Constitutionalism and the Rule of Law
Constitutionalism and the Rule of Law
Constitutionalism and the Rule of Law
BYU ScholarsArchive
Faculty Publications
1986
This Working Paper is brought to you for free and open access by BYU ScholarsArchive. It has been accepted for
inclusion in Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of BYU ScholarsArchive. For more information,
please contact [email protected].
CONSTITUTIONALISM AND THE RULE OF LAW
1986/87?
Noel B. Reynolds
Abstract:
Constitutionalism is the practical science of designing and balancing institutions of public
power and authority so as to prevent monopolies of power or the emergence of tyranny. In spite
of continuing attempts to ground constitutions in moralistic political theories, they are best
understood as formalizations of citizenry agreements to manage their affairs under the rule of law
following rules formulated by their legislatures and applied by their judges, all of which are to be
selected through established procedures. The emergence of rule of law in primitive societies and
in early modern European politics is noted, and the chief contributors to the twentieth century
discussion are identified.
Key Words: constitutionalism, rule of law, natural law, primitive law, F. A. Hayek, Francis
Wormuth, Ronald Dworkin, Charles McIlwain
The bicentennial of the Constitution of the United States of America invites our reflection
on the extraordinary historical success of this document and its attendant institutions. In the
history of mankind, it stands alone as the most successful of the sustained experiments in human
Such reflections may take on some urgency when we note the reduced level of basic
constitutional wisdom which prevails among both the politicians, who are most directly
responsible for maintaining the Constitution, and the political theorists, who provide our political
culture with its self-understanding. It seems that the eighteenth century may have seen the high
tide of such understanding in the western world. And the American Founders were without peer
In this essay I will attempt to articulate the underlying principles which account for the
success of the American constitutional experiment and indeed for similar freedoms that have
been achieved in different degrees and for varying lengths of times in human polities throughout
the world. The same analysis, by contrast, will serve to illuminate failures to achieve freedom
elsewhere.
One indication of the decline in understanding of these matters over the last century
occurs in the current edition of an authoritative reference work. The author announces somewhat
disdainfully that "constitutionalism is the name given to the trust which men repose in the power
of words engrossed on parchment to keep a government in order."1 Armed with such a narrow
definition it is no wonder that the author is able to insist that "the rise of constitutionalism may
be dated from 1776."2 From this most unpromising beginning the author goes on to develop a
cynical account of the means by which clever lawyers and judges transform the doctrines of the
Constitution over time to make of the document a useful instrument of social control. As if the
Constitution had been intended as a repository or oracle for doctrines to settle all future questions
of fundamental law! The appalling ignorance reflected in this authoritative source is only one
freedom, we can find numerous historical examples of its achievement within the framework of
rule of law and constitutional devices. This is important because it emphasizes the universality
Primitive Societies
problem in human societies, the problem of controlling the rulers. That there should be no rulers
or government is a thought comprehensible only to a few theorists locked away in their ivory
towers. That rulers need to be restrained has been the eventual discovery of every society.
2
3
Because of their distance from modern society primitive cultures are often used to
identify those elements of human societies which are universal. Studies of primitive political
systems reveal constitutional arrangements which are designed to prevent the emergence of any
single individual or group as a tyrant, while simultaneously providing for the necessary
Our primitive brothers have access to one important control on their authorities that we
have lost in modern secularized society--the requirement that they maintain the approval of the
gods. The disapproval of the gods can be discovered by councils of priests consulting oracles or
interpreting natural or social events. As one might expect, there are always very practical
In most primitive societies political power is balanced and authority is distributed for the
various kinds of community decisions which must be made. Councils are used in most cases to
provide representative decisions. Elaborate rituals of rebellion are enacted annually in some
monarchical societies to remind the king of his dependence on the support of the people. And
without exception kings, chiefs, and councils are not authorized to change the laws and customs
of the people. Furthermore, they are required to enforce those laws and customs and to obey
them in the conduct of their own affairs. The common wisdom of primitive man seems to be that
It might be thought that these primitive constitutional arrangements are ageless as they
occur in different societies. This common western belief proves to be a myth as observers note
the ongoing shifting of such arrangements in almost all such societies. Primitive peoples have
never been immune to the dynamic forces of nature and society that impose continual change on
4
their conditions of life. Wars, plagues, famines, and migrations disturb the important power
balances that have been worked out at any given point in time requiring that new arrangements
emerge.
Lucy Mair's studies of this process of change would support the conclusion that in times
elements of their societies to restructure their political system and regain constitutional balance.3
This is not to assert that such experimentation never misfires. But the politicization of social
clubs or councils and the transformation of functions of existing political institutions goes on
endlessly in the quest to balance power and authority within a continually changing society. The
suggestion for us is that the constitutional problem is an endless one never to be resolved once
For example, the Iroquois suffered a major historical crisis when their ill-fated alliance
with the English in the Revolutionary War forced them to leave the United States. Originally the
Iroquois had no central government but only a ceremonial council of fifty chiefs. Because the
English would only deal with the Iroquois through a single authoritative leader in the making of
treaties, the Iroquois responded by conferring upon the council more and more specialized
political functions and claiming for that council a monopoly of the representative right in
dealings with the British. As time went on other problems emerged. The fur supply declined and
the Iroquois resorted to war with distant Indian tribes to protect their control of the fur trade. To
maintain these wars standing war chiefs were established. The British government first gave the
Iroquois a Canadian endowment which embraced 12,000 square miles, but they were later forced
onto a vastly smaller seventy square mile reservation. Again the council responded with the
5
development of specialized offices. A welfare chief was appointed, then a forest warden, and so
forth.4
systems of many African tribes. Hilda Kuper found the constitutional arrangements of the Swazi
of South Africa focused on a form of dual monarchy in which the king, or Great Lion, shared
every prerogative with his mother.5 The queen mother, or Lady Elephant, had her own courts,
counselors, and troops, as well as some authority over the king. The queen mother actually
functioned as a court of appeal and would be replaced by her own sister or daughter should she
die. In addition to the balance of the dual monarchy there were permanent councils composed of
the heads of the various lineages that were also involved in decision making with the king.
Rituals of rebellion have been observed among certain African tribes and the Natchez
Indians of Louisiana. Max Gluckman reports that the king of the Zulu was required to make an
annual wandering through the villages of his kingdom naked and without arms or supplies.6 As
he appeared in each village he would be persecuted and even threatened with spears and abused
with language ordinarily reserved for the most vile members of this society. This ritual reminds
a king of the precariousness of his position and that a real rebellion may lead both to his death
and his replacement. If in fact he returns safely from the tour, he resumes his kingly regalia,
receives the praise of his people, and is reinstated in his position. But he has been sharply
warned that he must always remember to seek the welfare of his people.Classical
Constitutionalism
The failure to see the antiquity of constitutionalism is directly related to the failure to see
this institutional balancing of the social decision making process as its essence. Constitutional
6
thought, in this sense, was explicitly developed among the ancient Greeks and Romans, as
evidenced not only in the writings of Plato, Aristotle, Polybius, and others, but also in political
institutions over a period of many centuries. It seems clear that Plato saw that a primary function
of government was to protect and maintain the law of the people.7 He furthermore explicitly
discussed the various institutional designs that might be used to achieve this, namely monarchy,
aristocracy, and democracy. His almost casual, yet sophisticated, treatment of these concepts
betrays his assumption that his contemporary audience understood these matters completely and
that little detailed explanation was necessary. As Plato went on to name the corrupted forms of
his three constitutional regimes, he clearly saw the source of corruption in their failure to
maintain the rule of law as they fell into tyrannical practices. Plato was not an optimist; he
seemed to believe that each of the good regimes bore within itself the seeds of its own
destruction--a view of all worldly constitutions which Bentham echoed in the nineteenth century,
asserting that only the constitution of the Anglo-American United States "affords a reasonable
Because Plato wrote in dialogue form, his views in these matters are not as apparent as
those of his student, Aristotle, who used the philosophical treatise. To Plato's notion of a general
cycling through the different regimes and their corruptions, Aristotle added the idea of mixed
government wherein the democratic, aristocratic, and monarchical elements of the state could be
mixed into one regime which could have the potential for sustained balance of constitutional
power. The Aristotelian idea of mixed government formed the basis for classical constitutional
theory in conjunction with the commitment to the principle of rule of law.9 The idea was revived
and revitalized in modern Europe, particularly England, and even served as a guiding ideal to the
7
American founding fathers who struggled with the problem of institutional balancing in a society
Plato and Aristotle were writing within a tradition that had long treasured law and the
principle of rule of law. The early Greeks credited their laws to their divine ancestors and
therefore gave no earthly mortal a right to change those laws. The ancient poet, Pindar,
expressed that Greek view--"The law is king of all."10 In the early history of the Athenian
constitution the commitment to law was a constant. Over time a wide variety of political
institutions emerged to secure and maintain that law including monarchy, aristocracy, and
democracy. Even though none of these had authority to change the ancient law it was under
constant revision through one or another process of interpretation. But as late as the fifth century
the ancient Athenians maintained constitutional watch-dog bodies that could punish a magistrate
We know more about the law of ancient Rome, but find in it the same type of
constitutional commitments used by the Greeks. Private law was the original source for all
Roman law. The public law, as it developed, was conceived as a form of generalized private
contract. Government structures were developed over time explicitly to maintain and enforce the
law. This pattern is strikingly analogous to that of English common law centuries later. But as
time went on and the Romans enjoyed international success they had to adapt their law to
imperial circumstances. They adopted new fictions which allowed the emperor to announce the
will of the people, the recognized ultimate basis of all Roman law.
The later reputation of Roman absolutism unjustly descends from this Justinian
formulation. But the true Roman doctrine which was reasserted in the Middle Ages was that the
8
populace is the source of all law and that any public law and especially any tax must be based on
consent. One of the great twentieth century scholars of constitutionalism, Charles H. McIlwain,
concluded that "whatever our modern laws may be, Rome is the source of our jurisprudence, and
whatever our form of government, Greece has furnished us the main outlines of our political
science."11
Medieval Constitutionalism
The constitutional struggles of the Middle Ages were carried on at two different but
interrelated levels. On the international level the popes struggled with the emperors and the
kings while on the national level kings struggled with their own people. The story is far too long
and too complicated to be even summarized here, beyond noting that with respect to the papal
struggles the kings eventually won the right of approval for the appointment of bishops as well as
the right to rule over the bishops within their territory.12 Furthermore, as a concession to the
secular authorities, the selection of popes was finally regularized by a rule requiring the
agreement of two thirds of all the cardinals. The papal argument that all legitimate political
authority is derived from and subject to the pope and the view that all material goods in the world
are ultimately owned by the pope so that all earthly rulers are stewards to the pope--as advanced
John of Paris produced the most important constitutional analysis of the age. He
responded to this logical and perverse extreme, arguing that the pope is only a steward for the
Christian community and its properties. Following Aquinas, he saw in civil government intrinsic
dignity without any claim to ecclesiastical derivations, and concluded, therefore, in favor of a
justified popes in their spiritual censuring of kings and encouraged the deposition of wicked
monarchs. But kings, he thought, could assist the cardinals in deposing an evil pope by force of
arms! John was successful in bringing to the constitutional theory of the middle ages a view
which was consonant with developments within the individual kingdoms. The best government
in both church and state is representative and responsible to the people and protective of their
laws.
The classic doctrine of a mixed state died out as a political institution during the Middle
Ages except in the Italian republics. Yet the idea was kept very much alive in literature as
medieval writers tended to recall the successes of the Roman Republic. Aquinas argued that
mixed government was the form of rule provided by God for the Israelites. John of Paris
continued the defense of mixed government in his constitutional writings. The anti-papal writers
in the Conciliar controversy even went so far as to argue that the Church should develop a form
of mixed government. And finally, the Renaissance writers such as Machiavelli and Erasmus
succeeded in making the notion of a mixed state commonplace, even though the medieval pattern
The dualistic nature of medieval kingship probably resulted from the military
organization of the Teutonic tribes in the early Middle Ages. The kings, as military leaders, held
personal rule; and the business of government devolved upon the king as part of his household
responsibilities. Every subject was personally tied to his king with a bond of allegiance.
As the story is similar throughout Europe, the English experience can be representative.
Before the advent of feudalism, vast areas of life in England were organized without any
reference to the king. Land was owned outright by allodial tenure. The kings did not even enjoy
10
the right of taxation until the tenth century. And folk courts carried the responsibility for law
enforcement serving almost like private arbitration boards or tribunals. Clearly the political
function of the king was extremely limited and the law of the people was the primary source of
social control.
The early feudal kings attempted to redefine their political relationship to their subjects in
terms of a divided land title and to convert kingship into a legal office. The late medieval
struggles between the kings and the barons resulted in kings retaining position as a personal
rulers entitled to personal allegiance--but with limited power. Property retained its traditional
autonomy so that taxation never became a royal right, but took the form of a voluntary grant
given through parliament to the king. By virtue of his office, the king assumed responsibility for
the administration of the law, but his judges could only enforce the existing rules and analogies
of land law. They could not carry out new conflicting orders of the king.
Scholars have attempted a variety of analyses to explain this form of limited monarchy
that occurred in these middle centuries. The English jurist, John Fortescue, saw this as a
combination of "royal and constitutional rule," or in other words, a monarchy in which the king
ruled and made laws only with the assent of his subjects. Fortescue used this constitutional
feature to distinguish between the royal rule of France and the limited monarchy of England.
One modern scholar of medieval political theory treats the same idea under the rubric of
"double majesty."13 Gierke believed the various theories of double majesty emerged as means of
imposing limits on kings. But in the Middle Ages, two of these were most prominent--both
deriving from Roman sources. It was characteristic of medieval writers to assert natural or
universal law as a limitation on the prince. This ancient Stoic view had some influence,
11
especially with philosophers at different points in time. But the more compelling legal view was
the notion that law and the right to rule derive from the people in accordance with the ancient
McIlwain prefers to use Bracton's medieval distinction between qubernaculum the king's
unlimited sphere of action, and jurisdictio, that sphere within which the king is bound by law,
whether it be natural law or custom.14 The Achilles' heel of limited government in England was
the absence of an institutional device that could restrain the king. What could the barons do
when the king exceeded the understood limits? History shows that rebellion was their only real
McIlwain explains the breakdown of the medieval constitution as the outcome of a long
struggle between monarchs and subjects to extend their respective spheres of government at the
expense of the other. The tide of royal despotism crested in the sixteenth century with the royal
promotion of doctrines of unlimited obedience to kings and of divine right of kings. This trend
came to a head in the early seventeenth century with James I's assertion that the liberties of the
McIlwain does not believe that constitutional limitation could have survived had it not
been for several unique characteristics of English political and legal life. The incredible
toughness of English common law proved adequate to resist the royal attack. Determined
English judges in the late sixteenth century refused to obey explicit orders from the monarch on
the ground that they were of no force being "against the law of the land," and got away with it
until the Stuarts gained control. The religious schisms of the times led dissenters, most notably
12
Puritans, to revive old hostilities toward tyranny, bringing the defenders of law into an alliance
Although Parliament had not yet come into existence as an independent institution,
defenders of law such as Coke and Wentworth asserted as early as 1621 that Parliament was the
voice of the people--the essential premise of government on the Roman legal model. As the
courts began to cave in to the Stuart monarchs, giving them discretion to make gubernaculum
supreme over jurisdictio, double majesty was abandoned and revolution appeared to be the only
course left open to the parliamentarians. How else could they deal with the star chamber denials
Modern Constitutionalism
constitutional speculation spawned by the English civil wars.15 The Cromwellian years were
bicameralism, among many other principles and institutional devices. Though written at this
early date, James Harrington's Oceana served as a major inspiration for the American founders,
and notably John Adams. Many of the constitutional ideas which later came to fruition in the
American experience first had a serious hearing in England at this time. But they were largely
Republican thinking was not eliminated, but was preserved more in the principles than in the
institutions of politics. The Glorious Revolution formalized this arrangement in 1688 bringing to
13
an end once and for all the claims of English monarchs to any absolute right of rule.
Unfortunately, there was not sufficient foresight to provide against Parliament's filling the
vacuum.
There is little doubt that eighteenth century America was the setting for the historical high
point of constitutionalism. Never before or probably since have such broad segments of a single
population understood and valued the essential principles of the rule of law and the notion that
the arrangement of political institutions can best serve as the fundamental device for protecting
views of the men who produced the constitution of 1787. A few years ago I had the opportunity
of conversing at some length with a noted English historian and political theorist who made some
comments on the American revolution and constitution. But his account sounded more like a
description of the French experience after 1789. With some gentle probing I established to my
dismay that my friend actually believed that the American Constitution features abstract
announcements of natural law principles, and that the basic rationale used by the Americans for
declaring their independence was an appeal to nature and political theory. He was astonished and
even somewhat incredulous as I tried to point out that at no point does the American constitution
advance any principle of natural law or political theory, that it only specifies the respective
functions of and limitations on the various governmental agencies which it creates, and that the
revolution itself was quite deliberately justified in terms of the violation of the colonists' legal
rights as Englishmen by the Crown in abuse of its lawful authority. The opening sentence of the
Declaration announcing that all men are created equal cannot outweigh all the rest. It is certainly
14
true that the American founders did hold ideologies which included various principles of natural
and divine law. But their constitutional documents do not mention these, and certainly do not
The debates over the American Constitution provide us with some of the best discussions
of the basic rationale for constitutionalist theory, and James Madison provided the clearest and
most widely used examples of that rationale.16 Scholars are at least partially correct in tracing the
intellectual inspiration of American political thinkers to such writers as Locke, Montesquieu, and
the English radicals. But they are only now coming to realize the extent to which the Scottish
philosophers, and particularly David Hume, produced the theoretical insights which guided the
founders. The Constitution is not a Lockean contract. Rather it is an attempt, in the American
context, to achieve the kind of institutional balancing and protection of law so esteemed by
Hume in his History of England and Political Essays.17 One author has found throughout
Madison's and Hamilton's writings repeated references and borrowings from Hume, even beyond
the point where his arguments were relevant to the American context.18
A decade of experience with themselves and the Articles of Confederation had disabused
these American luminaries of any unwarranted optimism about their own abilities to stand aloof
from self-interest that might have been generated during their remarkable revolution. As they
drew themselves reluctantly back into the folds of Hume's philosophy, Madison's lament that
men are not angels became again an American commonplace. That basic assumption about the
nature of man or the expectations that we might have for human behavior lies at the very root of
constitutionalist thought. For if men will not abuse power and are capable of error free decision
making, there is no need of a constitution. Madison certainly did not claim that every man would
15
necessarily abuse power when given the opportunity. But, from a statistical point of view, he
would say that any institution which permitted or rewarded the abuse of power would eventually
This assumption about man shapes constitutionalist thought at several levels. Whether
articulated or not it is the insight that compels all human societies to recognize that laws are
essential for human interaction. Not only are men generally incapable of coming to a full
agreement on general moral principles of conduct, but they are even less capable of consistently
adhering to those principles once established. And so, law becomes necessary to make life in
society tenable. Law becomes a substitute for that moral and intellectual ideal which the human
imagination continually generates anew. Given the nature of man, law is the highest form of
with coercive power create a second level on which human selfishness and power lust can act out
their course. Constitutionalist thinkers have recognized the necessity of institutional constraints
on public authorities to prevent them from corrupting the rule of law. Legal rules limiting the
officials are of no value if there are no institutional procedures and balancing arrangements that
check them from corrupting the rules through arbitrary and self-interested interpretations.
For a society to maintain its laws over time, it must agree in advance on the procedures
and officials by which future disputes under the law will be decided. The community must also
determine how those officials will be selected at any point in time. These are constitutional
choices. But the science of constitutionalism focuses most importantly on a third choice--the
16
arrangements for balancing governmental institutions to prevent them from degenerating into
perverse instruments for advancing the private fortunes of government officials or a privileged
class.
Francis Wormuth was one of the first to help contemporary scholars see that the essence
of constitutionalism is this concern with "auxiliary precautions" as they were called by James
Madison or "contrivances which not only describe but confine government, at least in its
everyday activities."19 F. A. Hayek eventually came very close to this when he defined
constitutional law as a superstructure erected to secure the maintenance of the law, rather than
the source of all other law.20 McIlwain was less sensitive to the problem of institutional devices
studies of the English constitution clearly indicate that he saw the weakness of the English
constitution in its failure to develop institutions which could balance the governing authority of
the king over a period of four centuries.21 Much less appreciation for this definition is evident in
the writings of Tom Paine, for example, who saw constitutions as "antecedent to a government"
Because constitutions set the conditions for law making, it is commonly assumed that
laws are somehow derivative from and subsequent to constitutions. But the opposite view is
more easily defended from the historical record which shows that law usually precedes a
constitution. It is specifically to preserve the law and the regular administration of law that
constitutions have been designed. The whole point of a constitution is to protect the law of the
people which seems to be threatened by their rulers. The examples of the endless series of
medieval charters such as Magna Carta comes to mind where the people would rise up--not to
17
overthrow the king--but to compel him to promise to maintain and respect the law or "the
liberties of the people." History credits those wise conquerors who have preserved the law of the
conquered nations. This was the wisdom of the Romans and the Norman invaders of Britain.
of moralistic political theory committed to the task of discovering the correct fundamental
principles for reconciling liberty and equality. This latter moralistic enterprise has virtually
consumed the attention of our political and legal philosophers today. Few of these are concerned
to identify practical institutional devices that would prevent the kinds of inequities or violations
of right on which they focus. Rather their concern is to find some philosophical principle which
I do not question that this is an interesting and worthwhile enterprise. But to see its
connection with reality, we must remember that legal and constitutional thought have to start
from a recognition that people do not always act on the basis of disinterested moral principle.
Our experience teaches us that they act from self-interest and that before morality can become a
guiding feature of social life, self-interest must be controlled in practical ways. We will not pave
the way to Utopia by finally discovering the true philosophical account of justice. Rather, Utopia
could only be possible in a world where men had ceased to pursue self-interest at the expense of
others, where they had ceased to be men, and had become angels.
Much of the contemporary failure to recognize institutional safeguards as the true basis of
our freedoms stems from our uncritical acceptance of the claims of the moralistic enterprise.
One European historian praises the French Declaration of the Rights of Man of 1789 specifically
because it "is concerned with the rights of man, not the rights of the citizen." In other words it
18
focuses on "universal human rights" which focus will in time produce "the new man" and "the
new citizen."23
De Ruggiero gives us here a marvelous example of the naivete of the extreme liberal
view that once people hear the moral truth, they will naturally conform their lives and social
institutions to it. Where would the Americans be today if Madison had believed that?
It is not likely that we could find in the eighteenth century a document which reflects a
stronger commitment to the principles of freedom under law than does the French Declaration of
the Rights of Man. Yet the French Revolution failed to produce that freedom. My argument is
that a significant part of the reason for that failure is that the announcement of true political
government is not properly designed and balanced to prevent the emergence of a tyrant, the
principles will be interpreted by officials who are free to use the power of government to pursue
their own ends, and the principles will be as nothing. James Madison repeatedly referred to
Certainly the Americans believed in most of the principles announced so confidently to the world
by the French. But they mention none of them in their own Constitution. Upon reflection we can
see in their work profound evidence of the genius and effectiveness of centuries of constitutional
experience in England and colonial America. The Americans set their hands directly to the
problem of designing an internal balance and complication of decision making processes that
There is among English speaking populations a simple rule for dividing a cake which
epitomizes their constitutional wisdom. The rule does not say the cake must be divided evenly or
19
that it should be divided on some other principle of fairness. The rule simply says, "He who cuts
the cake must choose his piece last." This rule is no less concerned with equality and fairness
than is the liberal French rhetoric. But without mentioning such principles it brings them far
No legal theorist has attracted more attention in the last twenty years than has Ronald
Dworkin.25 Yet Dworkin has publicly urged the Supreme Court and judges generally to see their
responsibility to reach behind the law to the unquestionably true principle of equality to guide
them in the resolution of difficult cases.26 This dangerous course can only serve to provide
rationalizations for those that would promote their own political and moral views through law
and in the process create legal confusion and destroy our ability to predict the legal implications
constitutionalism, fails radically to see that the root of law is not moral truth. It is rather
convention, agreement, which may or may not be derived from the popular morality, but it is
emphatically not natural law. This may be a pessimistic view; but it is nonetheless true that it is
the lot of men in communities to live by law as a substitute for moral truth.
To live by moral truth as a community seems beyond us. And as every primitive society
and historical culture that has achieved freedom under a constitution has discovered, that
freedom has come through institutional design and balance and not through philosophical or
ethical discoveries.
The kind of attack that I have made on constitutional articulations of abstract rights or
metalegal principles is easily misunderstood and may need clarification. In the first place I
20
should stipulate that it is not an attack on the idea or the existence of rights. Rather, most
constitutionalists do assume that people have rights. Furthermore, I strongly endorse moral
rights. I believe that pro rights propaganda efforts are a very positive contribution to political
society and provide necessary encouragement for the maintenance and protection of those rights
However, on the basis of practical considerations we must reject the abstract rights
public authorities from corrupting the law. It is the law which articulates our liberties or rights.
argument is based on the observation that only institutional balancing has any real effect.
Furthermore, I would argue on the negative side that statements of abstract rights are potentially
very mischievous, this because an unchecked authority can interpret such general statements of
right to suit its own interest and then exploit the sweeping substantive language. The liberals
who do not believe this should remind themselves of the substantive due process reasoning
developed by conservative American judges near the end of the last century.
A further practical reason for avoiding the abstract rights approach is that it requires
theoretical agreement on the content and justification of the rights protected for adoption.
making can be reached between parties which might never be able to reach agreement on their
reasons or justifications for those policies, or their theories about rights. A moralistic approach
articulations thereof in constitutional documents has far lower prospects for developing adequate
popular support for any single theory to be adopted. We can agree much more quickly on
This has an essential and positive function. The error of many moralistic philosophers lies in
their uncritical jump from abstract moral thought to constitutional theorizing. I do not
necessarily disagree with their moral views. But I believe they are too often naive about
The most frequent mistake of the moralistic philosophers in making that jump is the
assumption of benevolence which sneaks in unnoticed. Rawls, for example, acknowledges that
there will be strains placed on the contract from the poor, but he does not anticipate the strains
which will come from the better off, who are being taxed to help the poor. The assumption of
approaches to constitutions, which overlook the problem of human nature at its crucial point of
application.
The constitutional problem is a permanent feature of human society which can never,
even in principle, be finally solved once and for all. There will never be one perfect institutional
design which will solve the problem of tyranny forever. As described above, human nature is
such that inventive men seeking their own interests will always find ways to work new angles
and corrupt or undermine institutional arrangements which may have functioned successfully in
the past. Natural or external events can also dramatically affect the artificial balances of a
constitution as migrations bring cultural mixing, or as famines, wars, and plagues change the
22
configuration of populations and the conditions of life. Economic growth has a similar effect.
permanent problem, it is essential that we pay attention to it in a systematic way and preserve the
wisdom that the centuries have brought us for dealing with these changes.
Finally, all constitutionalist thought assumes that law is the appropriate response to the
problems of human nature and community. The rule of law creates the context of freedom
whereby individual men may pursue moral perfection as they understand it without inflicting
their own views of perfection on others. Law is the means by which we prevent arbitrary or
willful interventions in the lives of individuals by those who must necessarily be chosen to
It could reasonably be argued that the beliefs of ordinary people influence the fortunes of
successful constitutional regimes has been a cultural commitment to rule of law. For a
constitution to succeed the community belief systems must support its aims. There must be a
commitment to the law and rule of law. "Constitutionalism means that all power rests on the
It is the absence of that cultural commitment among the people themselves which
explains the ongoing failure of Latin American attempts to imitate the American constitution. In
too many countries, the oppressive culture of the strong man is ingrained in the people. Even
when the peasants successfully revolt and come to power, they turn the tables and become
themselves oppressors, not only of their vanquished predecessors but of their own class, in a
23
cycle which has played itself out now for two centuries. Solzhenitsyn attributes the amazingly
cultural defect.28
The eighteenth century Americans, on the contrary, had the benefit of cultural
constitutionalism. A century of benign neglect had allowed them to develop de facto institutions
for self-government as well as inflated views of what their legal rights as Englishmen might be.
When the central government undertook to restore firm control over the colonies after 1760, it
was too late. And when the newly independent Americans undertook to form a new government,
they remembered that good government requires some private sacrifices. The Americans of the
late eighteenth century enjoyed a unique heritage in that they understood the dependence of
freedom upon rule of law and constitutional government, while they were also willing to make
some personal sacrifices to establish and maintain a republican form of government. Most of
At mid-century it might well have seemed that serious interest in the idea of rule of law
was almost dead among intellectuals. The concept had fallen into disuse, and the understanding
of that concept was certainly in decline among legal and political philosophers. The ideology of
democracy and equality had taken over center stage in the discussions of academicians.
However, in 1960 F. A. Hayek published an analysis of rule of law that went beyond anything
developed by earlier thinkers.29 Since Hayek's book other notable scholars have made further
statements on the subject. In 1964 Lon Fuller identified certain principles, or norms, which
24
analysis of rule of law that was also partially derived from Hayek's discussion.31 Finally in 1975
John Rawls used the notion to bolster his process theory of justice, even though he treats the
subject from a moralistic point of view.32 In his 1980 book, John Finnis used the idea of law to
try to bridge the classic gap between accounts of natural law and natural rights.33 And in 1983
Michael Oakeshott published the essay which brings formal discussion of the issues to its highest
level.34 But most political and legal philosophers continue to ignore this issue and do not put
essential that we develop an adequate account of the concept. On the face of it there are
discrepancies of serious magnitude between the various accounts mentioned above and within
each individual account. Even Hayek's ground breaking account fails to make certain elementary
and essential distinctions. The question then seems to be, how can we lay out the logical
elements of the concept to provide some coherent order for its attendant principles, assumptions,
and implications? The following paragraphs are only a summary of preliminary points that
Any discussion of rule of law begins with the assumption that liberty is desirable, that
there is a need to protect a sphere of individual freedom. That may be regarded as a moral value,
but it may also be regarded as a simple preference. People want to have freedom for themselves.
As we begin to answer the question of how that freedom might be obtained, we need to make a
further assumption about the nature of the world in which we live, particularly the nature of man
25
himself. What kind of a creature is it that we want to make free? This is not a metaphysical
question. Rather it is an empirical inquiry which asks what tendencies should we expect to
There are several answers that might be given to this. We might, for example, assume
that men are naturally cooperative and respectful of the rights of one another, in which case we
would then conclude that some form of anarchy or possibly a moral utopia of some sort might be
possible to achieve. If we assume with the more conservative tradition in western thought, that
men will generally pursue their own self interest--even, in many cases, at the expense of innocent
third parties--and that we cannot expect men to either know or discover the truth, then we will
conclude that a society of law offers the best practical alternative political regime. On that view,
laws would be the practical substitute for moral principles in a regime in which it is recognized
We can define the society of law, or the rule of law, as an arrangement in which the
individual is able to plan his own life by adhering to rules by which he will avoid all penalties
1. It assumes generality, that rules lay down general standards of conduct for all
citizens equally.
2. It assumes that the rules will be stated with sufficient clarity, that there is little or
3. It assumes that the rules are coherent, that is, that there is an established hierarchy
to determine which rules govern in cases of conflict and that there are not
4. It assumes that the rules are public, that they are available and known to the
citizens.
5. It assumes that the rules are possible, that they can be followed, that they do not
6. It assumes that the rules are prospective, that they refer to their own future and not
to the past.
7. It assumes that the rules are backed by authoritative enforcement, that there is
rules.
Once we have identified these necessary characteristics of the rules themselves, we can
inquire into the characteristics of the institutions which might be expected to maintain and
enforce this kind of rules without interjections of arbitrary will. Recognizing the natural
institutional tendency toward tyranny inherent in our assumption about human nature, we could
fundamentally a restriction that legislators may not enforce their own rules.
2. Every individual must have equal legal rights as he confronts the enforcement of
law.
3. The government must be subject to the periodic approval of the people which it
constitutional agreement. The second level is the consent to officials who will
decide on the laws and the enforcement of law. Republicanism was a modern
theory of consent.
5. Hayek has pointed out that there must always be provision for exceptions to any
of the above principles or to laws that may be valid in a given polity. But in
principle, such exceptions must be both justified and compensated at the time.
The principles listed above and others not mentioned seem to include rules which are
enjoined on legislatures and judges. But the rules are not self-enforcing. There needs to be
institutional devices that will carry the rules into effect. The actual devices used in any particular
political system might vary widely. Some devices will be more successful than others. But the
rules themselves will often appear ambiguous in concrete situations. It is therefore necessary to
institute procedural standards as the only effective way of enforcing the guidelines. As one
examines the provisions of the American constitution one is struck by the fact that none of the
principles of rule of law are announced or explained, or even set forth. Rather the document only
lists the procedures and the devices by which the founders hoped to achieve the effect of the
Many of these principles are implemented at least partially through specific prohibitions
on the powers of government or specific institutional devices. For example, the principle of
implemented by the prohibition on ex post facto laws. Some of Fuller's principles such as clarity,
28
system. We have a supremacy clause which gives some hierarchy and coherence in the legal
prohibitions on the infringement of free press and speech as well as the requirement that
legislatures publish their proceedings and that legislatures and courts deliberate in the public
view.
constitutional devices. Most notable among these are the division of the operation of
government into three branches and the further division of the legislative branch into two parts.
Institutions such as judicial review and the various checks and balances protect the independence
and integrity of the three branches, thus indirectly supporting the notion of separation of powers.
nobility as well as rules guaranteeing equal legal rights to citizens of every state. The principle
well as the provisions for the ratification of the constitution and subsequent amendments. An
independent judiciary is provided through prohibitions on juggling either the tenure or the
salaries of judges during their service. Protection from exceptions occurs in the eminent domain
clause.
Summary
In this essay I have briefly looked at the political institutions of a wide variety of societies
29
to demonstrate the universality of both the political problem (the tendency to tyranny) and the
best human solution (rule of law under the protection of constitutional arrangements.) As an
antidote to the decline in our understanding and appreciation for the idea of rule of law I have
designed to prevent the emergence of tyrants in the process of settling private or public disputes,
Secondly, I have insisted that not every collection of institutional devices will constitute
an adequate constitution. To succeed a constitution must preserve and promote the rule of law,
the point of which is to make official response to private action as predictable and avoidable as
possible for the citizen. No amount of moralizing or breast-beating will compensate for a well
conceived system that provides practical barriers to factional takeover of the powers of the state.
And inappropriate reliance on moral principle as law can give factional interests the weapon they
Finally, I have recognized that the possibility that any particular polity will be able to
achieve and maintain a system of law depends as well on the extent to which the political culture
includes a commitment to law as a means of creating that individual sphere of freedom to pursue
the good. Rule of law, by refusing to nationalize moral truth, makes its universal pursuit at the
NOTES
2. Ibid.
4. I am grateful to Merlin G. Myers for sharing these observations based on his dissertation
research.
5. Hilda Kuper, "The Swazi: A South African Kingdom," George and Louise Spindler
(eds.), Case Studies in Cultural Anthropology (New York: Holt, Rhinehart and Winston,
1963).
7. See Noel B. Reynolds, "Plato's Defense of Rule of Law," in the forthcoming proceedings
of the World Congress for the Philosophy of Law and Social Philosophy, Athens, 1985,
where I defend this controversial claim about Plato. That Plato understood and defended
the idea of rule of law as an appropriate ideal for human societies is clear in all the
epistles and in almost all of the dialogues. The exception is Republic, which gives an
ironic defense of philosophical totalitarianism, which many commentators have
mistakenly taken at face value.
9. See the excellent and very brief discussion in Harvey C. Mansfield, Jr.,
"Constitutionalism and the Rule of Law," Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy 8
(1985): 323-326.
10. Pindar, De Pindar: The Odes of Pindar, Including the Principal Fragments, Intro. and
trans. by Sir John Sandys, edited by T. E. Page, Loeb Classical Library (London: William
Heineman, Ltd., 1946), 169. The Greek text reads, "nomos ho panton basileus."
11. Charles H. McIlwain, The Growth of Political Thought in the West (London: Macmillan,
1932), 3.
31
12. See Brian Tierney, The Crisis of Church and State (Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall,
1964).
13. Otto Gierke, Political Theories of the Middle Age, trans. F. W. Maitland (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1900).
14. Charles H. McIlwain, Constitutionalism, Ancient and Modern, rev. ed. (Ithaca: Cornell
UP, 1947), 77-79.
15. Francis D. Wormuth, The Origins of Modern Constitutionalism (New York: Harper,
1949).
17. Frederick G. Whelan, Order and Artifice in Hume's Political Philosophy (Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 1985), 348-373 is an excellent new study which thoroughly
vindicates the eighteenth century Americans' reading of Hume.
20. F. A. Hayek, Law, Legislation, and Liberty (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1976).
26. Ronald M. Dworkin, Political Judges and the Rule of Law (London: The British
Academy, 1980), 282.
27. F. A. Hayek, The Constitution of Liberty (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1960),
181.
28. See especially the opening chapters of Alexander Solzhenitsyn, The Gulag Archipelago 3,
trans. H. T. Willetts (New York: Harper and Row, 1978).
30. Lon L. Fuller, The Morality of Law, rev. ed. (1969; New Haven: Yale University Press,
1964), 33-94.
31. J. R. Lucas, The Principles of Politics (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1966), 106-162.
32. John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1975), 235-243.
33. John Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980), 266-290.
34. Michael Oakeshott, "The Rule of Law," On History (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1983),
119-164.