Time
Time
H. D. Zeh
www.zeh-hd.de
2
its minimum (achieved for a wave function that nowhere changes sign) is in the Heisenberg
picture interpreted as describing 'zero point fluctuations' of the corresponding variables q.
This picture has led to much confusion – including the search for a 'time observable' T
that would depend on the specific system Hamiltonians H by obeying commutation relations
[T,H] = ih ,
in analogy to position and momentum observables (see the Introduction to [8] for a review).
However, since realistic Hamiltonians possess a ground state, their spectra are bounded from
below, and a time operator obeying this commutation relation cannot possess a spectrum
represented by the real numbers (as pointed out by Wolfgang Pauli [2]). It may nonetheless be
related to time intervals between certain pairs of events that can be measured at a system
characterized by the Hamiltonian H.
A formal equivalence between the Schrödinger and a Heisenberg picture for the
purpose of calculating expectation values of measurement results is known to hold for
isolated, unitarily evolving systems (which are exceptions in reality). For asymptotically
isolated objects participating in a scattering process one may use the interaction picture,
where part of the Hamiltonian dynamics is absorbed into the observables characterizing
asymptotic states. This includes the 'dressing' of quantum fields. However, macroscopic
systems always form open systems; they never become isolated, even when dressed. Such
systems may approximately obey effective non-unitary dynamics (master equations). In
principle, this dynamics has to be derived from the unitary (Schrödinger) evolution of an
entangled global quantum state, that would include all 'external interventions'. Under realistic
assumptions this leads to permanently growing →entanglement with the environment –
locally observed as →decoherence [5].
This extremely fast and in practice irreversible process describes a dislocalization of
quantum superpositions. It thereby mimics quantum jumps (events): components which
represent different macroscopic properties (such as different pointer positions or different
registration times of a detector) are almost immediately dynamically decoupled from one
another – though none of them is selected as the only existing one. Pauli, when arguing in
terms of the Heisenberg picture, regarded such events as occuring 'outside the laws of nature',
since they withstood all attempts of a local dynamical description. In the global Schrödinger
picture, the time-asymmetry of this dynamical decoupling of components ('branching') can be
explained in terms of the time-symmetric dynamics by means of an appropriate initial
condition for the wave function of the universe – the same condition that may also explain
thermodynamical and related time asymmetries ('arrows of time') [9]. In essence, this initial
condition requires that non-local entanglement did not yet exist just after the big bang, and
therefore has to form dynamically ('causally'). The resulting asymmetry in time may give rise
to the impression of a direction of time.
III. In quantum field theory, a Schrödinger equation that controls the dynamics of the
field functionals may well be relativistic – containing only local interactions with respect to
the space-dependent field variables (in this way facilitating the concept of a Hamiltonian
density in space). A wave function(al) obeying a relativistic Schrödinger equation never
propagates faster than light with respect to the underlying presumed absolute spacetime.
Recent reports of apparently observed superluminal phenomena were either based on
inappropriate clocks, or on questionable interpretations of the wave function. For example, the
exact energy eigenstate of a particle, bound to an attractive potential in a state of negative
energy E = -|E|, would extend to spatial infinity according to exp(-√|E|r) outside the range of
the potential. It has therefore been claimed to be able in principle to cause effects at an
arbitrary distance within any finite time [10]. However, if the wave function of the bound
system forms dynamically (according to the Schrödinger equation rather than by quantum
jumps), it can only subluminally approach the exact eigenstate with its infinite exponential
tail. This time-dependence requires a minimum energy spread that is in accord with the time-
3
frequency Fourier theorem. Similar arguments hold relativistically also for particle number
eigenstates, which cannot have sharp spatial boundaries because of Casimir type effects (in
principle observable for moving mirrors); all bounded systems must relativistically be in
superpositions of diffent particle numbers.
In the theory of relativity, proper times assume the role of Newton's absolute time for
all local systems, that is, for those approximately following world lines in spacetime. How-
ever, quantum states are generically nonlocal, and they do not consist of or define local
subsystem states. One may then introduce auxiliary time coordinates (arbitrary spacetime
foliations) in order to define the dynamics of global states on these artificial 'simultaneities'.
A Hamiltonian (albeit of very complex form – in general including a whole field of Coriolis-
type forces with effective 'particle' creation and annihilation terms) would nonetheless exist in
this case. As these artificial simultaneities may be assumed to propagate just locally, one
speaks of 'many-fingered time'. Dynamical evolution in quantum theory is in general locally
non-unitary (to be described by a master equation) because of the generic nonlocal entangle-
ment contained in the unitarily evolving global quantum state. Unitary evolution may there-
fore be confirmed only in exceptional, quasi-isolated (microscopic) systems.
IV. According to Mach's ideas, no concept of absolute time should be required or
meaningful. Any time concept could then be replaced by simultaneity relations between
trajectories of different variables (including appropriate clocks) – see [4] and Chap. 1 of [9].
Classically, timeless trajectories q(λ), where λ is an arbitrary and physically meaningless
parameter, are still defined. Mach's principle requires only that the fundamental dynamical
laws are invariant under reparametrizations of λ. In quantum theory, the wave function cannot
even depend on such a time-ordering parameter, since there are no trajectories any more that
could be parametrized. This excludes even dynamical successions of spatial geometries (the
dynamical states of general relativity), which would form a foliation of spacetime. On the
other hand, any appropriate variable q0 that is among the arguments of a time-less wave
function ψ(q) may be regarded as a more or less appropriate global physical clock. According
to the superposition principle, superpositions of different values q0 – that is, of different
'physical times' – would then have to exist as real physical states (just as the superpositions of
different values of any physical variable).
In conventional quantum mechanics, superpositions of different times of an event are
well known. For example, a coherently decaying metastable state (that can be experimentally
confirmed to exist by means of interference in the case of decay fragments only weakly
interacting with their environment) is a superposition of different decay times. Similarly, the
quantum state for a single variable x and a clock variable u, say, would have to be described
by a wave function ψ(x,u). This means that the classical dependence of x on clock time u,
defined by their time-less trajectory x(u), is replaced by the less stringent entanglement
between x and u that is defined by such a wave function [11]. The clock variable u becomes
quasi-classical only if it is robust under environmental decoherence, such that superpositions
of different times u always remain dislocalized (locally inaccessible). The same conclusion
holds for the mentioned superposition of different decay times if its corresponding partial
waves (wave packets forming thin spherical shells in space unless reflected somewhere) are
decohered from one another.
Atomic clocks, in particular, are based on the time-dependent superposition of two
close atomic energy eigenstates (defining 'beats'). These oscillating states would immediately
decohere whenever they were measured (read). Therefore, they have to be dynamically
correlated with the coherent state of a maser field that is in resonance with them. This time-
dependent coherent state is known to be 'robust' against decoherence – including genuine
measurements [12]. So it permits the construction of a quasi-classical atomic clock that can be
read. Exactly classical clocks would be in conflict with the uncertainty relations between
position and momentum of their 'hands'.
4
The above-described consequences of Mach's principle with respect to time do indeed
apply in general relativity to a closed universe. Spatial geometries on a time-like foliation of
spacetime, which would classically determine all proper times [13], are now among the
dynamical variables q (arguments of the wave function) – similar to the mentioned clock
variable u. Moreover, material clocks intended to 'measure' these proper times within a given
precision would have to possess a minimum mass in order to comply with the uncertainty
relations [14], while this mass must then in turn disturb the spacetime metric.
A time coordinate t in general relativity is a physically meaningless parameter (such
as λ – not u – in the above examples). Invariance of the theory under reparametrization, t →
f(t), requires a 'Hamiltonian constraint': H = 0 [1,15]. In its quantum mechanical form, HΨ =
0, this leads to the trivial Schrödinger dynamics ∂Ψ/∂t = 0, where Ψ is now a wave functional
on a configuration space consisting of spatial geometries and matter fields. As this conse-
quence seems to remain valid for all unified theories that contain →quantum gravity, one has
to conclude that there is no time on a fundamental level; all dynamics is encoded in the static
entanglement described by Ψ. Surprisingly, though, the time-less Wheeler-DeWitt equation
[1],
HΨ = 0 ,
(also called an Einstein-Schrödinger equation) becomes hyperbolic for Friedmann type uni-
verses – similar to a relativistic wave equation on spacetime (see Sect. 2.1 of [9]). This allows
one to formulate a complete boundary condition for Ψ in the form of an 'intrinsic initial
condition' [16]. It requires Ψ and its first derivative to be given on a 'time-like' hypersurface,
defined according to the hyperbolic form of the kinetic energy operator contained in H (now a
d'Alembertian), in this universal configuration space (DeWitt's 'superspace'). For example,
such initial data can be freely chosen at a small value of the expansion parameter a of the
universe. A low-entropy condition at a → 0 then leads to an 'intrinsic arrow of time': total
entropy on time-like hypersurfaces must grow (for statistical reasons) as a function of the size
of the universe – regardless of any external concept of time.
Quasi-classical time can here only be recovered within the validity of a Born-Oppen-
heimer approximation with respect to the square root of the inverse Planck mass [15], while
spatial geometry, which defines all fundamental physical clocks, is strongly entangled with,
and thus decohered by, matter [17]. In analogy to the coherent set of apparent light rays that
approximately describe the propagation of one extended light wave in space in the limit of
short wave lengths (geometric optics), quasi-classical times are defined approximately, but
separately for all quasi-trajectories in superspace. Each of them then defines a dynamically
autonomous quasi-classical world (an 'Everett branch' of the global wave function in unitary
description) – including a specific quasi-classical spacetime. As 'Schrödinger cat' states
evolve abundantly from microscopic superpositions in measurement-type interactions, there
cannot be just one quasi-classical world (analogous to just one light ray) according to the
Schrödinger dynamics. Material clocks, such as atomic clocks, require further (usually not
quite as strong) decoherence to become quasi-classical.
5
Literature
Primary
[1] B. S. DeWitt: Quantum theory of gravity, Phys. Rev. 160, 1113 (1967)
[2] W. Pauli: In Handbuch der Physik, ed. by H. Geiger and K. Scheel, 2nd edt., Vol. 24
(Springer, Berlin 1933)
[3] J. von Neumann: Mathematische Grundlagen der Quantenmechanik (Springer, Berlin
1932)
Secondary
[4] J.B. Barbour: The End of Time (Weidenfeld & Nicolson, London 1999)
[5] E. Joos, H. D. Zeh, C. Kiefer, D. Giulini, J. Kupsch, and I.-O. Stamatescu: Decoherence
and the Appearance of a Classical World in Quantum Theory, 2nd edn. (Springer, Berlin,
Heidelberg 2003)
[6] J. Hilgevoord: The uncertainty principle for energy and time, Am. J. Phys. 64, 1451
(1996)
[7] P. Busch: The time energy uncertainty relation, In [8]
[8] J. G. Muga, R. Sals Mayato, and I. L. Egusquiza: Time in Quantum Mechanics (Springer,
Berlin, Heidelberg 2002)
[9] H. D. Zeh: The Physical Basis of the Direction of Time, 5th edn. (Springer, Berlin,
Heidelberg 2007)
[10] G. Hegerfeldt: Causality problems for Fermi's two-atom system, Phys. Rev. Lett. 72, 596
(1994)
[11] D. N. Page and W. K. Wootters: Evolution without evolution: Dynamics described by
stationary observables, Phys. Rev. D27, 2885 (1983)
[12] O. Kübler and H. D. Zeh: Dynamics of quantum correlations, Ann. Phys. (N.Y.) 76, 405
(1973)
[13] R. F. Baierlein, D. H. Sharp, and J.A. Wheeler: Three-dimensional geometry as carrier of
information about time, Phys. Rev. 126, 1864 (1962)
[14] H. Salecker and E.P. Wigner: Quantum limitations of the measurement of space-time
distances, Phys. Rev. 109, 571 (1958)
[15] C. Kiefer: Quantum Gravity, 2nd edn. (Clarendon Press, Oxford 2007)
[16] H. D. Zeh: Emergence of classical time from a universal wave function, Phys. Lett.
A116, 9 (1986)
[17] E. Joos: Why do we observe a classical spacetime? Phys. Lett. A116, 6 (1986)