Introductory Modal Logic
Introductory Modal Logic
Introductory
Modal Logic
KENNETH KONYNDYK
Konyndyk, Kenneth.
Introductory modal logic.
Bibliography: p.
1. Modality (Logic) I. Title.
BC199.M6K66 1986 160 85-41007
ISBN 13: 978-0-268-01159-8 (pbk.)
ISBN 13: 978-0-268-02407-9 (hardback)
Preface ix
Introduction 1
1 Propositional Logic 3
1.1 Symbolism 4
1.2 Rule of Replacement and Equivalences 5
1.3 Rules of Inference 6
1.4 Proofs 9
1.5 Exercises 9
2 Propositional Modal Logic 11
2.1 The Modal Concepts 12
2.1.a An Explanation of Necessity 12
"Ungiueupable" 14
"Unable to be rationally rejected" 15
"Self-evident" 15
A priori 15
2.1.b The Possible Worlds Picture 16
2.1.c A Map of the Modal Concepts 17
2.1.d Symbols and Definitions 18
2.1.e Exercises 19
2.1.f Symbolizing Conditionals 20
2.1.g The Necessity of the Consequence and the
Necessity of the Consequent 21
2.1.h Exercises 23
2.2 The Logic of Modality 23
2.2.a The Need for a Logic of Modality 23
2.2.b Logical Relationships 25
2.2.c Systems of Propositional Modal Logic 30
2.3 The System T 31
Exercises 32
V
vi CONTENTS
2.3.a Rules 32
The necessity elimination rule 33
Necessity introduction subproofs 34
The necessity introduction subproof rule 34
The necessity introduction rule 35
The T-reiteration rule 36
2.3.b Hints 36
2.3.c Exercises 38
2.3.d More Rules 39
Possibility introduction 39
Possibility elimination 39
Modal modus ponens 40
Exercises 40
2.3.e Decision Procedure 41
2.3.f Counterexamples 41
2.3.g Exercises 44
2.3.h Iterated Modalities and Reduction of
Modalities 46
2.4 The System S4 49
2.4.a Rules 49
2.4.b Exercises 50
2.4.c Reduction of Modalities in S4 50
2.5 The System S5 51
2.5.a Rules for S5 52
2.5.b Exercises 53
2.5.c Reduction Laws 53
2.5.d Exercises 55
2.6 Philosophical Matters 55
2.6.a Differences between Systems 55
2.6.b Some Assumptions Implicit in Our
Presentation 60
2.6.c Is There Only One Correct System of
Modal Logic? 64
3 Quantification 69
3.1 Symbols 69
3.2 Interpretation 70
3.3 Equivalences 71
3.4 Rules 71
Universal Instantiation 72
Universal Generalization 72
Existential Generalization 72
CONTENTS vii
Existential Instantiation 72
Exercises 75
4 Quantified Modal Logic 77
4.1 Motivation 77
4.2 'l\vo distinctions 78
4.3 Symbolization 84
4.4 Some Objections to Quantified Modal Logic 85
4.5 Essential Properties and Possible Worlds 88
4.6 Considerations Bearing on Quantified Modal Logic 90
4. 7 The Systems 92
4.8 A Kripke System 92
Exercises 94
4.9 Objections to This System 95
4.10 Kripke's Revised S5 97
The necessity introduction rule 98
Possibility elimination 99
4.11 Reflections on Kripke's Revision 101
4.12 The Actualistic Version of Possible Worlds 103
4.13 Actualism and Quantification 105
Exercises 108
4.14 Actualistic Quantified Modal Logic 108
4.14.a Rules 109
4.14.b Exercises 112
4.15 Existence and Modality 113
4.16 The Problem of Transworld Identity 115
4.1 7 Superiority of Actualism 117
Appendix I 119
Appendix II 121
Appendix III 125
Notes 127
Bibliography 131
PREFACE
ix
X PREFACE
1
2 INTRODUCTION
3
4 PROPOSITIONAL Lome
1.1 Symbolism
OTHER COMMONLY
SYMBOL OPERATION EXAMPLE USED SYMBOLS
To these rules we add two more which will help simplify our proofs.
These rules also have the virtue of being "natural" -we often use them
in ordinary deductive reasoning. The first is the rule of implication
introduction, often called "conditional proof." This rule provides a
way of introducing implication statements into a proof.
1.5 Exercises
(There is no need for exercises of the usual sort here. Those given
are related to remarks made in the text.)
1. Show that the rule modus tollens is redundant (i.e., give a
derivation of ~ p from p ::Jq and ~ q that does not use the
rule modus tollens). Do the same for:
rule 3- Transitivity
rule 4- Disjunction elimination
rule 9- Reductio ad absurdum
10 PROPOSITIONAL Lome
11
12 PROPOSITIONAL MODAL LOGIC
ment of that form having true premises and a false conclusion, then
we might be committed to accepting as valid an argument form that
is patently invalid, just because no instance of it actually having
true premises and a false conclusion has ever been presented or
thought of.
Clearly the validity of an argument form must not depend solely
on what arguments may or may not have been given in that form.
The validity of an argument form is supposed to guarantee that we
cannot use it to go from truth to falsehood. But then the modal term
has been introduced into the definition, and we cannot get rid of it
and still have what we want. Some primitive understanding of modal
terms is essential to understanding the central concept of logic.
This chapter is concerned first with clarifying our grasp of the
modal concepts and with the idea of a modal logic. The bulk of the
chapter, however, is devoted to explaining three closely related sys-
tems of modal logic and developing facility in using them. The chap-
ter concludes with remarks about some metaphysical assumptions
implicit in our treatment and with some consideration of whether
there is a "correct" system of modal logic.
its denial, some propositions are true, is true and necessarily so. Still
other examples seem equally necessary, but their denials do not lead
to such obvious arguments.
(9) Nothing is both red all over and green all over at the same
time;
(10) Nothing weighs more than itself;
(11) No numbers are human beings.
Still other candidates for this title of broadly logically necessary truth
are hotly disputed, both as to their truth as well as to their neces-
sity. Here are some examples:
(12) Man is a rational animal;
(13) There is no private language;
(14) For everything, there is a reason why it is so and not other-
wise;
(15) Nothing happens without a cause;
(16) In an infinite stretch of time all possibilities (potentiali-
ties) are realized.
Although this concept of a logically necessary truth cannot be
defined precisely and simply, the above examples help to communi-
cate the concept. It is also helpful to look at some nearby concepts
which should not be confused with it. Broadly logical necessity has
already been distinguished from physical or causal necessity. But
there are several more concepts to be distinguished from logical pos-
sibility. Once again our discussion draws heavily on Plantinga (The
Nature of Necessity, chap. 1).
"Ungiveupable"
"Self-evident"
A priori
TRUE FALSE
NECESSARY
________ I
"'°oo>-+----------
Impossible
o>..,6
(0
CONTrGENT
18 PROPOSITIONAL MODAL LOGIC
and inferences
□ p, l:.◊p,
◊p, l:.~~◊p,
and p, !:. ◊p.
What interests us here is not how Aristotle knew these, nor whether
he understood "possibility" and "necessity" in exactly the same way
we use these terms, but rather that he saw logical relationships to
be worked out.
The expressions "if... then ... ," "... implies ... ," and "... en-
tails ... " are often used, especially in philosophical and theological
literature, in the sense we represent by our - . However, we should
take note of certain important exceptions, so that we do not repre-
sent as modal arguments arguments that were never so intended by
their authors. Sometimes conditionals may express causal relation-
ships:
If hydrogen and oxygen are mixed in the presence of a
flame, then there will be an explosion;
If you plant beans, then you will not get broccoli.
Sometimes they express subjunctive conditionals:
If the Papacy had remained in Avignon, then today's Pope
would be a Frenchman;
If Bach had written the 1812 Overture, he would have
known the melody of the Marseillaise.
And there are other kinds of conditionals:
If Jager buys a bicycle, it will be either a Schwinn or a Fuji;
If you sit in the front of the plane, then you may not smoke;
THE MODAL CONCEPTS 21
If you took the $100 from Jones' drawer, then you have vio-
lated the law;
If you expect your share of the inheritance, then you must
stop your carousing.
None of these expresses a conditional that is a necessary truth; in
each case it is possible for the antecedent to be true and the conse-
quent to be false. Yet each of these may, in the proper context, ex-
press a true conditional.
"Since God foreknew that man would sin, that which God foreknew
must necessarily come to pass."
What is the scope of "necessarily" here? Is Evodius claiming that
If God foreknew that man would sin, then it follows neces-
sarily that man would sin (or, equivalently, It is necessary
that if God foreknew that man would sin, then man would
sin),
or that
If God foreknew that man would sin, then it is (a) neces-
sary (truth) that man would sin?
The philosophical question being discussed in the passage is whether
God's foreknowledge necessitates what he knows. Which reading we
choose could make all the difference in how we answer that question.
However, since the question of God's knowledge gives rise to addi-
tional complications and confusions, it might be better to pursue the
question of interpretation with the help of a different exampl~.
Most philosophers have held that it is impossible to know, actu-
ally know, something false. In other words, if I know p, it necessarily
follows that p is true, i.e., □ (S knows p ::>p is true). I might, on some
occasion, express this truth by saying that if I know there is coffee
in my cup, then necessarily there is coffee in my cup. However, this
way of expressing myself might lead someone to think what I said
expresses the necessity of the consequent:
((I know there's coffee in my cup)::> □ (there's coffee in my
cup)).
But a brief moment's reflection is enough to lead us to reject that
as a serious interpretation, assuming that I was trying to say some-
thing true. For if this reading were correct, I would generate a quick
but specious argument for the necessary .truth of everything I know
or anyone knows.
In spite of what may now seem obvious, there is a strong and re-
curring temptation in philosophy and theology to transfer the neces-
sity of the connection in a conditional to the consequent of the con-
ditional. It is important to resist this temptation. Indeed, it is a good
rule of thumb in translating from natural language into symbols to
suppose that necessity expressed in a conditional should be taken
as expressing necessity of the consequence, unless there is overwhelm-
ing specific evidence to the contrary.
1'iIE Loa IC OF MODALITY 23
2.1.h Exercises
Earlier we said that modal logic was the logic of these notions of
possibility and necessity. Now that the concepts are before us, what
should a logic of these concepts be like and what should it tell us?
Clearly, a modal logic should provide us with a way of exhibiting
the logical structure of those inferences that use modal concepts in
a way which affects their validity. There is no need to introduce more
apparatus than we have in ordinary propositional logic to validate
inferences of the form
□p:::) □ q ◊p:::)◊q
□p or ◊p
:. □ q :.◊q
since both are simply instances of modus ponens.
There are, however, some inferences in which these modal concepts
obviously play an important role, and the validity of those infer-
24 PROPOSITIONAL MODAL LOGIC
T T F T F
F T F F T
1. Suggestion {1 is a truth-function that makes Op true
no matter what p is. Hence it makes Op equivalent to
(p V ~p);
2. Suggestion {2 is a truth-function that makes Op false
no matter what p is. Hence it makes Op equivalent to
(p& ~p);
THE LOG IC OF MODALITY 25
per group on a side implies the lower). The reader can easily verify
that this works out, except for contingency.
Modern work in modal logic, and much of the modal logic in this
book, owes its beginning to the work of C. I. Lewis. Lewis was un-
happy with material or logical deducibility. Russell and Whitehead,
when they introduced the '::>'in Principia Mathematica, called the
relationship "material implication" and this connective the "material
conditional" precisely because they recognized it differed from what
is often called implication. The main problem with it is that it seems
to allow too much: propositions turn out to "materially imply" lots
of propositions we would not want to say that they "imply." This ob-
jection can be summarized formally in the "paradoxes of material
implication":
p ::>(q :::>
p), i.e., a true proposition is implied by any propo-
sition
and ~p ::>(p :::>
q ), i.e., a false proposition implies any proposition.
That this understanding of implication led to these paradoxes was
not something Lewis discovered. The ancient Megaric philosopher
"'
Ill
contraries .,, "'
Ill
• I!,
;::, ;::,
·~ C' -<" ·~
.... o?
,!' •
'l,o
C,
....
<::! <::!
..
i:::
'I,-<
,..Q ~"
o,~· ..
i:::
-
Ill Ill
.... o"'
C',!'
o,..,,.
....
C,
<::! p <::!
..c d' ..c
;:! ;:!
Philo proposed defining the conditional in just the way material im-
plication is defined-false when the antecedent is true and the con-
sequent false, and true otherwise. This was quickly criticized by his
fellow philosophers, including his teacher Diodorus Cronos. Further-
more, these ancients discussed the understanding of the conditional
that Lewis favors - that a conditional is true precisely when the nega-
tion of the consequent is incompatible with the antecedent. 4
Lewis calls his definition of implication, which we adopt, "strict
implication"; it is also referred to as "entailment":
p-qiff ~◊(p&~q), which is equivalent to D(p:::)q).
However, this sense of implication is not without apparent paradoxes
of its own. Although the paradoxes of material implication do not
hold for it, there are analogues of those paradoxes:
□ p:::) (q:::)p) a necessary truth is strictly implied by
any proposition;
~ ◊ p:::) (p -q) an impossible proposition strictly implies
any proposition.
Lewis intended his sense of strict implication to represent the re-
lationship of logical deducibility. That is, if p entails q, q should fol-
low logically from p. Yet, as one can see from the analogues to the
paradoxes of material implication, Lewis's strict implication is not
completely faithful to the relationship of logical deducibility. It per-
mits the deduction of a necessary truth, such as 2 + 2 = 4, from any
proposition.
A. R. Anderson and Nuel Belnap, Jr., have criticized Lewis's no-
tion of strict implication, while concurring with his objection to ma-
terial implication. They claim that in addition to the requirement that
there be a necessary connection between a proposition and what it
implies, the premises or antecedent must be relevant to what is im-
plied. As we have just seen, the paradoxes of strict implication, like
the paradoxes of material implication, expose the possibility of hav-
ing a conclusion strictly implied by irrelevant premises. Anderson
and Belnap have done extensive work on a system of logic designed
to remedy these defects. 5
In the face of these objections, why do we adopt the Lewis account
of entailment? Why do we accept these paradoxes?
The "paradoxes," as Lewis likes to point out, are the consequences
of straightforward and obviously acceptable rules. Thus our options
are either to accept the paradoxes or to give up some obviously cor-
rect rule. Consider this demonstration of the claim that from a con-
tradiction anything follows.
28 PROPOSITIONAL MODAL Lome
A&~A prem
A conj elim
AvB disj intro
~A conj elim
:.B disj elim
One of the rules used in this proof will have to be declared incorrect
and forbidden in a logic of "logical deducibility," if Anderson and Bel-
nap are right. Which rule should we give up? Which rule is such that
its conclusion is not "logically deducible" from its premise or premises?
We could make the point in a slightly different way. It is plausible
to regard the following as expressing properties of the entailment re-
lationship and therefore theorems of any adequate system represent-
ing entailment:
1. ((p-q)&(q-r))-(p-r) transitivity
2. (p&q)-((pvr)&q) additivity
3. ((pvq)&~p)-q disjoinability
But any system that has the above as theorems (and uses modus po-
nens and conjunction as rules of inference) yields the alleged para-
dox as a theorem:
1'. (p& ~p)-((pvq)&~p) substitution instance of (2)
above
2'. ((pvq)& ~p)-q (3) above
3'. (((p& ~p)-((p V q)& ~p)) substitution instance of (1)
&(((p V q)& ~p)-q))- above
((p&~p)-q)
4'. (p& ~p)-((p V q)& ~p) 1', 2', conjunction
& (((p V q)& ~p)-q)
5'. (p&~p)-q steps 2~4' MP
The price of eliminating the paradoxes of strict implication is high:
we must give up a rule and the corresponding theorem from the proofs
just given. Lewis found it less strange to accept the paradoxical for-
mulas than to reject any of these rules or theorems. Anderson and
Belnap find the formulas so paradoxical that they choose to give up
a rule and corresponding theorem.
They argue that the rules of disjunction introduction and disjunc-
tion elimination, and the theorems labelled "additivity" and "disjoin-
ability" are invalid as they stand. The theorems involve a logically
disreputable and unfit sense of disjunction, if one's aim is (as Lewis's
is) to come up with a calculus of entailment that accurately repre-
sents the properties of logical deducibility. In effect their criticism
THE Loa IC OF MODALITY 29
goes like this: although the rules in question are valid for the truth-
functional 'v' introduced in the classical propositional calculus, they
permit fallacies of relevance. In any respectable sense of deducibility
the premises have to be relevant to the conclusion, but the rules in
question permit us to deduce conclusions from premises which are
patently irrelevant. E.g.,
Either Bach wrote the Coffee Cantata or there is a largest
prime number;
There is no largest prime number;
Therefore, Bach wrote the Coffee Cantata.
If we introduce restricted versions of these rules, restrictions that
forbid the deduction of irrelevancies, then we will find that we can
no longer deduce q from (p& ~p).
Here we favor Lewis's conclusion, retaining the rules Anderson
and Belnap reject and accepting the so-called paradoxes of strict im-
plication. Two of the three modal systems presented here are ones
formalized by Lewis, though none is the system Lewis himself favors.
Lewis refuses to adopt "officially" his stronger systems S4 and S5,
developed later in this chapter, because they include as a theorem
(p-q)-((q-r)-(p-r)).
but not the "exported" form above. Lewis is unable to believe that
(q -r)-(p -r) is logically deducible from p -q.
In moving from truth-functional propositional logic to modal logic,
we leave behind the genuinely puzzling paradoxes of material impli·
cation and obtain a system that better represents entailment or logi-
cal deducibility. Our goal, however, is not to represent strictly by
means of a formal system what "implies" or "is logically deducible
from" means in English. Rather it is to represent the logic of neces-
sity, where necessity is interpreted as ''broadly logical necessity."
We thus elect to use a system that sometimes fails to preserve
relevance. However, we may be surprised at the relevance a clever
person can find. Russell is reputed to have been challenged to prove
that the necessarily false hypothesis 2 + 2 = 5 implied that he was
identical with the Pope. Russell replied, "You admit that 2 + 2 = 5,
but I can prove that 2 + 2 = 4; therefore 5 = 4. 'laking 2 away from
both sides, we have 3 = 2; taking 1, 2 = 1. But you will admit that
I and the Pope are 2. Therefore, I and the Pope are one. Q.E.D."
30 PROPOSITIONAL MODAL Lome
This system is the only one of the three we study which was not
proposed by C. I. Lewis. It fits so neatly and naturally into the "fam-
ily" of systems proposed by Lewis that it is regarded as a Lewis modal
system. 6 A version of it was studied by von Wright in 1951 and called
M. However, it had been proposed earlier in a different form by Rob-
ert Feys, who called it T. These two forms were subsequently shown
to be equivalent. Our presentation will differ from both of theirs.
First, recall the symbols already introduced:
1. □, an operator attaching to sentences and forming sentences,
read as "it is logically necessary that," or "necessarily." This
is attachable to any well-formed formula or sentence of propo-
sitional logic.
2. ◊, the so-called weak modal operator, also attaching to sen-
tences and read as "it is logically possible that," or "possibly."
3. -, representing a logically necessary conditional, and read as
"necessarily if ... , then ... ," or also as "entails" or "(strictly)
implies."
32 PROPOSITIONAL MonAL Lome
2.3.a Rules
What are the right rules for modal logic? How should you proceed
if you had to devise rules by yourself? Perhaps the best thing to do
is to look carefully at the concept you want to represent, trying to
discover on an intuitive level what its implications are. Next you
would propose some formal rules grounded in what seem to be basic
inference patterns and investigate their consequences.
When we think about broadly logical necessity this way, one ob-
vious implication, so obvious we might overlook it, is that whatever
is logically necessary is true. We represent that in our symbolism
like this:
(1) □ p:::>p.
q
□q nee intro
or (ii) p is the assumption for an impl
intro subproof within the scope
of the nee intro subproof. (It
(ii)
Dr
may be helpful to recall that re-
ductio ad absurdum proofs are
cases of impl intro subproofs.) r
□r
THE SYSTEM T 35
When a nee intro subproof is opened, we will draw a vertical line with
a □ to the left of it alongside the subproof. The line is continued un-
til the subproof is discharged and indicates the scope of the subproof,
as the above schematic examples illustrate. Any subsequent line
within a nee intro subproof must be either
(i) the result of using the appropriate reiteration rule;
or (ii) an assumption for an impl intro subproof within the scope
of the nee intro subproof;
or (iii) the result of applying our rules to lines within the scope
of the nee intro subproof;
or (iv) the opening line of another nee intro subproof within the
scope of the original.
2.3.b Hints
Here are a few hints that will be quite helpful in using these rules:
THE SYSTEM T 37
(3) You may use impl intro within a nee intro subproof. See
the earlier example. As the rule is stated, it does not re-
quire that you discharge any assumption introduced within
a nee intro subproof. If you make an assumption and then
see that it does not lead to anything useful, you may sim-
ply terminate it, and the proof you produce will still be
"official." Remember, though, that you may not apply nee
intro to a formula from an interior subproof unless it is
first removed from the scope of the assumption.
(4) Observe that by using impl intro as illustrated in the ear-
lier example, you can prove formulas of the form Op with-
out being given any premises. All formulas derivable from
our rules without the help of premises are theorems.
(5) 'fypically, you will use the rule nee intro by constructing
a nee intro subproof and applying nee intro to its last line.
However, you are not restricted to the last line. You may
find it possible, in the course of a proof, to derive several
lines within a single nee intro subproof to which you want
to apply nee intro. The present statement of the rule per-
mits you to do this without constructing a separate nee
intro subproof for each. Let us illustrate this using the ex-
ample of a conjunction that is necessary, where we want
to derive the necessity of each conjunct.
1. 0 (p&q&r&s) /.·. 0 p & 0 q & 0 r & 0 s
2. 0 (p&q&r&s) T-reit
3. p
4. q
5. r 2, conj elim
6. s
7. Op 3 nee intro
8. Oq 4 nee intro
9. Or 5 nee intro
10. Os 6 nee intro
11. Op& Oq& Or& Os 7-10 conj intro
38 PROPOSITIONAL MODAL LOG IC
(6) Note that where you have one nee intro subproof within
the scope of another, you will not be able to T-reit a for-
mula into the innermost subproof unless it has a □ remain-
ing on it in the outer subproof. T-reit only allows you to
cross one vertical line( □ I) at a time. Each one you cross
counts as a separate application of the rule, and so a □
must be removed each time.
□p □□ p
□ p T-reit (correct) □ □p T-reit (correct)
□: □:
p T-reit (forbidden) p T-reit (correct)
2.3.c Exercises
A. Give proofs:
2. p-q 3. □ (p&q)
□p :. □ q
q-r
:. □ r
Keeping this in mind, we can see two things: (1) the theorems so writ-
ten may be taken as generalizations about all sentences and may be
read that way, e.g., 'p :::>
p' expresses the claim that every sentence im-
plies itself; (2) a proof we give of a theorem schema is a proof schema
for a proof of any substitution instance of the theorem schema.
B. Prove the following theorems. Then try to state in English the
general truth that each one expresses.
1. p-p
2. □□ p- □ p
3. (p-q)-( □ p:::> □ q)
4. ( □ p& □ q)-(p-q)
5. □ p-(q-p)
6. □ ~p-(p-q)
7. (p-(q&~q))- □ ~p
8. ((p-q)&( ~p-q))- □ q
Possibility introduction
p
: .◊p poss intro
Possibility elimination
The name and formulation of this rule are due to Fitch. The rule
is more intuitively viewed as a way of transmitting possibility than
eliminating it. However we continue the pattern of designating the
rules for our operators as "introduction" and "elimination" rules, even
though it is less obviously appropriate here.
This rule enables us to introduce a possibility sign onto a sentence
entailed by a sentence which is itself possible. The basis for the rule
is the theorem
◊p
□ 1:&q □t
p T-reit
(p&q)
◊p poss elim ◊(p & q) poss elim
◊q poss elim (Op & ◊q) =>◊(p & q)
◊p&◊q
◊(p &q):>(◊p & ◊q)
The rules just introduced are redundant in the sense they do not en-
able us to prove anything that we could not have proven without them.
We can get the effect of these rules with the rules introduced prior
to this section.
Your instructor may wish to add more rules of this sort to make
it easier to give proofs and solve exercises. It is convenient to have
some versions of modal modus ponens:
p-q p-q
p □p
:.q :. □ q
Exercises
The antecedent is now equivalent to our first assumption, a), and the
consequent is an obvious necessary falsehood. Consequently, we have
a general counterexample to the alleged inference. Any contingent
proposition and its denial will suffice.
Example 2: (Op & q) ::J□ (p & q)
Let q be a contingently true proposition. This means we have q
and (◊q & ◊~q). Let p be the necessary truth (q v ~q). Substituting,
we obtain
(□ (q V ~q) &q)::J □ ((q V ~q) &q)
44 PROPOSITIONAL MODAL LOGIC
2.3.g Exercises
A. Give proofs:
1. □ p- □ (pvq)
2. (p-q)::)(~q-~p)
3. ~◊p::) ~Op
4. (p-r)&(q-s)
□ p& □ q
:. □ rv □ s
5. (p -r) v (q -r)
□ (p&q)
:. □ r
3. (p:)q):)(~◊q:)~◊p)
4. (p:)q):)(◊~q:)◊~p)
5. [((p&q)-r)& □ qJ-(p-r)
6. [((p&q)-r)&qJ-(p-r)
7. □ p- □ (p&q)
8. ◊(pvq)-(◊pv◊q)
9. (◊p v◊q)-◊(p vq)
10. (~◊p&~◊q)-◊(pvq)
11. (p-r)v(q-r)
D(pvq)
:. □ r
12. (p-r)&(q-s)
D(pvq)
:.D(rvs)
13. (p-r) & (q -s)
□ pv □ q
:. D(rvs)
14. (p-r)v(q-s)
Dpv □ q
:. D(rvs)
So far we have not dealt with formulas which have "piled up" or
repeated modal operators, e.g.,
◊ □□ ◊ □ p
◊ □ ◊( □ ◊p::> □ ◊◊q)
◊ □ (◊ □ ◊p& ◊◊( □ ◊ □p-q)).
Such formulas are difficult to understand. Our modal intuitions fail
us when we try to make sense of them. What sense can we make,
under our interpretation of the modal operators, of the difference be-
tween □□□□ p and □□□ p? Thus it seems desirable to look for a
way of reducing repeated modalities in such formulas, if possible.
First, we need to make more precise the concept of a repeated mo-
dality, or, as it is often called, an iterated modality. A sequence of
modal operators containing two or more modal operators consti-
tutes an iterated modality. There are several points to notice in con-
nection with this concept. First, a well-formed formula can contain
several iterated modalities, e.g., □□□ p :::>◊◊q. Secondly, the occur-
rence of one modal operator within the scope of another does not nec-
essarily constitute an iterated modality. For example, in □ (p :::>◊q),
although the ◊ occurs within the scope of the □, we do not have an
iterated modality because it is not a sequence of modal operators con-
taining two or more consecutive modal operators. Thirdly, when nega-
tions occur within a sequence of modal operators, as in □ ~◊~ □ p,
the sequence still is an iterated modality. This is because the ne-
gation always can either be removed or replaced by a single nega-
tion at the beginning of the sequence by substituting equivalences.
THE SYSTEM T 47
2.4.a Rules
l □p □p S4-reit
□p nee intro
□ p:::> □□ p.
The way we modified the rules of T to obtain our rules for S4 makes
it clear that Tis contained in S4, in the sense that any theorem prov-
50 PROPOSITIONAL MODAL Lome
able in Tis provable in S4. And our earlier illustration with AS4 makes
it clear that S4 is not contained in T.
2.4.b E:cercises
The only difference between the rules of T and the rules for S4
comes in the restriction on the reiteration rule. The T-reiteration rule
allows only lines of the form Op to be reiterated into nee intro sub-
proofs and specifies that when these lines are reiterated, the [) must
be dropped. The S4-reiteration rule likewise allows only lines of the
form □ p to be reiterated, but it does not require that the □ be
dropped. We can obtain a rule for S5 by relaxing the restrictions still
more.
A look at the characteristic formula of S5 will show us how to re-
lax the restriction further so as to obtain the proper rule. The char-
acteristic formula of S5
2.5. b Exercises
A glance back at RLl and RL2 shows that we have appropriate re-
duction laws for the first two on the list. Furthermore, we have a
start on proving the required equivalences in the case of the latter
two. We have
D◊p:::>◊p
Dp:::>◊Dp
in T and S4. Now in S5, we are able to obtain equivalences and gain
the rernaining reduction laws. Indeed, the formula needed to prove
the necessary equivalence is the characteristic formula of S5. So we
may add to our stock of reduction laws in S5.
RL3 Dp-◊Dp
RL4 ◊p-D◊p
All the iterated combinations that were irreducible in S4 are now re-
ducible to a single modal operator in S5. In fact, whenever we have
iterated modal operators in S5, we may remove all the modal opera-
tors except the last one.
There is also another type of reduction that can be carried out in
S5. 'lb describe this, we introduce the concept of modal degree of a
formula. With iterated modalities, this concept works just as one
would expect: D ◊ D p is a formula t>fdegree 3; D ◊ D ◊ p :::> D ◊p is a
formula of degree 4. This concept also applies to formulas in which
a formula containing modalities itself occurs within the scope of mo-
dalities, even though no iteration occurs, e.g., D (D p :::,D p) has de-
gree 2. The concept of degree encompasses iterated modalities and
other situations as well. The degree of a formula can be precisely cal-
culated as follows:
1) a propositional variable has degree O;
2) if p has degree n, then ~p has degree n;
PHILOSOPHICAL MATTERS 55
2.5.d Exercises
A. Prove:
I. □ ◊ □p= □ p
2. ◊ □ ◊p=◊p
3. □ ◊ □ ◊(p- □ ◊q):::>( □ ~pv ◊q)
4. ~(r-◊~p):::>(Dp & ◊r)
5. (~(r-◊~p)&(◊r-q)) :::>(( □ pv◊~q)&◊r)
B. Give the degree and reduce to first degree formulas:
1. □ ◊ □ ◊(◊◊p::) □ ◊p)
2. □ (pv □ q)
3. ◊(Op v ◊◊q)
4. ◊(p& □ q)
5. ◊( □ ◊p:::>q)
p ~p
◊p ◊~p
□p ◊p
□ ◊p
I ► □ ◊p
I
p
◊p
◊~p
□ ◊~p
□ ◊p
Figure 1
- = is accessible to, where a world W1 is accessible to a world W2 just in
case any proposition true in W2 is possible in Wi.
p
◊p ~p
◊~p
□p
◊p
□□ p
□ ◊p I
I .. □ ◊p
p
◊p
□p
□□ p
□ ◊p
W2
Figure 2
[-=is accessible to]
we will not pursue them here, we will be forced to look at similar is-
sues later on in dealing with modality and quantification when we
deal with the existence of individuals. Now we tum to another ques-
tion raised not only by these conundrums but also by the fact that
there are so many systems of modal logic: Is there one correct sys-
tem of modal logic?
We have before us three systems of modal logic, and there are many
more systems which we have not considered. Are they all correct?
Is only one correct?
In an Aristotelian Society symposium addressed to these ques-
tions, E. J. Lemmon 13 suggests an analogy with a situation in mathe-
matics. There are many systems of geometry: Euclidean geometry,
and a host of non-Euclidean geometries. Now there is one weak sense
in which all of these geometries are correct: They are all consistent
formal systems. They can each be modelled so that all the theorems
of the system tum out to be true in the model. But which one is true
of actual physical space? Which is true of the lines and triangles and
circles, etc., with which we have to do in our daily lives? It seems that
only one system can be correct and that it is an empirical matter to
find out which one.
Alas, the question is not quite so straightforward as this. For to
answer the question in this way, we must make some assumptions
about the accuracy of our measurements - usually that our instru-
ments remain constant at different times and places. But, continues
Lemmon,
If we make this assumption, we shall find, according to Einstein that
in fact there are triangles whose angles do not add up to two right angles:
on this assumption, physical space does not conform to Euclidean ge-
ometry. On the other hand, we can preserv!) the Euclidean model for
physical space by sacrificing the assumption, by admitting instead that
one's measuring instruments are deformed in certain ways at different
points. 14
modal logic is correct. First, it is not sufficient to ask about the for-
mal systems alone or even the formal system interpreted with the
help of an abstract model, such as a set theoretical model. We must
ask about the system under its intended interpretation, some actual
application. Then we can sensibly ask whether one system rather
than another is correct. Secondly, our intended interpretation must
be clear enough to enable us to answer questions about the truth or
falsity of theorems once they are interpreted. And, finally, we must
consider the effect adopting the system will have on other theories
we hold (or want to hold).
There is another consideration important to our present case. We
have before us three systems that are all compatible. The larger ones
contain the smaller ones. So if S5 is correct, both S4 and T contain
no falsehoods; rather, they do not contain all the modal truths. In
such a situation T and S4 would not be incorrect but insufficient.
Yet the correct system should be as adequate as possible; it should
contain all the relevant truths.
Although only one system is most adequate under an intended
interpretation, and we have suggested that S5 is the preferred sys-
tem where necessity is understood as broadly logical necessity, it does
not mean that there is no interest in the other modal systems, in-
cluding ones not presented here. For there are other ways of under-
standing necessity, as we have just seen in our brief consideration
of Prior, and there are still other quite different interpretations of
modal operators that philosophers have considered. Relative to these
other interpretations, one of the other modal systems may be the cor-
rect one. Let us look at some of the alternative interpretations to get
an idea of the possibilities.
We have mentioned earlier that C. I. Lewis, the "inventor" of S4
and S5, rejects these systems in favor of a weaker one, S2. Lewis be-
gan exploring modal logic because of his dissatisfaction with ':J' as
the formalization of the concept of implication, as used in Principia
Mathematica and in nearly all symbolic logic textbooks today. He
thinks that one proposition implies another when it is impossible both
for the implying proposition to be true and for the implied proposi-
tion to be false. He further thinks of implication in terms of deduci-
bility. Lewis uses a fishhook as his symbol for implication and he
interprets the expression p -3 q as meaning that q is deducible from
p. However he defines p -3 q in the same way we have defined p -q
-as O(p:Jq).
He employs his interpretation when he rejects S4 and S5 for con-
taining (p-3q)-3((q-3r)-3(p-3r)) as a theorem:
66 PROPOSITIONAL MODAL LOGIC
Lewis is here claiming that this formula is at least dubious and per-
haps false when interpreted as being about deducibility. He does not
doubt that when q is deducible from p and r is also deducible from
q, it can be deduced that r is deducible from p. But he is reluctant
to believe that when q can be deduced from p, we can always go on
to deduce that r's deducibility from pis deducible from r's deduci-
bility from q.
In S4 and S5
□ [ □ (p=>q)=> □(□ (q □ (p:::>r))]
:::>r):::>
is provable as a theorem, and it seems acceptable under our inter-
pretation. This suggests that Lewis either rejects our interpretation
of □ and ◊, or that he rejects other principles that are needed for
the deduction of this formula. I think it is most plausible to suppose
that he is reading □ as something other than broadly logical neces-
sity, since he formally defines p -8 q the very same way we define
p -q. He obviously takes the concept of necessity to be more closely
connected with deducibility than we do.
Arthur Prior has studied tense-logical interpretations of several
modal systems. 16 One way of obtaining a tense-logical interpretations
of the modal systems we have considered is to read the operators as
follows:
◊p = itis or was or will be the case that p
□p = it is, was, and will be the
case that p (or it is always
the case that p)
p = it is (now) the case the p.
Obviously some of the basic axioms are true on this interpretation.
□p =>p = If it is, was, and will be the case that p, then it
is (now) the case that p;
□ (p =>q) =>(□ p =>□ q) = If it is always the case the p =>q,
then if it is always the case that p, then it is always the
case that q.
So is R - if p is a theorem of propositional calculus, then p is, was, and
will be the case. Other tense-logical interpretations are also possible.
PHILOSOPHICAL MATTERS 67
3.1 Symbols
Lower case letters from the end of the alphabet are used as variables,
and Roman capitals with a variable or variables written immediately
to the right represent what are variously called predicates, senten-
tial functions, open sentences, propositional functions and relations.
For example, the expression Ax might represent the predicate x is
an aardvark, and Axy might symbolize x is the aunt of y.
We also adopt the usual characterization of free and bound occur-
rences of variables. The occurrence of a given variable will be bound
in a given formula when it either occurs in a quantifier or within the
scope of a quantifier containing that variable. An occurrence of a vari-
able that is not bound is a free occurrence.
69
70 QUANTIFICATION
3.2 Interpretation
3.3 Equivalences
3.4 Rules
From (x) ax
infer ay (or ax) where y is free and replaces all free oc-
currences of x in ax.
From (3x)ax
use
IT where Uy is the result of replacing all
EI ~p ::: free occurrences of x in ax with y;
where y is a variable that does not oc-
cur in any line of the proof prior to its
to infer p EI concl
introduction in the EI subproof, and y
does not occur free in p.
This rule appears more complicated than the others. However, this
form of the rule with its restrictions fits some common sense insights
EQUIVALENCES 73
17UyJp
an assumption for impl
intro)
Impl intro
(x)(UxJp) UG
(x) (UxJp)J[(3x)UxJp] (Theorem)
(3x)UxJp MP
p MP
The restrictions on the EI rule are just those needed to guarantee
that this proof will always work. If the subproof were not carried out
in terms of a "new" variable, then it would not be guaranteed that
UG could be used. And if p contained any free occurrences of the
variable introduced in the subproof, then the theorem about quan-
tifiers could not be used.
This shows that the form of EI adopted here is both formally and
intuitively a good one for a natural deduction system.
74 QUANTIFICATION
l
(3x)~Bx) Asp
~Bx EI asp
Ax-:JBx UI
~Ax MT
(3x)~Ax EG
(3x)~Ax EI concl
(3x) ~Bx :J(3x) ~Ax impl intro
(x) (Ax:JBx):J((3x) ~Bx:J(3x) ~Ax) impl intro
~
EI asp
IQX:)
Q UI
MT
Q EI concl
(3x)Fx-:JQ impl intro
(x) (Fx :J Q) :J ((3x)Fx :J Q) impl intro
Prove ((3x)Fx:JQ):J(x)(Fx:JQ)
j(3x)Fx :J Q) Asp
~
Asp
,~~Fx EG
1
MP
Fx:JQ impl intro
(x)(Fx:JQ) UG
((3x)Fx :J Q) :J (x)(Fx :J Q) impl intro
EQUIVALENCES 75
Exercises
4.1 Motivation
Why extend modal logic by adding quantification? What benefits
do we expect? Are there inferences we can shed light on that are not
illuminated by the methods developed so far?
77
78 QUANTIFIED MODAL Lome
4.3 Symbolization
tant to note one thing. The nee intro subproof rule uses the reiter-
ated lines as assumptions. Any line introduced into a nee intro sub-
proof (this includes poss elim subproofs) by a reiteration rule (T-reit,
S4-reit, S5-reit) is an assumption within that subproof and thus is
subject to restriction (3) in the statement of the Universal General-
ization rule. In other words, if we bring a formula containing a free
variable into a nee intro or poss elim subproof by means of a reitera-
tion rule, we may not apply UG to that variable within that subproof.
'lb illustrate this system, we will prove a few theorems.
First, we prove a quantified de re version of the characteristic for-
mula of S5:
(x)◊Fx::J(x) □ ◊Fx
(x)◊Fx asp
◊Fx UI
□ l◊Fx S5-reit
□ ◊Fx nee intro
(x) □ ◊Fx UG
(x)◊Fx::J(x) □ ◊Fx impl intro
The following more interesting formula is also provable in this
system:
◊(3x)Fx=(3x)◊Fx
◊(3x)Fx asp
-(3x)◊Fx asp
◊-(3x)◊Fx poss intro
DI ◊-(3x)◊Fx S5-reit
□ ◊-(3x)◊Fx nee intro
-◊ □ (3x)◊Fx def of □ ,◊
□ (3xFx asp for poss elim
EI asp
Fx poss intro
◊Fx S5-reit
(3x)◊Fx EG
(3x)◊Fx nee intro
□ (3x)◊Fx EI
◊ □ (3x)◊Fx poss elim
(3x)◊Fx RAA
◊(3x)Fx ::J(3x)◊Fx impl intro
94 QUANTIFIED MODAL LOG IC
and
(3x)◊Fx asp
~◊(3x)Fx asp
□ (x)~Fx Def, DN
□ 1(x)~Fx T-reit
~Fx UI
□ ~Fx nee intro
(x) □ ~Fx UG
~(3x)◊Fx Def, DN
◊(3x)Fx RAA
(3x)◊Fx::> ◊(3x)Fx impl intro
Exercises
The Barcan Formula and its converse make de dicto and de re neces-
sity equivalent in this system. The Buridan Formula allows us to in-
fer de re possibility from de dicto possibility. We have already noted
that its converse is not a theorem of this system.
The Barcan and Buridan Formulas have proven to be highly con-
troversial under our present interpretation. Indeed, the situation is
even worse than that. These formulas seem to express false claims
96 QUANTIFIED MODAL LOG IC
is to say that all essential properties are the kind of properties noth-
ing can fail to have in any possible world- properties like being either
red or non-red and like being such that 2 + 2 = 4. These sorts of prop-
erties are sometimes called trivially essential properties. So to have
a quantified modal logic that can represent significantly essential
properties and do so without requiring that individuals have proper-
ties in worlds in which they do not exist or requiring that no possible
world have any individuals that do not exist in the actual world, we
will have to jettison the Barcan Formula.
We should consider, too, what effect including the Buridan For-
mula has on our possible worlds model. By the Buridan Formula, if
there actually is something that has an essential property, then in
every world there is something that has that property. Now if each
individual is essentially unique, i.e., has some property essentially
that cannot be possessed by any other individual, then no individual
in the actual world can be absent from any other possible world. For
example, if being identical with Socrates is essential to Socrates, and
only Socrates can have this property, as seems plausible, then there
are properties of this sort. But then we have the conclusion that no
world lacks any individual who exists in the actual world.
Combining the results of considering these two formulas, we have
the conclusion that exactly the same individuals exist in all possible
worlds. But that implies, of course, that all individuals exist neces-
sarily. So either we are stuck with that blatant falsehood, or we have
a modal system that is satisfied only by necessary beings - those
things that exist necessarily. This means that the system cannot deal
with essential properties of contingent beings, such as you and me
and our earthly possessions. Either way it seems desirable to look
for another system.
The problem is this. Just a few years before Kripke's 1959 paper,
Arthur Prior had published a deduction of the Barcan formula from
the axioms of standard quantification theory and S5. 34 It seemed
therefore that the Barcan Formula (and the Buridan and Converse
Barcan Formulas) were simply part of quantified S5 and that it was
impossible to get rid of them without going to a different system.
But in 1963 Kripke claimed that there is a subtle fallacy in Prior's
proof and that the system we have just considered is an improper
version of S5.
98 QUANTIFIED MODAL Lome
Recall that this rule provides a way of terminating a nee intro sub-
proof. The nee intro subproof rule remains as it was. The additional
restrictions introduced here will only affect the derivation of certain
formulas containing free variables and formulas obtained by a gen-
eralization rule. Propositional logic will not be affected at all.
nee intro
A nee intro subproof may be terminated at any point, and any line,
p, occurring within the subproof and that is not within the scope of
KRIPKE's REVISED 85 (1963) 99
1. □ (x)ax asp
2. □ I (x)ax T-reit
3. ax UI
4. □ ax* nee intro
5. (x) □ ax UG
6. □ (x)ax:::)(x) □ ax implintro
*Step 4 now is forbidden by the second pro-
viso, which requires that the step to which nee
intro is applied contain no free occurrences of
a variable introduced by use of an instantiation
rule within the subproof. Line 3 contains a free
occurrence of a variable introduced into the nee
intro subproof by UI.
As further exercises, look back at the proofs given in Section 9
of this chapter of the Barcan and Converse Barcan formulas and de-
termine which restrictions are now violated in those proofs. It may
also be a useful exercise to attempt proofs of the Buridan and Con-
verse Buridan formulas (◊(x)ax:::)(x)◊ax and (x)◊ax:::)◊(x)ax) to
see how such attempts run afoul of the restrictions.
The system under discussion includes as its theorems all and only
the closed formulas deducible by means of the natural deduction rules
given. A closed formula is one that contains no free occurrences of
variables. Many formulas containing free occurrences of variables are
deducible, but they are not theorems of the system. Kripke says in
stipulating this that such open formulas only make sense if we under-
stand them as implicitly closed anyway, so we are not depriving our-
selves of anything we should have, and we are getting rid of some
undesirable formulas. This system he regards (with some justice) as
the proper version of quantified S5. It has the advantage of not yield-
ing the Barcan and Buridan formulas, which run counter to the sense
of the modalities we want to capture. The system also has the advan-
tage of not requiring that the same individuals "populate" each pos-
sible world. We should remind ourselves here that these advantages
REFLECTIONS ON KRIPKE's REVISION 101
are advantages only when we consider the systems under our intended
interpretation.
tation of D differs from what we were looking for, and that the ab-
sence of the Converse Buridan Formula is a deficiency. Kripke reads
the Converse Barcan Formula as saying that if it is true in every pos-
sible world that everything in that world has property a, then a is
true of everything there is and true of it in every possible world.
Since Kripke also assumes, rightly, that things do not have atomic
properties in worlds in which they do not exist (his interpretation
makes it false in such a world that the individual has the property),
his system is incapable of expressing atomic essential properties of
entities that do not exist in every possible world. This means that
no contingently existing individuals, such as Socrates, can be said
to possess essentially such properties as being human or being ra-
tional, assuming these to be atomic properties. For it is not true of
Socrates in every possible world that he is human or that he is ra-
tional. Kripke's system is only capable of expressing trivially essen-
tial properties of contingently existing entities by using the □. A
trivially essential property is one that every individual has neces-
sarily, such as being red or non-red or, perhaps, the property of being
such that 2 + 2 = 4.
If, on the other hand, we understand having a property essentially
as not lacking that property in any world in which it exists, and if
we want D as attached to open sentences to express possessing a
property essentially, then it can be seen that the Converse Barcan
Formula should be a theorem of our system. For the CBF simply ex-
presses what is a necessary truth: if it is true in every possible world
that everything is a, then everything has a in every world in which
it exists. And we continue to assume that individuals do not have
properties in worlds in which they do not exist.
There is also a metaphysical difficulty with Kripke's interpreta-
tion of quantified S5 that we will not pursue in detail here: it seems
to require that there are some individuals that do not exist. Accord-
ing to the interpretation he proposes, for each possible world there
is a set of individuals that comprises the individuals that exist in
that possible world. There will be some "overlap" from world to world,
but also some individuals "lost" and others "added." 'Th.king this in-
terpretation, there must be a union of all these sets of individuals -
the total set of all individuals in all possible worlds. Now if we sup-
pose, as seems entirely plausible, that the actual world does not
contain all the individuals there could be, then some other possible
worlds "contain" individuals not to be found in the actual world. But
if this is so, then there must be a union of all the sets of individuals
in all the possible worlds that contains objects that do not actually
'fiIE ACTUALISTIC VERSION OF POSSIBLE WORLDS 103
state of affairs including another and that of one state of affairs pre-
cluding another. Let S 1 and S 2 stand for any states of affairs (not
necessarily different ones). Then S 1 is said to include S 2 if and only if
it is not possible for S 1 to be actual without S 2 also being actual, and
S 1 precludes S 2 if and only if it is impossible that S 1 and S 2 should
both be actual. So, for example, the state of affairs of Roger Maris's
hitting his 61st home run includes the state of affairs of Roger Maris's
having hit his 30th home run, while the state of affairs of something
being an obtuse triangle precludes that thing's being an equilateral
triangle.
These concepts now enable us to define a maximal state of affairs.
A state of affairs, M, is maximal just in case for any state of affairs,
S, M either includes S or precludes S.
According to this definition, given a maximal state of affairs and
any old state of affairs, the latter state of affairs is either already
part of the maximal state of affairs or cannot be added to the maxi-
mal one without yielding an inconsistent state of affairs as a result.
Any genuine enlargement of a maximal state of affairs will be in-
consistent.
Notice, however, that a maximal state of affairs need not be com-
posed of a large number of constituent states of affairs. It may be,
but it may also be composed of just one- a self-inconsistent one, such
as 7 + 5 = 13, which will, of course, preclude every state of affairs.
On the other hand, however, a check of the definition of includes shows
that inconsistent states of affairs tum out to include every state of
affairs, too. The point is that any inconsistent state of affairs is
maximal.
It is clear that we want nothing to do with these inconsistent maxi-
mal states of affairs. We define a possible world, then, as a state of
affairs that is both maximal and consistent. This explanation ac-
counts for possible worlds without the need to introduce any shadowy
metaphysical entities or strange doctrines. Possible worlds can be
nicely explained in terms of entities with which everyone is quite
familiar.
Not only is the notion of a possible world thus explained in quite
familiar terms, it is also explained in a way that makes it perfectly
plausible to suppose that there are possible worlds. If there are states
of affairs, as there surely are, then there are possible worlds. It has
to be kept in mind, of course, that these are abstract entities. It is
not as though there is some place at which possible worlds exist. All
possible worlds, including the one that has been actualized, are ab-
stract entities. Now, from this it does not follow that the physical
world is an abstract entity, but rather that the existence of a pos-
ACTUALISM AND QUANTIFICATION 105
sible world differs from the actuality of a possible world. All of a huge
number of possible worlds exist; at most one can be and is actual.
without allowing for objects that exist in other possible worlds but
not in the actual world, the alternatives are unpalatable. We either
(1) have to explain quantification in a possible world when part or
all of its domain does not exist, or (2) explain how something can have
a property (at least a nontrivial property) in a world in which it does
not exist, or (3) hold that there are things that do not exist, or (4)
hold that there are no possible worlds containing objects not con-
tained in the actual world.
Assuming we want to hold to a standard reading of quantifiers
and we want some possible worlds to "contain" individuals who do
not exist in the actual world, how shall we construe domains of quan-
tification for possible worlds? The domains of quantification for the
various possible worlds will have to be subsets of actually existing
things and be necessarily existing things in order to satisfy the re-
quirements we have laid down. Alvin Plantinga suggests that we use
essences - individual essences.
What are individual essences and how can it be made clear that
they will serve as the domain of quantifiers in modal contexts? We
have said that an object has a property in a world if it would have
been true that it has the property had that world been actual. For
an object to have a property essentially is to have the property in
every world in which it exists. The introduction of one further con-
cept will enable us to define individual essences. Let us define what
it means for a property to be exemplified in a possible world. A prop-
erty is exemplified in a possible world if the proposition that some-
thing has that property would have been true had that world been
actual. This definition enables us to offer our official definition of an
individual essence. An individual essence is a property that is exem-
plified in some possible world, and in every possible world any thing
that has this property has it essentially, and nothing else in any pos-
sible world has this property. 37 Although a given individual essence
need not be exemplified in any particular possible world, essences
are properties, and since properties presumably are necessary beings,
as such, they exist in every possible world. 38 So, for example, Julius
Caesar's essence exists in every possible world even though Julius
Caesar fails to exist in some possible worlds. We can exploit this fea-
ture of essences to explain quantification in modal contexts.
'lb conclude our explanation, we need to define one more concept,
that of coexemplification. We will say that two properties are coex-
emplified with each other in a possible world when the proposition
that something has both properties would have been true had that
possible world been actual.
ACTUALISM AND QUANTIFICATION 107
With this, we are in a position to say how the actualist who adopts
quantification over domains of essences reads various types of propo-
sitions. Consider first of all ordinary universally quantified proposi-
tions and existentially quantified ones.
(x) (x is a man::)x is mortal)
is understood as follows: any essence in the domain of essences that
are actually exemplified (i.e., any essence in the domain of the actual
world) is such that if it is coexemplified with the property of being
a man, then it is coexemplified with the property of being mortal.
The existentially quantified statement
(3x) (x is man & x is mortal)
is read like this: Some essence in the domain of essences exemplified
in the actual world is coexemplified in the actual world with the prop-
erties of being a man and being mortal. Some existing thing, which
of course has an individual essence and which is an example of (ex-
emplifies) that essence, has the properties of being human and mortal.
The advantages of this actualist view begin to emerge more clearly
as we consider statements which mix modalities and quantifiers. First
we look at quantifiers within the scope of a modality:
◊(x) (xis a man::)x is mortal)
is interpreted as meaning that in some possible world, every individ-
ual essence in the domain of essences that would be exemplified if
that world were actual is coexemplified with the property of being
mortal if a man. Or, more simply, ◊(x)Ux means that in some pos-
sible world, every individual essence that would be exemplified if that
world were actual is coexemplified with property a. Note that we say
"would be exemplified" and not "would exist." Every individual es-
sence exists in every possible world. But not all are exemplified in
every possible world. Similarly, ◊(3x)ax is interpreted as saying
that in some possible world, some individual essence (in the domain
of essences of that world) is coexemplified with the property a. This
reading boils down to saying that Opis true just in case there is a
possible world in which p is true.
How about examples of modalities within the scope of quantifi-
ers, as in
(x)◊(Ux)
and
(3x)◊ax?
108 QUANTIFIED MODAL LOGIC
Exercises
4.14.a Rules
Nee elim
Poss intro
Nee intro subproof rule
Reit (T-reit, S4-reit, S5-reit)
Quantification rules (UI, UG, EI, EG)
Nee introA
A nee intro subproof may be terminated at any point, and any line,
p, occurring within the subproof and that is not within the scope of
an assumption undischarged at that point in the nee intro subproof
may be entered as a line prefixed by □ with the justification "nee in-
tro," provided that the line p contains a free occurrence of every vari-
able that has a free occurrence in any line within the nee intro subproof
on which p depends.
Poss elimA
Where ◊ p appears as a line in a proof (and not within the scope of a
discharged assumption) and where an impl intro subproof opened with
p as its assumption within the scope of an nee intro subproof yields
a conclusion, q, both subproofs maybe terminated simultaneously and
◊q entered as the next line in the proof with the justification poss
elim, provided that every variable which has a free occurrence in q also
has a free occurrence in p.
The best way to see how the restrictions work and how to use them
is to consider some examples. Consider the following proof and be
prepared to compare it with the succeeding one:
Here the only step deduced within the nee intro subproof is line
6, derived from lines 4 and 5. Lines 4 and 5 contain free occurrences
of the variable x, and x occurs free in line 6, thus satisfying the re-
AcTUALISTIC QUANTIFIED MODAL Lome 111
The proofs may seem identical, but this latter proof violates the
restriction on nee intro subproofs in line 6, the starred line. Line 6
depends on lines 4 and 5. Lines 4 and 5 each contain free occurrences
of two variables, x and y, while line 6 contains only an occurrence
of x. The free variable y has been "lost." Hence the restriction has
not been satisfied and this second "proof" is fallacious.
Next, consider a pair of proofs illustrating the use and misuse of
the poss elim rule:
Prove: □ (x)Fx::>(x) □ Fx
1. □ xFx asp
2. □ 1(x)Fx T-reit
3. Fx UI
4. □ Fx nee intro
5. (x) □ Fx UG
6. □ (x)Fx::>(x) □Fx impl intro
The restriction on nee intro subproofs is trivially satisfied since the
only deduction within such a subproof is the deduction of line 3 from
2, and line 2 contains no free occurrences of any variable. Attempts
to prove the Barcan Formula run afoul of restrictions, however. The
reader can verify this by turning back to the proof of this formula
in section 9, earlier in this chapter. (There the formula appears in an
equivalent form, ◊(3x)Fx:::>(3x)◊Fx.) The Barcan Formula is not a
theorem of this system, which is just what we intended.
4.14.b Exercises
A. Symbolize
1. There is a being that possibly fails _toexist.
2. Possibly there is something brown that could be blue.
3. Necessarily everything that is red is colored.
4. Everything that is red is necessarily colored.
5. Everything that is red is necessarily colored essentially.
6. Anything that is six feet tall might not have been six feet tall.
EXISTENCE AND MODALITY 113
C. Give Proofs:
12. □ (x)((Ax&Bx):J ~Cx)
(x) □Ax
(x) □ (Bx:JCx) :.(x)~◊Bx
13. (x)( □Ax:::, □Bx)
□ (x)(Bx:::, Cx)
:.(x)( □Ax:::, □ Cx)
even true, to deny that my older brother exists, i.e., to deny that I
have an older brother.
the argument goes, we will no longer be able to tell who is Adam and
who is Noah. There do not seem to be any clear criteria for identify-
ing Adam and identifying Noah such that in any given possible world
we can tell which is which. So we are invited to surmise that perhaps
there are no individual essences of objects that would make trans-
world identification possible. Individual essences are supposed to in-
dividuate things, and they do not seem to be able to do that.
Initially it is important to note two things about this alleged dif-
ficulty. First of all, it should not be taken to imply that there are no
individual essences. It does not follow that a thing has no individual
essence. Rather, the argument suggests that all of a thing's proper-
ties are essential to it- a very implausible position. Secondly, the argu-
ment or puzzle generates an epistemic claim about our inability (in
some cases, anyway) to tell what individual essence a thing exempli-
fies or a claim about our inability to tell whether some thing x in
one possible world exemplifies the same individual essence as y in
some other possible world. But then it invites us to jump to the meta-
physical conclusion that there are no individual essences that can be
exemplified in more than one possible world. This conclusion does
not follow.
It is also important in this connection not to be misled by the "pic-
ture" we have been using. It is helpful to think instead in terms of
the official definitions and descriptions given earlier. Recall that possi-
ble worlds and individual essences are abstract objects. A possible
world is a maximally consistent state of affairs, and an individual
essence is a set of properties (or complex property) such that anything
that has (exemplifies) it, has (exemplifies) it essentially, and no other
thing can have (exemplify) it. Assuming that properties exist neces-
sarily, there is no question about the existence of individual essences,
and there is no question that they individuate (i.e.,whatever exempli-
fies one is a distinct individual). There is also no difficulty in the pos-
sibility that essences should be exemplified in more than one possi-
ble world.
This view leaves open questions about what properties might be
essential to various individuals and how we might be able to ascer-
tain whether a given individual has a given property essentially. But
this is not apt to confuse us about the nature of essences unless we
insist on using the metaphor of visually peering at two incompletely
known individuals in two possible worlds and supposing that we
should be able to tell whether they have the same essence.
SUPERIORITY OF ACTUALISM 117
119
120 APPENDIX I
S5 comes by adding its "characteristic formula" to T.
S5: T plus 7. ~ □p ::) □ ~ □p
(7.) is the form Godel gave. It also appears as
7'. ◊p::) □ ◊p
and 7". ◊ □p ::) □p.
The form (7) is used in order to specify the axiom solely in terms that
are primitive, i.e., undefined, within the system.
In an important paper on modal logic, Saul Kripke uses this basis
for T as a set of sufficient conditions for calling a modal propositional
calculus normal. Non-normal systems are ones that do not satisfy
R2.
In an interesting paper that groups some modal logics into vari-
ous "families," entitled "New Foundations for Lewis Modal Systems,"
E. J. Lemmon defines a Lewis Modal System as follows:
A Lewis Modal System is a system that
(i) contains the full classical propositional calculus;
(ii) is contained in S5;
(iii) admits substitutability of tautologous equivalents;
(iv) possesses as theorems:
Fl. □ (p:)q):)(0p:)0q)
F2. □ (p&q)=( □p& □ q)
F3. (D(p:)q)&D(q:)r)):) □ (p:)r)
F4. □p::)~ □ ~p.
It is easy to see that T, S4, and S5 are Lewis Modal Systems in the
defined sense, even though T was not among the systems Lewis him-
self proposed.
APPENDIX II
121
122 APPENDIX II
1' □ ~~q
p
I ~q
□p:) □ q
□ (p :)q) :)(Op:) □ q)
APPENDIX II 123
p
Op
Since each formulation contains the other, they are equivalent.
APPENDIX III:
AN EFFECTIVE DECISION PROCEDURE
125
NOTES
127
128 NOTES TO PAGES 66-97
16. See his Time and Modality (Oxford, 1957), Past, Present, and Future
(Oxford, 1967), and Papers on Time and Tense (Oxford, 1968).
17. Hintikka, Knowledge and Belief (Cornell, 1962).
18. Lemmon mentions several more in the paper cited in note 13.
19. Those interested in pursuing this may consult Leonard Linsky, "'l\vo
Concepts of Quantification," Nous, vol. 6 (1972), 224-39. [Reprinted as an
appendix to Linsky, Names and Descriptions (Chicago, 1977).] See also Ruth
Barcan Marcus, "Interpreting Quantification," Inquiry, vol. 5 (1962), 252-59,
and Nuel Belnap and J. Michael Dunn, "The Substitutional Interpretation
of Quantifiers" Nous, vol. 2 (1968), 177-85; Susan Haack, Philosophy of Logics
(Cambridge, 1978), chap. 4.
20. This technical term was defined a few pages earlier.
21. Quoted from Aristotle, The Works of Aristotle, ed. W. D. Ross, vol. I,
(Oxford, 1928), 166a pp. 24-30.
22. SCG, I, 67. 'Ir. Anton Pegis (Notre Dame, 1975). Note that the "fal-
lacy of composition and division" here mentioned is that of confusing the
composite and the divided senses of some expression.
23. Several of these topics will arise again in "Some Objections to Quan-
tified Modal Logic."
24. 'Divisible' itself appears to be a modal term. Here we will understand
it to mean 'having at least two parts.'
25. Quine, "Three Grades of Modal Involvement," The Ways of Paradox
(Random House, 1966), p. 174.
26. Quine, "Reference and Modality," in From a Logical Point of View, sec-
ond edition (Harper and Row, 1961), p. 143.
27. Ibid., p. 144.
28. We will not pursue any further Quine's objections and possible re-
sponses. Anyone interested in pursuing the issue in detail should consult
Leonard Linsky's anthology, Reference and Modality (Oxford, 1971), and the
appendix to Alvin Plantinga's The Nature of Necessity (Oxford, 1974), where
Quine's objection is discussed in detail.
29. And accidental properties as well. An accidental property is a prop-
erty an individual has in the actual world but lacks in some other possible
world in which the individual exists.
30. "Counterpart Theory and Quantified Modal Logic," Journal of
Philosophy, vol. 65 (March 1968), pp. 113-26.
31. For more on fictional characters, see N. Wolterstorff's Works and
Worlds of Art (Oxford, 1980), pp. 134-58.
32. What I give here is equivalent to the form ◊(3x)Ux:J(3x)◊ax
which was first discussed by Ruth Barcan, now Ruth Barcan Marcus, in 1946.
33. So named by Alvin Plantinga, The Nature of Necessity (Oxford, 1974),
p. 58, after Jean Buridan, who denied the truth of the natural interpretation
of it.
34. "Quantification and Modality in S5," Journal of Symbolic Logic, vol.
21, no. 1 (March 1958), 60-62.
NOTES TO PAGES 103-115 129
131
132 BIBLIOGRAPHY