Part 5: Epistemology
I. Epistemology
1. Definition
The term “epistemology” comes from the Greek words
“episteme” and “logos”. “Episteme” can be translated as
“knowledge” or “understanding” or “acquaintance”, while
“logos” can be translated as “account” or “argument” or “reason”.
Although the term “epistemology” is no more than a couple of
centuries old, the field of epistemology is at least as old as any in
philosophy. In different parts of its extensive history, different
facets of epistemology have attracted attention.
Plato’s epistemology was an attempt to understand what it was to
know, and how knowledge (unlike mere true opinion) is good for
the knower.
Locke’s epistemology was an attempt to understand the
operations of human understanding,
Kant’s epistemology was an attempt to understand the conditions
of the possibility of human understanding, and
Russell’s epistemology was an attempt to understand how modern
science could be justified by appeal to sensory experience.
Basically, epistemology is the explanation of how a person thinks.
It helps a person differentiate between truth and lie. Epistemology
makes use of four different sources to gather knowledge, namely,
intuitive, authoritative, logical, and empirical.
Source: Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
2. A priori/ A posteriori
Where does knowledge come from? It’s clear that some
knowledge, at least, comes from perception. You might find out
that the coffee cup is in front of you, that it’s snowing outside, and
that your dog is barking by seeing or otherwise perceiving these
facts, that is, through sense-experience. Much of what you know
by remembering it, or by relying on the testimony of what others
have experienced, also ultimately depends on your sense-
experience, or at least on somebody’s. But a major topic for
philosophical debate throughout all of the recorded history of
philosophy has been about knowledge that doesn’t ultimately
depend on the senses. Philosophy has often considered this kind
of knowledge: what sort it is, how extensive it is, and how to
account for it.
Knowledge that depends on sensation is called a posteriori
knowledge. This means, in Latin, from afterwards – after (that is,
dependent upon) sense-experience. Knowledge that doesn’t
depend on sense-experience is called a priori knowledge, Latin
for from beforehand – prior to (that is, independent of) sense-
experience. The questions in this chapter are: what kinds of a
priori knowledge are there? And how do we know that sort
of thing? The answer to the second question is not obvious: how,
after all, could you find out anything other than by using your
senses?
3. Rationalism and Empiricism
Basis of Rationalism Empiricism
Comparison
Definition Rationalism is the term used Empiricism is the term used
in philosophy to refer to the in philosophy in which the
knowledge that is derived main source of knowledge
from reason and logic. is experience and exp
Belief Rationalists believe that The empiricists believe that
reason can explain the evidence through
working of the world. experimentation can
explain reality.
Principles Rationalism is related to Empiricism is related to
mental processes and sensory experience and
organizing principles. association principles
History The history of rationalism The history of empiricism
goes far beyond the goes to the era between 600
Pythagoras’ time that is 570– to 200 BCE.
495 BCE.
Examples Mathematics is an example Experimental Science is an
of rationalism. example of empiricism
4. The Belief Condition
This requires that anyone who knows that p (where p stands for
any proposition or statement) must believe that p.
If, therefore, you do not believe that minds are brains (say,
because you have not considered the matter at all), then you do
not know that minds are brains.
A knower must be psychologically related somehow to a
proposition that is an object of knowledge for that knower.
Proponents of the standard analysis hold that only belief can
provide the needed psychological relation. Philosophers do not
share a uniform account of belief, but some considerations supply
common ground.
Beliefs are not actions of assenting to a proposition; they rather
are dispositional psychological states that can exist even when
unmanifested. (You do not cease believing that 2 + 2 = 4, e.g.,
whenever your attention leaves arithmetic.) Our believing that p
seems to require that we have a tendency to assent to p in certain
situations, but it seems also to be more than just such a tendency.
What else believing requires remains highly controversial among
philosophers. Some philosophers have opposed the belief
condition of the standard analysis on the ground that we can
accept, or assent to, a known proposition without actually
believing it. They contend that we can accept a proposition even
if we fail to acquire a tendency, required by believing, to accept
that proposition in certain situations. On this view, acceptance is
a psychological act that does not entail any dispositional
psychological state, and such acceptance is sufficient to relate a
knower psychologically to a known proposition. However this
view fares, one underlying assumption of the standard analysis
seems correct: our concept of knowledge requires that a knower
be psychologically related somehow to a known proposition.
Barring that requirement, we shall be hard put to explain how
knowers psychologically possess their knowledge of known
propositions. Even if knowledge requires belief, belief that p does
not require knowledge that p, since belief can typically be false.
This observation, familiar from Plato’s Theaetetus, assumes that
knowledge has a truth condition. On the standard analysis, if you
know that p, then it is true that p. If, therefore, it is false that minds
are brains, then you do not know that minds are brains. It is thus
misleading to say, e.g., that astronomers before Copernicus knew
that the earth is flat; at best, they justifiably believed that they
knew this.
5. The Truth Condition
This condition of the standard analysis has not attracted any
serious challenge. Controversy over it has focused instead on
Pilate’s vexing question: What is truth? This question concerns
what truth consists in, not our ways of finding out what is true.
Influential answers come from at least three approaches: truth as
correspondence (i.e., agreement, of some specified sort, between
a proposition and an actual situation); truth as coherence (i.e.,
interconnectedness of a proposition with a specified system of
propositions); and truth as pragmatic cognitive value (i.e.,
usefulness of a proposition in achieving certain intellectual
goals). Without assessing these prominent approaches, we should
recognize, in accord with the standard analysis, that our concept
of knowledge seems to have a factual requirement: we genuinely
know that p only if it is the case that p. The pertinent notion of
“its being the case” seems equivalent to the notion of “how reality
is” or “how things really are.” The latter notion seems essential to
our notion of knowledge, but is open to controversy over its
explication.
6. The Justification Condition
Knowledge is not simply true belief. Some true beliefs are
supported only by lucky guesswork and hence do not qualify as
knowledge. Knowledge requires that the satisfaction of its belief
condition be “appropriately related” to the satisfaction of its truth
condition. This is one broad way of understanding the justification
condition of the standard analysis. More specifically, we might
say that a knower must have adequate indication that a known
proposition is true. If we understand such adequate indication as
a sort of evidence indicating that a proposition is true, we have
reached the traditional general view of the justification condition:
justification as evidence. Questions about justification attract the
lion’s share of attention in contemporary epistemology.
Controversy focuses on the meaning of ‘justification’ as well as
on the substantive conditions for a belief’s being justified in a way
appropriate to knowledge. Current debates about the meaning of
‘justification’ revolve around the question whether, and if so how,
the concept of epistemic (knowledge-relevant) justification is
normative. Since the 1950s Chisholm has defended the following
deontological (obligation-oriented) notion of justification: the
claim that a proposition, p, is epistemically justified for you
means that it is false that you ought to refrain from accepting p.
In other terms, to say that p is epistemically justified is to say that
accepting p is epistemically permissible – at least in the sense that
accepting p is consistent with a certain set of epistemic rules. This
deontological construal enjoys wide representation in
contemporary epistemology A normative construal of justification
need not be deontological; it need not use the notions of
obligation and permission. Alston, for instance, has introduced a
non-deontological normative concept of justification that relies
mainly on the notion of what is epistemically good from the
viewpoint of maximizing truth and minimizing falsity. Alston
links epistemic goodness to a belief’s being based on adequate
grounds in the absence of overriding reasons to the contrary.
Some epistemologists shun normative construal of justification as
superfluous. One noteworthy view is that ‘epistemic justification’
means simply ‘evidential support’ of a certain sort. To say that p
is epistemically justifiable to some extent for you is, on this view,
just to say that p is supportable to some extent by your overall
evidential reasons. This construal will be non-normative so long
as the notions of supportability and an evidential reason are non-
normative. Some philosophers have tried to explicate the latter
notions without relying on talk of epistemic permissibility or
epistemic goodness. We can understand the relevant notion of
“support” in terms of non-normative notions of entailment and
explanation (or, answering why questions). We can understand
the notion of an “evidential reason” via the notion of a
psychological state that can stand in a certain truth-indicating sup-
port relation to propositions. For instance, we might regard non-
doxastic states of “seeming to perceive” something (e.g., seeming
to see a dictionary here) as foundational truth indicators for
certain physical-object propositions (e.g., the proposition that
there is a dictionary here), in virtue of those states being best
explained by those propositions. If anything resembling this
approach succeeds, we can get by without the aforementioned
normative notions of epistemic justification
Robert Audi - How Belief Systems
Affect Believers
Why do people believe the things they do? We like to think that
we are rational, that what we believe is true. But often we come
to our beliefs, unknowingly, as a product of our particular
‘belief systems’. How do belief systems work their credulous
magic? What principles enable belief systems to influence
individuals and commandeer groups?
Robert I've been interested in belief systems in examining why
we believe what we believe particularly about people who believe
in God or people or atheists who don't believe in God that there's
a certain whether it's a cultural psychological evolutionary
psychologist all these things that are built in to belief systems uh
you have a book and it focused on the concept of rationality and
religious commitment many people would think those contradict
each other and so in building a belief system how do you that that
is entails a religious commitment what's the role of rationality
you're asking about belief systems with a particular subsystem in
mind I think the religious ones but let's remember that that
interacts with the scientific belief system if one has it but the
common sense and ethical belief system which just about
everybody has of course now one thing to note is that belief is a
narrow term for cognition if I hope that somebody is going to
survive cancer that's a cognition but I don't believe it I hope so the
probability level if I were to assign a probability would be a lot
lower now I think when you look at a theistic commitment you
can find very often a great deal of difference among the cognitions
somebody may be certain that if God is perfectly good and created
beings of the complexity of you and me then God cares about us
you couldn't be good and create beings with our capacity for joy
and suffering and not care okay but one might have only hope that
God is going to save everybody from uh ultimate dissolution upon
bodily death right so the belief system actually contains
cognitions of different levels of conviction remember too that
you're asking about the relation to behavior and desire comes in
as well because Behavior comes from belief which guides it and
desire which energizes it so where is the will in what you're
calling a belief system I think that faith that something is so faith
for example that God God is Sovereign involves a positive
attitude toward its being so so faith has a kind of positivity about
it and it implies a position of the will to act in the positive ways
that go with the content of the faith so certainly a religious
Outlook where there's commitment is going to involve ordinary
behavior and interpersonal relations I'm looking at myself yes I
would I would have a hope that God exists the kind of God that
would ensure for all Humanity myself included life after death
and all of those things I have that hope but I I wouldn't I don't
have I certainly don't have the belief in terms of the the conviction
but I don't even have the faith uh that too strong that's too so I'm
at hope I haven't gotten to Faith certainly not to believe so so how
does that work because I have these words but I'm not sure what
they really mean that I have this hope but I don't have faith and I
certainly don't have right maybe you're disturbed by as many are
the problem of evil there are terrible things in human history and
we have the lines in Macbeth did Heaven look on and would not
take their part said by McDuff about his murdered wife and
children that outcry runs through human history and it takes a
great deal of sophistication to deal with the problem of evil I think
there are many things that can be said and here as in many cases
you can have hope that there is no gratuitous evil that all evil is at
least counterbalanced by a greater good you can have faith that
that is so you can have conviction that that is so okay now you're
asking also about the rationality of a system of cognitions I
distinguish rationality from justification rationality is contrasted
with irrationality justification with being unjustified it's the fate
of all of us sometimes to be unjustified in what we hold but many
of us do not suffer irrationality at least not often so you could be
unjustified but rational that is correct and so what's an example of
that well um you can be unjustified in believing you're right in the
solution to a problem but you're not irrational because you've got
evidence you did careful thinking you just made a mistake so
mathematicians doing careful proofs can be uh Justified or
unjustified but not irrational so justification implies rationality
but rationality doesn't imply justification being that link between
belief and and the truth of that well it's characteristically an
element in knowledge let's put it that way okay so what I'm
getting at is that it's easy to set the Baseline for irrational religious
commitment too high to set it at the level of justification where
you've got evidence of a kind that would convince a skeptic or at
least somebody neutral if you're rational then you have a
permissible view that's consonant with being an overall rational
person you're not a candidate for an asylum you're not just being
stupid so I have more categories of normative assessment for a
world view than some people do I also have more gradations
among religious cognitions and attitudes than many do so take a
life it'll have certain experiences negative and positive it will have
a certain exposure or none to Arguments for the existence of God
there will be lives in which non-theism is rational and lives in
which theism is rational and I think there are people who have
justification they have a really good case and experiences that go
with it so we have a lot of variety here what are your aggregations
and compare to others in this this hierarchy from Hope to
knowledge well suppose you have religious experience uh in
nature in um the uh hearing of certain Sacred Music in Reading
scripture suppose you have a Mastery of some of the best
Arguments for the existence of God so you have a cumulative
case suppose two that you find the kind of life that you're led to
by your religious commitment a very attractive kind of life and
one of the kinds of confirmation you feel in your world view
comes from interpersonal relations of a very positive kind so
overall pursuing that sort of life can be rational no two that
somebody who regards ethics as epistemically independent of
theology as I do will often be able to say I'm not forced to do
anything interpersonally that I can't justify from a secular point of
view so that helps to make the overall commitment rational in
terms of a pluralistic human life but you don't have to be justified
you can be rational but not justified that's correct though
pragmatically to say you're unjustified implies you ought to give
up the cognition so I want to say not justify doesn't imply being
patently unjustified just failing to have that strong position in
terms of evidence does not imply lacking rationality and it does
not imply anything to be ashamed of if I get myself where I
believe in God and I can be close at times and it turns out that
there is no God I was wrong yeah I'm still I was still rational when
I thought that and it was just not justified because the fact well
you might have been Justified too but you didn't have knowledge
because knowledge entails truth justification doesn't Okay so
we'd have to look at how much grounding you had to decide
whether you had justification or not and look there are degrees of
justification I'm talking about being justified simplicitor it's a
strong episode steaming position and I'm saying that it's easy to
think and Skeptics will want us to think that you shouldn't believe
it all and you shouldn't even have hope maybe unless you have
this strong epistemic position right that's a little narrow it seems
to me especially if the position isn't going to lead you to do um
immoral things so one of the beautiful things about a good
rational religious commitment is that it leads people to tend to do
and to prove of things that from a secular point of view are
admirable so that has to be fitted into the picture.
Robert Audi - Epistemology: How Do
We Know What We Know?
What do we know and how do we know it? What is knowledge?
What is belief? How is belief justified? What justifies us in
believing what we believe? Is justified belief knowledge? These
questions constitute “epistemology” – the theory of knowledge.
Robert, Closer to Truth is my passion, and for years we've been
exploring the cosmos—cosmology, consciousness, the brain, the
mind, and the nature of meaning. Is there a God? What about
God? We've had discussions with some of the top thinkers in the
world. But if I step back from that, there’s a deeper question: how
do I know what I know? What is knowledge? What is belief in
something? This is epistemology, which I’m eager to explore
more deeply. So, orient me to epistemology so I can understand
how I know what I know.
You're talking about epistemology as the theory of knowledge. I
think it should be construed as the theory of knowledge and
justification. Usually, what you know, you're justified in
believing, but there are exceptions. Maybe I'll mention one or
two. In any case, philosophy, in my view, should, when possible,
defend common sense, correcting it where necessary. So, I think
I know a lot about my surroundings right now, perceptually. I also
remember how I got here, and I hope I remember things from way
before that. I’m sure you feel the same way. I think I know
something about the future—immediately, I'm going to raise a
hand to give an illustration—but even the distant future.
How do we know? Knowledge is belief connected with the fact
known in the right way. Philosophers spend a lot of time on what
constitutes the "right way." When you see a hand, the hand affects
you, and if it does so in the right way, you know there’s a hand
before you. But it could do it in the wrong way, for example, by
activating a machine that causes you to hallucinate a hand even
when there’s a lead shield between you and me. So, we have to
understand how the world affects us to know if we truly know.
I’m taking knowledge to be constituted by belief. Knowledge is
always of truths or realities, while belief is not. One of our
problems is to decide when we merely believe and when we truly
know.
For example, if two years ago, I told you I believed Donald Trump
would be President of the United States, and now, two years later,
Donald Trump is indeed President, when I said that two years
ago—when everyone would have laughed—what was the nature
of my thought?
You had a belief, and you were lucky to be right. I would assume
you weren't justified in that belief.
Okay, so I had a belief, and the fact that it turned out to be true
didn't change the character of the belief at the time. That would
have been backwards causation, right?
Sure, sure. So, if you do know the future, presumably it’s because
something that causes the future event also causes your belief in
the right way.
Right, so in that case, it would be knowledge. You can have
knowledge of the future when the evidence that connects causally
with the future event also leads you to believe what that event will
be, which was not the case in this example.
Exactly. If I intend to raise my hand, my intention is a kind of
evidence that feeds into my belief, making it knowledge that I'm
going to raise my hand. Skeptics will say, "Yes, but there could
be interference with the causal chain." Well, there could be, but
normally there isn’t. As I said, I'm defending common sense.
You could also have some "evil demon" manipulating things, so
it seems causal, but it’s not. That’s a possibility philosophers deal
with, but in common-sense cases, we’re more concerned with real
counter-evidence, not hypothetical possibilities that we’re in
error.
Of course, we also have self-knowledge, but it can be limited. For
instance, you can’t be in pain without knowing you’re in pain, but
that doesn’t mean you’re right about everything you believe.
Some people may even whitewash their self-descriptions, taking
themselves to have beliefs that their behavior suggests they don’t
actually have.
What's an example of that?
Well, a person might think he’s utterly egalitarian, but in reality,
his treatment of people shows he’s not. Rationalization and
defense mechanisms come into play, as we see in both philosophy
of mind and psychology. One challenge in epistemology and
philosophy of mind is understanding the limits of self-knowledge.
So, we started with belief, knowledge, and justification.
Justification is what makes a belief knowledge, correct?
Well, no, because, unfortunately, you can have justified true
beliefs that are not knowledge. Bertrand Russell gave the example
of someone entering a room, expecting the clock to be accurate.
It happens to be noon, and the clock, though stopped, reads noon.
The person has a justified true belief that it’s noon, but they don’t
actually know, because the clock was stopped.
So, how do you define justification in this context?
It’s a controversial matter, but broadly, justification for a belief is
having some ground that supports the proposition, which you can
derive from memory, perception, or reasoning. I haven’t
mentioned reasoning yet because I’ve been talking about
empirical knowledge of the world. There’s also a priori
knowledge, which comes from reflection and reasoning. We have
a priori knowledge in logic, pure mathematics, and, I believe, in
basic moral principles. Some argue we don’t have moral
knowledge at all, or that it’s empirical. I think some moral
knowledge is empirical, but basic moral principles, I believe, can
be known a priori.
You describe your understanding of epistemology as "fallibilistic
foundationalism." Could you explain that?
We arrive at foundationalism by noting that we can't base a belief
on an endless chain of other beliefs—this would lead to an infinite
regress. Circular reasoning is also problematic. Foundationalism
posits that some beliefs, such as those based on experience, don’t
require further justification. For instance, when you see a hand,
you believe it’s there based on visual experience, not on another
belief. Skeptics might ask how you know, but your visual
experience is the starting point.
Visual experience is fallible, though. Is that what you mean?
Yes, exactly. You need a foundation for knowledge, but it doesn’t
have to be infallible or absolutely perfect.
How about ethics? Where would you find a foundation there?
Well, everyone agrees that if you're in pain, you have a reason to
change things to reduce the pain. It's also easy to agree that once
you recognize others are like you, you’ll see there's a reason not
to cause them pain either. Through our natural inclination toward
altruism, we move from self-interest to caring about others. This
foundation for moral reasoning doesn’t seem to be merely
empirical—it’s grounded in the nature of pain and human
relationships.
Avoiding pain is key to moral standards, and another foundational
principle is that if you make a promise, you have an obligation to
fulfill it. It’s not an absolute reason, but most people who
understand human relations agree that promises come with
obligations. That’s a basic principle of interpersonal relationships,
and I argue it can be known through reason.
Optional Video- Robert Audi -
Theological Epistemology: How Can We
Know God?
Can we know God? If so, how? We can we believe in God. But
is such belief justified? How to apply the principles
of epistemology to knowledge of God and belief in God? What
would make belief in God justified true belief?
Robert, the question of whether God exists and what God is like
is a question that all human beings grapple with. I certainly have
throughout my life, and I've approached it analytically, trying to
discern answers through natural theology or logic. Some people
suggest that understanding God requires more of an experiential
factor, while others argue that only personal experience will
suffice. Stepping away from these perspectives, we can turn to
epistemology, the theory of knowledge, to explore what can be
learned about this question, particularly through religious
epistemology—the epistemology of religion and theology.
First, we must consider whether we're discussing God as a
personal figure known through the Bible, or the God of "perfect
being theology"—the omniscient, omnipotent, and perfectly good
God of the philosophers. Epistemology considers which being we
are referring to when we ask how we might know God. In my
work, I've emphasized that there can be knowledge without belief.
For example, consider a "meteorological knee" that acts like a
barometer, accurately predicting weather. The person might know
it's going to rain but wouldn't necessarily be justified in their
belief. This idea suggests that knowledge can exist without
justification.
If God is possible, and if God is omnipotent, it’s conceivable that
some people might have knowledge of God that is implanted in
them, as theologian Alvin Plantinga suggested with the concept
of a sensus divinitatis, as John Calvin also proposed. However,
this kind of knowledge might lack justification, which is what
many philosophers and skeptics demand. It’s important to
recognize that someone who believes in God could know God
exists without being justified in their belief. When someone
claims to have religious knowledge from experience, the
challenge shouldn't be that it's impossible to know but rather that
it lacks justification.
Now, there are many arguments for the existence of God, and if
these arguments form the basis for a person's belief, then the
belief is not "basic" but rather built upon evidence. However, if
belief in God comes from something like a sensus divinitatis, it
may be basic and akin to quasi-perceptual knowledge that arises
directly from experience, not inference. This experiential
knowledge could combine with various philosophical arguments
to create a cumulative case for belief in God. Theistic belief can
thus become rational for a person based on both experience and
reason.
There is a significant distinction between philosophical
arguments for God and personal experience. Philosophical
arguments are third-person communicable, while personal
experiences are subjective and cannot be easily conveyed to
others. For instance, if you tell me you've had a religious
experience, it might not have any effect on me. However, even in
something like art, those who are trained to appreciate it may have
perceptual experiences that others don't. Similarly, someone who
has had a religious experience might be able to argue that the
experience offers something meaningful, though it doesn't
directly prove God’s attributes like omniscience or omnipotence.
Arguments for God's existence, such as the ontological or
cosmological arguments, are intellectually stimulating, and I
enjoy them despite understanding their critiques. Yet, if I had a
religious experience, I might not trust it because of the potential
for emotional or physiological influences. I don’t think anyone
should rely solely on a single experience as intellectually
compelling without further evidence. However, hope can offer
another way forward. You can hope that God exists and is
sovereign in the universe, and hope doesn’t require as much
evidence as knowledge or firm belief.
In fact, you can move from hope to faith, which entails trusting in
God, even without strong evidence. This trust can motivate a
person positively without requiring certainty. The progression
from hope, to faith, to belief, and finally to knowledge reflects
different levels of engagement with the idea of God. Some theistic
beliefs might aspire to knowledge, but even those who hold firm
faith without extensive justification can live meaningful lives
based on that hope. Philosophers like Plantinga and Swinburne
have provided an array of arguments, each with some weight,
leaving individuals to discern the strength and significance of
these ideas for themselves.
Rationalism vs Empiricism Debate
Hello and welcome to Philosophy Vibe, the channel where we
discuss and debate different philosophical ideas. Today, we're
going to be discussing the difference between rationalism and
empiricism and looking at which approach is the preferable
explanation of attaining true knowledge.
Fascinating! Rationalism and empiricism have often been seen as
two opposing views within the subject of epistemology. I will
give a brief overview of each, and then John and I will look into
a number of different areas of life to determine which of the two
provides a better foundation for the discovery and source of
knowledge. Great, let's begin.
Rationalism Explained
Okay, so starting with rationalism, this is the idea that reason is
the main source of all knowledge. True knowledge is not just
discovered by empirical evidence or sensory experience, but in
fact, it can be discovered by the abilities of our rational minds.
The intellect alone is able to understand and discover true
knowledge.
I see. For rationalists, the main components for attaining
knowledge derive firstly from intuition—a built-in mental faculty
that allows us to recognize and understand what is true. This can
be described as a rational insight. Secondly, there's deduction,
which involves arriving at true knowledge based on logical, valid
premises. For example, we understand the concept of a triangle
and that it has three sides, so if we were to hold a triangular object,
we can deduce that the object we would be holding would have
three sides. Thirdly, there's the concept of innate knowledge or
innate concepts. This is the idea that the human mind is created
with certain types of knowledge already programmed. It can be
seen as a priori knowledge—it is knowledge we do not need
experience of to know, although experience may trigger the
knowledge into consciousness or awareness. Ultimately, it is part
of our nature and is there since birth. Innate knowledge can be
seen as coming from God, from another life, or even from a higher
reality, like Plato's world of forms. Nonetheless, all humans have
a certain innate knowledge.
Empiricism Explained
Interesting! Now, on the opposite side, we have empiricism. Quite
simply, this is the theory that all knowledge must derive from
sensory experience. The only way we can ever gain knowledge is
through experience; all knowledge is a posteriori and solely relied
upon the senses. Empiricists deny the existence of any innate
knowledge or innate concepts and hold that when we are born, we
are tabula rasa—we are a blank slate. There is no programmed
knowledge, ideas, concepts, or intuition; this is all gained over the
years via our sensory experiences within the empirical world.
Sense experience is therefore our only source of knowledge, and
nothing else.
Yes, yes, I understand. So, that is the brief but general overview
of rationalism and empiricism. So, I would ask you: which
approach would you see as the source for knowledge? Based on
the definitions, I would see myself as an empiricist.
Problems with Innate Knowledge
Why? I guess the main problem I see with rationalism is around
the belief in innate knowledge. I tend to agree with the idea of
tabula rasa for the simple fact that if we had innate knowledge
from a previous life, from God, or from a greater reality, then why
do we not carry this when we are born? Why do we have to learn
how to speak if we could once speak in a previous life? Why do
we have to learn how to go to the toilet or how to use cutlery or
how to ride a bike, and so on? Surely, if we had innate knowledge,
we would be born with all this knowledge already programmed;
we wouldn't need to learn it, but we do. To me, a baby seems more
like a blank slate rather than having innate knowledge.
I don't think that's entirely accurate. Although rationalists may
differ quite a lot in their beliefs around innate knowledge, I think
it's fair to say that no rationalist would argue that all knowledge
from another life or another world is with us as innate knowledge.
Only some core concepts or principles that we can recognize. And
even this may need to be brought to the forefront of our
consciousness by an empirical experience.
Problems with Tabula Rasa
Secondly, I would argue that tabula rasa, as a concept, is a lot
more problematic than innate knowledge. Think about how
different people are. Think about how some people excel in
certain areas compared with others, even though they have had
the same empirical experiences. How can two people attend the
same school, yet one is fantastic at writing while the other is a
gifted musician? This is definitely down to some innate ability.
We also see how different people have different interests; they
like different things. I, for example, enjoy country music, while
you enjoy heavy metal. I enjoy literature, while you enjoy
football. How, if we do not have an innate disposition, can we
differ so much? Surely if we were born blank slates, we would be
more similar than not. It seems people have their own natural
desires and interests, and these are with us from birth. These are
innate; we come stocked with these from birth. We are not blank
slates.
Rationalism vs. Empiricism for Scientific Knowledge
Okay, but still, all scientific discoveries—everything we have
developed in medicine, in technology—all of this is down to our
empirical observations. We rely on our understanding of the
empirical world, and our scientific laws are discovered a
posteriori via sense perception. This, for me, shows that the
empirical method of discovering knowledge is the only concrete
approach.
Again, I disagree with this point. We just need to look at
mathematics as concrete a priori truths developed from the
rationalist approach. Mathematics is a major part of science, of
all physics and technology. Mathematical concepts do not rely on
our experience—they are purely a rational game. Their truths
exist in our intellect, not in our five senses. You do not need
empirical experience to understand the concept of one and two
and to understand that one plus one equals two.
Really? I'm not so sure about that. Yes, we do use our intellect for
mathematics, but this is also grounded in sense experience. We
actually experience the concept of one; we see single objects, we
also see multiple objects. So, I can see one tree, and I know if I
see another tree, then this would make two trees. I think the
concepts of numbers need sensory experience to understand the
concepts.
No, I have to disagree here. We understand the concept of pi
without seeing a physical representation of 3.1415, etc., etc. I
would argue numbers are purely a rational a priori game, and so
to dismiss rationalism as having nothing to do with scientific
truths is a mistake.
Rationalism vs. Empiricism for Ethical Knowledge
Okay, so outside of science, I would say rationalism is a better
approach to ethical truths. How come?
Because an intuition and innate knowledge explains why we can
recognize good and evil, moral and immoral, instinctively.
Although we may struggle to exactly define what morality is and
come up with a universal behavioral code, we can still recognize
morality. We understand it. We know when something is good,
and we know when something is evil. And it is just our intuition
guiding us. We cannot use our senses to determine whether
something is right or wrong; our senses cannot determine justice,
loyalty—these are larger concepts. We just recognize them when
we see them; these are our innate concepts.
Well, assuming morality is realist and does exist external to an
individual's personal emotions, it can be argued that it can be
discovered through the senses. We can see when people are hurt,
when people are suffering, we can feel this as well, and we usually
judge pain as being morally wrong. This is enough to say that
moral truths can be discovered by the empirical method.
Without getting into an ethical debate, I would say that morality
is a lot deeper than pain and pleasure, so I don't think the
empiricist position is sufficient in discovering ethical truths.
Beyond the Empirical Knowledge and the Problem of
Induction
Very well, moving on. I would say rationalism is our only
approach to any metaphysical discussions. Empiricism cannot
shine any light on anything beyond the empirical world. Meaning
any conversation or discussion that goes beyond what we
perceive with our senses needs a rationalist position.
Okay, but you must agree the empiricist approach is much
simpler. It is grounded in the empirical world that we all perceive
and feel. Rationalism needs almost a mystical, spiritual, or
religious belief to accompany it. We all prefer to work with that
in which we can verify with our senses, rather than blind belief.
Occam's Razor would say the simplest theory is the better theory,
and empiricism is definitely a simpler theory as it does not rely
on unobservable concepts such as intuition or innate knowledge.
But empiricism falls into a dead end once we realize that how we
perceive the empirical world is not necessarily what truly exists.
We all know and are aware that our senses are fallible; they
deceive us, they lie to us, and they do not represent what actually
exists. We also understand that our senses are inconsistent—not
only with other people's senses, but with our own previous
experiences at different times of our lives. Now, how can we
honestly say the empirical method is the only way of attaining
true knowledge if we know that our senses deceive, misrepresent,
and are inconsistent?
Yes, I see. If we only use the empiricist approach, then we come
to see that our sense experience can only offer us deductive
knowledge at best. If I visit a pond for the first time in my life and
I see five white ducks, I can reach the empirical conclusion that
all ducks are white. This is based on my sense experience, but it
is obviously wrong. All sense experience offers is predictions
based on what we have experienced; it does not offer concrete
absolute truth. This leads us to the problem of induction, where
we cannot have
Justified True Belief & The Gettier
Problem (Epistemology)
Hello and welcome to Philosophy Vibe, the channel where we
discuss and debate different philosophical ideas. Today we're
going to be focusing on some epistemology and looking into the
theory of justified true belief.
Interesting. Now, epistemology is the philosophical study of
knowledge. It looks into the very nature of knowledge: what is
knowledge and how can it be defined? The justified true belief
theory was devised as an answer to the philosophy of
epistemology. In this video, we will explain what justified true
belief is and look into the objection raised against the theory,
known as the Gettier problem.
Excellent. So, justified true belief has been widely accepted as the
criteria for knowledge, some say as far back as the works of Plato.
When looking into the nature of knowledge, one can be said to
know something, or have knowledge of something, if it is justified
true belief. Meaning, someone has a belief, is justified in having
that belief, and that belief is actually true.
So, let's say I know X. I have a belief in X, I have justification in
believing in X—meaning my belief in X is well-supported based
on good evidence and reason—and X is, in fact, true. This would
classify as my knowledge of X.
Can you frame this in a specific example? Okay, so let's say I have
knowledge that there is a tree at the bottom of my road. Yes, this
can only be considered knowledge if it meets the justified true
belief criteria. So, I have a belief that there is a tree at the bottom
of my road. Now, I have seen this tree with my own eyes, I have
seen it at different times of the day, for months on end. Other
people have also seen this tree and have discussed it with me. So,
I am justified in having this belief. The belief that there is a tree
at the bottom of my road is perfectly justified, and finally, the
belief I have is true. There is a tree at the bottom of my road. If
we went there now, the tree would be there, or if we got live
images by satellite of the road, we would see the tree. This then
becomes knowledge. It is knowledge because my belief is
justified and true.
I see. Take out any of the criteria, and it does not become
knowledge. You could have a belief, and it could be true, but if
it’s not justified, it is not knowledge—just a guess. For example,
I have a belief that there is a tree at the bottom of my road, and
the reason is because I saw a tree there 10 years ago, but I haven’t
traveled to the bottom of my road since. Let us say it is true, the
tree is still there. My belief is true, but my belief was not justified.
In 10 years, the tree could have been chopped down. My belief
was not justified; it was just a guess. So, even though it is true,
my belief is not knowledge.
Yes, I understand. Likewise, even if your belief is justified but
false, this would obviously not be knowledge. Let’s say I saw the
tree two minutes ago, left the scene, and it was immediately cut
down. My belief that there is a tree at the bottom of the road is
entirely justified, but it is false, and so it is not knowledge.
Yes, that makes sense. So, the only way we can be said to know
something is if we have a belief, we are justified in having this
belief, and this belief is, in fact, true. Only then can we say we
have true knowledge. This makes perfect sense and is a
reasonable and logical approach to epistemology. However, when
we dig a little deeper, we do find problems with the justified true
belief approach.
Explain.
So now, I want to bring up the Gettier problem. This problem was
named after the philosopher Edmund Gettier, who came up with
some scenarios in a 1963 paper to show how having justified true
belief could still result in not having knowledge.
Go ahead. In the first scenario, Gettier asks us to imagine Smith
and Jones, who have both applied for the same job. Jones
interviews first, then Smith has his interview. At the end of
Smith’s interview, the CEO of the company tells Smith that he
will be hiring Jones. Smith also remembers that Jones has exactly
10 coins in his pocket; he saw Jones counting them earlier. So,
based on all of this, Smith forms the following belief: the person
who will get the job has 10 coins in his pocket. This is Smith’s
belief, and based on the evidence, Smith is perfectly justified in
having this belief.
Correct.
However, the CEO comes out of his office and loudly claims that
the job will be going to Smith, not to Jones.
Okay, so Smith’s justified belief was, in fact, false.
No. See, Gettier asks us to imagine that Smith himself actually
does have 10 coins in his pocket. He just completely forgot about
them, but after the CEO congratulates him, he puts his hand in his
pocket and realizes he has 10 coins. Okay, so think about it:
Smith’s belief was justified, and Smith’s belief was true, as the
person who got the job did have 10 coins in his pocket. However,
Smith did not know he would be getting the job. He had justified
true belief that was not knowledge. This scenario shows that
justified true belief cannot be a universal condition for
knowledge.
I see. Gettier then had a second scenario. Upon leaving the
interview, Smith sees Jones driving off in a Ford. At the same
time, Smith remembers his friend Brown, who once owned a
Ford, but now Smith has no idea where Brown is. So, Smith
develops the following belief: either Jones owns a Ford, or Brown
is in Barcelona. Smith is justified in this belief as he has seen
Jones driving off in the Ford. As it happens, Jones is just hiring
the Ford; he does not own it. And, by coincidence, Brown actually
is in Barcelona. So, Smith’s justified belief is again true. Only,
Smith had no knowledge of where Brown was, and he had no
knowledge that Jones did not own the Ford. Once again, this
shows problems with the justified true belief approach.
Yes, yes, I see. From this, many more scenarios have been
developed showing the problems with the JTB approach.
I do see how the Gettier problem poses a flaw for the justified true
belief approach. However, in the two scenarios, Smith’s beliefs
are based on incorrect information and incorrect premises. Even
though the belief was justified and true, it was reached based on
a falsehood, namely that Jones would get the job and that Jones
owns a Ford. We may be able to salvage the JTB theory if we
change it slightly.
In what way? We could say that any belief based on a false
premise or even based on fallible information cannot be
considered justified. Even though the belief is true and the
justification seems right, the method in which the justification
was met was based on false information. In order for the belief to
be justified, it must be provided by infallible support; it cannot
have any errors or falsehoods.
This seems like too much of a rigid and narrow path to
knowledge. What exactly do we mean by infallible supports, and
how can we know what is false information while we are forming
our beliefs? How many true beliefs have we developed as
knowledge throughout our lives, even though we may have
reached them through some false information? And surely, all
justification for beliefs will have some element of fallibility. Even
our senses are not infallible, so evidence we see with our eyes or
hear with our ears would then not qualify as justification for
belief. This would pretty much render all beliefs unjustifiable, and
all knowledge will be thrown out the window, opening the door
to extreme skepticism.
Hmm, good point. If you enjoy the Philosophy Vibe discussions
and want to help support the channel, then please check out the
Philosophy Vibe Anthology book set available on Amazon. These
are a collection of our scripts compiled into three volumes:
Philosophy of Religion, Metaphysics and Ethics, and Political
Philosophy—a great read for anyone getting into philosophy or
studying it academically. All purchases really help us out; the
links are below.
But that’s all the time we have for now. Thank you for watching;
we hope you enjoyed the vibe. And what does everyone else
think? Is justified true belief the best method in defining
knowledge? Let us know in the comments below. Don’t forget to
like and share, and for more philosophical debates, please
subscribe to the channel. Take care, and we look forward to seeing
you all soon.