DocScanner 06-Dec-2024 9-59 am
DocScanner 06-Dec-2024 9-59 am
DocScanner 06-Dec-2024 9-59 am
Given the insights and limitations of the models reviewed so far, a more systematic
explanation of the emergence of party systems must be based on the integration of two
theoretical steps. The first step is strictly analytical and consists in describing the
structure of incentives within which voters vote and politicians decide to run for
office. Depicting the institutional mechanisms of any representative democracy, that
is, the ways in which elections, government formation, and policy making work, will let
8 Most explanations of the choice of institutions either depict institutions as efficient solutions to
collective action and time consistency problems (Knight 1992) or simply refer to them as self-reinforcing
equilibria (Putnam 1993). The adoption of proportional representation has been related to the trade
requirements of small countries (Rogowski 1987) or to its capacity to manage political conflict in
heterogeneous societies (Katzenstein 1985; Lijphart 1977). Political parties have been purported to solve
coordination failures (Aldrich 1995; Cox 1987). Still, efficiency theories have clear difficulties in account
ing for cross-temporal and cross-national variation and, particularly, in explaining the choice of
suboptimal institutions, the pervasive existence of instances of political stagnation, and the breakdown
of political regimes. As a matter of fact, the predominance of these rather functionalist approaches is
doubly surprising given a central insight of analytical institutionalism: that, precisely because they shape
political equilibria, institutions are themselves the outcome of political strategies (Riker 1986).
<br>
us predict, at a most general or abstract level, the ways in which voters and politicians act
to maximize the probability ofreaching their objectives-given the institutional rules in
which they operate. This can done by drawing upon the very extensive contemporary
literature on elections, spatial theory, and strategic coordination (driven by electoral
rules) to describe the workings of representative government.
The second step is historical. Starting from the incentive structure that shapes the
behavior of voters and parties, we need to describe and make sense of the sequence of
historical events through which politicians coordinated in parties, choosing particular
programs and electoral strategies, and voters then rallicd around them. Such an approach
should show why certain parties emerged at certain historical junctures; why others did
not or, if they did, failed at the ballot box; and, finally, why they chose particular electoral
institutions which, in turn, shaped the number and type of viable parties.
These two steps are complemerntary. Without analytical foundations, the historical
description of party systems and elections would remain an amorphous, variegated set
of facts. With some partial (and very laudable) exceptions, most of the scholarly
literature on this problem still has this character. Conversely, without any attention
to the historical sequence at work, we would be unable to account for the dynamics of
institutional change that were at the heart of the process of party formation we want to
explain. And therefore we would be unable to sort out which variables preceded which
events and how. As discussed before, this lack of attention to history (and, more precisely,
timing) handicaps most of the formal work on clectoral systems and party systems.
The findings that institutional structures covary with the number of parties are mostly
correlations that tell us little about the way in which institutions and parties unfolded
over time and how actors shaped the mechanisms of democratic representation.
Consider now in more analytical detail the way in which democratic elections
work. As summarized in Figure 21.1, in any election, some citizens first decide to
advance their candidacy (jointly with a particular electoral platform or list of policy
promises). Voters then cast their ballots and only a few candidates become elected,
that is, only a few gather a sufficient number of votes (where sufficient is defined by
the electoral law in place) to get into public office. After elections, the elected
representatives convene to form government and set policy until new elections take
place. These policies, which may well include the procedures to select candidates in
future elections (i.e. the electoral laws), purportedly have an impact on the well
being of citizens (and politicians) and should affect how the next election is fought
and how voters will decide again.
system, actors (the states) do not choose the rules of the game -in fact, there are
hardly any, except for some informal cooperation within a general condition of
anarchy. In markets, firms only partially (if at all) define the rules of competition.
By contrast, in representative democracies, politicians set the very rules according to
which they will be selected. And they generally draft them to maximize their electoral
chances. This simple fact forces us to tackle the causes underlying the choice of the
rules of the game. In other words, a theory of party formation would be incomplete if
we did not pay attention to the incentives that make politicians maintain the legal
status quo (something that happens most of the time) or alter it (something that
oCcurs very rarely and with substantial consequences).