in The Empire Strikes Back [1980]). To keep stoking that fear
between moments of release, to produce a fearful-relaxed-fearful-relaxed-
fearful-relaxed pattern, an ideal pattern for hooking the suspicious eye,
editors will cut back and forth between medium-long or long shots of the
motion (including vehicles, stunt actors, and background with intensified
scenic illumination) and matching very close shots meant to indicate that the
player we have been watching is “really” the star we love. The star we love,
now amazingly a race driver, a mountain climber, a skydiver, an acrobat.
Some moments of performer disappearance are without intrinsic threat.
The character and some associate are to be seen driving swiftly down a road,
with enough of the road visible that the car and the passengers are very
small. Here, stand-in stunt drivers are used (they cost less per day than the
star does). In car chase scenes, we move back to the close/distant paradigm
I discuss above, some particularly challenging and, for many, pleasurable
examples being the car chases in Paul Greengrass’s Bourne films. In these,
the intercut shots of Matt Damon as Bourne are very swift, sometimes of a
hand on a gear knob for only eight or nine frames. The head shots typically
show expressions of extraordinary intensity, but only to lead into long shots
of a vehicle operating entirely outside the rules (such as driving against
oncoming traffic on the wrong side of a busy road).
The action sequence tends to be arranged in such a way that the viewer
must make a trade-off. To get the full value of the attractions phase, the
shots of cars flipping or exploding, mountains crumbling, helicopters
bursting into flame, shots looking down on dinosaurs or on faces smashed
in or on marksmen grimacing as they eye their scopes . . . the payoff must
be a thrill, not a recognition: one temporarily relinquishes a hold on the
star/character as a discrete individual. One must be ready to do this, and a
290 THE FILM CHEAT
common strategy for handling the cognitive dissonance (as Leon Festinger
called it) is to deny that the star/character is being taken away. The denial is
effected through wholesale acceptance of the stunt substitute as character,
this allowing for a continuity of belief that the same person we see behind
the wheel in a close shot is the one driving the car off a cliff. “The star
vanishes.” = “The star cannot vanish.” In this curious way, stardom with
all its accompaniments is congealed with attraction, the flamboyance of
personality with the flamboyance of the screen as a whole (because that
screen flamboyance is essentially what the action sequence achieves for the
viewer’s pleasure).
Ansel Elgort’s spectacular driving sequences in Baby Driver (2017)
perfectly exemplify the action problem, while at the same time humorously
mocking stunt driving itself, since Baby drives as though his dream in life
is to be a stunt driver in the movies. Here we must cut between clear shots
of the actor at the wheel, or using his hand to yank the emergency brake
as he turns, and shots of the car speeding down the road balletically with
“Baby” at the wheel, Elgort here supplanted by a stunt driver. It is possible
nowadays to photograph inside a moving car with a hand-held camera
so that rear-projected backgrounds are not needed, but the car cannot be
moving so quickly that the world outside becomes only a blur.
The conventions of action design and editing notwithstanding, a very
elegant ornament can be played upon the “disappearing star” theme. Given
our expectation, once it has been cultivated, for seeing star portraits and
action long shots in alternation, and for knowing or suspecting that doubles
are being used in the long shots, a filmmaker might try something daring,
something we may think a cheat of a higher order. The star could be asked
to shoot the entire passage, yet in such a way that, relatively invisible in
them, she appears not to inhabit the long shots and be replaced by a stunt
double, while in fact this is not the case. (For obvious reasons this couldn’t
be done in shots posing actual danger.) In such a construction, the star-
character identity does dissolve in the longer shots, to be replaced by a
stunter-character identity, except that the actor is the stunter. Given poor
visibility (strategized in any number of ways), the star face is not visible as
such. The viewer thus experiences the same alternation between recognition
and calculated observation, recognition of the star up close and calculation
of the trajectory of the act seen at a distance, as in conventional action
sequences, without realizing fully that there are no substitutions being made.
Again, the viewer is tricked.
One can see this system in place very dramatically in the locomotive
sequences of John Frankenheimer’s The Train (1964), in which Burt
Lancaster does all the engine-driving shots himself. Lancaster was an athlete
before he was an actor, however. He had the training for moving skillfully
in undoctored space, such as the cabin of an engine or the river area beside
a railway track. But a very elegant passage illustrating the apparent absence
“BITE THE DUST” 291
[1] A long shot (14 sec.) of Ryan Stone* (Sandra Bullock) in full
spacesuit outside her capsule, black space in the background, as she
plummets toward the camera writhing desperately. (Treble high-
tech static soundtrack.) As she somersaults her leg is caught in some
floating cabling attached to the vessel. She comes toward, then past
the camera, moving swiftly so that the face inside the helmet is not
identifiable. She flies off screen-right as the camera turns to show the
earth beneath her. She comes to the end of the tether and is drawn to
the side, first across a land mass and then across several strands of
cloud. CUT.
[2] Picking her up on the return, as with the earth below she approaches
us again. When she is close, and we can see the Bullock face inside
the helmet, she is reaching forward (toward us) with her extended
right hand. Her hand fills the upper left of the screen. (7 sec.)
[3] CUT TO her view, with that hand at screen right reaching. The vessel
is in the background with *Kowalski (George Clooney) heading her
way on his own tether as the camera rotates. He is upside-down to
her alignment, and their hands graze each other but do not connect.
Upside-down he moves away as they still reach. Her extended hand
grasping nothing signals the desperation of the moment. His tether
extends from lower screen left. He becomes smaller as, with one hand
and then the other, she keeps reaching. (8 sec.) CUT.
[4] MATCHING SHOT, her hand at screen left, *Kowalski twisting
against the background of the earth in the distance, flailing. Her
hand, foreground, has his tether. (2 sec.) CUT.
[5] *Him appearing to glide off. (1/4 sec.) CUT.
[6] Ryan has his tether in hand, ship behind her, being drawn forward
across the screen. (2 sec.)
[7] EXTREME LONG SHOT. Fragment of capsule at left, fragment
of earth at right, black space filling the screen. **Two very tiny
creatures, the left one tethered to the ship and holding the tether of
the second. (2.5 sec.)
[8] With tether extending from screen left, Kowalski looking forward at
Ryan and both twisting and yanking with a shout. (1 sec.)
292 THE FILM CHEAT
Whenever a stunt performer “bites the dust” in order that the star’s character
may appear to do so, a fundamental postulate of cinema is invoked, one well
“BITE THE DUST” 293
known to insiders and camouflaged from the public by cheats: that a star
is not always a star. Effectively others may appear in the star’s place, not
only adequately filling in but fully appearing to be the star in action. Thus,
the action sequence does not augment or diminish the star persona nearly
as much as transmogrify it. The actor and character become together a new
creature with and without a face, with and without gestural skill, technically
adept while being innocent.
44
Reflect On That
FIGURE 44 Christian Bale in Empire of the Sun (Steven Spielberg, Amblin, 1987).
The speech was to hear and think about, but one could do this only when
some still riper riposte did not instantaneously follow onscreen (as happens
incessantly in His Girl Friday [1940], thanks to the sound work by Lodge
Cunningham). The principal agent controlling the pace of story procession,
instant by instant, was the editor. When an actor had been shot in close-up
uttering a precious line, film would be exposed before the utterance and
after it, making a head and a tail. It was finally up to the editor (here, Gene
Havlick) how much of either to use in the cut.
By controlling the “space” around a speech, the editor can modulate
the pace at which the actor’s body would seem to move from one point
to another, and the juxtaposition of talk against that movement, thus
fashioning a character for which the actor had provided only working
material. Assuming, for a quick example, that a portrait shot of a woman
saying something while she sits in a chair is made with a longish tail, the
“tail” being continuing silent footage as she remains where she is after
delivering the line, the editor can make her seem to reflect on what she
has just said, and urge us to reflect, too, by using two or three seconds of
that tail. When Bette Davis was encountered by Rudi Fehr, the man who
had edited most of her pictures, she said, “Rudi, you’re it!” (Bell 139).
She knew with surety what he had done to the work she had offered in
front of the camera to give it pace, duration, echo, and pause. The editor
is also in control of how long we will wait before a speaking companion
rejoins in a conversation. And of much else that we see and hear. The
impression generally given in cinema is that, magically and unseen, the
lens has recorded all of what happened before it, that what we catch here
happened as recorded. But the editor systematically cheats that impression,
and cheats the real action on-set in order to produce, to sculpt, to create
the scene as we see it.
Let us look at a very moving scene in a late 1980s film made with a
classical grammar, the moment in Steven Spielberg’s Empire of the Sun
(1987) when young Jamie (Christian Bale) witnesses the United States Air
Force attack on the Japanese prison camp in which he is interred. Shot
after shot shows planes racing across the sky, sometimes heading for the
camera and swooping away, other times seen in lateral motion across the
screen, and with quick cutaways to all the principal protagonists: Julianne
Moore and Peter Gale staring up through a window; John Malkovich and
Joe Pantoliano doing likewise; Nigel Havers coming into the fresh air and
staring up in shocked anxiety; Masatô Ibu, the commandant, looking up
with fear and concern. Jamie has been seen already racing up the staircase
to the balcony of a building, suitcase in hand. He has reached the balcony:
along the balcony (as camera pans), arriving at the [our] right end
and staring off-right. CUT TO:
[B] (A longer shot from behind Jamie, seeing the camp beyond him.)
He runs back, to his right again, back where he came from, staring
out intently. Then runs halfway back left. A plane coming left-
to-right down the runway strafes it. Plane moves off-right and
Jamie runs right to follow it with his gaze. An explosion in the far
right distance. A plane soars toward him, up and overhead, motor
buzzing. CUT TO:
[C] (Medium-close shot of Jamie) He stands at the railing, seen face-on,
with his hands raised to his temples and a look of anxious fear on his
face. Eyes furrowed. (Theme music strikes up extra-diegetically.) Jamie
crosses his arms over his chest as he steps back. Another step back. A
step forward. A smile beginning to crease the boy’s face. Stepping to
his right (screen-left) with the smile growing. Turning to look to his
left and stepping a little that way. (Theme ascending.) CUT TO:
[D] (Long shot. Fighter jet coming our way, very low, flying at the same
height as Jamie’s balcony.) (Vocal humming in the sound track,
ethereal, magical.) Wings tilting the plane comes forward. THIS
SHOT HAS BEEN FILMED WITH CAMERA CRANKED UP AND
PROJECTS IN SLOW MOTION. CUT TO:
[E] (Medium shot of Jamie staring off at the plane.) (Vocal music
continuing.) Frame cuts off top of boy’s head but he ducks down
squinting forward. CUT TO:
[F] (Close-focused long shot, Jamie’s back in foreground, jet at left
moving to pass him.) CUT TO:
[G] (Medium-long of Jamie, with camera lower than in [A], looking
up at balcony and boy with arms out excitedly at his sides.)
THE CAMERA SWOOPS IN SOME, AND SWIFTLY GLIDES
LEFTWARD (imitating the plane’s movement). CUT TO:
[H] (Medium-close of plane passing left to right.) Pilot is looking at
Jamie, giving him a brave wave of the hand.1 “Tugboat” is written
behind the propeller. THIS SHOT IS MADE FOR SLOW MOTION
(with vocal humming continuing). CUT TO:
[I] (Extreme close shot of Jamie, frontal.) His eyes explode with joy, he
stretches out his arms, he throws back his head, and yells at the top
of his lungs: “Wowwww! (Music harmonically echoing his voice.)
Go! B-51! Cadillac of the sky!!!”
The shot was created using a miniature plane with the flyer matted in. My thanks to Linda
1
that the plane passes just as he catches his breath, that one needs—
that Jamie needs—to race if he is to see it. That racing feeling, added
in by the editor who would have had plenty of film to work with
either way, allows us to share Jamie’s eager sensibility. Many have
written about Spielberg’s career at this point being one in which he
relishes the pleasures of his child characters; but the editing here
shows precisely how he displays that relished pleasure and entices us
to share it by means of the viewing we are given to have.
●● When we cut to [G] we are suddenly below Jamie again, looking up
in wonder at him looking up in wonder (the Wondering Boy as cause
for wonder). He stands in for the thing he is looking at (he looks up;
we look up at him looking up) and our looking at him becomes a
sympathetic adjunct to, or substitute for his looking. [G] is a more
exciting, more stimulating shot than [F], the long shot from behind;
the rapidity with which we are brought from [F] to [G], from behind
Jamie to a low spot in front of him, is an indication of the editor’s
decision to bring us a thrill without making us wait for it. It is as
though Jamie is whispering, “Hurry, love this!”
●● [H] is an interesting shot technically, because once the film has
been exposed with the camera cranked up it can be worked in the
optical printer to project at virtually any desired rate: a normal 24
fps projection of film shot at, say, 48 fps would lead to conventional
slo-mo; for film shot at 36 fps, say, slightly faster if still slow; 20 or
18 fps notably slower; or any number of frames per second at all.
That is, the hovering, floating, dreamy slowness of the thing as the
pilot waves is under aesthetic control. This shot directly addresses
and mirrors Jamie’s feeling as he sees the plane. The longer the shot
can last, the longer the boy’s thrill of contact with the pilot, for him
a true hero of the sky, the person he has dreamed of being. Jamie is
meeting his dream self.
However, the technical virtuosity hides itself. Given that [H] is a matte, there
are actually two pieces of film that must be composed together, in the optical
printer, one of them a shot of a model with the camera’s reverse motion
simulating the plane’s forward motion; the other a shot of the pilot making
his move. To make this matte seamlessly is a challenge to begin with, but
here and now it must be done at an accelerated frame rate—for both pieces
of film—thus giving the optical printer or digital compositor more frames
to work with (and potentially more frames with which to make a mistake).
●● The cut into the close-up portrait [I] can come at any point during
the plane’s movement in [H] as long as the pilot’s wave is registered
first (and that wave can be calculated, given the length of film
exposed and the speed of projection). It must interrupt our reverie
REFLECT ON THAT 299
* * *
If one saw this tiny sequence again, but in a re-cut form, say with all of the
shots [A] through [I] in the same order but cut so that each ran the exact
same number of frames (with [H] multiplied by two, to get the slo-mo effect
but for no longer than any other shot), the impression of the scene would
be radically altered. Our emotional attachment is struck, shaped, modified,
heightened because of the way the editor, Michael Kahn, is lengthening and
shortening the shots, our experience, and film time.
2
Joseph McBride offers an astute comment about Jamie and airplanes: “Preparing Bale for Jim’s
separation from his mother, Spielberg said, ‘I think the reason I want you to have a plane in
your hand is because you need to make a choice between your mother’s hand or your airplane,
which drops, and you choose your airplane. You let go of your mother to get the airplane and
your mother is swept away in this force’” (397).
45
Presence and Presentation
For a breath, let us return to Jamie on the balcony with that slowly passing
B51, “Cadillac of the sky!!!” It is plain enough that a passing aircraft is
being presented, that is, shown to a character and in such a way that it is also
shown to us. But as the item was filmed as a miniature, authentic B51s being
unavailable, with a pilot matted in, one could argue the plane was never
PRESENCE AND PRESENTATION 301
present: not for Jamie, not for Spielberg, not for us. Screen presence—as in,
the condition of being directly present—involves the entirely extra-diegetic
relation an object or person can have with a camera, beyond simply existing
in and of itself; whereas presentation involves the entirely diegetic relation an
object or person can have with a character’s eyes (and with ours--sometimes
in film we see what a character sees, sometimes not).
Spielberg’s diegetic “airplane” has presentation but not presence.
We could imagine a condition in which something or someone had
presence but not presentation. In Hitchcock’s Dial M for Murder, the painted
canvas of a bucolic scene hangs on the wall in almost every other shot of
the film, always decorating the space but never featuring in it. This canvas is
entirely present in itself, but is never actually presented. A nice equivocal case
occurs in Martin Scorsese’s The King of Comedy (1982) as Rupert (Robert
De Niro) entertains Rita (Diahnne Abbott), a girl he wishes to impress, at
lunch by paging (ostentatiously) through his autograph collection for her.
They are at a table very near the camera. His boorish straining to catch her
whim takes our attention, as does her somewhat interested (in the names)
but also somewhat disinterested (in him) attitude. Far in the background,
at a table all by himself, sits a man who has obviously been watching these
two and who is entertaining himself by mocking all of Rupert’s gestures in
sync (Chuck Low). There is no presentation shot of this man, yet he is very
evidently present. One could appreciate the nuances of the scene without
noticing him at all. The Hitchcock wall decoration works in the space, too,
but its working is never made part of the show.
Thanks to the “magical” cheat of special effects the bulk of what appears
on camera is a presentation without presence. We are meant to think—
encouraged to think—of such material as having presence, most notably by
the care with which it is shot in order to convey the effect of realism. One
important presence that is established with care but almost never made the
subject of presentation is what could be called “design tone.” When a number
of different sets must be constructed for a film, the reality “tone” established
in the first one we are to see in the final edit will call for replication in the
others, and designers know that by establishing the scene at first in a certain
key they will be required to keep “in harmony” in succeeding sets. For a
good model of this “key retention,” see Blade Runner (1982), designed by
Lawrence Paull. The apartment interiors could be exterior alleyways, and
vice versa.
But painted backings open another possibility for presentation without
presence. When a film scene is shot in studio in front of a large painted
backing the seamed canvas, sometimes more than 40 feet high and as much
as 180 feet long, is drawn and filled in such a way that from a distance the
eye sees it as real. The paint used is specially manufactured at the studio not
to suffer under intense illumination. And for illuminating the field, gaffers
use round dish lights called “skypans,” mounted at the top of the backing
302 THE FILM CHEAT
and uniformly lighting it. The cornfield in The Wizard of Oz (1939) and the
poppy field are painted backings; the surface of the moon in Destination
Moon (1950), seen in numerous differing shots, is one, too. The Scottish
hills around Brigadoon (1954); the atmosphere and mountains of Altair-4
in Forbidden Planet (1956); the Triboro Bridge (now the Robert F. Kennedy
Bridge) visible through the windows of the delegates’ lounge at the United
Nations in North by Northwest (1959); the black star field in 2001: A Space
Odyssey (1968); much of “Las Vegas” in Coppola’s One From the Heart
(1982); that spreading city one so frequently sees through the plate glass
windows of skyscrapers. The painted backing, expertly done, gives a very
strong sense of presentation and works to convince the viewer (falsely) of
presence, too. Painted mattes work similarly, as we see in numerous films
from Gone with the Wind (1939) and The Thief of Bagdad (1940) through
Star Wars: The Empire Strikes Back (1980) and An Age of Innocence (1993)
and Titanic (1997), to the Lord of the Rings films (2001, 2002, 2003) and
onward. As we believe the action to be occurring in a place, and believe
ourselves to share that place, we must accept the presentation as flowing
from direct presence if we are not to witness an artisanry that, being explicit,
yanks us out of engagement.
Obviously fill-in performers of all kinds affect to give a presentation
without announcing an actor presence, although we are usually tricked
(cheated) into finding presence where there is little more than physical
occupation of a space. When in Tootsie (1982) we see in long shot Dustin
Hoffman’s Dorothy Michaels stumbling on high heels through a sidewalk
crowd, Hoffman is present and also presented (via Michaels). But the
thousands of streetwalkers moving around him are only presented. While
we recognize that of course those people must have been there, their being
there does not register as a palpable fact for us in the way that Hoffman
does; they are merely streetwalkers (that is, the diegetic characters they are
playing to crowd the scene).
Two paradoxes:
●● Presentation Without Presence. That everything presented cannot
always be present was true as far back as the Keystone Kops and
Harold Lloyd and Charlie Chaplin and continued forward through
sci-fi space epics and highly charged, but in the everyday world
impossible, action sequences. Tricks of one kind or another are
unavoidable, even at the very most basic level in dramatic film. An
actor plays a character who delivers a pungent line—“Here’s looking
at you, kid”—and his character seems to reverberate in our screen
consciousness as he speaks. But a real presence is hidden here, as
neither Rick nor Bogie composed that line, although both of them
act to animate it, Bogie with his embodied self and Rick with his
coherent surface. The line actually comes from Julius and Philip
PRESENCE AND PRESENTATION 303
for Big Profit replaces speech). Special effects are mysterious because though
it is widely known they are there it is widely not known how and through
what combination of labors they work.
Presentation can be separated from presence in another, more chilling
way. Between October and December 1950, Hitchcock filmed Strangers on a
Train (1951), using numerous locations some of which were in Washington
D.C. A principal shot shows the villainous Bruno (Robert Walker) standing
on the steps of the Jefferson Memorial looking out to eye another character.
The film, assembled by Rainbow Productions, was released by Paramount.
Walker was signed to film Leo McCarey’s My Son John (1952) afterward,
mostly between August and October of 1951. This was also a Rainbow
Productions film, released by Paramount. But on the 28th of August 1951,
Robert Walker died (from an improperly administered drug, in hospital),
thus being unavailable to film all his scenes for McCarey. Some of the
footage of Strangers is copied into John with the diegetic context entirely
altered. The copying was unobstructed because the footage was owned by
Rainbow and was available from Paramount, both companies having made
both films. When we see the Jefferson Memorial shot from My Son John, for
one example, we are watching a presentation without a presence.
While it was not a secret, the death of Robert Walker also did not gain
broad publicity, and the edit substitutions in My Son John were not broadcast.
A far more notable and popularly recognized case of presentation without
presence was the opening, October 29, 1955, of Nicholas Ray’s Rebel
Without a Cause, starring the meteoric James Dean. Dean had been killed
in Cholame, California one month before, when his Spider was demolished
in a road accident. As Dean’s reputation was already keenly established
because of his electric performance as Cal Trask in Elia Kazan’s East of
Eden (April 10, 1955) the news of his death spread, so that with Rebel and
then with George Stevens’s Giant, which opened in November 1956, the
stark mismatch between a vibrant character scuttling through the drama
with intense emotion on one side and the entirely absent performative spirit
on the other could not have been more evident. Viewers at the time were as
saturated with news of Dean’s untimely death as they were deeply moved by
the performances they saw. Vivacity married to morbidity.
When I say “viewers at the time” I am touching on the tip of what seems
to me a very great iceberg indeed. When today we watch a film that has
been made “today,” that is, within the past year or so, in the great majority
of cases we read the actor beneath the character as a living person, just such
as we are, presently at work on some other film or at home with family or
friends somewhere: enjoying a life. We acknowledge that we have no access
to the privacy of the actor, yet also that there is such privacy and it coexists
with our own in time. There is thus a kind of depth to the screen images we
see, a penetration from the surface characterization through to the working
actor through to the citizen under-standing that actor in society. Presentation
PRESENCE AND PRESENTATION 305
[1] The optical rectangle of the screen image is brought into both technical
and cognitive focus through a differentiation of the relative values of objects
(in this case, bodies and things) in sight. A selection is made that establishes
something as central, crucial, important, special, valuable against other
things that necessarily recede at the same time. The camera’s focus is almost
always a guide to meaning, and when the focus changes during a static
shot our “composition” of the screen is altered to fit—that is, we follow
the guide. Following means, among other things, not reading presentational
status onto every presence before us. Fixation of vision can be aided by a
306 THE FILM CHEAT
sharp musical cue, too—a kind of downbeat, but one sounding a torturous
orchestration so as to alarm.1 As to the problem of rectangular boundary,
when they are worrying about what might be sliding over the edge or kept
out of frame the default tendency among film viewers is to trust that the
camera has captured the relevant rectangle inside the broader diegetic space.
Innumerable rectangles are theoretically possible, but this rectangle is the
optimal one, here, now. (Clearly, in horror film a very great frisson can be
produced by the filmmaker who is willing to play with this formula.)
When we concentrate on two bodies engaged in conversation, put before
us in medium shot, say, we take anything either of them says as being
centrally relevant to the moment; and we let our concentration bleed away
from the walls, the curtains, the hung pictures, the fireplace, the door. One
cannot see everything.2 Yet at the same time a set will be fully decorated so
that no telling lacuna gives away that singular dispiriting fundamental fact,
that this is always, and always was, only a set built of plywood and painted
up, an emptiness filled in with décor. Unless the camera picks out some
design element for us to focus on, we take the whole as a coherent presence
without expecting a highlit presentation of detail. And if there is a highlit
presentation of detail, we fold the detail into our consideration of diegetic
value and importance. The little piece of notepaper on the desk . . .
[2] But in addition, the cinematographer’s lighting crew will select out
some particular features of the scene for special highlighting in circumstances
where a shot is to be made that will later be adjoined in editing to another
one, in order that a pulsing sense of plot movement be given. Since screen
shots are complex to begin with, and since they last but a very short time, the
viewer must be given aid in selecting out the feature that will most relevantly
afford a sense of direct continuity when connected with a design feature
upcoming. The chase sequence at the end of E.T. the Extra-Terrestrial (1982)
gives a brilliant illustration. We see shot after shot of chase vehicles (from an
unidentified federal agency, possibly the F.B.I.) racing after a pack of kids on
dirt bikes through the unfinished construction of a hilly Los Angeles suburb.
The action is fast, and the cars are meant to be speeding, swerving, jamming
to a halt at a sudden precipice, and so on. But the screen is continually
composed using the flashing front bumpers of the cars, as they race across
the screen, to catch our eye and lead to the next flashing item in the next
shot. In effect the screen is an empty canvas on which Spielberg and team
are inscribing first one sweeping abstract line (the front of the car moving
in), then another but contradictory one (with another car on the other side;
1
The limiting case here is Bernard Herrmann’s screeching violins during the shower scene in
Psycho (1960), inspired, I am reliably told, by the sound of a violin tuning up.
2
Those who work with pausable media, able to stop on a frame, back up, and repeat several
times see, at least, more than their predecessors.
PRESENCE AND PRESENTATION 307
or a low shot of the bicycles speeding away, the pumping feet constituting
the match). Pretty much everything else has to be taken as read, since the
eye is taken up following the brightest parts of the screen: the bumpers, the
bike fenders, the dirt base.
And in this E.T. sequence the screen composition is gracefully managed
so that by looking straight forward at the screen the viewer can be offered
all the relevant moving objects seriatim, each swooping into a fixed field of
vision in turn. The filmmaker constantly reminds us that he knows we can
only look straight ahead in the theater. There is no other field. Therefore
what he needs us to see, what he needs to present, must be arranged so that
it will be seen directly and frontally, will have a presence that dissipates the
presence of other things that are also there and not being presented. The
scene itself, taken as a diegetic space, has presence; but only what is relevant
to the story at each instant will be presented there.
46
By Contrast
Roger Donaldson’s slick The November Man (2014) has Peter Devereaux,
a cast-iron CIA man (Pierce Brosnan), brought out of retirement by Hanley,
an old friend (Bill Smitrovich), so that he can seek out and handle Arkady
Federov, a Russian bureaucrat waiting to become president (Lazar Ristovski).
On the way we meet a Russian contract killer (a woman with long hair)
(Mediha Musliovic); a much-violated Serbian woman whose family were
exterminated by the soon-to-be president and who was for two years raped
by him (a woman with long hair) (Olga Kurylenko); a young CIA officer
trying to show the older one how good he is (Luke Bracey); an American
case officer, more or less impotent (a woman with long hair); a newspaper
reporter, sweet-mannered and doomed to a hideous death (Patrick Kennedy);
a CIA director, taciturn and slimy (Will Patton); and countless nameless
Slavic-looking thugs not one of whom can shoot straight. Who is on what
side here? What, in fact, are the sides? Will Brosnan’s Peter Devereaux
manage to escape from all the different sorts of folk who want to kill him?
Will he be reunited with his twelve-year-old daughter (a very young girl with
long hair) who has been kidnapped to keep him at bay? Will the would-be
president become president? To get an extremely vague sense of the quality
of this film, a film which is in so many ways like countless others of its type,
all of them starring actors like Pierce Brosnan, travel back to the beginning
of this paragraph and read it aloud as fast as you possibly can. When you
come to the end, stand on a pretty parapet overlooking a beautiful river on
a nice, sunny day and deeply inhale.
The filmmaker and his team are trying to do two somewhat contradictory
things here, of necessity. First, make a story both involving and complicated
enough to convince even the most cynical viewer (in an audience now filled
with cynics) that the picture has something to say, was worth making, and
deserves both attention, the restricted rating it will most surely be awarded,
and fifteen dollars at the box office. Secondly, take this exceedingly
complicated and heavily ornamented tale and find a way to simplify it, in
a way that is undetectable (because the cynics will be put off by simplicity)
but also indelible (so that viewers unaccustomed to the form, viewers half
sleeping, viewers with much else on their minds can manage to follow well
enough to be satisfied—or at least think they ought to be satisfied—by the
conclusion, and thus willing to pay at the box office still again for more fare
like this). Signpost it, but subtly.
If you don’t signpost it, the viewer may get lost or lose interest—certainly
sit back without involvement and watch the thing rather like a kaleidoscope.
If you signpost it too much you risk giving away the show.
There are two major muddles:
●● The moral muddle: Who is ultimately on the side of Good, who
ultimately on the side of Evil? Imperative that the nature of the
Good not be explored in depth. Goodness must be taken entirely
310 THE FILM CHEAT
for granted (thus showing off its hegemony). The good characters
die sadly, the bad ones perfunctorily. The good shouldn’t die and the
bad should (just as Oscar Wilde suggested1). What is involved here
politically is the problem of economic and military alignment and
the power imbalance that must occur when alignments shift. At this
writing, for instance, Turkey is threatening to “unfriend” America
in the name of a “bond” with Russia. In the sense that the film’s
characters will be spread across a moral spectrum they in effect
constitute opposing teams, teams each suffering the possibility of
infiltration by spies pretending to be bona fide members. The action
film, the western, the crime film, and the adventure film all work
by aligning the viewer’s moral compass and desire for satisfaction
with the heroic side, but the game will be all the more extensive and
challenging if the villain and company are not just threatening but
interesting and also in disguise.
To clear the moral muddle, any or all of these cheats will be employed,
part of the basic language of writers, directors, and producers but entirely
unhighlighted (as cheats will be):
[1] Have the hero brush his or her teeth. Only good characters brush
their teeth. Brushing the hair doesn’t work: liars brush their hair
sometimes. Another equally effective ploy is to have a sensitive
character (almost always a woman, although in Kiss of the Spider
Woman [1985] a man) tend to a heroic character’s open wound.
Heroes must be guarded from infections.
[2] Have the hero spare a critical moment to look upon some severely
wounded innocent, as though showing regret for stray bullets or, in
the case of a compadre, as though trying against all odds to prevent
a death. The key here is that time must slow almost to a halt as
the hero bends down to look, to touch, to care, to speak, to press
on the wound. “Stay with me! Stay with me!” Thus, when we have
a hospital scene with doctors and nurses caring for the brutally
wounded, these medical folk are not defined as good by virtue of
their occupational action; they are not taking time out. Goodness
stops the clock. And “bad guys” never stoop to comfort fallen
comrades. Humaneness is entirely a property of The Good.
[3] Have the hero avoid sexual culminations, or, for that matter, sex
altogether. The hero must be reserved for instantaneous physical
combat, and the exhaustion produced by orgasm is disempowering
1
“The good ended happily, and the bad unhappily. That is what Fiction means” (The Importance
of Being Earnest).
BY CONTRAST 311
•• The resilience muddle: The hero and villain (and their separate
crews) must seem radically different not only morally but also
because of the strengths they possess and demonstrate, physical,
spiritual, or intellectual. Thus, heroism cannot be claimed simply
to exist as a principle but must be demonstrated ongoingly, must
be claimed to flow from a cultural base widely acknowledged
and accepted; ditto villainy. In Shane (1953), to take a good
example of a morally bifurcated universe onscreen, the hero (Alan
Ladd) rides into the picture from the East, locus of high culture,
connector to Europe and the Old World. He makes not only his
cleanliness but also his origins clear in his tailored clothing and
in his mannerly dialogue with Marion Starrett (Jean Arthur). The
archvillain Wilson (Jack Palance), by contrast, also attired with
taste and at expense, thus perhaps also from an Eastern city, has
not picked up sociability. We see him excluded from the group,
leering at others, smiling obnoxiously, without grace. He is a man
bought on command, a mercenary type, whereas Shane has solid
working-class values as well as couth, knows how to ask for a
job and how to work hard for his pay. Wilson uses his tricks but
never works hard. Yeoman vs. charlatan.
BY CONTRAST 313
[1] The hero will not only tolerate but appreciate cultural expression
(expression, not over-expression), even showing an ability to drop
a significant keyword. In November Man, again, Devereaux is
resting in her apartment with Alice Fournier (Kurylenko), and at
one point she sits at her grand piano and begins to play one of Erik
Satie’s “Gnossiènnes.” He stands beside her, focused and patient,
his ears open. “Satie!” he says quietly. She admits Satie is one of her
favorites. We quickly imagine him as a teenaged boy, studying music
in a conservatory!
[2] While villainous display of etiquette will be oily, overcooked, and
often out of place, heroic etiquette will be precise and appropriate
and quiet. Jason Bourne (Matt Damon) is in flight with Marie
(Franka Potente) (The Bourne Identity, 2002), and it becomes
necessary that her hair be changed. We see him gently massage
color into her hair in a sink, his technique exceptionally tender
and considerate. When he uses scissors on her, he touches with the
most exquisite combination of affection and care. The villainous
Al-Saleem (Alon Aboutboul) in Ridley Scott’s Body of Lies (2008)
speaks with false, troubling quietness and a pleasant (too pleasant)
smile as he interrogates Ferris (Leonardo DiCaprio) chained to a
table. Slowly, pacifically he walks up. Then in an abrupt move takes
a hammer and slams it down to break Ferris’s finger.
[3] The villain will have recourse to nefarious weaponry all through the
story but the hero shows goodness by using weapons only as a last
resort or when in an equivocal situation, facing a small army to be
cleared through. When he does become physical, however, regardless
of how evenly or unevenly matched he is against his opponent, it
becomes startlingly evident that he is straining more, urging himself
toward some superhuman (divine?), hitherto unattained goal. Tries
harder. He will escape, for instance, from a cloistered imprisonment
in a secret, dark place or from a lethal stranglehold being laid on by
a very muscular, much bigger enemy. Or he will have to realign or
reorient some physical construction, a door, a safe, a wall, a builder’s
crane, an aircraft, showing remarkable ability to handle almost
any equipment without training (as though before being a hero he
held odd jobs as a crane operator, an elevator boy, a paver of roads,
a pilot, etc.). The hero will be notably less than successful until
the finale moment, when his “spontaneous” success will “save the
world.”
More than handling equipment, heroes and villains have signal
contact with their immediate environment, working the world.
314 THE FILM CHEAT
For the Good Man, the whole is malleable, giving, yielding, a true
material out of which salvation can be forged: cell phones without
service suddenly have service, door locks can be jimmied, shackles
can be opened and knots untied, light can emerge into darkness.
By contrast the Evil One, the one under whose command the
mechanism of the story is at some key point shown to operate,
finally cannot save himself, cannot escape the all-consuming
explosion, cannot find an escape through the forest of the city.
Stubborn to the wicked, kind to the beneficent is the world. An
ambiguous environment. Unless (as in Alien [1979]), a sequel is in
the works . . .
[4] The “world,” indeed, becomes a salient locus for the villain, who
almost invariably has concocted an expensive and tricky plan to
control Everything, to “Take Over the World,” to “DOMINATE.” At
the end of November Man the villainous Hanley lectures Devereaux
on how elevating Federov to the Russian presidency will “change the
world” because Russia will be joining NATO! This because Federov
(along with all the commitments and engagements to which Federov
is attached) is under his thumb. All James Bond villains are World
Dominator wannabes. The hero demonstrates goodness by “saving
the world” but this is, in a way, inadvertent; he holds back, stymies,
or defeats a villainous type who wants to “endanger the world” and
thus the world comes into question. Beyond that the hero’s concerns
are always local and situational. The hero is local, the villain is
global; the more global the more villainous.
[5] At a critical story moment, the villain will bluntly insult, deprecate,
and verbally diminish the hero, whom we know already to be of
superior mettle and thus a very model of dignity easily sloughing
off the insults as empty and inappropriate. At the end of The Train
(1964) the neurotic and desperate Nazi commander Von Waldheim
who has been trying to run a train filled with the treasures of French
art to Germany (Paul Scofield) confronts the French resistance hero
(Burt Lancaster) with a blunt sneer. “Labiche: You are nothing.” This
comes at a point when we have already seen, as has the bitter Von
Waldheim, that Labiche is anything but nothing.2
* * *
2
The villainous deprecation of the hero works as well in historical epics. The King (2019) has
a brief confrontational moment between King Henry (Timothée Chalamet) and the Dauphin
of France, who wishes to antagonize him. He comments that the king has big balls but a tiny
BY CONTRAST 315
What is worth noticing about all these cheats, the cheats that join the two
sides of the moral coin into a cubist treasure, is not their identity, since
in effect these, and other cheats, constitute nothing other than the generic
identity of a kind of film. What is significant is the filmmaking team’s ability
to employ these flags without permitting them at any point to actually look
like “flags,” a possibility only partly because viewers know the formula.
With ever more sophistication and richness as time goes by, the hero covers
his exquisite etiquette by saying, “Umm.” The villain covers his covetousness
in myriad silent macro-close-ups where he is evidently pondering: a thinker,
a philosopher. And so on. The effect of the secretion of cheats is a kind of
glorious brilliance. The film takes on the quality of a rich and energetically
charged story (failure to follow along with which would be unthinkable) but
not what it more practically is: a necklace of repeatable tropes (stemming,
often, from melodrama) expressed through gestural dances of intent and
poetic songs of regard. We may find pleasure in remembering that while the
villain will feel free to slur the hero—“You and your preposterous attempts
. . .”; “You will never have the stamina . . .”; “I pity you”—the hero does not
slur the villain at all, much like St. George, who did not curse his dragon.
penis, and he wiggles his pinky finger. Henry looks at him quizzically, as though to ask, “What
on earth can you possibly mean?” but says absolutely nothing.
47
The Blood Effect
FIGURE 47 Neil Patrick Harris in Gone Girl (David Fincher, Twentieth Century
Fox, 2014), with Rosamund Pike.
on how much flow the director wants. David Ayer’s Sabotage (2014) has a
large number of sequential, bizarre, unimaginably brutal, and exceedingly
bloody killings, in which whole or partial slain bodies are shown swimming
in, caked in, dripping with, or altogether saturated with blood; there are
also countless lesser killings where much blood is shed, but rapidly. If the
bloodshed is to be put on camera, the viscosity could help determine the
required length of the shot. It would not be an overstatement to say the
shedding of characters’ blood has gone rampant in film, with the blood
effects swollen more and more as time goes by. In military or quasi-military
plots, a member of a tightly bonded fraternal team takes a bullet hit and
bleeds profusely (from a vital location, such as the point where the neck
meets the shoulder); a compadre rushes up and presses on the wound, but
through the helpless fingers blood fountains out. Or a noxious villain is
machine gunned, half a dozen or more bullet holes being produced in the
torso. Blood is everywhere. In Some Like It Hot (1959) the Mafia hits are
intended as comedy (the entire film is intended as comedy) and so explicit
blood loss is avoided.
Two considerations:
●● Blood isn’t actually anywhere in the peridiegesis, the production
area surrounding the photography space, at least not as a matter
of routine. At the same time, within the diegesis it abounds. Blood
simultaneously present (to extremes) and absent. This of course
raises the issue of dramatic conviction and audience engagement,
fertile ground for planting cheats, and raises it with special acuity
since the loss of blood is potentially lethal, thus serious, and bloody
circumstance must therefore be sharply set off as fictional. Indeed,
climactic or semi-climactic. Of all fakeries onscreen, the blood fake
has a special power because when we see blood flowing from a
character we know instantly that it cannot be real (unless injury
was intentionally produced on set: unthinkable). The dramatic
fiction—involving the dissolution of the actor’s presence and the
actor’s habitation of the character—is vulnerable variably but
never so much as when blood flows. Blood in our lives is not
only distinctively real; it is life-sustaining. And, of course, from a
cinematographer’s point of view, especially in color, quite a visible
substance.
This vulnerability may well be one reason why in an age where filmmakers
strive harder and harder for social realism, efforts are undertaken to make
bloody scenes as extensive as possible. Extensive, as in “beyond the bounds
simple fakery could achieve.” Every stretch of the ribbon, every extra bullet
hole increases the odds of a moment of credibility. The viewer’s “How did
they do that?” has to be rapidly multiplied with numerous grotesque bullet
THE BLOOD EFFECT 319
hits, and finally becomes lost, therefore moot. One buys into the fiction by
default, since the labor of calculating the multiple effects is just too great
to achieve speedily. The helicopter massacre in Brian De Palma’s Scarface
(1983) nicely illustrates, as does the Nice car chase in John Frankenheimer’s
Ronin (1998).
One diegetic strategy that adds reality to the blood effect is a character’s
“sudden” discovery of a blood-saturated victim and shocked withdrawal in
disgust. “I’m OK,” protests a character, who then collapses and is seen to have
sustained a massive and fatal abdominal wound. This is a variant of the play-
within-the-play, in which however mocked-up the performance (the victim’s
body) may be it gains authenticity by virtue of the belief demonstrated by
on-scene watchers.1 In Sabotage there is a scene where Olivia Williams and
Arnold Schwarzenegger discover the body of Sam Worthington folded up
inside a refrigerator. The throat has been slashed, and the entire figure is
saturated with red. Williams jumps back in horror, and the shot is held so
briefly we do not have time to rationalize the “corpse” as either a posing
actor in make-up or a latex model. Coroner scenes are played obversely: the
doctor examines the (now somewhat cleaned) body of a brutally murdered
character, but instead of pulling away physically exhibits professional
rationale, a much experienced and well-trained calm objectivity, often using
ambiguous humor as a way of pulling “back” without pulling back.
●● In “bloodbath” scenarios, blood is everywhere, or so it seems, and
the audience is meant to take the presence, the quantity, and the
spread of blood seriously as indicative of gravity, that is, as actual.
(Consider the character who calls himself a “painter” in Martin
Scorsese’s The Irishman [2019].) But viewers know that movies are
made by people and that all the people one ever sees onscreen are
always already full of blood. Even in film stories where no blood is
shed, one is watching “blood everywhere” all the time, yet it does
not manifest itself. A good deal of the horror of diegetic “bloodshed”
is thus not the simple presence of blood in the world of the scene,
but its actual appearance outside the body in clearly specified
spots we think to be blood free: on clothing, furniture, walls, floor,
ceiling. Blood has come out of hiding in the body and now stains
the setting. Macula as drama. But not: blood has come out of the
body and therefore the body cannot support life. That is true but
insufficient. What is needed is blood as a stain in the fictional world,
leading us to imagine it as a stain in the everyday world, too. Blood
as optically rendered substance, not only red but slick, not only
1
On audience belief and the play-within-the-play see Goffman, Frame Analysis 475 and my
discussion of Gone Girl (2014) in Virtuoso 241–5.
320 THE FILM CHEAT
The “tactility” of screen blood both adds to its realism, helping to induce
us toward belief, and makes for good screen business, indicating a material
actors can have their characters attend to and react against.
●● Part of the emotional thrust of bloody scenes has to do with
the abject nature of blood in Western society, its confinement,
both physical and cultural, to proper embodiments; its use, say,
substituted by wine, in ritual celebrations; the broad-based sense
of its vitality and preciousness, its symbolic representation of life.
Violent bloodshed in drama breaks with social form, aggravating
conditions in the name of drama. In Hamlet, bloodshed, signally
diffuse in the dramatic population by story’s end, elevates the
tragedy to heroic proportions. The violent police thriller or criminal
adventure film uses substantial blood flow for the same elevation,
lifting shooters above victims and the force of authority who finally
shoots the shooters, above everybody. As Kurt Vonnegut Jr. writes in
The Sirens of Titan:
Any man who would change the World in a significant way must have
showmanship, a genial willingness to shed other people’s blood, and a
plausible new religion to introduce during the brief period of repentance
and horror that usually follows bloodshed. (176)
Can it be thought the same thing, escaping from reality by way of Gene
Kelly and Judy Garland in The Pirate (1948), as by way of Joan Crawford
in The Women (1939), or Laurence Olivier in Richard III (1955), or Monica
Vitti in La notte (1961) or Brando in The Godfather (1972) or Wallace
Shawn in My Dinner With Andre (1981), or Minnie Driver in Good Will
Hunting (1997), or Elizabeth Taylor in Who’s Afraid of Virginia Woolf?
(1966), or Tilda Swinton in I Am Love (2009), or Armie Hammer in Call
Me By Your Name (2017)? Is there only one tunnel of escape, no matter the
painted hieroglyphics on its walls? And when we go, if we go, do we head
into a substitute present or a substitute past, and if a past, whose past, what
kind of a past, a past that is liberating how?
The argument that cinema offers an “escape from reality” may or may
not have genuine weight, but even if it does it goes only part way toward
an understanding of our experience with the screened image. Cinema does
many things to many people, as many people do many things to make
cinema. The implication throughout these pages has been that one of the
most serious allures of film, taken for granted and thus unheralded, is its
absolute guarantee of offering pleasing lies, by means of which, of course,
it comes around to offering unspeakable truths (secret truths, perhaps, or
truths for which words do not suffice, or truths that cannot be sung). We
are attracted to, enchanted by, always hungry for more of cinema’s many
cheats, those devious little workings that, knowably false still put forward
an inviolable presentation of life, coherent and apparently seamless,
angled for participation and lensed for startling clarity: clarity of the clear,
clarity of the less than clear. It makes no difference to be aware that the
pictures we watch are pictures only, instead of the things they are pictures
of, because we have no difficulty substituting the pictures for the things,
which is to say, believing that the pictures picture things reliably and fully,
and more: that the pictures are for us, as we watch them, better than the
things. It makes scant difference to know that moving pictures are made
through fakery of one kind or another as long as we wish to gaze at them
and in gazing find some hitherto undiscovered territory in ourselves. As
long as we wish.
The cinematic cheat is one of cinema’s principal attractions, then:
●● That all these lively characters, seeming to be intensively present, are
not really there, that the characters are only “such stuff as dreams
are made on,” made round and given flesh by the unseen actors who
bring them before us. We follow characters, we accept the premises
of their experience, we note the circumstances of their lives, we are
caught up with their fates, although they are nothing, we know;
and knowing they are nothing does nothing to displace us from our
satisfaction, nothing to prod us away from the vital path they lead
as we follow. The character is through and through a cheat, but
EPILOGUE 323
Here are five ways the film viewer finds accommodation and excitement not
in the pathways cinema openly affords but in its cheats. Not the supposed
realities as putative realities but the supposed realities as pure suppositions.
sharp and articulate tongue (such as no one of us can muster on the street
corner); the graceful sweep of the arms and consummate, dancer’s balance;
the replete vocabulary of gestures, small and huge; the diva’s capacity
to modulate the voice for subtlety and extensivity; the uncanny sense of
spontaneous presence (that Nicholas Ray found to his great delight in James
Dean). The green glare of the eye. The pause between words, for emphasis,
for rhythm. The sweeping exit (none better than by Bette Davis). In The
Fantasticks (1960) the old actor regales his listeners about his long career
and how audiences particularly favored his various ways of dying. “Do it
again, Oliver!,” he says they cried, “Do it again!” To see what seems real
in the full and reassured knowledge that it is not. Encore!!! To intimate
consequence when we know the consequence is only false. To see gravity
when if there is gravity it is elsewhere.
So that no matter the assiduity with which an actor can race through his
paces, no matter the blunt accuracy with which he can deliver his lines, a
bad performance still, and always, stinks. It leaves us wanting, but surely
not wanting the factualities of the imposture, the gun pulled, the threat
chewed out, the awkward hesitation, the finger on the trigger . . . these may
be not enough as cooked, but it is something more that we want. We want
the glory of the fakery. As Gene Hackman puts it in Heist (2001), eyeing a
character who is pointing a gun into his face, “Don’t point that if you’re not
going to shoot it. It’s so insincere.” We need the sincerity of the character
seeming to be alive in his moment, not secretly alienated from it through
some puppeteer’s manipulative consciousness smartly denied us. We need
Hamlet to be suicidal while not being suicidal. We need Romeo and Juliet
to be lost in the madness of young love while not being lost. We need Lee
Marvin in Point Blank (1967) to be hell bent on revenge, at all costs. We
need Geraldine Fitzgerald in Interiors (1978) to behave as though nothing
on the face of the earth is more crucial than placing each piece of furniture
at exactly the right spot in a well-designed room. We need Sean Connery as
James Bond to be absolutely relaxed in his confidence in his well-trained
strengths. We need Elliott Gould in The Touch (1971), eyeing the termites
eating the wooden statue of the Virgin from the inside, to be shaken, while
not being shaken at all.
Luke Skywalker is not really fighting Darth Vader, you know, with his
light saber. This is not really a battle to the death.
“Yes, yes! But I want to see!” (And if, as did not happen in 1977 but by
this time is very likely to happen, one sees the arcing, flashing light sabers as
“effects” not light sabers, the whole performance starts to stink. One must
will to believe it all real, while knowing it is an effect.)
One must will to believe.
And being given we want still more. That the character, unlike folk of
the everyday, should at each instant be at a peak of emotion or form, never
less than spectacular, never in front of a mirror getting ready to seem that
326 THE FILM CHEAT
way. Even waking up and crawling out of bed, the character must act with
brilliance, even brilliant stupor. Even the before-the-mirror moments must
be spectacular in themselves (see David Warner checking himself out in his
gorilla suit in Morgan: A Suitable Case for Treatment [1966]). No stumbling
that is not dramatically wonderful in itself (Van Johnson in 23 Paces to
Baker Street [1956]). No speech troubles that are not sweet and attractive,
or poignantly indicative (Patty Duke in The Miracle Worker [1962]). No
song but eloquent song (Julie Andrews in The Sound of Music [1964]; Jerry
Lewis in The Delicate Delinquent [1957]).
And we want the kind of grace it would be naïve or churlish to expect in
the world of the everyday, that every streetcar arrives with its doors open at
the precise instant the desperately fleeing heroine needs a ride from Berlin
Alexanderplatz; that the multiple bodies spinning, leaping, and vocalizing in
bravura color never collide, never even brush or accidentally touch things
that have been arranged so much like a Swiss clockwork (the opening number
of La La Land [2016]). A symphony of movements expressing the height of
style (Brando in Streetcar [1951]) and, too, the high aeries of emotionality
(Wendy Hiller in I Know Where I’m Going! [1945]). There is a delicious
moment in Michael Powell and Emeric Pressburger’s The Thief of Bagdad
(1940) when in his ornate pink palace the Sultan of Basra (Miles Malleson)
is being visited by the (evil) wizard Jaffar (Conrad Veidt) and he decides to
regale his guest with a little tour through his collection of toys. One of these
is a tiny theater, with a stage and a curtain. A group of acrobats are set to
perform, tiny figurines, but the Sultan makes the toy operate and the figures
“come to life,” going through a whole beautiful routine: no accidents, no
flaws, no bumping, no falling. This has been achieved with a matte-in of
an acrobatic routine filmed life-size on a stage against a black curtain, and
before optical printing the matte image has been several times reduced in
size—because we do see at least one shot of the Sultan standing beside
the theater looking at it with awe. This little fakery-within-a-fakery has a
lesson: very like these tiny acrobats are the figures (figurines) of cinema,
mechanically placed and constructed, moving according to plan, everything
seen and foreseen, everything polished, everything sized to fit the screen.
Everything a joy.
Give me someone who is saying something, anything, so very believably,
with such generosity of feeling laid upon each breath . . . something he or
she doesn’t believe at all, since he or she has no mind, no belief, and a writer
wrote all this. Give me that absent writer through the shining body of this
bewitching genius. Give me puppets.
Let me see a growing up that isn’t growing up, a dying that isn’t dying,
a love that isn’t love, devouring a chicken leg that isn’t real devouring,
inebriation that I can trust is sober, malevolent intent that is only a puff.
Give me brilliantly choreographed fear and desperation (the car chase),
give me startling intelligence from a being who, were I to encounter her or
EPILOGUE 327
him in the everyday world, would seem only pleasant, polite, and pale. Or
would seem, indeed, supremely gracious and sweet (I have found many very
celebrated performers to be this way) but not as scathingly expressive, as
chilling as they were onscreen. (They don’t go through real life with a writer
at the side.) Give me a realm that is another realm, filled with creatures of
superhuman proportion and form, unearthly expressivity, color to bleach
the rainbow.
It was in the 1960s that film productions began remorselessly to use location
exteriors and often location interiors, rather than studio set-ups. Call it social
realism, call it economy, since studio space rental was not cheap. A very
frequent tactic was to shoot set-ups and exteriors on location (sometimes
with a second unit) and do the interiors on soundstage sets. The idea of giving
the viewer a location to view bloomed in the 1950s, of course, with exotic,
often Technicolor epics set in such desirable spots as postwar Rome, Hong
Kong, Paris, Istanbul, and London. The idea of a lush travel experience,
fostered on land through such agencies as Gourmet magazine and onscreen
in films such as Three Coins in the Fountain (1954), Topkapi (1964), An
Affair to Remember (1957), Love Is a Many-Splendored Thing (1955), The
Man in the Gray Flannel Suit (1956), Love in the Afternoon (1957), The
Barefoot Contessa (1954), Light in the Piazza (1962), The Roman Spring
of Mrs. Stone (1961), Midnight Lace (1960), or To Catch a Thief (1955)
accustomed audiences to the expectation of being taken somewhere by film,
taken in luxury and shown only the richest sights of the territory. The act of
viewing thus entailed the viewer taking as given a description of narrative
space, its geographic identity flashed onscreen through a title card. One
cherished authenticity as regards architecture, quality of light, human and
vehicular traffic, language, and cultural emphases. One did not recognize
what was in fact playing out through the images:
●● A story scripted in the United States, mostly Hollywood, by writers
familiar with foreign customs (because of their own wartime
experience, often; or their own travel) or else deftly based on a
detailed published fiction (deriving from the same kinds of source),
and very meticulously researched by studio departments with
enormous library and personal resources.
●● Scenarios imaginatively but tactically set in foreign locations,
usually very specific foreign locations, such as the hilltop hospital in
Hong Kong where Dr. Han Suyin (Jennifer Jones) works in Many-
Splendored Thing or Rome’s Trevi Fountain in Three Coins.
●● Visions of splendid—for many North American viewers, hitherto
inconceivable—panoramas effected by special photography or
328 THE FILM CHEAT
if there were any—intolerable, as though, flying through the air with the
greatest of ease we had suddenly come upon a patch where all the oxygen was
missing. To get the intensified eventfulness, scripts are drafted and redrafted
countless times, scenes polished or curtailed or eliminated, establishing
shots dropped away, lines of dialogue clipped, editing rhythms established,
clues planted about what lies ahead down the road and then some object
is sent barreling down the road soon afterward, lest the audience forget
about having been given clues. All of this cheats authenticity, but creates the
believable surface, and the believable surface is everything.
As we watch, authenticity—actual authenticity, if we could ever determine
what that was—is of no value.
[4] Dance
We are not given access, by cinema, to performers and artists as they train
or prepare. Fred Astaire’s long, long, long hours of off-camera practice,
refining those splendid dance moves to perfection . . . impossible even to
know which direction to point the compass to find him doing this. Hein
Heckroth mixing his paints to do the sets of the Ballet of the Red Shoes
(1948) for Powell and Pressburger—unthinkably hidden. Vittorio Storaro
getting ready to shoot scenes of One From the Heart (1982) for Coppola
and testing out various theatrical gels to see what effect they will have on
various film stocks with certain patterns of lighting: all backstage. Leonardo
DiCaprio or Meryl Streep or Pierce Brosnan or Ian McKellen (born Los
Angeles; New Jersey; Ireland; Lancashire) learning how to put on believable
South African accents (for Blood Diamond [2006], Out of Africa [1985],
Survivor [2015], Six Degrees of Separation [1993]). McKellen doing makeup
tests for Lord of the Rings (2001), Apt Pupil (1998), X-Men (2000), or Mr.
Holmes (2015). Johnny Green re-populating and re-seating and rehearsing
the MGM Orchestra to record for An American in Paris (1951).
Without access we are led to take the realized performance as a
spontaneous outpouring, and this spontaneity, this unprepared spirit is
what we come not only to believe we are always seeing in cinema but also
to desire to see, again and again. (Desire does not spring from a vacuum;
“Nothing will come of nothing.”) We much prefer the cheated gloss to the
untouched, and would not choose the latter over the former if given free
opportunity (even in documentaries, which have their own backstage). We
wish not to see labor but to revel instead in the fruits of labor, success. This
even in the many strange, utterly ironic cases where labor, not performance,
is openly given onscreen as the content of the performed dramatic moment:
the prisoners’ work laying bricks in One Day in the Life of Ivan Denisovich
(1970), the actor’s dressing-room labor in The Dresser (1983; 2015), the
engineer’s control of the train in The Train (1964), the botched rehearsals
of a wannabee diva in Florence Foster Jenkins (2016). We happily see the
332 THE FILM CHEAT
We want to believe that all of the lines composing all of the spaces we see
can be projected further than the limit of our sight, on and on, so that a
corner becomes a neighborhood, a neighborhood a city, a city a portion
of a state, the portion the state, the state the country, the country the
hemisphere, the hemisphere the planet, and on and on until the end of time.1
That space is both fluid and continuous, that the border does not really
exist, that fragmentation is a theoretical construct but not a fact of life. The
truth is that outside what is depicted onscreen, very little exists of the scene
involved, not the ceiling, not the other side of the bedroom. The qualities of
screen space end not very far from the camera’s framing. On the other side
of the door to the office is a storage space full of boxes and rolled canvas
and spare light bulbs. The skyscrapers we see through the office window are
painted on a backing that is thirty-seven feet high, and from the top of that
upward one finds only ropes, hanging work lights, a fixed grid. Everything
of cinema is built to appear perfect in the frame but is not built the way
the world is built, except, of course, that what is built for the camera is in
the world. And when something is made to fit a frame, the designers think
about how long the shot might be on the screen, whether the camera will be
in motion, which colorations will stand out and which recede, how much
that is already familiar to the viewer will be filled in by the imagination and
need not be constructed. In The Wizard of Oz (1939), Dorothy, Toto, the
Scarecrow, the Tin Man, and the Lion go dancing off on the yellow brick
road, away, away, away from the camera, diminishing, diminishing, and
then quickly the scene dissolves to another. Just at the last point of the shot,
before the dissolve begins, the dancers were only inches from the painted
backing that showed the road continuing onward as far as one could see;
but that backing was only twenty or so feet from the camera. What is built
as a set is what will be seen by the camera, not what would exist in a world
such as the world depicted (suggested) in the frame. Thus, cinema has its
own geometry, but the cheat of the medium is to convince viewers they
are looking at some natural geometry instead, the mountains receding, the
distant clouds.
1
André Bazin wrote, “What the screen shows us seems to be a part of something prolonged
indefinitely into the universe” (166). One might add, indefinitely and perhaps not without form.
EPILOGUE 333
And in the contest between fake and real geometry, watchers want the
fake to win.
* * *
The cheats multiply, far beyond what I have pointed to in these pages.
Punch cheats, rooftop chase cheats, language cheats, makeup cheats, cheats
upon cheats upon cheats. Should we be embarrassed or ashamed to confess
our delight with all these? Should we be upholding the search for truth and
only truth, and decry all these cinematic fabrications or opiates? Or should
we accept ourselves, and accept the cinema we so deeply wish to accept? To
put it differently: reality isn’t truth, so the imitation or cooking of reality
through “reality”-making is no evasion of truth. “Human kind cannot bear
very much reality,” sang T. S. Eliot.
As concluding example, I take a cinematic moment of trite sentimentality,
yet one that seized and transformed a generation of filmgoers and still,
repeated as it has so often been, manages to lift the spirit. Note: the thought
of it does not lift the spirit. The knowledge about it does not lift the spirit.
But as we actually watch it onscreen we are lifted. There can be no question
of how blatantly inauthentic it is, nor any doubt that the inauthenticity
bears the least weight of importance. This is the iconic instant in E.T. the
Extra-Terrestrial (1982) when basketed in the boy’s mini-bike, with little
Elliott frantically pedaling, E.T. causes the device to fly in front of the full
moon. Obviously an animation—-yet caused when, where, how, and by
whom we are not to see. The musical theme, already stirring, is here soaring
over its highest harmonic Alp. The moon is notably gigantic, silver yellow,
both radiant and mysterious and confounding. It is the moon over Los
Angeles, thus the movie moon, the moon that illuminates and substantiates
the transformative magic we are watching. The bike and its two riders are
fully, and only, a silhouette, thus a call-back to the nineteenth century as
much as a call forward to the future. The movement is the movement of
liberation, snapping one’s tether to conventional reality and to budgetary
constraint and to moral proscription and to the rule-guided business of the
everyday. It is also, of course, escape from noxious people who were quite
prepared to use rifles on the creature and on Elliott. And ultimately, it is
proof positive—within the narrative constraints, always present yet always
invisible—of the alien’s awesome power, his freedom from gravity, his ability
to protect against all evil, his beneficence without bound here shown in a
notably unbounded glyph.
Movie cheats are contingencies finally, always kept in treasure but always
lost. They hauntingly invoke the strange and plastic yesterday. They bravely
summon a strange and plastic tomorrow.
WORKS CITED
Albers, Josef. Interaction of Color. New Haven: Yale University Press, 2013.
Almendros, Nestor. A Man with a Camera. London: Faber & Faber, 1985.
Altick, Richard D. The Shows of London. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press, 1978.
Altman, Rick, ed. Sound Theory, Sound Practice. New York: Routledge, 1992.
Alton, John. Painting with Light. Berkeley: University of California Press, 2013.
Arthur, W. J. G. Ord-Hume. Clockwork Music: An Illustrated History of
Mechanical Musical Instruments. London: Allen & Unwin, 1973.
Bartsch, Shadi. The Mirror of the Self: Sexuality, Self-Knowledge, and the Gaze in
the Early Roman Empire. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2014.
Bazin, André. What Is Cinema? Vol. 1. Trans. Hugh Gray. Berkeley: University of
California Press, 2005.
Beck, Jay. Designing Sound: Audiovisual Aesthetics in 1970s American Cinema.
New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press, 2016.
Bell-Metereau, Rebecca. “Searching for Blobby Fissures: Slime, Sexuality, and the
Grotesque,” in Murray Pomerance, ed., BAD: Infamy, Darkness, Evil, and Slime
Onscreen, Albany: SUNY Press, 2004, 287–300.
Belton, John. “Technology and Aesthetics of Film Sound,” in Elisabeth Weis and
John Belton, eds., Film Sound: Theory and Practice, New York: Columbia
University Press, 1985, 63–75.
Benjamin, Walter. Charles Baudelaire: A Lyric Poet in the Era of High Capitalism.
Trans. Harry Zohn. London: Verso, 1997.
Benjamin, Walter. The Arcades Project. Trans. Howard Eiland and Kevin
McLaughlin. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999.
Berger, Peter L. and Thomas Luckmann. The Social Construction of Reality: A
Treatise in the Sociology of Knowledge. Garden City: Anchor, 1967.
Berman, Marshall. “Too Much Is Not Enough: Metamorphoses of Times Square,”
in Terry Smith, ed., Impossible Presence: Surface and Screen in the Photogenic
Era. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2001, 39–69.
Bordwell, David. “Intensified Continuity: Visual Style in Contemporary American
Film,” Film Quarterly 55: 3 (Spring 2002), 16–28.
Brewster, David. Letters on Natural Magic, Addressed to Sir Walter Scott, Bart.
London: John Murray, 1834.
Brown, Norman O. Love’s Body. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1966.
Brown, Norman O. Apocalypse and/or Metamorphosis. Berkeley: University of
California Press, 1991.
Burke, Kenneth. A Grammar of Motives. Berkeley: University of California Press,
1969 © 1945.
336 WORKS CITED
Carey, John. “Temporal and Spatial Transitions in American Fiction Film,” Studies
in the Anthropology of Visual Communication 1: 1 (1974), 45–50.
Cavell, Stanley. The World Viewed: Reflections on the Ontology of Film.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1982.
Cavell, Stanley. Little Did I Know: Excerpts from Memory. Stanford: Stanford
University Press, 2010.
Chion, Michel. Audio-Vision: Sound on Screen. Trans. Claudia Gorbman. New
York: Columbia University Press, 1994.
Chion, Michel. La toile trouée. Paris: Éditions de l’Étoile, 1996.
Chion, Michel. The Voice in Cinema. Trans. Claudia Gorbman. New York:
Columbia University Press, 1999.
Clark, Kenneth. The Nude: A Study in Ideal Form. New York: Pantheon,
1956.
Crafton, Donald. “Pie and Chase: Gag, Spectacle and Narrative in Slapstick
Comedy,” in Kristine Brunovska Karnick and Henry Jenkins, eds., Classical
Hollywood Comedy, New York: Routledge, 1994, 106–19.
Dastur, Françoise. “Phenomenology of the Event: Waiting and Surprise,” Hypatia
15: 4 (Autumn 2000), 178–89.
DeRosa, Steven. Writing with Hitchcock: The Collaboration of Hitchcock and John
Michael Hayes. N.P.: CineScribe Media, 2011.
Dixon, Wheeler Winston. It Looks At You: The Returned Gaze of Cinema. Albany:
SUNY Press, 1995.
Durkheim, Émile. The Division of Labor in Society. Trans. W. D. Halls. New York:
Free Press, 1997 © 1933.
Durrell, Lawrence. Justine. London: Penguin, 1991.
Ellis, Bret Easton. Glamorama. New York: Vintage, 2000.
Eyman, Scott. The Speed of Sound: Hollywood and the Talkie Revolution 1926–
1930. New York: Simon & Schuster, 2015.
Fielding, Raymond. The Technique of Special Effects Cinematography. New York:
Focal Press, 1965.
Fiedler, Leslie A. The Return of the Vanishing American. New York: Stein & Day,
1968.
Fiedler, Leslie A. Freaks: Myths and Images of the Secret Self. New York: Simon &
Schuster, 1978.
Fried, Michael. Absorption and Theatricality: Painting and Beholder in the Age of
Diderot. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1980.
Galsworthy, John. The Forsyte Saga. Auckland: The Floating Press, 2009.
Garfinkel, Harold. “Passing and the Managed Achievement of Sex Status in an
Intersexed Person, Part 1,” in Studies in Ethnomethodology, Englewood Cliffs:
Prentice-Hall, 1967, 116–85.
Gay, Peter. The Naked Heart: The Bourgeois Experience Victoria to Freud. New
York: W. W. Norton, 1996.
Gay, Peter. Pleasure Wars: The Bourgeois Experience: Victoria to Freud. New York:
W. W. Norton, 1998.
Gibson, Walker. “Authors, Speakers, Reader, and Mock Readers,” College English
11 (1950), 265–69.
Goffman, Erving. “On Cooling the Mark Out: Some Aspects of Adaptation to
Failure,” Psychiatry 15: 4 (1952), 451–63.
WORKS CITED 337
Perkins, V. F. Film as Film: Understanding and Judging Movies. New York: DaCapo
Press, 1993.
Pirandello, Luigi. Shoot! (Si gira): The Notebooks of Serafino Gubbio,
Cinematograph Operator. New York: E. P. Dutton, © 1926 (Chicago: University
of Chicago Press, 2005).
Pomerance, Murray. An Eye for Hitchcock. New Brunswick: Rutgers University
Press, 2004.
Pomerance, Murray. The Eyes Have It: Cinema and the Reality Effect. New
Brunswick: Rutgers University Press, 2013.
Pomerance, Murray. The Man Who Knew Too Much. London: BFI, 2016.
Pomerance, Murray. “Bells Are Ringing: Rear Projection and Audience
Engagement,” Film International 15: 4 (February 2018), 37–55.
Pomerance, Murray. Cinema, If You Please: The Memory of Taste, the Taste of
Memory. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2018.
Pomerance, Murray. Virtuoso: Film Performance and the Actor’s Magic. New York:
Bloomsbury, 2019.
Rickitt, Richard. Special Effects: The History and Technique. New York: Billboard,
2007.
Ryave, A. Lincoln and James N. Schenkein. “Notes on the Art of Walking,” in Roy
Turner, ed., Ethnomethodology, London: Penguin, 1974, 265–74.
Sacks, Oliver. “The Lost Mariner,” in The Man Who Mistook His Wife for a Hat
and Other Clinical Tales, New York: Simon & Schuster 1998, 23–42.
Salt, Barry. Film Style and Technology: History and Analysis. Second ed.. London:
Starword, 1992.
Schatz, Thomas. Hollywood Genres: Formulas, Filmmaking, and the Hollywood
System. New York: McGraw-Hill, 1981.
Scheff, Thomas J. “Audience Awareness and Catharsis in Drama,” The
Psychoanalytical Review 63: 4 (Winter 1976–77), 529–54.
Schivelbusch, Wolfgang. The Railway Journey: The Industrialization of Time and
Space in the Nineteenth Century. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1986.
Schivelbusch, Wolfgang. Disenchanted Night: The Industrialization of Light in the
Nineteenth Century. Trans. Angela Davies. Berkeley: University of California
Press, 1995.
Sinclair, Iain. American Smoke: Journeys to the End of the Light. New York: Farrar,
Straus & Giroux, 2013.
Solomon, Matthew. “Laughing Silently,” in Murray Pomerance, ed., The Last
Laugh: Strange Humors of Cinema, Detroit: Wayne State University Press, 2013,
15–29.
Starobinski, Jean. The Living Eye. Trans. Arthur Goldhammer. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 1989.
Steimatsky, Noa. The Face on Film. New York: Oxford University Press, 2017.
Sternberger, Dolf. Panorama, oder Ansichten von 19. Jahrhundert. 3rd ed.
Hamburg: Claassen & Goverts, 1946.
Strachey, Lytton. Eminent Victorians. New York: G. P. Putnam’s Sons, 1918.
Sudnow, David. Ways of the Hand: The Organization of Improvised Conduct.
Cambridge: M.I.T. Press, 1993.
Swift, Jonathan. Gulliver’s Travels into Several Remote Nations of the World.
London: J. Walker, 1815.
WORKS CITED 339
Truffaut, François. Hitchcock. Trans. Helen Scott. New York: Simon & Schuster,
1984.
Tuan, Yi-Fu. Space and Place: The Perspective of Experience. Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press, 2001.
Tuan, Yi-Fu. Romantic Geography: In Search of the Sublime Landscape. Madison:
University of Wisconsin Press, 2013.
Vaz, Mark Cotta and Craig Barron. The Invisible Art. San Francisco: Chronicle,
2002.
Vonnegut, Kurt Jr. The Sirens of Titan. New York: Dial Press, 1998.
Weis, Elisabeth and John Belton. Film Sound: Theory and Practice. New York:
Columbia University Press, 1985.
Worth, Sol and John Adair. Through Navajo Eyes: An Exploration in Film
Communication. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1972.
INDEX
Conversation, The (Francis Ford Day for Night ([La nuit américaine]
Coppola, 1974) 163 François Truffaut,
Conway, Jack 90 1973) 167, 173
Cooper, Gary 90, 165 Day-Lewis, Daniel 330
Cosgrove, Jack 201 Day of the Locust, The (John
Costner, Kevin 260 Schlesinger, 1975) 45
Côte d’Azur 222ff studio catastrophe scene 50–1,
Cotten, Joseph 64, 65, 66 173
Courtship of Eddie’s Father, The Day the Earth Stood Still, The (Robert
(Vincente Minnelli, Wise, 1951) 32, 65, 66, 303
1962) 237 Gort 240
Coward, Noël 58, 58 n.2 Dead Man (Jim Jarmusch, 1995) 279
Crafton, Donald 28 Deadpool (Tim Miller, 2016) 265
Craig, Daniel 105 Deakins, Roger A. 186
Crawford, Joan 32 n.3, 280, 322 Dean, James 304, 305, 325
Creature from the Black Lagoon, The death 304
(Jack Arnold, 1954) 150 De Balzac, Honoré, artist 201
Cries and Whispers (Ingmar Bergman, De Banzie, Brenda 227
1972) 185, 221–2 Debussy, Claude
Cronenberg, Brandon 151 n.1 “Arabesque No. 1 in E”
Crouching Tiger, Hidden Dragon (1888) 134
([Wo hu cang long] Ang Lee, Deer Hunter, The (Michael Cimino,
2000) 185 1978) 100
Cruise, Tom 3, 174, 303, 328, 333 De la Tour, Frances 273
Cuarón, Alfonso 186 Delicate Delinquent, The (Don
Cumberbatch, Benedict 324 McGuire, 1957) 326
Cunningham, Lodge 295 Dench, Judi 46, 84
Curtis, Tony 91, 131 n.1, 189, 280 De Niro, Robert 15–16, 100, 301
Cusack, John 180 Depp, Johnny 65, 143, 144, 150–2,
279
Damon, Matt 105, 161, 249, 313 Deren, Maya 282
Dances with Wolves (Kevin Costner, Dern, Bruce 179
1990) 185 Descartes, René [1596–1650],
Daniels, Jeff 21 n.1 deception 48, 253
Daniels, Leroy 55, 58 Destination Moon (Irving Pichel,
Daniels, William 171 1950) 302
Dark Knight Rises, The (Christopher Detective, The (Gordon Douglas,
Nolan, 2012) 262, 265 1968) 83
Darkman (Sam Raimi, 1990) 265 Detour (Edgar G. Ulmer,
Dastur, Françoise 279 1945) 254, 255
David and Lisa (Frank Perry, Deulen, Eric 105
1962) 135 De Vaucanson, Jacques 86
Davis, Bette 181, 295, 325 DeVito, Danny 100
Davis, Judy 162 Dhiegh, Khigh 328
Davitt, Theodora 139 Dial M for Murder (Alfred Hitchcock,
Davy, Humphrey 170 1954) 301
Dawn, Norman O. 214, 215 Diamonds Are Forever (Guy Hamilton,
Day, Doris 40ff, 156, 227, 228ff, 303 1971) 308
INDEX 345
Errand Boy, The (Jerry Lewis, 1961) Fiddler on the Roof (Norman Jewison,
“dubbing studio” sequence 1971) 184
139 15:17 to Paris, The (Clint Eastwood,
Escape from Alcatraz (Don Siegel, 2018) 163
1979) 321 Film as Film (V. F. Perkins) 73
Escape from L.A. (John Carpenter, Finney, Albert 89, 207
1996) 321 Fiore, Mauro 186
E.T. the Extra-Terrestrial (Steven Firewall (Richard Loncraine,
Spielberg, 1982) 237, 306, 2006) 226
321, 334 Fitzgerald, Geraldine 325
Evelyn, Judith 282 Five Easy Pieces (Bob Rafelson,
Expression of Emotions in Man 1970) 252
and Animals, The (Charles 5,000 Fingers of Dr. T., The (Roy
Darwin) 85 Rowland, 1953) 159
Extras (2005) 1 Florence Foster Jenkins (Stephen
Eye for Hitchcock, An (Murray Frears, 2016) 331
Pomerance) 2 Florida, swamps as setting 323
Eyes Wide Shut (Stanley Kubrick, Flowers and Trees (Burt Gillett,
1999) 303 1932) 239
Fly, The (Kurt Neumann, 1958) 283
FAA (Federal Aviation Flynn, Errol 100
Administration) 49 Foch, Nina 175
Fabray, Nanette 57ff Foley tracking 140
Face Off (2011) 84 n.4 Fonda, Peter 246
facial recognition aphasia 13–15 Fontaine, Joan 3
Family Plot (Alfred Hitchcock, Forbidden Planet (Fred McLeod
1976), downhill car Wilcox, 1956)
sequence 140, 179 Altair–4 302
Fanny and Alexander (Ingmar Altaira projection 270
Bergman, 1982) 185 Krell power room 240
Fantasia International Film Robbie the Robot 240–3
Festival 151 Ford, Harrison 144, 164
Fantasticks, The (Harvey Schmidt and Foreign Correspondent (Alfred
Tom Jones, Sullivan Street Hitchcock, 1940), umbrella
Playhouse, New York, May 3, sequence 163
1960) 325 Forster, Robert 273
Fapp, Daniel 275 Forsyte Saga, The (John
Farrell, Nicholas 46 Galsworthy) 109
Fehr, Rudi 295 Forsyte Saga The (2002) 117ff
Fellini Satyricon (Federico Fellini, Foster, Jodie 155, 162
1969) 73 Foxx, Jamie 174
Ferris Bueller’s Day Off (John Hughes, Frampton, Hollis 282
1986) 29 Francis, Freddie 185
Ferzetti, Gabriele 284, 284 Frankenstein (James Whale,
Festinger, Leon, cognitive 1931) 26, 82, 303
dissonance 290 Freed, Arthur 56
F for Fake (Orson Welles, 1973) Freed Unit at MGM (see
259 Hollywood, Studios)
INDEX 347
Red Shoes, The (Michael Powell Ronan, Saoirse 53, 111–12, 320
and Emeric Pressburger, Ronin (John Frankenheimer, 1998) 319
1948) 331, 333 Rooney, Mickey 251, 252
Ballet of the Red Shoes 331, 333 Roosevelt, Teddy, characterized 160
Rees, Roger 273 Rope (Alfred Hitchcock, 1948) 229
Reeves, Keanu 105 Rosemary’s Baby (Roman Polanski,
Regression (Alejandro Amenábar, 1968) 226
2015) 99, 191, 191–4 Ross, Katharine 144
Reimann, Walter 220 Roth, Tim 161
Remember (Atom Egoyan, Rousselot, Philippe 185
2015) 127, 132 Rush, Barbara 232
Renoir, Pierre-Auguste 168 Ruskin, John 27
Return of the Vanishing American, The Russell, Bertrand 247 n.1
(Leslie Fiedler), and American Russia 310, 314
literature 220 Ryan’s Daughter (David Lean,
Revenant, The (Alejandro G. Iñárritu, 1970) 184
2015) 186 Ryder, Winona 330
Reynolds, Debbie 65, 137, 140
Richard II (William Shakespeare) 2 Sabotage (Alfred Hitchcock, 1936) 329
Richard III (Laurence Olivier, Sabotage (David Ayer, 2014) 71,
1955) 322 318, 319
Richardson, Ian 207 Sabrina (Billy Wilder, 1954) 237–8
Richardson, Robert 185, 186 Sacco, Dan 100 n.1
Richter, Dan 37 Sacks, Oliver 14–15, 17
Ringwald, Molly 106 Saint, Eva Marie 107, 197
Ristovski, Lazar 309 Sandgren, Linus 186
River Runs Through It, A (Robert San Francisco 48, 276
Redford, 1992) 185 Santa Barbara, as location 180
Riviera, French, see Côte d’Azur Satie, Erik 313
Road Runner cartoons 26, see “Gnossiènnes” (c. 1895) 313
also Hollywood, studios, Saturday Review, The 120
Warner Bros. Saving Private Ryan (Steven Spielberg,
Road to Perdition (Sam Mendes, 1998) 185
2002) 185 Scarface (Brian De Palma, 1983) 319
Robbins, Jerome 275 Scheff, Thomas 23 n.1
Robinson, Nick 106 “ladder of awareness” 42, 48
Rohmer, Éric (Maurice Scheider, Roy 101, 163
Schérer) 21 n.1 Schell, Maximilian 94
Röhrig, Walter 220 Schindler’s List (Steven Spielberg,
Roma (Alfonso Cuarón, 2018) 186, 226 1993) 185
Romance and the “Yellow Peril” (Gina Schivelbusch, Wolfgang
Marchetti) 90 light 167–8
Roman Spring of Mrs. Stone, The (José panoramic perception 199ff
Quintero, 1961) 327 Schlesinger, John 51
Rome 327 Schwarzenegger, Arnold 100, 319
Trevi Fountain 327 Scofield, Paul 314
Romeo and Juliet (William Scorsese, Martin 15–16
Shakespeare) 325 Scott, Campbell 1, 7
INDEX 359