research paper

Download as docx, pdf, or txt
Download as docx, pdf, or txt
You are on page 1of 16

1

RESPECT FOR ANIMALS AND ECOLOGY

TAKING LIFE: ANIMALS

Group 3(sem III)


1. Coral Upadhyay (coordinator)
2. Ashutosh Chaturvedi
3. Pankhudi Gautam
4. Mayank Raj
5. Silica Mangal
6. Bengia Yemin
2

ACKNOWLEDGEMENT
We would like to convey our heartfelt gratitude to our teacher
Mr.Krishna Mani Pathak for his Tremendous support and
assistance in the completion of our project and for providing us
with this wonderful opportunity to work on the Research Paper
entitled RESPECT FOR ANIMALS AND ECOLOGY - TAKING
LIFE (Animals) . The completion of the Project would not have
been possible without his help and insights. We Acknowledge that
this project was completed entirely by us and not by someone else.
3

Index
Chapter I
1. Abstract
2. Introduction
3. Arguments For Equality
Chapter II
1. Defining Personhood
2. Notable examples
3. Criticism
Chapter III
1. Utilitarianism
2. Speciesism and The Argument Of Need
3. Criticism
Chapter IV
1. Capacity for Self Consciousness
2. The Utilitarian Approach
3. The Replaceability Argument
4. Killing Of Non Self Conscious Being
Chapter V
1. Conclusion
2. References
4

Respect For Animals and Ecology


Taking Life- Animals
Group 3 (seem III)
CHAPTER I
Abstract
This paper is based on Peter Singer's ethical approach towards animals. Singer is
known for his controversial that people should not be evaluated based on their species,
but rather on their ability to suffer. This argument, referred to as speciesism, opposes
the assumption that human beings possess a life that is intrinsically richer than that of
all other animals. Animal welfare has several aspects, one of which is the attitude
towards animals which will be discussed in this paper. This paper will seek to address
the issue of whether or not it is ethical to kill animals having in mind their complexity,
environmental factors, consciousness and suffering.In conclusion, this research
expects a more complete, sensitive, and empathetic understanding of the moral issues
in respect to animals. This essay will argue that animals should be treated with greater
respect and humaneness by focusing on their suffering and the expansion of animal
rights through the lens of Singer’s utilitarianism.

Introduction
Now a days, we often here debates on topics such as vegetarianism versus non-
vegetarianism, to be a vegetarian or a vegan, should we stop the experiments that
include animals as test subjects. These are just some of the key debates under this
wider umbrella topic about killing animals or treating them as means for satisfying
human ends. This topic about whether we should treat animals as ends or means has,
now, been debated for an aeon. This paper will try to put forward some key debates
regarding this topic and try to analyse these arguments.

Arguments for Equality


One of the arguments in favour of not killing animals is given by Paul W. Taylor, in
his work, “Ethics of Respect for Nature”, he has talked about the ‘Good of a being and
the inherent worth of all life’ (Taylor, 1981, p – 2). Taylor mentions that all life on this
planet have inherent value and that, their value is not decided according to their use
for humans but, as per their own ‘good’, that is, the ability for the survival and
5

sustenance of their species. A similar argument was proposed by Tom Regan, in his
work, “The case for Animal Rights”, he argues that we must develop respect for all
life since, they all are having intrinsic value or worth (Regan, 1983, p- 4). So, he is
suggesting that we should just accept their value as life form and not as means to
satisfy our personal or collective needs. Another point of view that can be taken is that
provided by Immanual Kant in his “Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals”. Kant
has mentioned the difference between things that have price and dignity, he says,
“what has a price can be replaced by something else as its equivalent, what on the
other hand is raised above all price and therefore admits of no equivalent has a
dignity”. (Gregor, 1998, p- 42). Kant is suggesting, by this, that there is nothing that
can equate or balance dignity and therefore, dignity must be respected and we as
humans are naturally having this dignity. So, this point of view of Kant can also be
extended to include other life forms and then, we can ensure that the dignity of those
lives is protected as it cannot be replaced by any price. Moreover, we as rational
beings must realize that our own life will not be possibly without all other life forms,
hence we must extend the moral status of equality and dignity to other life forms.
Furthermore, Peter Singer, the Australian thinker in his book, “Practical Ethics”, has
provided some arguments in favour of us, not killing animals and how we should go
about stating logical justifications for the same. The next section of this paper will
examine and evaluate these arguments given by Peter Singer.

CHAPTER II
Can a Non-Human Animal Be a Person
The question of whether a non-human animal can be a person is one that sits at the
intersection of philosophy, ethics, and animal cognition studies. The term "person" is
typically reserved for human beings, but it is important to clarify what is meant by
"personhood." In this presentation, we will explore definitions of personhood, the
cognitive capacities of non-human animals, and philosophical arguments for and
against attributing personhood to non-human animals.

I. Defining Personhood
The first step in addressing this question is to define what we mean by "person." The
concept of personhood typically involves a cluster of characteristics:
6

1. Self-awareness – The ability to recognize oneself as distinct from others.


2. Rationality – The ability to reason and solve complex problems.
3. Autonomy – The capacity to make decisions and control one’s actions.
4. Moral agency – The ability to discern right from wrong and be held
accountable for actions.
5. Communication – The capacity for complex communication, including
language or symbols.
6. Social relations – The ability to form meaningful relationships with others.
Historically, these traits have been associated primarily with humans. However,
modern studies in animal cognition have prompted a revaluation of whether these
criteria might also apply to certain non- human animals.

II. Notable Examples

1. Great Apes (Chimpanzees, Bonobos, Gorillas)


 Self-Awareness (Mirror Test): Chimpanzees and bonobos are known to pass
the mirror test, which is a measure of self-awareness. When placed in front of a
mirror with a mark on their body, they will use the mirror to inspect and touch
the mark, indicating that they recognize the reflection as themselves.
 Tool Use and Problem Solving: Chimpanzees use tools in the wild, such as
sticks to extract termites from mounds or rocks to crack open nuts. This
suggests a level of rationality and problem-solving ability, which are
traditionally associated with personhood.
 Communication: The famous gorilla Koko learned to communicate through
American Sign Language (ASL). She reportedly knew over 1,000 signs and
could express emotions such as sadness and joy, demonstrating a capacity for
symbolic communication and emotional depth.
2. Dolphins
 Self-Awareness (Mirror Test): Dolphins are another species that passes the
mirror test, indicating self-recognition. They are aware of themselves and can
understand their own reflection, which is a strong indicator of higher-level
cognitive processes.
7

 Complex Communication: Dolphins use complex vocalizations to


communicate with one another, and they are capable of understanding artificial
languages created by researchers. Some studies suggest that dolphins have
individual "names" in the form of signature whistles, which is similar to how
humans use names to identify individuals.
 Emotional Intelligence and Social Behaviour: Dolphins display empathetic
behaviour and social cooperation. For example, there are accounts of dolphins
helping injured pod members and even assisting humans in distress. Their
ability to form strong social bonds and act altruistically suggests a level of
emotional intelligence akin to that of humans.
3. Elephants
 Empathy and Mourning: Elephants are known for their deep emotional bonds
and their capacity for empathy. They engage in behaviours that suggest
mourning for deceased members of their group, such as standing vigil over the
body and showing signs of distress. This level of emotional complexity hints at
a form of moral awareness and social relationships that may meet some criteria
for personhood.
 Problem-Solving and Tool Use: Elephants can use tools to solve problems,
such as modifying branches to swat away flies. They also exhibit cooperation
and teamwork in certain tasks, which demonstrates planning and decision-
making skills.
 Self-Awareness (Mirror Test): Elephants have also passed the mirror test,
further supporting their capacity for self-recognition and reflection, which is a
key marker for some definitions of personhood.
4. Octopuses
 Problem-Solving and Intelligence: Octopuses are highly intelligent
invertebrates capable of solving puzzles and escaping from enclosures in
captivity. Their ability to navigate complex mazes and their use of tools, like
coconut shells for protection, suggests that they have cognitive abilities that
challenge traditional assumptions about the intelligence of non-human animals.
 Autonomy: Octopuses show a high degree of autonomy in their decision-
making, from exploring their environment to displaying creative problem-
solving strategies when faced with new challenges.
5. African Grey Parrots
8

 Language Use: The African Grey Parrot Alex, who was studied by Rd. Irene
Pepperberg, showed remarkable cognitive and linguistic abilities. Alex was able
to recognize shapes, colours, numbers, and even understand abstract concepts
like “same” and “different.” His use of language indicated that he could
communicate his desires and understand questions in a way that resembled
human communication.
 Emotional and Social Understanding: Alex demonstrated an understanding of
emotional concepts, such as displaying frustration when he didn’t want to
participate in a task. His capacity for communication and comprehension
suggests that some birds may possess traits we associate with personhood.
6. Whales
 Social Structures and Communication: Whales, especially orcas (killer
whales), are known for their complex social structures and highly developed
forms of communication. Orcas live in matrilineal societies where knowledge is
passed down through generations, and different pods use unique vocal dialects,
which may be considered a form of culture.
 Empathy and Social Bonds: Whales have been observed to demonstrate
empathy and care for one another, including caring for sick or injured pod
members. They also exhibit mourning behaviours when a calf dies, showing the
emotional complexity that can be tied to social relationships.
7. Crows and Ravens (Corvids)
 Tool Use: Crows and ravens are known for their impressive problem-solving
abilities and tool use. For instance, New Caledonian crows can craft tools from
sticks to extract insects from tree bark. Some crows have even been observed
bending wires to create hooks for retrieving food, a behaviour that demonstrates
foresight and innovation.
 Planning and Memory: Crows are capable of planning for the future, storing
food in specific locations and remembering those spots for later. They also
display the ability to deceive others by pretending to store food in one location
while actually storing it in another, indicating an understanding of others’
intentions and perspectives.

III. Criticism
9

1. Human-Centric Definition of Personhood


 The concept of personhood is often seen as intrinsically tied to human beings.
Philosophers like Immanuel Kant argue that personhood is based on rationality
and moral autonomy, traits that are fully realized only in humans. Non-human
animals, even if intelligent, do not possess moral reasoning or the ability to
reflect on abstract ethical principles, making them unqualified for personhood in
this view.
2. Lack of Moral Agency
 A key criterion for personhood in many philosophical traditions is moral agency
—the ability to make moral decisions and be held accountable for one's actions.
Most animals, while they may exhibit empathy or social behaviours, do not
engage in moral deliberation in the same way humans do. Critics argue that
lacking moral agency disqualifies non-human animals from being considered
persons.
3. Practical and Legal Challenges
 Granting personhood to non-human animals would have far-reaching legal and
practical implications. Critics argue that this would disrupt human activities,
including food production, medical research, and pet ownership. The legal
system is not designed to accommodate non-human persons, which could create
logistical and ethical dilemmas that are difficult to resolve in practice.
4. Gradations of Cognitive Abilities
 While some non-human animals exhibit advanced cognitive abilities (e.g., self-
awareness, problem-solving), these traits vary widely across species. Critics
argue that if personhood is tied to cognitive abilities, it becomes difficult to
draw a clear line between which animals qualify and which do not. This raises
concerns about inconsistency and arbitrariness in how personhood is granted.
5. Personhood as a Social Construct
 Some philosophers argue that personhood is a socially constructed concept,
designed to confer rights and responsibilities within human societies. Non-
human animals do not participate in human social, legal, or moral frameworks
in the same way humans do, and therefore, applying the concept of personhood
to them may be inappropriate or incoherent.

CHAPTER III
10

Killing Non-Human Animals


Understanding Nonhuman Personhood At the heart of this debate is the idea that
personhood should not be confined to humans. Historically, personhood has been
characterised by characteristics like as self-awareness, rationality, and the ability to
maintain a consistent sense of self. While most humans display these characteristics, a
growing body of data suggests that some non-human animals also possess them.
Pioneering researchers such as Jane Goodall have documented complex social
behaviours, emotional connections, and problem-solving ability in chimps, while
studies on dolphins and whales show similar cognitive capacities. If we accept that
certain nonhuman creatures can be considered as individuals, we must reconsider the
ethical consequences of ending their lives. The idea of the "sanctity of personal life"
contends that the value of life is not limited to humans but applies to all beings who
embody persons. This viewpoint encourages us to reconsider behaviours such as
animal testing, factory farming, and the exploitation of animals for entertainment,
encouraging us to consider the moral respect and protection these creatures deserve.
Philosopher Peter Singer has been a notable advocate for the moral consideration of
animals. In his seminal work, Animal Liberation, Singer criticises the arbitrary
differences that separate human and non-human life, arguing that many animals,
notably giant apes, deserve equal moral treatment based on cognitive capacity. Singer
emphasises the idea of equal consideration of interests, suggesting that nonhuman
beings' goals in avoiding pain and death should be given equal weight to those of
humans. He emphasises how present procedures involving nonhuman persons
frequently violate this notion by prioritising human convenience over the lives and
welfare of these animals.

I. Utilitarianism

Utilitarianism provides a serious ethical framework for considering the subject of


killing non-human beings, emphasising the need of minimising suffering while
maximising total well-being. Classical utilitarians, such as Jeremy Bentham, claimed
that the capacity to suffer, rather than personality, should be the basis for moral
concern. From this perspective, non-human animals' interests in avoiding pain and
suffering are just as morally meaningful as humans. A more complex version of this
concept, known as "preferential utilitarianism," expands the discussion regarding
personhood. This viewpoint contends that beings capable of self-awareness and future
planning merit special moral concern. As a consequence, the act of murdering non-
11

human persons—such as chimps or dolphins—becomes a more serious ethical matter


than killing non-person animals.

II. Speciesism and The Argument of Need

In case you are unaware, I would like to draw your attention to the fact that rabbits
are employed for cosmetic testing simply because they lack tear ducts, which
prevents them from washing off the items like our eyes do. They suffer pain,
become blind as a result, and are subsequently put to death. Hens are housed in tiny
enclosures, their beaks are clipped to prevent injury to one another, and those that
are unable to lay eggs are murdered and turned into a delicacy to satisfy human
tastes. Would you ever do these things to a human? The answer is no; nobody
would. Peter Singer correctly referred to this as speciesism, which Favors our own
species over others. For a long time, people thought that distinctions in skin colour,
which are morally meaningless, were acceptable for members of one group to
discriminate with members of another group. But the idea that if something is bad
for humans, it's bad for animals, too. Making a distinction between animals and
human beings based solely on intelligence is incredibly illogical. Carl Cohen, a
proud speciesism, states, "Every species is struggling to claw its way to the top,
and that's how it should be. Each and every species is very concerned about
protecting itself. Right now, humans are at the top, which means they are the best
and can do whatever they want." The issue here is that if you belong to the
privileged species, you will be perfectly fine with this kind of social structure, but
if you are not, you will not be okay with it. Another justification used here is that
this is how things have always been done. It is true that we are dominant; it is a
part of our culture; our lives as farmers, fishermen, and so forth are based on it, but
the fact that something has been done a certain way doesn't necessarily mean that it
is necessarily good. According to the argument of need, it is acceptable to take a
human life in order to defend oneself or to eat in order to exist, but not for aesthetic
reasons or simply because you are able to kill someone. These days, people can
live perfectly healthy lives without consuming any animals. Today, humans can be
perfectly healthy without eating animals. Singer says we should talk about
nonhuman animals in terms of equal consideration of interest. This means identical
interests should be given equal weight regardless of the type of being they occur in.
All the species on earth have different interests because of the different intellects
and perseverance’s of the world, but we do share a common interest that is
avoiding pain; nobody likes suffering. emery Bentham, Singer's utilitarian ancestor,
12

contends that the inquiry is "can they suffer" rather than "can they reason" or "can
they talk." We are all equally capable of feeling pain and equally inclined to avoid
it. Utilitarians hold that we have no right to prioritize humans above other species
and that all interests should be taken into account equally. They are not against the
prohibition of using animals but rather against the thinking that animals are at our
disposal. Since they are also creatures that feel they need to be a part of the
utilitarian calculus. Simply because we can, we do it. We entitle ourselves to
believe that all life was created to serve human beings; billions of animals are
killed per year just because we self-entitle that we are the greatest species on earth.
Yes, we do have a right to nourishment, but we do not have a right to kill.

III. Criticism (antithesis)

However, the compassionate framework regarding the moral considerations of


animals, supported by Peter Singer's argument doesn't come without any criticisms.
1) Immanuel Kant’s ethical idea:
“Only humans, who can reason and follow moral laws, have moral agency and deserve
to be treated as ends in themselves.” can be desperately exaggerated as in the case
Philosophers like Roger Scruton and John Finnis who dives into the conflict between
moral agency & moral patient hood, argues that the idea of personhood should be
limited to the moral agents only, in this case only humans. For that the human only can
decide what is wrong and what is not. I personally disagree with this idea, as the
parameter of personhood can Never be conflated with the ability to make moral
judgements, for the ability to do something and actually doing something are two
different things that we should consider. For example, there are many incidents where
humans, even though equipped as sophisticated moral agents, does ruthlessly,
something which is immoral even in the darkest oceans of Mariana trench. On the
contrary many recorded incidents, on social media platforms and others, shouts loudly
referring to the empathic nature of animals even though they are not considered as
“moral agents”
2) religion-centric Point of view:
Certain religious doctrines, particularly those rooted in the belief that humans are
made in the image of God, oppose Peter Singer's notion of extending personhood to
animals. These doctrines emphasize the unique moral status of humans, viewing them
as special creations with inherent dignity and value that sets them apart from other life
forms. This perspective often critiques Singer's utilitarian approach as morally
13

relativistic, suggesting that it undermines the intrinsic worth of human life. In contrast,
many Oriental religions advocate for a deep respect for all life forms, promoting a
holistic view of existence where every being has a role and deserves consideration.
This respect for the interconnectedness of life challenges the anthropocentric
viewpoint, encouraging a more inclusive ethical framework that acknowledges the
value of all living entities, thereby enriching moral discourse beyond the limitations of
relativism.
3) It's a slippery-slope:
Peter Singer's argument for extending personhood to certain animals is met with
slippery slope critique on how to determine which species qualify for moral
consideration. By relying on subjective criteria such as IQ or emotional capacity, we
risk making arbitrary distinctions that lead to contradictions. For example, if cognitive
capacities are the major criterion, do we ignore animals with complex behaviours,
such as pigs and chickens, while eliminating those considered "lesser"? This raises
serious concerns regarding who selects which animals are deserving of personhood
and the justification for those standards. Such subjectivity can lead to discrimination
against species that do not fulfil artificial criteria, complicated ethical debates and
perhaps weakening the values of equality and respect for all sentient beings.
4) Anthropocentrism
Critics of Peter Singer's extension of personhood to animals frequently point out its
anthropocentric consequences. Detractors claim that by prioritising particular species
depending on subjective characteristics such as IQ or emotional capacity, Singer
unintentionally encourages a human-centric worldview. This viewpoint contends that
human characteristics should define moral consideration, which can result in a species
hierarchy that maintains humans at the top. Critics argue that this approach
undermines the fundamental value of all living beings by implying that certain lives
are more valuable than others simply because they have human characteristics.
Furthermore, this anthropocentric approach runs the risk of rationalising the
exploitation of animals that do not fit these arbitrary standards, perpetuating a circle of
moral contradiction while ignoring all living forms' ecological interdependence.

CHAPTER IV
Ethical Issues in Killing Other Animals
14

I. Capacity for Self-Consciousness

A central point in the opposition to the killing of animals is the fact that they view
themselves as individuals across time. This applies primarily to the higher
mammals like chimpanzees, gorillas among other animals that are known to behave
in a self-conscious manner. Therefore, the argument against killing such animals is
as convincing as the argument against killing people who have low intelligence.
Such beings not only feel pain but also possess some level of self that makes their
killing ethical equal to killing a person with low intelligence. This view calls for
the need to recognize the rights of animal to be particular about their mental
capacities, in agreement with Tooley’s view on rights.

II. The Utilitarian Approach:

A Point of View that Advocates for the Welfare of Animals if it Brings About
Greater Benefits. Involving the primal method of killing non-self-conscious animal
beings, especially those non humans often raise tension. The axiom of
utilitarianism in a very simplistic way is: try as much as it is possible to make as
happier and less of suffering as it gets. Thus, the morality of actions like killing fish
or other animals is dependent on the brutality involved and the larger impact for
the fish or animals’ society. Common ways of Utilitarianism include killing that
causes no pain to the fish and or their family members such as birds or mammals.
The explanation itself is transferred to modern day farms where animals undergo
pain for long before being killed. Though, utilitarianism is an all-inclusive theory
for the dispassionate killing. One of the Estimates Here chanson is simply changed
from the pain inflicted on the animal to the question: does this animal enjoy more
in its life than it suffers? Utilitarianism contains the so-called ‘prior existence
view’ which holds that killing an animal may be alright as long as that animal’s
death does not affect the possibility of a greater good being served. It is so extreme
that considering eating meat is wrong most conditions. The ‘total view’, on the
other hand, tends to even conceptualize the loss of an animal in terms of the birth
of another, as if in killing there is no such thing as moral wrong if the animal’s
death leads to the creation of a similarly pleasurable existence for a new
animal.

III. The Replaceability Argument


15

The replaceability argument is polarizing. In the broadest sense, animals can be


replaced by other animals. For instance, when an animal raised for food is
slaughtered and served, but another animal possesses the exact purpose and is bred
for it, the net utility in this scenario is unchanged and the slaughter is, therefore,
justified under the total view of utilitarianism. This argument is weakened,
however, by the reality that animals raised for consumption, particularly in factory
farms, often live miserable lives. The pain and agony that such animals undergo
prior to being slaughtered involuntarily cancels out the logic also advanced towards
the use of replaceability. There is also, as noted by opponents such as Henry Salt, a
cognitive issue with regard to the absence of a comparison to existence, and vice
versa. It is untenable to suggest that giving rise to a being enhances that being
because no being exists to receive such an enhancement prior to their conception.
Hence, even though the replacement argument could, in theory, support the
killing of animals in optimal settings, it cannot do that in a significant majority of
everyday circumstances.

IV. Killing of Non-Self-Conscious Being:

For non-self-conscious beings, dying is not regarded as a great loss. These animals
do not have, as humans or other self-conscious beings do, thoughts or expectations
about things that may happen in the future. As such, their death is merely the end of
having experiences, rather the same way that birth is the beginning of having
experiences. Thus, killing a non-self-conscious animal does not contradict the same
moral principles as killing a self-conscious one subject to the
condition that the killing should not inflict pain and harm–emotional or physical–to
other people
and animals.

CHAPTER V
Conclusion
The question of whether killing animals is right or wrong involves ethical, ecological,
and cultural considerations. Ethically, many of you think that killing animals is
unjustifiable as it causes suffering and disregards the intrinsic value of human beings.
While some claim-controlled killing can serve ecological purposes, contemporary
16

perspectives increasingly project this advocating for alternative bases to manage


ecosystems without harming animals. Cultural practices and traditions may justify
killing in certain contexts, but this is being increasingly challenged in Favor of more
compassionate approaches. Peter Singer's philosophers claim that it is unethical to kill
animals due to their ability to suffer. Animal liberation fingers are used that
consideration should be given to such an entity regardless of whether it is human or
nonhuman. This is called speciesism, a tendency that is unjust in attempting to Favor
one's own species. In singers view, killing animals for no good reason is morally
permissible because it is against the idea of equal consideration of the interests of
nonhuman animals. To such a level they have interest, which includes evading pain in
continuing existence. If the interest in nonhuman animals is treated in the same way as
the human interest, it would be apparent that inflicting either food-based, sport-based,
or other forms of ill treatment upon them is ethically unjustifiable. This view is
specifically utilitarian, where an effort is made towards reduction of suffering and
enhancing well-being, and since animals are also capable of suffering, exterminating
them in the absence of considerable justification causes unnecessary injury. We should
never kill animals because they are sentient beans capable of feeling pain, fear, and
suffering just like us. Their lives have value, and taking them away causes
unnecessary harm and heartbreak. By choosing compassion and nonviolence, we can
honour their right to live freely without causing suffering and create a world where
kindness extends to all living creatures.

References
1. Peter singer's article Taking life: Animals
2. Stuart Hampshir, oxford philosopher: Human nature
3. Singer, Peter. Animal Liberation. HarperCollins, 1975.
4. Cohen, Carl. “Do Animals Have Rights?” Ethics & Behavior, 1986.
5. Gregor, M. (1998), Immanual Kant: Groundwork of the Metaphysics of
Morals, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
6. Regan, T. (1983), The Case for Animal Rights, Berkeley: University of
California Press.
7. Taylor, Paul W. (1981), The Ethics of Respect for Nature. Environmental
Ethics 3, 197– 218.

You might also like