Module 4
Module 4
Deontology
Deontology is an ethical theory which implies that our actions are to be determined,
whether good or bad, according to a set of rules or moral duties. It came from the
Greek word Ντέον (deon) which means “necessary” or “duty.” Hence, deontology is
also called duty ethics. Immanuel Kant is said to be the main proponent of this ethical
system.
Immanuel Kant (1724-1804)
German philosopher Immanuel Kant was born on April 22, 1724, in Konigsberg,
Prussia. As a student, he went to the University of Konigsberg and obtained his
bachelor and post-graduate degrees. In 1779, he was appointed chair of logic and
metaphysics in the same university. On February 12, 1804, just short of
his 80th birthday, he died. Kant influenced different philosophers who followed him.
His works on epistemology, ethics, aesthetics, and philosophy of religion
were influential to the rise of German Idealism. His legacy was greatly appreciated by
his peers and successors and regarded him as one of the greatest philosophers who
lived. Kant’s most famous works are the Critique of Pure Reason (1781), the Critique
of Practical Reason (1788), and the Critique of Judgment (1790).
Kant’s philosophy seeks to answer three fundamental questions: “What can I know?”
“What I ought to do?” and “What can I hope for?”. These three questions correspond
to each major branch of philosophy during Kant’s time, namely, epistemology which
deals with the nature of knowledge, ethics or moral philosophy, and philosophy of
religion. In this module, we will focus on Kant’s ethics.
Unlike the Divine Command Theory and the natural law ethics, Kantian ethics does not
make God as the basis or foundation of morality. Nor does it assume that there is a
universal principle of morality as the natural law ethics believes. Instead, Kant
believes that there is a pure a priori that is independent of experience or divine
influence, ethics of duty. The categorical imperative is his ultimate moral rule founded
on the human person’s sheer rationality and autonomy.
Kant’s Fundamental Principles
Kant writes in the Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysics of Morals (1797), that he
seeks a single and universal law of moral action that is neither dictated by some
universal moral principle as in the case of natural law nor some divine reality as in the
case of the Divine Command Theory. Instead, what Kant seeks to establish is a moral
system dictated by reason alone.
When Kant stated that two things fill our mind, the “starry heavens above me and the
moral law within me,” he was referring to the innate human tendency to inquire about
the nature of reality and morality. More importantly, Kant suggests that ethical
judgment can be found solely within the human person with no external factors
that dictate our understanding of the moral law. He enumerates reason, good will, and
duty as the criteria for his proposed ethical system. Kant writes, “there is no possibility
of thinking of anything at all in the world, or even out of it, which can be regarded as
good without qualification, except a good will.” What Kant means by this statement is
that no object or end is intrinsically and universally good. Things we
normally consider as good in themselves such as happiness, love, or
health are compatible with moral wrong. In other words, these objects of morality can
be corrupted. According to Kant, we can love, desire to be happy or healthy all for the
wrong reasons. Even belief in God, for Kant, cannot serve as the basis of morality for
we can believe in God for the wrong reasons. History is replete of people who did
atrocious acts all in the name of God. If what is morally right cannot be understood in
terms of these ends, what, then, can serve as the foundation of morality that is
immune to moral wrong? Kant believes that morality is the conformity of act to a rule.
In other words, we must do what is right because it is the right action and not for any
other reason or end. We must act not according to duty but from or because of duty.
In Kant’s ethical system, consequences are morally irrelevant because we cannot
judge the morality of an act based on its consequences or ends.
Moreover, you act not because you want to but because you have to. Minsan may
mga bagay na napakahirap gawin dahil labag sa loob natin pero kailangan gawin dahil
ito ang tama. Hence, a person acting in accordance with duty is not motivated by any
other factors. This person is simply motivated by the sole intention of doing what is
right because this is what the moral law demands.
For example, you are a tricycle driver and you hit a luxury car in a rotonda or a
roundabout. Since you are a tricycle driver, your initial response is that you do not
have enough money to pay for the damage that you caused. By looking at the owner
of the car, you thought of driving away since you think that that person has a lot of
money because he drives a luxury car. However, because you know that the right
thing to do is to stop and converse with the driver, you did not run away. While talking
with each other, the driver of the car said that he understood your situation and
would let you pay a little amount. He did not cause you any further harm since he did
not charge you with a huge amount of money nor sue you for hit and run. After your
conversation, you both settled and went home with relief.
What lesson can we get in this situation? The means do not justify the ends. How is
this? If you drive away to not be caught, you do not do the right thing. In this situation
of conversing with the driver, you did your moral duty and complied with the moral
demands. In brief, acting in accordance with duty urges us to obey the moral law even
if it is not what we want. We just simply do our moral duty because it is the right thing
to do. There must not be any other intentions or qualifications. Simply, we do what is
right.
Categorical Imperative
In this module, we veered away from ethical systems based on God and the natural
law. Instead, we introduced an ethical system that is solely humanistic and based on
mere duty. Such an ethics, known as deontology, implies that all our moral actions are
anchored on the fact that it is simply right to do the right thing not because of any
impending punishment or reward. The consequences of Kantian ethics are enormous
both in Kant’s time and our town time. In Kant’s time, he was able to personalize and
subjectivize morality, severing it from any moral authority, such as religion and
society, and relegating it to the individual person by the merit of his or her freedom
and dignity not be treated as means but as an end. Kant’s ideas also affected our own
way of thinking particularly in the realm of human rights reflections in that we saw
human beings as deserving of dignity or respect not on the merits of their deeds but
simply because of being a human being. Perhaps the most important lesson that we
may draw from Immanuel Kant’s radical take on ethics is that we do not need to be
good simply because we fear God’s punishment or we await some kind of reward or
recognition but simply because being good is just part of being human.