Economic Growth Under Transformative AI
Economic Growth Under Transformative AI
transformative AI
A guide to the vast range of possibilities for output growth,
wages, and the labor share
∗
Thanks to Tim Blomfield and Nicholas Emery for contributions to the literature sum-
maries and organization.
†
Global Priorities Institute and Department of Economics, University of Oxford.
Contact: [email protected].
‡
Department of Economics and Darden School of Business, University of Virginia,
NBER and CEPR.
1
Contents
1 Introduction 2
2 Economics background 5
2.1 Production and factor shares . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 5
2.2 Substitution . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 6
2.3 Exogenous growth . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 8
2.4 (Semi-)endogenous growth . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 11
5 AI in technology production 38
5.1 Learning by doing . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 39
5.2 Automated research . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 40
5.3 AI assistance in research . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 45
5.4 Growth impacts via impacts on technology investment . . . . 47
8 Conclusion 55
A Proofs 59
2
1 Introduction
At least since Herbert Simon’s 1960 prediction that artificial intelligence
would soon replace all human labor, many economists have understood that
there is a possibility that sooner or later artificial intelligence (AI) will dra-
matically transform the global economy. AI could have a transformative
impact on a wide variety of domains; indeed, it could transform market struc-
ture, the value of education, the geopolitical balance of power, and practically
anything else.
We will focus on three of the clearest and best-studied classes of potential
transformations in economics: the potential impacts on output growth, on
wage growth, and on the labor share, i.e. the share of output paid as wages. On
all counts we will focus on long-run impacts rather than transition dynamics.
Instead of attempting to predict the future, our focus will be on surveying
the vast range of possibilities identified in the economics literature.
Standard growth models imply that the potential impact of AI on the
growth rate of output could take the form of
• a decrease to the growth rate, even perhaps rendering it negative;
• a permanent increase to the growth rate, as the Industrial Revolution
increased the global growth rate from near zero to something over two
percent per year;
• a continuous acceleration in growth, with the growth rate growing
unboundedly as time tends to infinity (what, following Aghion et al.
(2019), we will call a “Type I growth explosion”); or even
• an acceleration in the growth rate rapid enough to produce infinite
output in finite time (a “Type II growth explosion”).1
Basic physics suggests that the last of these scenarios is impossible, of
course—as is eternal exponential or super-exponential growth. The relevant
possibility is that AI induces a growth path that resembles these benchmarks
for some time, until production confronts limiting factors, such as land or
energy, that have never or have not recently been important constraints on
growth. We will thus also consider how increases in growth may eventually
be choked off by such limiting factors.
1
Type II growth explosions, as we will call them, are the literal mathematical singular-
ities after which views of rapid AI-induced growth are sometimes called “singularitarian”.
The term “singularity” is used in several different ways throughout the literature covered
here, however, so we will generally avoid it—except in the context of the “singularity
condition” of Mookherjee and Ray (2017) (§3.4).
3
2 Economics background
Literature on the economics of AI extends prior literature on the economics
of production and growth. Those without backgrounds in economics may
therefore find it helpful to review the latter briefly. Those with backgrounds
in economics may want to skim the section to familiarize themselves with the
notation and terminology we introduce.
—is termed the “labor share”. Likewise, the “capital share” is the fraction
of output that accrues to the owners of capital.
We will assume through most this document that everyone is employed.
In reality, of course, many cannot work, or will not work if the wage rate is
sufficiently low. Model scenarios in which the wage rate falls dramatically
may therefore be more accurately interpreted as scenarios in which unem-
ployment is widespread. For our purposes this will not be an important
distinction.
2.2 Substitution
Given a production (or utility) function and a list of factor (or consumption
good) prices, suppose a purchaser spends a fixed budget so as to maximize
output (or utility). Suppose furthermore that the production plans (or pref-
erences) are homothetic: that is, that the production (utility) function is
CRS, or a monotonic transformation of one that is CRS. The elasticity of
substitution for some factor i is then, intuitively, the value ϵ such that, if the
relative price of i falls by a small proportion (say, 1%), the relative quantity
of i purchased—Xi /Xj , for j ̸= i—will rise by an ϵ-times larger proportion
(ϵ%).5
Conversely, then, given a list of factor quantities, the elasticity of substi-
tution is the value ϵ such that, in order for the relative quantity of i sold to
5
Note that, absent homotheticity, elasticity of substitution is not defined: a 1% rise in
the price of i and a 1% fall in the price of other items may have different impacts on the
relative quantities purchased, even though they would produce the same impact on the
relative price of i.
7
increase by a small proportion (say 1%), the relative price of i must fall by
a (1/ϵ)-times larger proportion ((1/ϵ)%).
Suppose that goods 1 and 2 are divided among many owners, and suppose
there are many interested purchasers. (The sets of owners and potential
purchasers need not be disjoint, but it may be easier to imagine that they
are.) The price of 1 should then equal the market-clearing price: the price
such that, given the price of 2, precisely the entire supply of 1 is purchased.
If the price of 1 were higher than this, anyone who owns some of it would
do well to sell her unsold goods at just less than the market price. If it were
lower, i.e. if purchasers would have been willing to buy more than the entire
supply of 1 at the given price, then anyone who owns some 1 could charge
more than the given price and still sell all she has.
Now consider the consequences of exogenously increasing the relative
quantity of good 1 by 1%, say by increasing its absolute quantity by 1%
across each of its owners and leaving the quantity of good 2 unchanged. The
market-clearing relative price of good 1 will then fall by (1/ϵ)%. As we can
see, marginally increasing the relative abundance of a good results in smaller
relative expenditure on that good—i.e. its owners receive a smaller share of
total income—precisely when the elasticity of substitution between it and
other goods, on the current margin, is less than 1.
For illustration: food and other goods are not very substitutable. When
food was much scarcer, its owners were able to command such higher prices
for it that people spent larger shares of their incomes on it. On the other
hand, industrially produced goods and handmade goods are very substi-
tutable. As the former grew more plentiful, following the Industrial Revolu-
tion’s explosion in manufacturing, people spent larger shares of their incomes
on them.
Goods are perfect complements if ϵ = 0. In this case, output (or utility)
is some constant times the minimum of the goods’ quantities, in some ratio.
(Consider left shoes and right shoes, in the 1:1 ratio, or bicycle frames and
wheels, in the 1:2 ratio.) However the goods’ relative prices change, the
relative quantities purchased will stay fixed at the given ratio.
The case of perfect substitutability is approached in the limit as ϵ → ∞.
In this case a positive quantity of each good is only purchased if their prices
are equal; if their prices differ, only the cheaper is purchased.
ρ > 0 respectively.
A production function exhibits constant elasticity of substitution (CES)
if its elasticity of substitution does not depend on the factor prices and quan-
tities. A two-factor CES production function that is also CRS, with factor-
augmenting technology, must take the form
if ρ ̸= 0 and
Y = (AK)a (BL)1−a , (4)
for some a ∈ (0, 1), if ρ = 0.6 In the second case, the function is called
“Cobb-Douglas”. When ρ ≤ 0, output requires strictly positive quantities of
both factors.
If we have more than two factors i, natural extensions of the above func-
tions look similar, with the Cobb-Douglas exponents ai still summing to 1.
When ρ ̸= 0, the share of output paid to factor X, with factor-augmenting
technology C, equals (CX/Y )ρ . When ρ = 0, a factor’s share equals the
exponent on that factor. In general, the share of factor X is decreasing in
CX/Y when ρ < 0, independent of CX/Y when ρ = 0, and increasing in
CX/Y when ρ > 0.
Observe that there is a deep similarity between cases (a) in which there
is a single consumption good, but multiple factors to its production, and (b)
in which consumer utility is defined over multiple consumption goods, each
of which employs a single production factor. Consumers in the latter cases
function like factories in the former cases, as if consumer goods were inputs
to the production of utility.
is constant over time; that is, iff the change in the number of researchers just
offsets the change in the difficulty of producing proportional productivity
increases. This in turn will obtain iff (ϕ − 1)gB + λgL = 0, or13
λgL
gB = . (9)
1−ϕ
Because we are holding 1 − St fixed, the number of non-research workers
will grow at rate gL . So the number of effective non-research workers will
grow at rate gB + gL . As we have seen, under a constant saving rate, capital
and output will grow at this rate too, and output per person will grow at
rate gB .
Observe that the steady-state rate of labor productivity growth is here un-
defined when ϕ = 1. The calculation also breaks down when ϕ > 1, absurdly
predicting a negative rate. This is because the value assumed to exist in
the derivation, namely a steady-state productivity growth rate gB under a
growing research workforce, does not exist when ϕ ≥ 1. When ϕ = 1, it
is straightforward to see that a positive growth rate in the number of re-
searchers produces an increasing rate of labor productivity growth. When
12
Indeed, some reserve the term “endogenous” for growth models in which ϕ = 1, since
an unexplained process of exponential population growth is needed when ϕ < 1. Models
of this form with ϕ < 1 are then termed “semi-endogenous”.
13
It follows from gB,t = θBtϕ−1 (SLt )λ that the corresponding growth path is stable. If
Bt is “too high”, growth subsequently slows, since ϕ − 1 < 0. Likewise, if Bt is “too low”,
growth accelerates.
13
If σ is bounded above by σ̄ < 1, this is always negative. Over the long run,
gS must be negative and g1−S must be zero, since both terms are in the long
run non-positive. Thus we have, in the long run, gS ≤ (σ̄ − 1)gD . Finally,
since Z = DSK, we have
gZ ≤ σ̄gD + gK . (13)
we are using the term. But given the speed of Moore’s Law, it would be a
dramatic shift.
The definition of a “unit of consumption” is somewhat arbitrary, in the
presence of changing relative prices, and an exploration of the relevant work
on quantity indices would be outside the scope of this survey. In short,
though, the analysis of the previous paragraph effectively defines total con-
sumption in a given year in units determined by goods’ relative prices in the
starting year, whereas one might instead hold that units of Z contribute ever
less to “consumption” as the relative price of Z falls. Doing so only exacer-
bates the result above. Low substitution elasticity not only slows growth in
the production of Z but also generates a rapid fall in the relative price of Z,
which further slows the growth of measured consumption. On this account-
ing, therefore, the posited increase in the substitutability between “Y ” and
“Z” does even more to increase the measured consumption growth rate.
The wage and labor share are not defined in this model, since capital is
the only factor of production. As should be clear, however, an analogous
model with labor would behave similarly, as long as instead of simply
positing growth in capital gK , we also posit equal growth gB = gK in
labor-augmenting technology. Then the labor share will be constant (by
CRS), and consumption-denominated wages will grow at the consumption
growth rate.
Models in which labor and capital must be combined in more complex ways
tend to produce the same broad conclusion. If labor and capital are suffi-
ciently substitutable, then increasing capital productivity can increase the
capital share, but it will still increase the absolute wage rate. Berg et al.
(2018) detail a variety of such models. We will not work through them here.
18
gY = gK , and thus
a
gY = a(gA + gK ) ⇒ gY = gA (20)
1−a
before the threshold is crossed. Finally, the threshold will still eventually
be crossed: if all capital were used as equipment indefinitely, the marginal
productivity of capital used as equipment AFQ = aY /K would fall below
that of labor FL = bY /H.
After the threshold is crossed, we will have
a
gY = a(gA + gK ) + bgK ⇒ gY = gA . (21)
1−a−b
Note that this is still a growth rate increase, though not as large as that in
the first model above.
To see what happens to wages, however, observe that when p is chosen
so that invested output is split optimally between equipment and robotics,
it will satisfy AFQ = FL , or
aY bY H +K a
= ⇒ p= . (22)
pK H + (1 − p)K K a+b
As K → ∞, we have p → a/(a + b) < 1, and therefore gL = gK = gY . As
above, because the production function is Cobb-Douglas, the labor share
is constant. Now, however, the quantity of effective labor grows no more
quickly than output, so labor payments per labor quantity—i.e. wages per
human worker—merely stagnate.
∗
Long-run output will be maximized by setting SH = SH , the value that
∗ ∗ ∗
maximizes (1 − SH )H + SH R̄—i.e. SH = 1 if the robotization condition is
∗
met, because in this case R̄ > H, and SH = 0 if not. Long-run output will
∗ ∗
then approach an upper bound of Ȳ ((1−SH )H +SH R̄)/(H + R̄). The human
labor share will approach 1, either because it is the scarce input to output
directly or because robotics is the scarce input to output and human labor
is the scarce input to robotics. The absolute wage will of course stagnate.
In short, robotization can raise the output ceiling, but it cannot on its own
produce a sustainably positive growth rate.
One might expect that, if we do not fix SR = 0, it will eventually be
optimal to use robotics in the production of robotics. In fact, this will only
happen if D is large enough that, as the quantity of capital allocated to
robotics production grows large, one unit of robotics can produce more than
one unit of robotics: that is, if limk→∞ fL (k, H) > 1/D; or equivalently,
24
because f (·) is CRS, if fL (k, 0) > 1/D for k > 0. The identification of such a
condition in their more general setting is Mookherjee and Ray’s key insight,
and they call the condition the “von Neumann singularity condition”, after
the work by Burks and Von Neumann (1966) on self-replicating automata.
It is of course very closely analogous to the robotization condition above, but
stronger since we are imposing D < 1. We might take this to be the natural
case; robotics production is presumably harder to automate than most other
tasks are.16
Suppose that this condition is met, and that SK K is large enough that
fL (SK K, H) > 1/D. Then there is an optimal quantity of robotics to allocate
to robotics production, so as to maximize net robotics production. This is the
quantity such that use of a marginal unit of robotics on robotics production
increases robotics output by exactly one unit. That is, it is optimal to set
SR > 0 such that SR satisfies fL (SK K, H + DSR∗ R) = 1/D.
The value of R depends on SR , since more inputs to robotics production
will correspond to higher robotic output. Nevertheless we know that a unique
SR ∈ (0, 1) satisfying the above equality exists, for a given SK K. To see this,
recall that fL (SK K, H + DSR R) > 1/D at SR = 0, by supposition. And
we must have limSR →1 fL (SK K, H + DSR R) < 1/D, or else the quantity of
robotics output R and thus also SR R would grow without bound, fixing SK K,
as SR → 1; but in this case fL → 0, by the assumption that the substitution
parameter in the robotics production function is bounded below 0. By the
concavity and continuous differentiability of f (·), therefore, there is a unique
SR∗ : fL (SK K, H + DSR∗ R) = 1/D.
∗
Under the singularity condition, SK and SR approach constants SK and
∗ 17
SR , strictly between 0 and 1, as the capital stock grows. Growth proceeds
as in an AK model, with the rate of capital accumulation, final good output
growth, and robotics output growth all asymptotically constant and propor-
tional to the saving rate.18 The wage level is constant and lower than it is in
16
Presumably at least some other tasks are more difficult to automate, however. As
Mookherjee and Ray present in the original paper, their central result does not depend on
robotics production being more difficult to automate than all other tasks, just on robotics
production being sufficiently difficult to automate.
17
See Appendix A.1 for a proof.
18 ∗ ∗
The model will approximate an AK model with A = Y /K = F ((1–SK ), (1–SR )R/K),
∗ ∗
where R/K likewise satisfies R/K = f (SK , SR R/K). Technological progress that allows
capital to produce more robotics increases long-run R/K and functionally “increases A”,
though it will never exceed its upper bound of F (1, ∞). This will be finite, by the as-
sumption that F (·)’s substitution parameter is bounded below 0.
25
the absence of the singularity condition, since the ratio of capital to labor in
robotics production is still asymptotically constant but now positive rather
than zero. The share of income accruing to human labor falls to zero.
As with Hanson (2001), moderate tweaks to this model could result
in absolute human wages rising or falling, rather than merely stagnating.
Also, in the presence of population growth or labor-augmenting technology
growth, introducing automation can increase the growth rate of final good
output (or final good output per capita) from the rate of effective labor
(or labor-augmenting technology) growth to something much higher, given
sufficient saving.
As we saw in §3.3, when human work must compete with robotics for which it
is perfectly substitutable, the standard result is that the human labor share
falls to 0 and the wage stagnates or changes (likely falls) as well. Above,
however, we saw that modeling robotics production explicitly, rather than
stipulating a frictionless conversion of the final output good into robotics,
allows for a channel through which human work can remain necessary. A
positive human labor share can be maintained, even when robotics can fully
substitute for human work in the final good production function, when human
work cannot be fully substituted for in robotics production.
Korinek (2018) presents another model in which humans and robots must
in some sense compete and in which robots are not simply “capital that can
function as labor” but items that must be produced and sustained. He too
finds that the human labor share, and in his case also the wage rate, can fall
to 0 unless human labor remains necessary for the maintenance of the robot
population. But we will not explore his model further here.
Now suppose robotics grows slightly more productive, so that At+1 > At .
Let GA ≜ 1 + gA denote At+1 /At . For a single period, total output and
the incomes of the old grow. The young see a fall in wages, however, and
investment therefore falls as well. This fall in investment outweighs the fact
that some of the investment, namely that in robotics, is now more productive.
Output therefore falls. The wage rate falls too, due both to the abundance
of robotics and to the lack of investment in equipment.
More formally: in the new equilibrium, the marginal product of robotics is
again equal to that of equipment. Because the “relative cost” of robotics has
now been multiplied by 1/GA and because here ρ = 0, the relative quantity of
labor must be GA times higher. Letting asterisks denote the new equilibrium
outcomes, L∗ /Q∗ = GA Lt /Qt . So
1 L∗ −1/2 1 Lt −1/2
FL∗ = , FL,t = (29)
2 Q∗ 2 Qt
−1/2
⇒ FL∗ = FL,t GA < FL,t .
The new rate of return on investment is r∗ = At+1 FL∗ = GA At FL∗ , the new
wage is FL∗ , and the saving rate remains 1/2. The consumption of the old
thus equals half their income while young, times 1 + r∗ :
FL∗ 1/2 FL,t
(1 + GA At FL∗ ) = (1 + At GA FL,t ) 1/2 (30)
2 2GA
−1/2 FL,t FL,t
= (GA + At FL,t ) < (1 + At FL,t ) .
2 2
The new equilibrium therefore features lower output in all subsequent peri-
ods, and lower consumption for both young and old.
If robotics productivity continues to grow at rate gA , the wage rate, and
1/2
thus the consumption of the young, will continue to fall to 0 at rate GA −
1. The consumption of the old (and thus also output) will fall at a falling
rate, and will eventually stabilize above 0, as the increasing productivity of
invested equipment ever more closely compensates for the falling absolute
amount invested.21 The human labor share thus falls to 0.
Again, the direction of these impacts is sensitive to whether the “winners”
from advances in AI save more or less than the “losers”. As Berg et al. (2018)
21
Technically, if flow utility is logarithmic in consumption (see footnote 20), lifetime
utility falls to negative infinity as the consumption of the young falls to zero.
29
point out, for instance, those who make most of their incomes from wages
currently empirically exhibit lower saving rates than those who make most
of their incomes from capital rents, so the mechanism identified by Sachs
and Kotlikoff should if anything increase output growth. In any event, the
key point is just a reiteration of the well-known fact that, in a neoclassical
growth model with finitely lived agents and no (or imperfect) intergenera-
tional altruism, the rate of saving is not necessarily optimal. Accordingly,
policymakers must always consider not only the impact of a policy or techno-
logical development on short-term output, but also its impact on the saving
rate. When a given development produces a suboptimal saving rate, it should
be counterbalanced by investment subsidies or by transfers from those with
high to those with low propensity to consume: in this model, from the old
to the young.
Y = AK a L1−a , (32)
22
A = a–a (1–a)a–1 , which ranges from 1 (at a = 0 or 1) to 2 (at a = 1/2).
31
gY = a(gA + gK ) + (1 − a)(gB + gL )
a
⇒ gY = gA + gB + gL . (37)
1−a
The impact of a one-time increase to a, or of increases only up to some
bound strictly below 1, is therefore straightforward. The capital share rises
32
with a. If gA > 0, the growth rate increases, ultimately raising the wage rate;
otherwise the growth rate is unchanged, and the impact on the wage rate is
ambiguous.
Given asymptotic complete automation, with 1 − a falling to 0 expo-
nentially or faster, the model approximates an AK model. If gA = 0, the
growth rate rises to sA. If gA > 0, the growth rate rises without bound, and
wages too rise superexponentially.
Automation, as we have defined it, allows capital to perform more tasks. One
might therefore imagine that it is equivalent to the development of some sort
of capital-augmenting technology. Aghion et al. (2019) observe, however, that
automation in the above model is actually equivalent to the development of
labor -augmenting—and capital-depleting!—technology, as long as ρ < 0 and
the automation condition holds. To see this, recall our production function:
24
The capital share here equals βt1−ρ (Kt /Yt )ρ . As β → 1, the capital share rises to an
upper bound of (K/Y )ρ , where K/Y is the long-run capital-to-output ratio, as long as
this exists and is finite. It follows from sYt = Kt+1 − Kt that sYt /Kt = gK,t ; and since
gK = gY = gB + gL , we have K/Y = s/(gB + gL ). The labor share will thus fall to
1 − (s/(gB + gL ))ρ . This is nonnegative because sA ≥ gB + gL , by sufficient saving, and A
is asymptotically 1; and it is strictly positive as long as we are not in the knife-edge case
of sA = gB + gL .
25
One might however take the position that what we have here been calling automation
is not a new force on the horizon, promising to augment pre-existing drivers of growth,
but a microfoundation for the process of labor-augmenting technological development we
have observed for centuries. On this view, advances in AI will continue to push β ever
closer to 1, but this process will simply continue the existing trend.
34
This balanced growth result is, however, sensitive to the assumption that ad-
vances in automation technology (increases in β) and task creation (increases
in N ) proceed at the same rate.
If task creation oustrips automatability, the labor share rises, and as
β − N + 1 → 0 asymptotically, the labor share rises to 1. In this case, we
37
5 AI in technology production
Throughout the discussion so far (except for the brief note at the end of the
previous section), technological development has been exogenous, when it has
appeared at all. Even in this circumstance, developments in AI have proved
capable of delivering transformative economic consequences. When techno-
logical development is endogenous, and in particular when more advanced
AI can allow it to proceed more quickly, the resulting process of “recursive
self-improvement” can generate even more transformative consequences.
39
Yt = (At Kt )a L1−a
t , (40)
where
Ȧt = θAϕt Ytλ ⇒ gA,t = θAϕ−1
t Ytλ (41)
for some ϕ < 1 and λ > 0. One might interpret this as a model in which
the production process itself contributes to the generation of productivity-
increasing ideas.
Given a constant saving rate, gK = gY . So, from our production function,
a
gY = a(gA + gY ) + (1 − a)gL ⇒ gY = gA + gL . (42)
1−a
From our formula for gA,t , the steady state of gA (if it exists) will be that
which satisfies (ϕ − 1)gA + λgY = 0. Substituting for gY in this expression
and solving for gA , we have
λ(1 − a)
gA = gL . (43)
(1 − a)(1 − ϕ) − λa
This exponential growth path will exist as long as the denominator is positive:
that is, as long as
1−ϕ
a< . (44)
1−ϕ+λ
40
(1 − a)(1 − ϕ)
gY = gL . (45)
(1 − a)(1 − ϕ) − λa
Robotics—by which they broadly mean capital that can substitute for
human labor in various ways, instead of complementing it—has of course
had many applications. It has also been the subject of a substantial
majority of the theoretical literature on the economics of AI, including all
that discussed in this survey so far. They propose however that the most
transformative possibilities come from deep learning systems, by which they
mean systems that can learn as human researchers can: artificial systems
that can participate directly in the process of technological development.
Citing Griliches’s (1957) discussion of the implications of “inventing a
method of invention”, they argue that deep learning systems (in their use
of the term) will have qualitatively more radical consequences than mere
robotics. As we will see, this appears to be correct.
all values of ρ, have then been included for generality. To explore the case
in which no technology growth is exogenous, simply posit that C and D are
constant throughout the discussion below.
As usual, we will assume a constant saving rate, so that capital accumu-
lation in the long run tracks output.
Suppose ρ < 0. Recall that in this case sustained growth in effective capital
and in effective research labor are both necessary to sustain growth in output
technology, and growth will be driven by whichever factor grows more slowly.
Observe that when growth is constrained by effective capital accumulation,
we have gA ∝ Atϕ−1 (Ct Kt )λ , and that when it is constrained by effective
research labor growth, we have gA ∝ Aϕ−1 t (Dt Lt )λ .
Regarding ϕ:
• Recall from the reasoning of §2.4 that, if ϕ < 1, we have gA = λ(gC +
gK )/(1−ϕ) on the capital-constrained path and gA = λ(gD +gL )/(1−ϕ)
on the labor-constrained path. In the former case, since gK = gY = gA +
λ
gL , we can substitute for gK and rearrange to get gA = 1−ϕ−λ (gC + gL ).
A capital-constrained path with this growth rate exists when ϕ < 1−λ.
λ λ
Thus, if ϕ < 1 − λ, gA = min( 1−ϕ−λ (gC + gL ), 1−ϕ (gD + gL )). A
one-time increase to Ct , Dt , Lt , or S, as long as S remains below 1, does
not affect the output technology growth rate. A permanent increase
to gC , gD , or gL , on the other hand, does increase the growth rate of
output technology and thereby output per capita.
• If ϕ ∈ (1 − λ, 1),28 output technology growth cannot be constrained by
capital accumulation; such a scenario would imply gA ∝ Aϕ−1t (Ct Kt )λ ∝
Aϕ−1+λ
t (Ct Lt )λ , contradictorily producing superexponential growth in
λ
output technology, output, and capital. We have gA = 1−ϕ (gD + gL ).
• If ϕ = 1, suppose labor remains fixed at L and labor-augmenting tech-
nology remains fixed at D, while effective capital accumulates. In the
long run we then have gA = DSL. A one-time increase to D, S, or
L increases the growth rate of output technology and thereby output
(again, as long as S remains below 1). If we begin from a state in
which gD = gL = 0 and introduce positive labor or labor-augmenting
technology growth, the result is a Type I growth explosion.
28
The dynamics of the knife-edge ϕ = 1 − λ case are somewhat complex and will be
omitted for clarity.
43
Suppose ρ > 0. Recall that in this case sustained growth in effective capital
or in effective research labor suffice to sustain growth in output technol-
ogy, and growth will be driven by whichever factor grows more quickly.
Now, when growth is driven by effective capital accumulation, we have
gA ∝ Atϕ−1 (Ct Kt )λ , and when it is driven by effective research labor growth,
we have gA ∝ Aϕ−1t (Dt Lt )λ .
Regarding ϕ:
• If ϕ < 1 − λ, the capital- and labor-driven technology growth rates
λ λ
equal 1−ϕ (gC + gK ) and 1−ϕ (gD + gL ), respectively. In the former case,
since gK = gY = gA + gL , we can substitute for gK and rearrange to get
λ λ λ
gA = 1−ϕ−λ (gC + gL ). Thus gA = max( 1−ϕ−λ (gC + gL ), 1−ϕ (gD + gL )).
Growth rate increases require increases to gC , gD , or gL .
• If ϕ > 1 − λ,29 we have a Type II growth explosion regardless of the
other parameters.
Let Y = A(1−S)L, as before, and hold S fixed but posit labor growth gL > 0.
Given A existing “technological ideas”, a researcher has access to only Aϕ ,
for some ϕ ∈ (0, 1), perhaps due to some sort of cognitive limitation.30 New
ideas are made from combinations of existing ideas. Given access to Aϕ
ϕ
ideas, a researcher therefore faces 2A idea-combinations. Of these, not all
can generate new technological ideas, perhaps due to some other sort of
cognitive limitation. Instead, each researcher’s idea-generation function is
“isoelastic” in ideas available:
ϕ
(2A )α − 1
Ȧ = θ , α > 0;
α (53)
ϕ
Ȧ = θ ln(2A ) = θ ln(2)Aϕ , α = 0,
λgL
Ȧ = θ ln(2)Aϕ (SL)λ ⇒ gA = . (54)
1−ϕ
This is just the standard Jones model, with a coefficient of ln(2) rescaling θ.
Now suppose that α > 0 (or that α is bounded below by α > 0 as
A → ∞). Then collective technological development is bounded below (at
30
The model requires ϕ > 0 such that the fishing-out effect does not predominate. As
discussed in §2.4, Bloom et al. (2020) estimate ϕ = −2.1.
31
The formula for α = 0 is the limiting case of the formula for α > 0, as α → 0.
46
least asymptotically) by
ϕ
(2A )α − 1
Ȧ = θ (SL)λ (55)
α
ϕ
(2A )α − 1
⇒ gA = θ (SL)λ .
Aα
It follows from the second term that, for large A, gA increases more than
polynomially in A. That is, gA increases quickly enough in A to produce
a Type II growth explosion. If the above model approximates reality,
therefore, we presumably currently have α = 0.
We can now consider the growth regimes that obtain under different values
of ρY and ρA . For simplicity, we will not allow for labor growth or exogenous
sources of technology growth. To begin, let us list the cases we have already
implicitly covered.
49
If ρY < 0, little changes from the case of §5.2. Output is still bottle-
necked by the scarce factor, namely labor. Output therefore asymptotically
resembles A(1 − SL )L, as before. How technology evolves depends on ρA , as
covered in §5.2.
If ρY = 0 but ρA < 0, we are in the well-worn territory of Cobb-Douglas
production—so, given capital depreciation, production per capita that grows
with technology—and technology that grows sub-exponentially (unless re-
search labor inputs grow exponentially).
If ρY > 0 but ρA < 0, we reach the Type I growth explosion discussed in
§3.2. Output in the absence of growth in A grows at rate sA, but A grows
without bound, even without growth in research labor inputs.
where SK ∈ (0, 1), a ∈ (0, 1), s > 0, θ > 0, ϕ < 1, and λ > 0. Also, define
λ
γ≜ . (59)
(1 − a)(1 − ϕ)
Then
• If γ > 1, Y exhibits a Type II growth explosion.
• If γ = 1, Y grows exponentially, with
θ λ 1−a
λ SK 1+λ−a
lim gY,t = s 1+λ−a . (60)
t→∞ 1 − a (1 − SK )a
• If γ < 1, Y grows power-functionally.
Note that the production function of (56) is Cobb-Douglas with an implicit
constant labor stock normalized to 1, and/or a constant land stock also
32
What follows is in essence an elaboration on Aghion et al. (2019), §4.1, Example 3.
50
normalized to 1, and (given CRS) the exponents on labor and land summing
to 1 − a. Note likewise that technology production, as described by (58),
may be interpreted as Cobb-Douglas with inputs other than capital fixed.
A proof of the above can be found in Appendix A.2, but an intuition for
the exponential growth threshold provided by γ = 1 is as follows. If growth
in A and Y were driven by exogenous exponential growth in K, we would
have, in steady state,
λ
gA = gK (61)
1−ϕ
and thus
λ
gY = + a gK . (62)
1−ϕ
But gK is not exogenous: future growth in K roughly equals past growth in
Y , since capital accumulation is driven by saving a proportion of output. If
λ
1−ϕ
+ a > 1, therefore, a given growth rate in K generates a higher growth
rate of Y , and this higher growth rate is subsequently exhibited by K. The
λ
growth rate of K therefore grows over time. Likewise, if 1−ϕ + a < 1, a
given growth rate in K generates a lower growth rate of Y , and this lower
growth rate is subsequently exhibited by K. The growth rate of K there-
λ
fore falls. Finally, observe that 1−ϕ +a > 1 iff γ > 1, and likewise for < and =.
Human
labor Human
Scenario33 Growth34 share35 wages36
LS in production & = →1 +
capital-augmenting tech growth
§3.1 Acemoglu and Restrepo (2018a)
HS in consumption goods ++ C ++
§3.2 Nordhaus (2021)
HS in production ++ →0 ++
§3.2 Nordhaus (2021)
PS in production & I →0 L
capital-augmenting tech growth
§3.2
PS in production, capital-augmenting ++ →0 →0
tech growth, & MS land constraint
33
“PS”, “HS”, “MS”, and “LS” stand for perfect, high, moderate, and low substitutabil-
ity, and refer to substitution parameters ρ = 1, > 0, = 0, and < 0 respectively. Unless
otherwise noted, the “HS” case allows for perfect substitutability. In the scenarios with
endogenous research, “negative”, “positive”, “low”, “intermediate”, and “high [research]
feedback” refer to research feedback exponents ϕ < 1 − λ, > 1 − λ, < 1, = 1, and > 1
respectively.
34
+ and – refer to cases in which AI shifts the output path up or down without changing
the growth rate, e.g. by increasing or decreasing the plateau level in a circumstance where
output plateaus regardless of AI. --, ++, I, and II refer to cases in which AI allows for
decreases to the long-run growth rate, increases to the long-run growth rate, Type I growth
explosions, and Type II growth explosions. = refers to cases in which AI does not change
the long-run output level or growth rate.
35
C means that AI pushes the human labor share to some positive constant, not neces-
sarily lower or higher than the value it would take in the absence of AI.
36
L means that human wages are driven to some low but constant rate (typically the
rental rate of effective capital). C means that they are pushed to some positive constant,
not necessarily lower or higher than they would be in the absence of AI. All other symbols
are defined as in the Growth column.
53
PS in production, equipment-augmen- ++ →0 L
ting tech gr., & MS land constraint
§3.3
AI-assisted multiplication of ++
combinatorial idea discovery
§5.3 Agrawal et al. (2019)
The human labor share and wage are technically undefined in the models
of endogenous technology production, since, as noted in §2.4, we cannot
straightforwardly assume that the factors of technology production will tend
to be paid their marginal products (or anything else in particular). As often
presented, however, human labor is the lone factor of final good production
in these models, and the technology being produced is labor-augmenting.
Taken literally, therefore, the wage rate in these models should grow in line
with technology and so with output. That is, it should exhibit growth rate
decreases, increases, Type I growth explosions or Type II growth explosions
as listed above.
8 Conclusion
The set of models discussed here cover a wide range of AI’s possible long-
run macroeconomic impacts. It can hopefully serve as a bridge between
the tools of economics—whose use is typically restricted to shorter-term and
smaller-scale possibilities (but need not be)—and the longer-term and larger-
scale questions posed by futurists, who typically do not draw on the tools of
economics (but could, we believe, sometimes learn from doing so).
Nevertheless, of course, many topics relevant to the economics of AI, and
even of transformative AI, could not be covered here.
Finally, the subject most conspicuously absent here that features most heav-
ily in futurist discussion about AI is the most transformative macroeconomic
possibility of all: the risk of an AI-induced existential catastrophe (see e.g.
Bostrom (2017)). Unlike the possibility of transformative growth effects,
AI risk appears to be absent from the economics literature not primarily
“by choice” but because there is no particularly obvious mechanism through
which accelerating automation or capital productivity, within existing models
of production or growth, can pose a danger.
It is possible, of course, to write down economic models in which produc-
tion and/or technological development pose catastrophic risks in the abstract,
as e.g. Jones (2016) and Aschenbrenner (2020) have done. As outlined above,
however, the only growth-slowing AI possibilities economists have considered
to date are those mediated by impacts on saving (Sachs and Kotlikoff, 2012)
and on innovation incentives (Aghion et al., 2019; Acemoglu and Restrepo,
2019). These scenarios are very far from those that motivate most concern
about AI risk. The latter typically feature superintelligent agents, with goals
not fully aligned with ours, who take control of the world.
The tools of economics can shed at least some light on these concerns as
well. Most simply, to the extent that AI development poses such a risk, AI
safety is a global and intergenerational public good. Through that lens, much
of the analysis of public goods, and in particular many of the tools developed
by environmental economists for the pricing and provision of climate risk
58
A Proofs
A.1 Asymptotically positive fractions of capital and
robotics used in robotics production
We will work within the framework of §3.4.
Consider a time t at which SR,t > 0, and let m > 1 denote Kt′ /Kt for some
t > t. From t to t′ , the capital input to robotics production is multiplied
′
by mSK,t′ /SK,t . Because f (·) is CRS, to maintain the condition that fL,t′ =
fL,t = 1/D the labor input to robotics production must also be multiplied
by mSK,t′ /SK,t , and robotics production will then also be multiplied by this
factor. We thus have
Substituting (64) into (63) and (65) and solving for SK,t′ and SR,t′ , we find
that, as m → ∞,
∗ DRt (1 − SR,t )
SK,t′ → SK ≜ SK,t and (66)
DRt (1 − SR,t ) − (1 − SK,t )H
SR,t′ → SR∗ ≜ SR,t + H/(DRt ). (67)
where A0 > 0, K0 > 0, SK ∈ (0, 1), a ∈ (0, 1), s > 0, θ > 0, ϕ < 1, and
λ > 0, and where (68)–(70) are defined for t ∈ [0, ∞)—or, if the system
exhibits a Type II growth explosion at some time t∗ , for t ∈ [0, t∗ ).
Observe first that, for all t,
Let ĝK (≜“ggK ”) denote the proportional growth rate of gK itself, and let ĝA
be defined likewise. It then follows from (71) and (72) that, for all t,
If, for any time τ , ĝKτ > 0 and ĝAτ > 0, then
Likewise, if for any τ we have ĝKτ < 0 (= 0) and ĝAτ < 0 (= 0), then
γ < 1 (= 1, respectively).
For any τ ,
The “⇒” direction follows from (73). If ĝKτ = 0, then σgAτ = (1 − a)gKτ ; so
if the right-hand side is constant around τ , so is the left. The “⇐” direction
follows likewise from (74).
Also, ĝK and ĝA are continuous in t wherever they are defined. So by
the intermediate value theorem, if either term is negative at some time and
positive at another time, it must equal zero at an intermediate time. By
(79), we must then have γ = 1.
It follows that, if γ ̸= 1, either
with case 4 incompatible with γ > 1 and case 1 incompatible with γ < 1.
We will now show that cases 2 and 3 are also incompatible with γ ̸= 1.
Consider case 2. From ĝKt > 0 ∀t, and (73), it follows that
shown, it must be that limt→∞ ĝKt = limt→∞ ĝAt = 0. Taking the limits of
terms (73) and (74), we then have
gA∗ = (1 − a)gK
∗
and (81)
∗ 1−ϕ ∗
gK = g , (82)
λ A
which jointly imply gA∗ = γgA∗ and thus γ = 1.
Case 3 can be shown to imply γ = 1 by a precisely analogous proof.
Thus γ > 1 implies case 1 and γ < 1 implies case 4.
where
θ̃ ≜ (1 − a)sθ(1 − SK )a SK
λ
. (86)
If the relationship of (83) were an equality at all t, then A would always grow
at precisely the same proportional rate as K 1−a . Noting that
2 − λ+a−1 ϕ+ λ+a−1
gAt > θ̃A0 1−a
K0λ+a−1 At 1−a
∀t. (92)
so
λ 1−a
θSK 1+λ−a
=⇒ lim At Kta−1
= by γ = 1 (100)
t→∞ s(1 − a)(1 − SK )a
θ λ 1−a
∗ λ SK 1+λ−a
=⇒ gK = s 1+λ−a by (71). (101)
1 − a (1 − SK )a
Finally,
References
Acemoglu, Daron and David Autor, “Skills, tasks and technologies: Implica-
tions for employment and earnings,” in “Handbook of Labor Economics,” Vol. 4,
Elsevier, 2011, pp. 1043–1171.
and , “What Does Human Capital Do? A Review of Goldin and Katz’s ‘The
Race Between Education and Technology’,” Journal of Economic Literature,
2012, 50 (2), 426–463.
and , “The Race Between Man and Machine: Implications of Technology for
Growth, Factor Shares, and Employment,” American Economic Review, 2018,
108 (6), 1488–1542.
and , “Automation and New Tasks: How Technology Displaces and Rein-
states Labor,” Journal of Economic Perspectives, 2019, 33 (2), 3–30.
, Joshua Gans, and Avi Goldfarb, Prediction Machines: The Simple Eco-
nomics of Artificial Intelligence, Harvard Business Press, 2018.
Autor, David, “Why Are There Still So Many Jobs? The History and Future of
Workplace Automation,” Journal of Economic Perspectives, 2015, 29 (3), 3–30.
Bloom, Nicholas, Charles I Jones, John Van Reenen, and Michael Webb,
“Are Ideas Getting Harder to Find?,” American Economic Review, 2020, 110
(4), 1104–1144.
Brynjolfsson, Erik and Andrew McAfee, The Second Machine Age: Work,
Progress, and Prosperity in a Time of Brilliant Technologies, WW Norton &
Company, 2014.
Freeman, Richard B, “Who Owns the Robots Rules the World,” 2015. IZA
World of Labor.
Goldin, Claudia Dale and Lawrence F Katz, The Race Between Education
and Technology, Harvard University Press, 2009.
67
Gordon, Robert J, The Rise and Fall of American Growth: The U.S. Standard
of Living since the Civil War, Princeton University Press, 2016.
Hémous, David and Morten Olsen, “The Rise of the Machines: Automation,
Horizontal Innovation and Income Inequality,” 2014. Centre for Economic Policy
Research, Discussion Paper No. DP10244.
, “Life and Growth,” Journal of Political Economy, 2016, 124 (2), 539–578.
and Joseph E Stiglitz, “Artificial Intelligence and Its Implications for Income
Distribution and Unemployment,” 2019.
Mookherjee, Dilip and Debraj Ray, “Capital and Inequality in the Long Run:
Automation Without Technical Progress,” 2017. Working paper.
Oberfield, Ezra and Devesh Raval, “Micro Data and Macro Technology,”
2014. National Bureau of Economic Research, Working Paper No. 20452.
Purdy, Mike and Paul Daugherty, “Why Artificial Intelligence Is the Future
of Growth,” 2016. Accenture.
Simon, Herbert A, The New Science of Management Decision, Harper & Broth-
ers, 1960.