Full Between Sanity and Madness: Mental Illness From Ancient Greece To The Neuroscientific Era 1st Edition Allan V. Horwitz Ebook All Chapters
Full Between Sanity and Madness: Mental Illness From Ancient Greece To The Neuroscientific Era 1st Edition Allan V. Horwitz Ebook All Chapters
Full Between Sanity and Madness: Mental Illness From Ancient Greece To The Neuroscientific Era 1st Edition Allan V. Horwitz Ebook All Chapters
com
https://textbookfull.com/product/between-sanity-
and-madness-mental-illness-from-ancient-greece-to-
the-neuroscientific-era-1st-edition-allan-v-
horwitz/
https://textbookfull.com/product/creating-mental-illness-1st-edition-
allan-v-horwitz/
textbookfull.com
https://textbookfull.com/product/whats-normal-reconciling-biology-and-
culture-1st-edition-allan-v-horwitz/
textbookfull.com
https://textbookfull.com/product/madness-and-genetic-determinism-is-
mental-illness-in-our-genes-patrick-d-hahn/
textbookfull.com
https://textbookfull.com/product/handbook-of-innovations-in-cns-
regenerative-medicine-1st-edition-antonio-salgado-editor/
textbookfull.com
Handbook Of Theory And Research In Cultural Studies And
Education 1st Edition Peter Pericles Trifonas
https://textbookfull.com/product/handbook-of-theory-and-research-in-
cultural-studies-and-education-1st-edition-peter-pericles-trifonas/
textbookfull.com
https://textbookfull.com/product/lidar-remote-sensing-and-
applications-1st-edition-pinliang-dong-2/
textbookfull.com
https://textbookfull.com/product/information-systems-a-manager-s-
guide-to-harnessing-technology-version-8-0-8th-edition-john-
gallaugher/
textbookfull.com
Nursing Care of the Pediatric Neurosurgery Patient 3rd
Edition Cathy C. Cartwright
https://textbookfull.com/product/nursing-care-of-the-pediatric-
neurosurgery-patient-3rd-edition-cathy-c-cartwright/
textbookfull.com
Between Sanity and Madness
Between Sanity and Madness
Mental Illness from Ancient Greece to the Neuroscientific Era
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by
any means, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, by license, or
under terms agreed with the appropriate reproduction rights organization. Inquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of
the above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above.
You must not circulate this work in any other form and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer.
This material is not intended to be, and should not be considered, a substitute for medical or other professional advice. Treatment
for the conditions described in this material is highly dependent on the individual circumstances. And, while this material is
designed to offer accurate information with respect to the subject matter covered and to be current as of the time it was written,
research and knowledge about medical and health issues is constantly evolving and dose schedules for medications are being
revised continually, with new side effects recognized and accounted for regularly. Readers must therefore always check the
product information and clinical procedures with the most up-to-date published product information and data sheets provided by
the manufacturers and the most recent codes of conduct and safety regulation. The publisher and the authors make no
representations or warranties to readers, express or implied, as to the accuracy or completeness of this material. Without limiting
the foregoing, the publisher and the authors make no representations or warranties as to the accuracy or efficacy of the drug
dosages mentioned in the material. The authors and the publisher do not accept, and expressly disclaim, any responsibility for any
liability, loss or risk that may be claimed or incurred as a consequence of the use and/or application of any of the contents of this
material.
To my daughters: Rebecca, Jessica, and Stephanie
Contents
Preface
References
Index
Preface
My interest in mental illness began as an undergraduate during the late 1960s when questions
about this topic were prominent aspects of the youth culture. At the time, the work of such
figures as Ken Kesey, R. D. Laing, Thomas Szasz, and Erving Goffman were widely read and
discussed. When I entered graduate school in sociology at Yale in 1970, I encountered far more
conventional, but equally fascinating, views of psychiatric disorders. I was exposed to the
rigorous and pathbreaking sociological research of Sandy Hollingshead and Jerry Myers about
how factors such as social class and family structure profoundly shaped definitions of and
responses to those who were perceived as mentally ill. In addition, Donald Black’s innovative
studies of law and social control, which relied on a huge range of cross-cultural and historical
material, provided a model of inquiry that I have tried to emulate ever since. My own work
focused on the then-new topic of how social network structures influenced the processes through
which people came to enter psychiatric treatment. My first book, The Social Control of Mental
Illness (1980) attempted to generalize the findings from my thesis about how individuals in New
Haven defined their conditions and sought psychiatric help to a far broader range of settings.
After graduate school, I joined the faculty of the Sociology Department at Rutgers University,
which I never left. A few years after my arrival, I experienced an unusually rare stroke of luck.
David Mechanic, probably the foremost medical sociologist in the world, moved to Rutgers and
we became close collaborators. I was well-versed in David’s scholarship but had no idea that he
was also an extraordinary institution builder. In 1985 he established the interdisciplinary Institute
for Health, Health Care Policy, and Aging Research (IFH), which strongly influenced my
subsequent work.
One of the core members of IFH was the historian Gerald Grob, whose prolific studies on
American psychiatric history and policy had a major impact on my own writings. I was fortunate
to collaborate with Gerry on a number of projects before his untimely death in 2015. This book is
deeply indebted to Gerry’s scholarly vision and perspective. The postdoctoral program in mental
health at IFH was another major inspiration for my research. Gerry’s presence attracted many
leading young historians of mental illness including Elizabeth Lunbeck, Nancy Tomes, and the
late Jack Pressman, all of whom became major figures in this field. The postdoctoral program
also led to my collaboration with the extraordinary theorist of mental illness Jerry Wakefield,
with whom I co-authored two books, The Loss of Sadness (2007) and All We Have to Fear
(2012) as well as a number of articles and chapters. Jerry’s brilliant thought has infused my
writings for the past quarter-century. More recently, I have been fortunate to work with another
former postdoc, historical sociologist Owen Whooley, who is producing dazzlingly insightful
work on the history of psychiatric knowledge in the United States. IFH also brought me into
contact with a wide range of interdisciplinary researchers including Deborah Carr, Stephen
Crystal, Peter Guarnaccia, Ellen Idler, Howard Leventhal, Jane Miller, Kathleen Pottick, Sarah
Rosenfield, Keith Wailoo, and Jamie Walkup. My colleague in the Rutgers Sociology
Department Eviatar Zerubavel provided a model of creative sociological thinking. All of these
scholars not only provided an incredibly congenial work environment but also models for
imaginative and innovative scholarship.
In addition to the many wonderful faculty and postdocs that I encountered at Rutgers, I have
been fortunate to work in a field—the social and historical study of mental illness—that is filled
with exceptional scholars. Those who have had especially important influences on this book
include David Healy, George Makari, Andrew Scull, Edward Shorter, and the late Roy Porter.
This book is the result of these many diverse sociological, historical, anthropological, and
philosophical influences. Consequently, it is unusual in a number of ways. Although the volume
is organized chronologically, it does not adhere to a traditional concentration on a single culture
or historical era. Instead, it considers how various societies have defined madness and sanity,
viewed the relationship between psychic and physical disorders, and understood the origins and
appropriate responses to mental illnesses. Bookended by an analytic introductory chapter and a
synthetic concluding one, the first three substantive chapters involve understandings of mental
illness in Ancient Greece and western European societies while the following five chapters focus
on American psychiatry. Many of these chapters draw upon my previous writings, which are
noted in the Acknowledgments section in each chapter.
Terminology represents a great challenge in writing about mental illness. Terms such as
“mad” and “insane” that were historically descriptive labels have become highly pejorative. I
continue to use them, despite the considerable baggage they carry, because they convey
meanings that have traditionally accompanied understandings of mental illness. In addition, I use
the more general terms “mental illness” and “mental disorder” interchangeably although others
employ them more distinctively.
Finally, I have been fortunate to continue my affiliation with Oxford University Press. I am
especially grateful to my editors, Andrea Knobloch and Jacqueline Buckley, for their support
throughout this project. I am also indebted to the anonymous reviewers of this manuscript for
their many insightful suggestions, which have resulted in an immensely improved book.
1
Puzzles of Mental Illness
[In ancient Israel] it was proposed that a person who wandered about alone at night, who spent the
night in a cemetery, or who tore his garments and destroyed what was given to him might be
considered deranged—if such behavior appeared irrational. However, it was pointed out that otherwise
normal persons could also behave in this way, e.g. one who spent the night in a cemetery might have
done so to practice magic, or that another who tore his clothes might have done so in a fit of anger, or
because he was a cynic philosopher exhibiting his contempt for material things.
—George Rosen, Madness in Society (1968)
Every society, regardless of time or place, regards some of its members as mad. Typically, this
label has been reserved for a small number of seemingly senseless behaviors. For example, the
Native Alaskan term for crazy, “nuthkavihak,” refers to “such phenomena as talking to oneself,
screaming at someone who does not exist, believing that a child or husband was murdered by
witchcraft when nobody else believes it, believing oneself to be an animal . . . killing dogs, and
threatening people.”1 Similarly, the Kalumburu people in Australia use the word “wambaba” to
mean mad or crazy; it refers to “an excited or assaultive individual who talks strangely, swears a
lot, forgets his manners, opens his bowels where people live, knocks over his water holder, or
runs off in fright to the bush. He behaves in a highly disturbed and incomprehensible way.”2
Early 20th-century German psychiatrist Karl Jaspers comparably isolated “incomprehensibility”
as the most distinctive aspect of madness: “All the sudden impulses, the unfathomable affect and
lack of affect, the sudden pauses in conversation, the disconnected ideas. . . . Some call these
actions eccentric, silly. But with all these terms we are at the end of the day saying the same
thing: The common factor is ‘incomprehensible.’ ”3 The inexplicable aspects of madness contrast
with the socially shared conceptions of reality that mark sanity.
Present views of what constitutes a mental illness encompass such unfathomable conditions
but far more as well. Despite general agreement regarding the pole of madness, huge disparities
exist on where dividing lines should be placed between it and sanity and even if there is any clear
demarcation at all. The range of current mental disorders includes, among much else, depression,
anxiety, post-traumatic stress disorder (PTSD), various addictions, attention-deficit/hyperactivity
disorder (ADHD), and numerous personality disorders. The most highly regarded surveys
indicate that a quarter of the U.S. population experiences some mental illness in any particular
year and well over half at some point in their lives.4 Other, more comprehensive, studies show
that two-thirds of people will become mentally ill over their lifetime.5 Recent cohorts of young
people report especially vast amounts of disorder: in the early 21st century, half of American
adolescents seemingly have some mental illness by age eighteen.6 Global data from the World
Health Organization indicate that mental illnesses now account for more years of disability than
any other disease category.7
Enormous historical and cultural disparities also exist regarding what sort of authority should
respond to mental illnesses. Dominant current practices—following a long tradition—regard
these conditions as brain-based defects that medical and other mental health professionals should
treat. In other times and places, however, similar behaviors have been viewed as sins that require
confession, possessed states in need of exorcism, crimes that entail punishment, or creative
inspirations that should be cultivated.8
While various groups provide an extensive array of answers to questions about the nature of
mental illness and its boundaries with sanity, all have confronted the same issues. What
distinguishes mental illnesses from other sorts of devalued conditions and from normality?
Should medical, religious, psychological, legal, or no authority at all respond to the mentally ill?
Which factors lead people to become mad? What treatments might help them recover? The
various responses that societies have provided to these puzzles are both widely divergent and
surprisingly similar to current understandings.
For these ancient observers, the characteristic feature of mentally ill people did not lie in their
behavior. Instead, it involved the absence of contextually appropriate reasons for their actions.
The mad often wandered at night, slept in cemeteries, or tore their clothes off. Yet, sorcerers,
angry people, or philosophers also did the same things. The essential difference was that the
latter had socially comprehensible motivations—practicing magic, fits of anger, philosophical
principles—for their behaviors. In contrast, observers could not connect the activities of the
mentally ill to any socially explicable purpose. Inferences about sanity and madness, therefore,
involved whether or not actions could be linked to understandable motives.
Two thousand years later, acclaimed sociologist Erving Goffman made a similar point: “The
delusions of a private can be the rights of a general; the obscene invitations of a man to a strange
girl can be the spicy endearments of a husband to his wife; the wariness of a paranoid is the
warranted practice of thousands of undercover agents.”10 Judgments about whether some
behavior is deluded or justified, obscene or romantic, and paranoid or reasonable require
knowledge of relevant contextual information. When observers can find a socially plausible
reason for some action, they do not define it as a sign of mental disturbance.
The Sebei people of East Africa provide an example of how groups differentiate mental illness
from other devalued behaviors such as criminality, drug use, intellectual deficiency, bad
manners, or ignorance. Anthropologist Robert Edgerton recounts a dialogue among a group of
Sebei who are discussing the behavior of a young man that they observed talking nonsense,
making abrupt and jerky movements, flapping his arms like a bird, and giggling like a child:
Visit https://textbookfull.com
now to explore a rich
collection of eBooks, textbook
and enjoy exciting offers!
SALIMU: He is a strange boy.
SAYEKWA: He is a foolish boy. Why does he behave that way?
SALIMU: He may be mad or he may be foolish (mentally retarded).
SAYEKWA: It could also be bewitchment or a fever or something like a fit. . . .
INTERPRETER: There is something wrong. People here smoke bhang. Perhaps he may be a bhang
man.
SAYEKWA: No. I don’t think that. He is more like he is crazy.
SALIMU: I think he may be a fool.
INTERPRETER: It is impossible to know without knowing about his family. We could ask one of
these people about him.
ANTHROPOLOGIST: What is the difference between a fool and a madman?
SALIMU: A fool was born without sense. A madman becomes senseless because of a disease or
witchcraft. We would have to know his history to tell about this young man.11
This debate shows the typical constructions involved in making attributions of insanity.
Observers use factors such as family history, biographical circumstances, and situational
contingencies to decide among the various possible interpretations of inappropriate behaviors.
Before participants use mental illness to explain some strange behavior, they rule out other
designations such as foolishness, bewitchment, psychotropic drug use, or epilepsy. The answers
to the questions that the Sebei pose also imply the kind of response that should be made to the
strange behavior. If he is a “bhang man,” then the village equivalent to the police might be
called. If he is a fool, he was born that way and no remedies are available. If, however, the boy is
deemed to be mad, they might summon a witchdoctor to expel the possessing force. Similar
distinctions persist in current psychiatric diagnostic manuals.
Much like the Sebei, the DSM strives to isolate the particular qualities that distinguish mental
disorders from other kinds of devalued conditions and from normality. Its characterization has
four central aspects, two that try to express what mental illnesses are and two that attempt to
delineate them from non-disordered behaviors.
Dysfunctions
At the heart of the way that the DSM identifies a mental disorder—comparable to the various
definitions of premodern groups—is the presence of a “dysfunction in the psychological,
biological, or developmental processes underlying mental functioning.” Although the definition
does not specify what a “dysfunction” is, the term presumably indicates that some process is not
simply undesirable or rare but that something has gone wrong with mechanisms involving
cognition, emotional arousal, perception, memory, and the like.13 The resulting symptoms are
neither explicable responses to circumstances nor culturally normative. The definition does not
stipulate whether dysfunctions involve defective brain or psychic processes but allows for either
sort of account. Nor does it mention what qualities mark the appropriate functioning of
psychological, biological, or developmental processes.
The DSM’s placement of dysfunction at the heart of its definition of mental disorder echoes a
long historical tradition. For example, a renowned Ancient Greek physician, Aretaeus of
Cappadocia (~2nd century AD), described melancholics in these terms: “Sufferers are dull or
stern: dejected or unreasonably torpid, without any manifest cause.”14 Here, “without any
manifest cause” implies that melancholic symptoms result from some inner dysfunction as
opposed to reasonable grounds for melancholy such as the loss of an intimate relationship,
economic catastrophe, or diagnosis of a serious physical disease. Two thousand years later, one
of the founders of 19th-century biological psychiatry, German psychiatrist Wilhelm Griesinger
(1817–1868), made a comparable distinction between identical symptoms that result from a
dysfunction or from some appropriate external cause:
The melancholia which precedes insanity sometimes appears externally as the direct continuation of some
painful emotion dependent upon some objective cause . . . , e.g. grief, jealousy; and it is distinguished from
the mental pain experienced by healthy persons by its excessive degree, by its more than ordinary protraction,
by its becoming more and more independent of external influences, and by the other accessory affections
which accompany it.15
Symptoms that are rooted in external situations are “healthy”; those with disproportionate
severity or duration to their generating contexts indicate insanity. The DSM follows this
enduring line of thought, emphasizing how only symptoms that reflect an internal dysfunction
rather than some appropriate situational cause mark some disorder. If nothing is wrong with
someone’s inner functioning, they do not have a mental illness.
As the debate among Talmudic scholars shows, it is often difficult to distinguish conditions
that arise from a dysfunction or from some other reason. Consider the case of Michael Phelps,
who has won more Olympic medals than any athlete in history. When he was nine years old,
Phelps received a diagnosis of ADHD, which is made when someone is unable to focus, sit still,
or concentrate, presumably because of some inner dysfunction. “I was told by one of his teachers
that he couldn’t focus on anything,” his mother recounts.16 This suggests that Phelps had some—
possibly biological—inability to pay attention. Yet, he had no comparable problems of focus
when it came to his swimming. “For the past 10 years, at least, he’s never missed a practice,”
Phelps’s mother recalled. “Even on Christmas, the pool is the first place we go, and he’s happy
to be there.” Did Phelps have a dysfunction or, instead, a compelling competing interest that
preoccupied him?17 Alternatively, he could have been one of the youngest children in his class
so that his relative immaturity put him at greater risk for receiving an ADHD diagnoses.18 All
groups have faced the intrinsic uncertainties in distinguishing behaviors that stem from
dysfunctions or from other reasons.
Pederasty—sexual relations involving adult men and prepubescent boys—provides another
example of the problems involved in making decisions about the presence of some dysfunction.
Our culture views pederasty as perhaps the most reviled form of sexual behavior. The DSM-5
defines adults who are aroused by having sex with children (generally thirteen years or younger)
as having a pedophilic disorder, which involves inappropriate targets of sexual preferences.19 In
our society, some inner dysfunction is likely to motivate pedophiliacs’ anomalous sexual
preference because their desires persist despite strong social sanctions.20
Yet, many cultures have institutionalized sexual relationships between older men and
prepubescent and adolescent boys. Most notably, the ancient Greeks esteemed intergenerational
erotic ties among males, which were deeply embedded in their civic life: “A whole philosophy
was built up round [pederasty], based on the idea that the lover was the educator and military
trainer and partner of the beloved, and would do everything to earn his admiration,” historian
Michael Grant notes.21 Involvement in culturally approved man–boy sex among the ancient
Greeks (and other societies that do not condemn such relationships) would rarely stem from
defective sexual arousal mechanisms but instead are learned and culturally approved practices.
The Siwan group in North Africa provides an example: “All men and boys engage in anal
intercourse. Males are singled out as peculiar if they did not do so.”22 In such groups, a
dysfunction is unlikely to underlie pederasty. Therefore, similar modes of sexual attraction are
likely to stem from dysfunctions in groups where they arise in the face of harsh disapproval but
not in others where they are customary and, sometimes, even mandated.
The example of pederasty illustrates some of the many issues raised by the requirement that a
mental disorder must stem from some dysfunction: is it possible to know what the appropriate
functions of psychological mechanisms are without reference to cultural values; can a
mechanism that is dysfunctional in some groups be functional in others; do many negatively
valued behaviors such as extreme jealousy, hatred of outgroups, fear of strangers, or intercourse
with pubescent adolescents stem from natural, rather than dysfunctional, processes?23 Such
concerns raise the question of the objective or value-laden nature of dysfunctions. “The most
fundamental issue, and also the most contentious one,” psychiatrist Robert Kendell contends, “is
whether disease and illness are normative concepts based on value judgments, or whether they
are value-free scientific terms; in other words, whether they are biomedical terms or socio-
political ones.”24 The DSM introduces a normative component into its definition through
invoking the distress or disability associated with some dysfunction.
Distress or Disability
The DSM implicitly deals with the issue of whether definitions of mental disorder are objective
or value-laden through stating that a dysfunction in itself typically does not provide sufficient
grounds to infer the presence of a mental disorder. Only dysfunctions that are “usually associated
with distress or disability” are disorders.25 Therefore, adequate characterizations of mental
disorder contain elements of both a dysfunction that involves incapacity to perform a natural
function and a cultural judgment that defines the dysfunction as undesirable. Jerome Wakefield’s
term “harmful dysfunction” captures this dual quality of mental disorder.26
The necessity of harm means that dysfunctions are not mental disorders when they are neither
distressing nor disabling. Many psychological dysfunctions—for example, persistent
depressions, crippling compulsions, or inexplicable anxiety—intrinsically entail distress. Yet,
many others do not involve any misery at all. For example, anosognosia—the unwillingness of
people to believe that anything is wrong with their minds—can characterize people with
schizophrenia.27 Or, the manic stage of bipolar disorder is marked by euphoria, seemingly
exceptional ideas, highly pleasurable behaviors, and often unusual degrees of creativity.28 The
DSM takes this into account by saying that dysfunctions that do not involve distress must entail
“disability in social, occupational, or other important activities” if they are to be considered as
disorders. In contrast to distress, which refers to the feelings of the disturbed individual,
disability often involves problems with other people such as parents, spouses, teachers, bosses,
or social control agents.
The DSM’s distress or disability constraint means that, although all mental disorders result
from some inner dysfunction, all dysfunctions are not disorders. Only dysfunctions that also have
impairing consequences for selves or others are mental disorders, presumably because it would
be pointless to be concerned with conditions that are unproblematic for both individuals and
those around them. One important consequence of this aspect of the DSM definition is that,
while dysfunctions can be grounded in universal organic or psychic processes, mental disorders
can be cross-culturally relative. Because the degree of distress or disability that any dysfunction
entails varies considerably across cultures, the definition implies that dysfunctions can be
disorders in some cultures but not in others.
Anthropologist Ruth Benedict’s “Anthropology and the Abnormal” (1934) presented the
classic statement that the concept of mental disorder is culturally relative. Benedict (1887–1948)
questioned the validity of applying Western definitions of normality and abnormality to different
cultures. Instead, she asserted that various groups around the world consider as normal and
appropriate the sorts of behaviors—paranoia, seizures, trances, and the like—that Western
psychiatry defined as abnormal. She used as an example the Dobuans of Melanesia, who display
a constant fear of poisoning that they saw as normal rather than as paranoiac. Or, she noted that
the Shasta Indians in California and the native people of Siberia did not view seizures as dreaded
illnesses but instead as signs of special connections to supernatural powers that singled out
people for authority and leadership. She also discussed catalepsy—a state that involved
trancelike states, hearing voices, losses of voluntary motion, and rigid limbs—to illustrate how
some other cultures treated as valued conditions what Western psychiatry considered as the
mental disorder of catatonic schizophrenia. “There are,” Benedict asserted, “well-described
cultures in which these abnormals function at ease and with honor, and apparently without
danger or difficulty to the society.”29
Conversely, Benedict described behaviors that were normalized and even rewarded in our
culture that would be considered mad in other cultures. Dobuans, for example, would regard a
person who was always cheerful, happy, and outgoing as crazy. Divisions between justified
suspicions or paranoia, ritualistic invocations of spirits or hallucinations, and unnaturally
prolonged or appropriate periods of grief were often blurry, tied to context, and subject to value
judgments. Normality thus resided in culturally approved conventions, not in universal biological
or psychological standards of appropriate functioning. “All our local conventions of moral
behavior and of immoral are without absolute validity,” Benedict concluded.30
Advocates of the DSM definition could use the distress or disability requirement to challenge
Benedict’s assertion that there is no validity to Western conceptions of schizophrenia because
some groups place people who hallucinate, have delusions, fall into trance states, and speak
incoherently into valued and honored social roles. From their perspective, such individuals have
dysfunctions that their cultures do not evaluate as harmful.31 The distress or disability
requirement implies that the universal aspects of dysfunctions are compatible with the culturally
relative nature of mental disorders.
Like decisions about the presence of a dysfunction, judgments about distress or disability can
be difficult to make. Take the example of the poet Emily Dickinson who, by the time she was
forty, would not leave her home and hid in her room, unwilling to see even her longtime
friends.32 Nothing about Dickinson’s circumstances could account for her refusal to walk outside
or to meet with people she had known for extended periods of time. Her extreme social isolation
seems likely to have stemmed from some inner dysfunction. Yet, it was arguably neither
distressing nor disabling. Indeed, many people regard her as the greatest American poet, largely
because of the poems she wrote during her period of seclusion. Whether her extreme fear of
going out in public or seeing friends should count as disabling or, on the contrary, a precondition
for her genius has no easy answer.
The distress or disability stipulation is a complicating factor in setting boundaries between
sanity and madness. It also raises challenging issues related to the value-laden component of
definitions of mental disorder. Both feelings of distress and social impairments often arise
because of negative societal attitudes rather than any intrinsic qualities of some dysfunction. For
example, the DSM-III diagnosis of “ego-dystonic homosexuality,” which applied to
homosexuals who were distressed by their sexual orientation, seems to result more from
individual responses to oppressive social norms than from a dysfunction.33 It shows how the
harm that some condition engenders can stem from cultural values rather than from the
dysfunction. Separating the normative from the biomedical elements of mental disorder is often
an imposing task.
Kleinman’s symptoms easily meet the DSM criteria for major depressive disorder. Yet, as long
as emotions have been recorded, experiences of grief—feelings of deep sadness that follow the
death of an intimate—have been central to portrayals of basic human nature. Kleinman’s grief, as
the DSM definition recognizes, is a normal response to an intense loss. Accordingly, his distress
gradually eased over time in the absence of any treatment: “This dark experience lightened over
the months, so that the feelings became much less acute by around 6 months.”36 The intense
depressive symptoms that Kleinman and other grievers experience are not products of a
dysfunction but are explicable in light of their circumstances of loss.
Like Kleinman’s grief, anxious emotions that could indicate a dysfunction when no danger is
present are appropriate in perilous situations. Psychiatrist Kenneth Kendler uses the example of a
mountain climber who suffers a full-blown panic attack when he loses his grip and falls before
his rope catches him. “A panic attack,” Kendler explains, “is not—in and of itself—
psychopathological. It only becomes pathology when it occurs in certain contexts—at times and
in places when it should not. Thus the diagnostic status of panic disorder is inherently contextual.
It is not a disorder in and of itself but only in certain contexts.”37
As is the case with grief, not panic symptoms alone but their relationship to the circumstances
in which they emerge accounts for the distinction between “expectable” panic attacks that are not
disorders and “unexpectable” ones that are disorders. Identical symptoms that are explicable in
one context, such as falling down a mountain, are signs of a mental disorder when there is no
contextually appropriate explanation for them. “Most negative mental states such as sadness,
despair, anxiety, fear, agitation, and anger,” Wakefield and psychiatrist Michael First observe,
“are not abnormalities but normal responses to life’s vicissitudes.”38
PTSD illustrates some of the nuances involved in distinguishing “abnormalities” from “normal
responses to life’s vicissitudes.” It definitionally arises from exposure to some traumatic event
and so might seem to be an “expectable” response to a stressor and, therefore, not a dysfunction.
However, the characteristics that Griesinger noted in regard to depression—“excessive degree,”
“more than ordinary protraction,” and “becoming more and more independent of external
influences”—suggest that continuing symptoms of PTSD have become detached from their
initial generating context. Their intrusive, recurrent, and involuntary nature indicates that an
extreme environmental stressor has led the natural functioning of memory mechanisms to
breakdown.39 Because such symptoms are also almost invariably associated with distress and/or
disability, PTSD would be a genuine mental disorder and not simply a contextually explicable
response to circumstances. Needless to say, it is often difficult to distinguish behaviors that are
“dysfunctional” from those that are “expectable” reactions to given contexts.
Medicine is a science which hath been more professed than labored, and yet more labored than
advanced; the labour having been, in my judgment, rather in circle than in progression. For I find
much iteration, but small addition.
—Francis Bacon, The Advancement of Learning (1605)
A dedicated profession of psychiatry did not emerge until the late 18th century in Europe and the
mid-19th century in the United States. Nevertheless, before that time all groups confronted
questions about how to define mental illness, which authority had jurisdiction over the mad, what
caused madness, and the best ways to treat it. Their answers show both divergences from and
similarities to more recent conceptions.
PLATE III.
Moreover, many of the same faces, that is, faces having the same
relation to the symmetry, are present on all three varieties, the
“forms” to which they equally belong being the common heritage of
calcite wherever found. A “form” is the technical term for a set of
faces having an equal value with respect to the symmetry. Thus the
prismatic form in Fig. 6 is the hexagonal prism, a form which is
common to the hexagonal and trigonal systems of symmetry, and the
form “indices” (numbers[1] inversely proportional to the intercepts
cut off from the crystal axes by the face typifying the form) of which
are {2̄1̄1}; the large development of this form confers the elongated
prismatic habit on the crystal. The terminations are faces of the flat
rhombohedron {110}. The pyramidal form of the dog-tooth spar
shown in Fig. 7 is the scalenohedron {20̄1}, and it is this form which
confers the tooth-like habit, so different from the hexagonal prism,
upon this variety of calcite. But many specimens of dog-tooth spar,
notably those from Derbyshire, consist of scalenohedra the middle
portion of which is replaced by faces of the hexagonal prism {2̄1̄1},
and the terminations of which are replaced by the characteristic
rhombohedron {100} of Iceland spar; indeed, it is quite common to
find crystals of calcite exhibiting on the same individual all the forms
which have been mentioned, that is, those dominating the three very
differently appearing types. The author has quite recently measured
such a crystal, which, besides showing all these four forms well
developed, also exhibited the faces of two others of the well-known
forms of calcite, {3̄1̄1} and {310}, and a reproduction of a drawing of
it to scale is given in Fig. 8. Instead of indices the faces of each form
bear a distinctive letter; m = {2̄1̄1}, r = {100}, e = {110}, v = {20̄1}
(the faces of the scalenohedron are of somewhat small dimensions on
this crystal), n = {3̄1̄1}, and t = {310}.
It is obviously then the “habit” which is
different in the three types of calcite—Iceland
spar, prismatic calc-spar, and dog-tooth spar
—doubtless owing to the different local
circumstances of growth of the mineral. Habit
is simply the expression of the fact that a
specific “form,” or possibly two particular
forms, is or are much more prominently
developed in one variety than in another.
Thus the principal rhombohedron r = {100},
parallel to the faces of which calcite cleaves so
readily, is the predominating form in Iceland
spar, while the scalenohedron v = {20̄1} is the
habit-conferring form in dog-tooth spar. Yet
on the latter the rhombohedral faces are
Fig. 8.—Measured frequently developed, blunting the sharp
Crystal of Calcite. terminations of the scalenohedra, especially
in dog-tooth spar from Derbyshire or the
Hartz mountains; and on the former minute
faces of the scalenohedron are often found, provided the
rhombohedron consists of the natural exterior faces of the crystal
and not of cleavage faces. In the same manner the prismatic crystals
from Egremont are characterised by two forms, the hexagonal prism
m = {2̄1̄1} and the secondary rhombohedron e = {110}, but both of
these forms, as we have seen on the actual crystal represented in Fig.
8, are also found developed on other crystals of mixed habit.
This illustration from the naturally occurring minerals might
readily be supplemented by almost any common artificial chemical
preparation, sulphate of potash for instance, K2SO4, the
orthorhombic crystals of which take the form of elongated prisms,
even needles, on the one hand, or of tabular plate-like crystals on the
other hand, according as the salt crystallises by the cooling of a
supersaturated solution, or by the slow evaporation of a solution
which at first is not quite saturated. In both cases, and in all such
cases, whether of minerals or chemical preparations, the same planes
are present on the crystals of the same substance, although all may
not be developed on the same individual except in a few cases of
crystals particularly rich in faces; and these same planes are inclined
at the same angles. But their relative development may be so very
unlike on different crystals as to confer habits so very dissimilar that
the fact of the identity of the substance is entirely concealed.
A further example may perhaps be given,
that of a substance, hydrated sulphate of lime,
CaSO4.2H2O, which occurs in nature as the
beautiful transparent mineral gypsum or
selenite—illustrated in Fig. 9, and which is
found in monoclinic crystals often of very
large size—and which may also be chemically
prepared by adding a dilute solution of
sulphuric acid to a very dilute solution of
calcium chloride. The radiating groups of
needles shown in Fig. 10 (Plate II.) slowly
crystallise out when a drop of the mixed
solution is placed on a microscope slip and
examined under the microscope, using the
one-inch objective. These needles, so
absolutely different in appearance from a
crystal of selenite, are yet similar monoclinic
prisms, but in which the prismatic form is
enormously elongated compared with the
other (terminating) form. Fig. 9.—Crystal of
Gypsum.
This difference of facial development,
rendering the crystals of one and the same
substance from different sources so very unlike each other, was
apparently responsible for the very tardy discovery of the
fundamental law of crystallography, the constancy of the crystal
angles of the same substance. Gessner, sometime between the years
1560 and 1568, went so far as to assert that not only are different
crystals of the same substance of different sizes, but that also the
mutual inclinations of their faces and their whole external form are
dissimilar.
What was much more obvious to the early students of crystals, and
which is, in fact, the most striking thing about a crystal after its
regular geometric exterior shape, was the obviously homogeneous
character of its internal structure. So many crystals are transparent,
and so clear and limpid, that it was evident to the earliest observers
that they were at least as homogeneous throughout as glass, and yet
that at the same time they must be endowed with an internal
structure the nature of which is the cause of both the exterior
geometric regularity of form, so different from the irregular shape of
a lump of glass, and of the peculiar effect on the rays of light which
are transmitted through them. From the earliest ages of former
civilisations the behaviour of crystals with regard to light has been
known to be different for the different varieties of gem-stones.
About the year 1600 Cæsalpinus observed that sugar, saltpetre,
and alum, and also the sulphates of copper, zinc and iron, known
then as blue, white and green vitriol respectively, separate from their
solutions in characteristic forms. Had he not attributed this to the
operation of an organic force, in conformity with the curious opinion
of the times concerning crystals, he might have had the credit of
being the pioneer of crystallographers. The first two real steps in
crystallography, however, with which in our own historic times we
are acquainted, were taken in the seventeenth century within four
years of each other, one from the interior structural and the other
from the exterior geometrical point of view. For in 1665 Robert
Hooke in this country made a study of alum, which he appears to
have obtained in good crystals, although he was unacquainted with
its true chemical composition. He describes in his “Micrographia”
how he was able to imitate the varying habits of the octahedral forms
of alum crystals by building piles of spherical musket bullets, and
states that all the various figures which he observed in the many
crystals which he examined could be produced from two or three
arrangements of globular particles. It is clear that the homogeneous
partitioning of space in a crystal structure by similar particles
building up the crystal substance was in Hooke’s mind, affording
another testimony to the remarkably prescient insight of our great
countryman.
Four years later, in 1669, Nicolaus Steno carried out in Florence
some remarkable measurements, considering the absence of proper
instruments, of the angles between the corresponding faces of
different specimens of rock-crystal (quartz, the naturally occurring
dioxide of silicon, concerning which there will be much to say later in
this book), obtained from different localities, and published a
dissertation announcing that he found these analogous angles all
precisely the same.
In the year 1688 the subject was taken up systematically by
Guglielmini, and in two memoirs of this date and 1705 he extended
Steno’s conclusions as to the constancy of crystal angles in the case of
rock-crystal into a general law of nature. Moreover, he began to
speculate about the interior structure of crystals, and, like Hooke, he
took alum as his text, and suggested that the ultimate particles
possessed plane faces, and were, in short, miniature crystals. He
further announced the constancy of the cleavage directions, so that
to Guglielmini must be awarded the credit for having, at a time when
experimental methods of crystallographic investigation were
practically nil, discovered the fundamental principles of
crystallography.
The fact that a perfect cleavage is exhibited by calcite had already
been observed by Erasmus Bartolinus in 1670, and in his
“Experimenta Crystalli Islandici” he gives a most interesting account
of the great discovery of immense clear crystals of calcite which had
just been made at Eskifjördhr in Iceland, minutely describing both
their cleavage and their strong double refraction. Huyghens in 1690
followed this up by investigating some of these crystals of calcite still
more closely, and elaborated his laws of double refraction as the
result of his studies.
There now followed a century which was scarcely productive of any
further advance at all in our real knowledge of crystals. It is true that
Boyle in 1691 showed that the rapidity with which a solution cools
influences the habit of the crystals which are deposited from it. But
neither Boyle, with all his well-known ability, so strikingly displayed
in his work on the connection between the volume of a gas and the
pressure to which it is subjected, nor his lesser contemporaries
Lemery and Homberg, who produced and studied the crystals of
several series of salts of the same base with different acids,
appreciated the truth of the great fact discovered by Guglielmini, that
the same substance always possesses the same crystalline form the
angles of which are constant. Even with the growth of chemistry in
the eighteenth century, the opinion remained quite general that the
crystals of the same substance differ in the magnitude of their angles
as well as in the size of their faces.
We begin to perceive signs of progress again in the year 1767, when
Westfeld made the interesting suggestion that calcite is built up of
rhombohedral particles, the miniature faces of which correspond to
the cleavage directions. This was followed in 1780 by a treatise “De
formis crystallorum” by Bergmann and Gahn of Upsala, in which
Guglielmini’s law of the constancy of the cleavage directions was
reasserted as a general one, and intimately connected with the
crystal structure. It was in this year 1780 that the contact goniometer
was invented by Carangeot, assistant to Romé de l’Isle in Paris, and it
at once placed at the disposal of his master a weapon of research far
superior to any possessed by previous observers.
Fig. 11.—Contact Goniometer as used by Romé de l’Isle.
The important work of Romé de l’Isle had paved the way for a
further and still greater advance which we owe to the University of
Paris, for its Professor of the Humanities, the Abbé Réné Just Haüy,
a name ever to be regarded with veneration by crystallographers,
took up the subject shortly after Romé de l’Isle, and in 1782 laid most
important results before the French Academy, which were
subsequently, in 1784, published in a book, under the auspices of the
Academy, entitled “Essai d’une Théorie sur la Structure des
Crystaux.” The author happens to possess, as the gift of a kind friend,
a copy of the original issue of this highly interesting and now very
rare work. It contains a brief preface, dated the 26th November 1783,
signed by the Marquis de Condorcet, perpetual secretary to the
Academy (who, in 1794, fell a victim to the French revolution), to the
effect that the Academy had expressed its approval and authorised
the publication “under its privilege.”
The volume contains six excellent plates of a large number of most
careful drawings of crystals, illustrating the derivation from the
simple forms, such as the cube, octahedron, dodecahedron,
rhombohedron, and hexagonal prism, of the more complicated forms
by the symmetrical replacement of edges and corners, together with
the drawings of many structural lattices. In the text, Haüy shows
clearly how all the varieties of crystal forms are constructed
according to a few simple types of symmetry; for instance, that the
cube, octahedron, and dodecahedron all have the same high degree
of symmetry, and that the apparently very diverse forms shown by
one and the same substance are all referable to one of these simple
fundamental or systematic forms. Moreover, Haüy clearly states the
laws which govern crystal symmetry, and practically gives us the
main lines of symmetry of five of the seven systems as we now
classify them, the finishing touch having been supplied in our own
time by Victor von Lang.
Haüy further showed that difference of chemical composition was
accompanied by real difference of crystalline form, and he entered
deeply into chemistry, so far as it was then understood, in order to
extend the scope of his observations. It must be remembered that it
was only nine years before, in 1774, that Priestley had discovered
oxygen, and that Lavoisier had only just (in the same year as Haüy’s
paper was read to the Academy, 1782) published his celebrated
“Elements de Chimie”; and further, that Lavoisier’s memoir
“Reflexions sur le Phlogistique” was actually published by the
Academy in the same year, 1783, as that in which this book was
written by Haüy. Moreover, it was also in this same year, 1783, that
Cavendish discovered the compound nature of water.
Considering, therefore, all these facts, it is truly surprising that
Haüy should have been able to have laid so accurately the
foundations of the science of crystallography. That he undoubtedly
did so, thus securing to himself for all time the term which is
currently applied to him of “father of crystallography,” is clearly
apparent from a perusal of his book and of his subsequent memoirs.
The above only represents a small portion of Haüy’s achievements.
For he discovered, besides, the law of rational indices, the
generalisation which is at the root of crystallographic science,
limiting, as it does, the otherwise infinite number of possible crystal
forms to comparatively few, which alone are found to be capable of
existence as actual crystals. The essence of this law, which will be
fully explained in Chapter V., is that the relative lengths intercepted
along the three principal axes of the crystal, by the various faces
other than those of the fundamental form, the faces of which are
parallel to the axes, are expressed by the simplest unit integers, 1, 2,
3, or 4, the latter being rarely exceeded and then only corresponding
to very small and altogether secondary faces.
This discovery impressed Haüy with the immense influence which
the structure of the crystal substance exerts on the external form,
and how, in fact, it determines that form. For the observations were
only to be explained on the supposition that the crystal was built up
of structural units, which he imagined to be miniature crystals
shaped like the fundamental form, and that the faces were dependent
on the step-like arrangement possible to the exterior of such an
assemblage. This brought him inevitably to the intimate relation
which cleavage must bear to such a structure, that it really
determined the shape of, and was the expression of the nature of, the
structural units. Thus, before the conception of the atomic theory by
Dalton, whose first paper (read 23rd October 1803), was published
in the year 1803 in the Proceedings of the Manchester Literary and
Philosophical Society, two years after the publication of Haüy’s last
work (his “Traité de Minéralogie,” Paris, 1801), Haüy came to the
conclusion that crystals were composed of units which he termed
“Molécules Intégrantes,” each of which comprised the whole
chemical compound, a sort of gross chemical molecule. Moreover, he
went still further in his truly original insight, for he actually
suggested that the molécules intégrantes were in turn composed of
“Molécules Elémentaires,” representing the simple matter of the
elementary substances composing the compound, and hinted further
that these elementary portions had properly orientated positions
within the molécules intégrantes.
He thus not only nearly forestalled Dalton’s atomic theory, but also
our recent work on the stereometric orientation of the atoms in the
molecule in a crystal structure. Dalton’s full theory was not published
until the year 1811, in his epoch-making book entitled “A New
System of Chemical Philosophy,” although his first table of atomic
weights was given as an appendix to the memoir of 1803. Thus in the
days when chemistry was in the making at the hands of Priestley,
Lavoisier, Cavendish, and Dalton do we find that crystallography was
so intimately connected with it that a crystallographer well-nigh
forestalled a chemist in the first real epoch-making advance, a lesson
that the two subjects should never be separated in their study, for if
either the chemist or the crystallographer knows but little of what the
other is doing, his work cannot possibly have the full value with
which it would otherwise be endowed.
The basis of Haüy’s conceptions was undoubtedly cleavage. He
describes most graphically on page 10 of his “Essai” of 1784 how he
was led to make the striking observation that a hexagonal prism of
calcite, terminated by a pair of hexagons normal to the prism axis,
similar to the prisms shown in Fig. 6 (Plate III.) except that the ends
were flat, showed oblique internal cleavage cracks, by enhancing
which with the aid of a few judicious blows he was able to separate
from the middle of the prism a kernel in the shape of a
rhombohedron, the now well-known cleavage rhombohedron of
calcite. He then tried what kinds of kernels he could get from dog-
tooth spar (illustrated in Fig. 7) and other different forms of calcite,
and he was surprised to find that they all yielded the same
rhombohedral kernel. He subsequently investigated the cleavage
kernels of other minerals, particularly of gypsum, fluorspar, topaz,
and garnet, and found that each mineral yielded its own particular
kernel. He next imagined the kernels to become smaller and smaller,
until the particles thus obtained by cleaving the mineral along its
cleavage directions ad infinitum were the smallest possible. These
miniature kernels having the full composition of the mineral he
terms “Molécules Constituantes” in the 1784 “Essai,” but in the 1801
“Traité” he calls them “Molécules Intégrantes” as above mentioned.
He soon found that there were three distinct types of molécules
intégrantes, tetrahedra, triangular prisms, and parallelepipeda, and
these he considered to be the crystallographic structural units.
Having thus settled what were the units of
the crystal structure, Haüy adopted Romé de
l’Isle’s idea of a primitive form, not
necessarily identical with the molécule
intégrante, but in general a parallelepipedon
formed by an association of a few molécules
Fig. 12. intégrantes, the parallelepipedal group being
termed a “Molécule Soustractive.” The
primary faces of the crystal he then supposed
to be produced by the simple regular growth or piling on of
molécules intégrantes or soustractives on the primitive form. The
secondary faces not parallel to the cleavage planes next attracted his
attention, and these, after prolonged study, he explained by
supposing that the growth upon the primitive form eventually ceased
to be complete at the edges of the primary faces, and that such
cessation occurred in a regular step by step manner, by the
suppression of either one, two, or sometimes three molécules
intégrantes or soustractives along the edge of each layer, like a
stepped pyramid, the inclination of which depends on how many
bricks or stone blocks are intermitted in each layer of brickwork or
masonry. Fig. 12 will render this quite clear, the face AB being
formed by single block-steps, and the face CD by two blocks being
intermitted to form each step. The plane AB or CD containing the
outcropping edges of the steps would thus be the secondary plane
face of the crystal, and the molécules intégrantes or soustractives
(the steps can only be formed by parallelepipedal units) being
infinitesimally small, the re-entrant angles of the steps would be
invisible and the really furrowed surface appear as a plane one. Haüy
is careful to point out, however, that the crystallising force which
causes this stepped development (or lack of development) is
operative from the first, for the minutest crystals show secondary
faces, and often better than the larger crystals.
An instance of a mineral with tetrahedral
molécules intégrantes Haüy gives in
tourmaline, and the primitive form of
tourmaline he considered to be a
rhombohedron, conformably to the well-
known rhombohedral cleavage of the mineral,
made up of six tetrahedra. Again, hexagonal
structures formed by three prismatic cleavage
planes inclined at 60° are considered by him Fig. 13.
as being composed of molécules intégrantes
of the form of 60° triangular prisms, or
molécules soustractives of the shape of 120° rhombic prisms, each of
the latter being formed by two molécules intégrantes situated base to
base. This will be clear from Figs. 13 and 14, the former representing
the structure as made up of equilateral prismatic structural units,
and the latter portraying the same structure but composed of 120°-
parallelepipeda by elimination of one cleavage direction; each unit in
the latter case possesses double the volume of the triangular one, and
being of parallelepipedal section is capable of producing secondary
faces when arranged step-wise, whereas the triangular structure is
not. The points at the intersections in these diagrams should for the
present be disregarded; they will shortly be referred to for another
purpose.
Probably, the most permanent and important of Haüy’s
achievements was the discovery of the law of rational indices. At first
this only took the form of the observation of the very limited number
of rows of molécules intégrantes or
soustractives suppressed. In introducing it on
page 74 of his 1784 “Essai” he says: “Quoique
je n’aie observé jusqu’ici que des
décroissemens qui se sont par des
soutractions d’une ou de deux rangées de
molécules, et quelquefois de trois rangées,
mais très rarement, il est possible qu’il se
trouve des crystaux dans lesquels il y ait
Fig. 14.
quatre ou cinq rangées de molécules
supprimées à chaque décroissement, et même
un plus grand nombre encore. Mais ces cas me semblent devoir être
plus rares, à proportion que le nombre des rangées soutraites sera
plus considérable. On conçoit donc comment le nombre des formes
secondaires est néçessairement limité.”
The essential difference between Haüy’s views and our present
ones, which will be explained in Chapter IX., is that Haüy takes
cleavage absolutely as his guide, and considers the particles, into
which the ultimate operation of cleavage divides a crystal, as the
solid structural units of the crystal, the unit thus having the shape of
at least the molécule intégrante. Now every crystalline substance
does not develop cleavage, and others only develop it along a single
plane, or along a couple of planes parallel to the same direction, that
of their intersection and of the axis of the prism which two such
cleavages would produce, and which prism would be of unlimited
length, being unclosed.
Again, in other cases cleavage, such as the octahedral cleavage of
fluorspar, yields octahedral or tetrahedral molécules intégrantes
which are not congruent, that is to say, do not fit closely together to
fill space, as is the essence of Haüy’s theory. Hence, speaking
generally, partitioning by means of cleavage directions does not
essentially and invariably yield identical plane-faced molecules
which fit together in contact to completely fill space, although in the
particular instances chosen from familiar substances by Haüy it
often happens to do so. Haüy’s theory is thus not adequately general,
and the advance of our knowledge of crystal forms has rendered it
more and more apparent that Haüy’s theory was quite insufficient,
and his molécules intégrantes and soustractives mere geometrical
abstractions, having no actual basis in material fact; but that at the
same time it gave us a most valuable indication of where to look for
the true conception.
This will be developed further into our present theory of the
homogeneous partitioning of space, in Chapter IX. But it may be
stated here, in concluding our review of the pioneer work of Haüy,
that in the modern theory all consideration of the shape of the
ultimate structural units is abandoned as unnecessary and
misleading, and that each chemical molecule is considered to be
represented by a point, which may be either its centre of gravity, a
particular atom in the molecule (for we are now able in certain cases
to locate the orientation of the spheres of influence of the elementary
atoms in the chemical molecules), or a purely representative point
standing for the molecule. The only condition is that the points
chosen within the molecules shall be strictly analogous, and similarly
orientated. The dots at the intersections of the lines in Figs. 13 and 14
are the representative points in question. We then deal with the
distances between the points, the latter being regarded as molecular
centres, rather than with the dimensions of the cells themselves
regarded as solid entities. We thus avoid the as yet unsolved question
of how much is matter and how much is interspace in the room
between the molecular centres. In this form the theory is in
conformity with all the advances of modern physics, as well as of
chemistry. And with this reservation, and after modifying his theory
to this extent, one cannot but be struck with the wonderful
perspicacity of Haüy, for he appears to have observed and considered
almost every problem with which the crystallographer is confronted,
and his laws of symmetry and of rational indices are perfectly
applicable to the theory as thus modernised.
CHAPTER IV
THE SEVEN STYLES OF CRYSTAL ARCHITECTURE.