Materialism Without Matter - Deleuze
Materialism Without Matter - Deleuze
Materialism Without Matter - Deleuze
2017
This work is made publicly available by the City University of New York (CUNY).
Contact: [email protected]
Draft of forthcoming contribution to Genealogy of the Posthuman,
http://criticalposthumanism.net/genealogy/deleuze-gilles/
Steven Swarbrick
If there is a commonplace among philosophies of nature, it’s that the physical world is
unthinking, incapable, that is, of thinking its own evental becoming. Not only in its everyday
sense but also in the clichés of “high” theory, sense is bracketed from sensation, psyche from
soma. Sense, the story goes, organizes sensation and gives bodies their meaning. The book of
nature is written in figures, and “we” alone—human animals endowed with sense—are its
readers and cognizers.1
For Gilles Deleuze, by contrast, there is a higher level of sense that is inhuman. In one of his
earliest published essays, “Mathesis, Science and Philosophy,” Deleuze was already searching
for an answer to the problem of sense, namely, that “the knowing mind, as distinct as it might
be in itself from […] extension […], nonetheless deploys the order of things in thinking the order
of its representations.”2 How can it be, in other words, that “the knowing mind,” which is one
of nature’s figures, stands outside nature as its measurer and surveyor?
The answer Deleuze ventures is a kind of philosophical nonsense—the most rigorous nonsense
imaginable. Whereas Deleuze’s early interest in mathesis naturalis (the universal knowledge of
life) points in the direction of the differential calculus of his first major monograph, Difference
and Repetition, it is the astonishing nonsense of Lewis Carroll and the Stoics that points the way
to a theory of sense in which sense does not only inhere in propositional statements, describe
or reflect states of affairs. Sense in its pure state reaches the infinitive, which could be
described as a kind of nonsense because it does not reflect or re-present bodies and things but
rather unfolds bodies and things: greening as the event of green, wounding as the event of
being wounded, and so on.3 Alice’s adventures in Lewis Carroll’s novel illustrate the paradox of
sense—its “infinite identity”—because Alice moves in two directions at once: “Alice does not
grow without shrinking, and vice versa.”4
This higher level of sense that Deleuze (after the Stoics) calls “incorporeal” (“in-” not only
because it is of matter, immanent to matter, but also, paradoxically, the idea of matter: matter
as the power to think beyond the here and now) is in fact closer to sensation, to what happens
between bodies: the event.5
The event conditions thought, but is itself unconditioned, unknowable, and therefore pre-
philosophical: “It is as if events enjoyed an irreality which is communicated through language,”
Deleuze writes.”6 Elsewhere he states: “Events are like crystals, they become and grow only out
of the edges, or on the edge”—by eluding the present. The event occurs on the plane of
immanence, which is both material and incorporeal. We can think here of Bergson’s light-
2
What does this problematic of the surface entail for our thinking of the posthuman?
Deleuze’s theory of the event, which is both ideal and material, and not only by turns, presents
a significant challenge then to theories that privilege not only cognition and social construction
but also bodies and things. For Deleuze, bodies become actualized on the plane of immanence
through the movement of concepts. These concepts, unlike bodies, occur outside history: they
are not of space and time but create relations of space and time. Ideas or concepts incarnate
bodies. At the same time, however, bodies, through their actions, create problem-events
demanding new concepts. Neither bodies nor ideas determine the other.
This relation of events, problems, and concepts is not only human but decidedly inhuman. All of
nature is self-framing in its movements, bifurcations, connections, and creations. All of nature is
problematizing or mentalizing.10
The plane of immanence can be thought of as Deleuze’s reworking of the Freudian unconscious.
For Freud, the plane is the plane of sexuality, imagined as the drives, pure unbound energy—
akin to Bergson’s light-matter-energy. The ego is a map of the body’s surface—a psychosomatic
mixture.11 For all of his brilliance in discovering the unconscious, however, Freud interprets the
unconscious as a plane of transcendence. Hence psychoanalysis becomes a science of
uncovering the Oedipus complex, the triangle plan that, like a Platonic form, governs psychic
life unconsciously.12 Deleuze insists instead that the unconscious is a plan(e) of immanence,
meaning that what occurs on the plane is not a pre-given plan (the mommy-daddy complex)
but movements of desire. The surreal assemblage or dream-work (Lacan calls the drives
montage-machines13) is therefore not a mask disguising something beyond the work of the
drives (the transcendent plane) but the light-matter-energy of the drives themselves. The drives
are ideal-material compounds, events of relation-encounter.14 What this means for Deleuze is
that the unconscious must not be uncovered but must rather be produced: “We say […] you
haven’t got hold of the unconscious, you never get hold of it, it is not an ‘it was’ in place of
3
which the ‘I’ must come. The Freudian formula must be reversed. You have to produce the
unconscious.”15
The goal for Deleuze is not to uncover the transcendent plane. This, according to Deleuze, is the
source of all our misery. Rather, the goal for Deleuze is to create more and more differences
(material and conceptual) through encounters. An encounter occurs outside recognition;
indeed, it is of the outside, which is not beyond nature but rather beyond recognition:
encounters occur on the plane of immanence, when causes outside our awareness (Freud’s
drives, for example) disrupt our sense of meaningful harmony, disordering our frames of sense
or our “sensory-motor-schemas.” Encounters are problematizing. Instead of solving problems
(discovering the hidden transcendent plane behind problems), Deleuze insists that thinking,
which is of nature, creates new frames for mapping and organizing nature’s chaos. In short,
thought and language do not bar nature, such that the event can only be thought by re-
cognizing its latent structure. Instead language, being just one of the many ways that nature
makes sense of itself, by folding back on itself, utilizes concepts (planes or frames) that nature
or immanence creates. Thinking takes place beyond the here and now, on the plane of
immanence; it is eventalized by encounters with bodies and things but, at the same, in the
same movement, deterritorializes “place” to create (with) concepts that have no fixed location.
Rather than mind on one side and body on the other, matter, according to Deleuze, is already
sense-making. There is a logic of sense.16
The illusion is to think that because we are synthesizing machines, that “mind” is therefore the
origin of that synthesizing activity. In fact, mind is already a synthesis of myriad inhuman
encounters. What Deleuze calls “transcendental empiricism” is precisely his attempt to think
the genetic evolution of the thinking subject, and to trace lines of potential deviation-
transformation. This is not to say, however, that “matter” provides the missing origin to our
investigation, as if switching from verso (mind) to recto (body) is somehow more radical or
political. It’s not. The posthuman problem, read according to the letter of Deleuze, places
serious doubt on the separability of mind-matter, such that an idealism of the event may be the
most radical materialism there is.
It is because mind and matter are convolved (to use an old Miltonic term) that thought can be
tasked with thinking its own emergence.17
Instead of solving Descartes’ “error,” it’s high time we attempt to problematize it further: to
think, along with Deleuze’s theory of the event, of a strange “materialism without matter.”18
FURTHER READING
Claire Colebrook, “Materiality: Sex, Gender, and What Lies Beneath” in The Routledge
Companion to Feminist Philosophy, eds. Anne Garry, Serene J. Khader, and Alison Stone
(London: Routledge, 2016).
1 Galileo Galilei, The Assayer [1623], in The Essential Galileo, trans. Maurice A. Finocchiaro
(Indiana: Hackett, 2008), p. 183.
2 Gilles Deleuze, “Mathesis, Science and Philosophy” in Collapse III, ed. Robin Mackay
Spinoza, Nietzsche, Simondon, and Deleuze, see Elizabeth Grosz, The Incorporeal: Ontology,
Ethics, and the Limits of Materialism (New York: Columbia University Press, 2017). I have also
learned a great deal from Sean Bowden’s The Priority of Events: Deleuze’s Logic of Sense
(Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2011).
6 Deleuze, The Logic of Sense, 3.
7 See Henri Bergson, Matter and Memory, trans. N.M. Paul and W.S. Palmer (New York: Zone
Books, 1988).
8 I am riffing on film scholar Eugenie Brinkema’s argument in The Forms of the Affects (Durham:
Duke University Press, 2014), in which the “turn to affect” is posited as a turn away from formal
investigation in favor of the re-substantialization of bodies.
9 On this point, Derrida’s critique of logocentrism is as potent as ever. For a concise statement
on the relation of materialism to idealism and the practice of deconstructive reading versus
metaphysical reversal (body, yes; mind, no), see Derrida, Positions, trans. Alan Bass (Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1981), pp. 39-43.
10 This is one of the essential points of contrast between Deleuze’s theory of the “event” and
Alain Badiou’s. For the latter, the “event” is always eventalized (recognized, prolonged) by the
thinking (human) subject.
11 For more on this topic, see Elizabeth Grosz, Volatile Bodies: Toward a Corporeal Feminism
13 See Jacques Lacan’s important chapter on “The Deconstruction of the Drive” in The Seminar
of Jacques Lacan, Book XI: The Four Fundamental Concepts of Psychoanalysis, trans. Alan
Sheridan (New York: Norton, 1977).
14 It is for this reason, too, that Samo Tomšič calls the psychoanalytic concept of the drive an
“ontological scandal.” See Tomšič, The Capitalist Unconscious: Marx and Lacan (London: Verso,
2015), 22, 134-141.
15 Gilles Deleuze with Claire Parnet, “Dead Psychoanalysis: Analyze” in Dialogues II, trans. Hugh
Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam (New York: Columbia University Press, 2007), 78.
16 Although the “event” changes names over the course of Deleuze’s vast philosophical oeuvre,
from his early structuralist writings to his late political writings (co-authored with Félix
Guattari), the logic of the sense-event can be traced throughout his wide-ranging concepts,
from the “time-image” in Cinema 2, to the “Figure/figurative” distinction in Francis Bacon: The
Logic of Sensation, to the “impersonal life” theorized in Deleuze’s last essay, “Pure Immanence:
A Life.”
17 John Milton, Paradise Lost 6.328.
18 On the expression “materialism without matter,” see Etienne Balibar’s reading of Marx in The